Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

Only $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

Problem Animal Behavior: Funtional Assessment & Constructional Contingency Management
Problem Animal Behavior: Funtional Assessment & Constructional Contingency Management
Problem Animal Behavior: Funtional Assessment & Constructional Contingency Management
Ebook698 pages7 hours

Problem Animal Behavior: Funtional Assessment & Constructional Contingency Management

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars

()

Read preview

About this ebook

Problem Animal Behavior is an essential textbook providing detailed coverage of the functional assessment of problem animal behavior and the design and implementation of constructional contingency management plans. It introduces the natural science of behavior and the basic laws and principles of behavior. It places a strong emphasis on constructional positive reinforcement-based methods throughout. The strategies and procedures are applicable to all species. Functional assessment forms are provided for the reader’s use.

LanguageEnglish
Release dateJan 1, 2016
ISBN9781617812002
Problem Animal Behavior: Funtional Assessment & Constructional Contingency Management
Author

James O'Heare

James O'Heare is a Behaviorologist who has spent over 25 years researching animal behavior and animal rights. He lives in Ottawa, Canada.

Read more from James O'heare

Related to Problem Animal Behavior

Related ebooks

Dogs For You

View More

Related articles

Reviews for Problem Animal Behavior

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars
0 ratings

0 ratings0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    Problem Animal Behavior - James O'Heare

    Problem Animal Behavior

    James O’Heare

    BehaveTech Publishing

    Ottawa Canada

    Copyright © 2016 by James O’Heare. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or by an information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the author.

    Title: Problem Animal Behavior

    Publisher: BehaveTech Publishing, Ottawa, Canada, www.BehaveTech.com

    Author: James O’Heare

    Cover art and book design: James O’Heare

    Limits of Liability and Disclaimer of Warranty:

    The author shall not be liable in the event of incidental or consequential damages or loss in connection with, or arising out of, the furnishing, performance, or use of the instructions or suggestions contained in this book. This book provides information of a general nature. Working with nonhuman animals IS risky.

    ISBN 9781-927744-11-6

    PREFACE

    Problem Animal Behavior is an advanced level textbook on all fundamental aspects of assessing problem animal behaviors, and constructing and implementing contingency management plans to resolve them.

    The material is condensed and concise and should be read as any other textbook, not as a novel or other light reading. It must be read slowly and carefully, and in many cases, reread, to ensure that the appropriate expansion of one’s repertoire is achieved. It should also be read actively, that is the reader should reframe concepts in different terms and devise one’s own examples. If the reader is stuck, they should avoid skipping over the challenging content; they should reread the section and find the solution before proceeding. Readers should question themselves on how to apply what they are reading and not proceed until they are proficient with the material they have read. In other words, this material is intended to be studied, not just read.

    Readers will find that some terms will be used in context before they are covered in depth. The terms used and the context they are used in will provide adequate familiarity for their use at that point and to make their elaboration later on easier. Furthermore, many of the topics intertwine to such an extent that discussing one requires reference to other principles or processes, perhaps not yet introduced. This will also require the elaboration of some points in more than one section. The repetition in elaborating these complex topics will provide more effective conditioning. By the time the reader gets to the major section elaborating a particular topic, they may find they already have a basic familiarity with that topic. Readers may also refer to the glossary at the back of the book for added clarity.

    The material is applicable to any species of animal, though the emphasis in on common species of companion animals such as dogs, cats, parrots, and horses. Most of the examples relate to dogs, but the concepts can be equally applied to other species, including humans. The same fundamental laws, principles, strategies, and procedures related to analyzing, assessing and changing behavior apply to all of these species.

    There are broadly two kinds of contingency management categories. One relates to resolving a behavioral deficit and the other to resolving behavioral excess. With behavioral deficits, the subject either does not exhibit a target behavior at all or does not exhibit the behavior in response to the designated cue. With behavioral excesses, the so deemed problematic behavior is exhibited, but the owner seeks to reduce or eliminate its occurrence. This distinction is somewhat arbitrary in some ways, but not in others. Those who deal exclusively with resolving behavioral deficits are usually referred to as trainers, while those who also deal with resolving behavioral excesses are usually referred to generically as behavior consultants, or from a behaviorological orientation, behavior technologists. The companion animal behavior field tends to recognize this distinction, since there is an increase in the scope of repertoire proficiencies required for also resolving behavioral excess.¹ The distinction is useful in other ways as well, since there are different objectives, strategies, and procedures associated with each, despite the significant overlap. In this book, I will place the emphasis on resolving behavioral excesses, although this usually involves replacing the problematic behavior with another behavior, which then also involves addressing a behavioral deficit. For an in-depth treatment of the topic of training, see O’Heare (2014).

    As with all books that I write, they remain an approximation to be improved with subsequent editions. I hope that you find the material useful.

    CONTENTS

    PREFACE

    CONTENTS

    INTRODUCTION

    BEHAVIORAL ENGINEERING

    CHAPTER 1. BEHAVIOROLOGY

    BEHAVIOROLOGY

    Definition and History

    Philosophy of Natural Science

    Natural Science

    Radical Behaviorism

    Modes of Causation

    Evolutions via Selection by Consequences

    Selection by Consequences

    Biological Evolution

    Repertoire Evolution

    Cultural Evolution

    Selection and Causation: Summary and Conclusion

    PSYCHOLOGY

    BEHAVIOR ANALYSIS

    ETHOLOGY

    MEDICAL MODEL

    ORIENTATION OF THIS BOOK

    THE VERBAL BEHAVIOR OF NATURAL SCIENTISTS OF BEHAVIOR

    BEHAVIOROLOGY IS COMPREHENSIVE

    CHAPTER 2. BEHAVIOR–ENVIRONMENT RELATIONS

    BEHAVIOR, STIMULATION, AND FUNCTIONAL RELATIONS

    Behavior

    Categories of Behavior

    Operant versus Respondent Behavior

    Unconditioned versus Conditioned Behavior

    Stimulation

    Functional Relations and Contingencies

    Structure of Operant Contingencies

    Causation in Operant Contingencies

    Respondent Contingencies

    Conditioning

    Definition

    The Physics of Behavior

    Effects of Conditioning on Behavior

    Why Do Consequences Function as Such?

    Contingency Analyses

    Depicting Contingencies

    Analyzing Episodes of Behavior

    Component Contingencies in the Three-Term Contingency

    Externalizing Contingencies

    Increasing Complexity in Accounting for Behavior

    CHAPTER 3. OPERANT CONDITIONING

    POSTCEDENT PRINCIPLES, PROCESSES, AND PROCEDURES

    Law of Effect

    Basic Terms and Categories

    Reinforcement

    Added Reinforcement

    Subtracted Reinforcement

    The Premack Principle and Activity Reinforcers

    Some Potentially Confusing Distinctions

    Punishment

    Added Punishment

    Subtracted Punishment

    Extinction

    Variables Influencing Effectiveness of Reinforcement

    Contiguity

    Contingency

    Motivating Operations

    Reinforcer Characteristics

    Task Characteristics

    Concurrent Contingencies

    Variables Influencing the Effectiveness of Punishment

    Contiguity

    Contingency

    Intense

    Management of Reinforcement

    Alternative

    ANTECEDENT PRINCIPLES, PROCESSES, AND PROCEDURES

    Stimulus Control

    Terms and Relations

    Generalization and Discrimination Training

    Generalization

    Discrimination

    Transferring Stimulus Control

    Prompting

    Function-Altering Stimuli

    Motivating Operations

    Terms, Processes, and Distinctions

    Differentiating Between Motivating Operations and Evocative Stimuli

    Differentiating Between Motivating Operations and Other Function-Altering Stimuli

    Emotional Arousal as Motivating Operations

    Other Function-altering Stimuli

    Depicting Function-altering Stimuli in Contingency Analyses

    FADING AND ESTABLISHING FUNCTION-ALTERING STIMULI

    N-TERM CONTINGENCIES

    Added Consequating Terms

    Added Behavior Terms

    BEHAVIORAL COMPLEXITIES

    Concurrent Contingencies

    Law of Cumulative Complexity

    CHAPTER 4. RESPONDENT CONDITIONING

    TERMS, PRINCIPLES, AND PROCESSES

    OTHER RESPONDENT PROCESSES

    THE IMPORTANCE OF RESPONDENT CONDITIONING

    CHAPTER 5. SCHEDULES OF ADDED REINFORCEMENT

    SIMPLE SCHEDULES OF ADDED REINFORCEMENT

    Continuous Reinforcement

    Extinction

    INTERMITTENT REINFORCEMENT

    Fixed Ratio Schedule of Added Reinforcement

    Variable Ratio Schedule of Added Reinforcement

    Fixed Interval Schedule of Added Reinforcement

    Variable Interval Schedule of Added Reinforcement

    Fixed Duration Schedule of Added Reinforcement

    Variable Duration Schedule of Added Reinforcement

    Variations on Interval Schedules

    Differential Reinforcement of Low Rate of Responding

    Differential Reinforcement of High Rate of Responding

    Differential Reinforcement of Diminishing Rates

    Schedule Extensions

    Limited Hold

    Jackpotting

    COMPOUND SCHEDULES OF REINFORCEMENT

    Differential Reinforcement

    Differential Reinforcement of Incompatible Behavior

    Differential Reinforcement of Alternative Behavior

    Differential Reinforcement of Other Behavior

    Differential Reinforcement of Successive Approximations of a Terminal Behavior (Shaping)

    MANAGING SCHEDULES OF REINFORCEMENT

    CHAPTER 6. AVERSIVE STIMULATION AND ITS PROBLEMATIC SIDE EFFECTS

    INTRODUCTION

    WHY IS THE OCCURRENCE OF AVERSIVE STIMULATION SO PERVASIVE?

    PROBLEMATIC EFFECTS OF AVERSIVE STIMULATION

    Respondent Side Effects: Aversive Emotional Arousal and Conditioning

    Operant Side Effects: Escape Behavior

    CLARIFYING PUNISHMENT AND ITS ROLE IN CHANGING BEHAVIOR

    Punishment is Less Efficient than Extinction

    Some Problems with Effective Punishment

    Does Punishment Work?

    ALTERNATIVES TO AVERSIVE CONTROL OF BEHAVIOR

    CHAPTER 7. MINIMALLY AVERSIVE CONTINGENCY MANAGEMENT PLANNING

    INTRODUCTION

    AVOIDING EXTREMISM AND DOGMATISM

    AVERSIVENESS-RATCHETING STRATEGIES

    EMPHASIZING CONSTRUCTIONAL ADDED REINFORCEMENT-BASED METHODS

    WHY IMPLEMENT THE CONSTRUCTIONAL ADDED REINFORCEMENT-EMPHASIZED BEHAVIOR CHANGE STRATEGY?

    STRATEGY FOR AVOIDING VERSUS BANNING AVERSIVE METHODS AND TOOLS

    The Strategy

    Box 1. Functional Assessment and Behavior Objectives

    Box 2. Construct and Implement a Constructional Minimally Aversive +R-emphasized Contingency Management Plan

    Box 3. Analysis of Failure: Identify and Resolve the Cause of Inadequate Progress

    Box 4. Escalate Efforts to Identify and Resolve Cause of Inadequate Progress

    Does Failure Constitute an Unmanageable and Unacceptable Safety Risk?

    Box 5. Complete Review and Consider Supplements/Medications

    Box 6. Emergency: Consider more Aversive Procedure

    Box 7. Euthanasia

    CHAPTER 8. TRAINING HUMANS

    INTRODUCTION TO VERBAL BEHAVIOR

    ENCOURAGING PRODUCTIVE VERBAL BEHAVIOR

    GENERAL STRATEGY FOR TRAINING HUMANS

    Establish Objective

    Describe, Explain, and Demonstrate

    Assess Proficiency

    Follow-up

    CHAPTER 9. FUNCTIONAL ASSESSMENT

    INTRODUCTION

    EXPLANATORY FICTIONS

    FUNCTIONAL ASSESSMENT

    Screening

    Functional Assessment Interview

    Contingency Analysis

    Defining the Target Behavior

    Direct Observation

    Introduction

    Observe the Behavior

    Measuring Behavior

    Measures of Behavior

    Choosing Among Measures of Behavior

    Measurement Systems

    Selecting a Measurement System

    Tracking the Target Behavior Quantitatively

    Clarifying Contingency Analyses with ABC Analyses

    Establishing a Baseline

    Functional Analysis

    AB Design

    Reversal Design

    Guidelines for Engaging in Functional Analyses

    FINAL NOTE ON FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS

    DIAGRAMMING THE CONTINGENCY ANALYSIS

    FUNCTIONAL DIAGNOSIS

    1.0 Direct Access (DA)

    1.1 DA: Immediate Sensory Stimuli

    1.2 DA: Tangible Reinforcers

    2.0 Socially Mediated Access (SMA)

    2.1 SMA: Human Attention

    2.2 SMA: Conspecific Attention

    2.3 SMA: Tangible Reinforcers

    3.0 Direct Escape (DE)

    3.1 DE: Aversive Social Situation

    3.2 DE: Task Challenge (Duration)

    3.3 DE: Task Challenge (Difficulty)

    3.4 DE: Aversive Physical Stimuli

    4.0 Socially Mediated Escape (SME)

    4.1 SME: Aversive Social Stimuli

    4.2 SME: Task Challenge (Duration)

    4.3 SME: Task Challenge (Difficulty)

    4.4 SME: Aversive Physical Stimuli

    Multifunctional Behavior

    CHAPTER 10. STRAGETGIES IN CONSTRUCTIONAL CONTINGENCY MANAGEMENT PLANNING

    INTRODUCTION TO CONSTRUCTIONAL CONTINGENCY MANAGEMENT PLANNING

    What is a Contingency Management Plan

    Contingency Management Plan as Test of Contingency Analysis

    Contingency Management Planning as a Comprehensive and Systematic, yet Practical, Scientific Process

    The Constructional Approach

    The Graded Approach (aka Errorless Conditioning)

    CHARACTERISTICS OF AN EFFECTIVE CONTINGENCY MANAGEMENT PLAN

    Changing the Environment to Change Behavior

    Contingency Management Plans are Derived from the Functional Assessment Data

    Contingency Management Plans Must be Realistic and Flexible

    Contingency Management Procedures are Consistent with the Principles of Behavior and Empirically Supported Intervention Strategies and Procedures

    Contingency Management Plans Make the Target Problem Behavior Irrelevant, Inefficient, and Ineffective

    Contingency Management Plan Makes Target Behavior Irrelevant

    Contingency Management Plan Makes Target Behavior Inefficient

    Contingency Management Plan Makes Target Behavior Ineffective

    THE BEHAVIOR REPLACEMENT STRATEGY

    MINIMALLY AVERSIVE INTERVENTION STRATEGIES

    CHAPTER 11. ESTABLISHING FORMAL BEHAVIOR OBJECTIVES

    DETERMINING FORMAL BEHAVIOR OBJECTIVES

    STATING THE FORMAL BEHAVIOR OBJECTIVE

    Evocative Stimulus

    Target Behavior and Replacement Behavior

    Level

    TRACKING TARGET AND REPLACEMENT BEHAVIORS

    ESTABLISHING BEHAVIOR OBJECTIVES

    Example 1. Jumping Up

    Example 2. Separation Related Behaviors

    Example 3. Biting

    Example 4. Cowering

    Example 5. Coprophagia

    Example 6. Scratching Furniture

    CHAPTER 12. CONSTRUCTIONAL CONTINGENCE MANAGEMENT PLANNING AND PROCEDURES

    COMPREHENSIVE CONTINGENCY MANAGEMENT PLANNING

    ANTECEDENT CONTROL PROCEDURES

    Evocative Stimulus Control

    Preclusion

    The Graded (Errorless) Approach

    Function-Altering Stimulus Control

    Environment Enrichment

    Noncontingent Functional Reinforcement (NCR)

    Eliminating Establishing Operations

    Changing Emotional Behavior and Arousal

    Respondent Conditioning Procedures and Externalizing Contingencies

    Noncontingent Functional Reinforcement

    Medication and Supplementation

    Other Function-Altering Influences

    Rehabilitating Conditioned Helplessness and/or Response Depression

    POSTCEDENT CONTROL PROCEDURES

    Tolerance versus Replacement Escape

    Postcedent Contingency Management Procedures

    Response Effort Control

    Managing the Target Behavior: Preclusion vs. Extinction vs. Chain Interruption

    Differential Reinforcement

    Differential Reinforcement of Incompatible or Alternative Behavior

    DRI/DRA for Access-Functional Behaviors

    DRI/DRA-like Procedure for Escape Functional Behaviors

    Differential Reinforcement of Other Behavior

    DRO for Access Functional Behaviors

    DRO-like Procedure for Escape Functional Behaviors

    Differential Reinforcement of Low Rate of Responding

    Graded Differential Subtracted Reinforcement of Other Behaviors (Tolerance Training)—Transitioning to Added Reinforcement

    Added Punishment

    Steps for Applying Differential Reinforcement Procedures

    GENERAL CONTINGENCY MANAGEMENT STRATEGIES BY FUNCTIONAL CLASSIFICATION CODE

    Direct Access

    Direct Access: Immediate Sensory Stimuli

    Antecedent Control Tactics:

    Postcedent Control Tactics:

    Direct Access: Tangible Reinforcers

    Antecedent Control Tactics

    Postcedent Control Tactics

    Socially Mediated Access

    Socially Mediated Access: Human Attention

    Antecedent Control Tactics

    Postcedent Control Tactics

    Socially Mediated Access: Nonhuman Attention

    Antecedent Control Tactics

    Postcedent Control Tactics

    Socially Mediated Access: Tangible Reinforcer / Activity Reinforcer

    Antecedent Control Tactics

    Postcedent Control Tactics

    Direct Escape

    Direct Escape: Aversive Social Situation

    Antecedent Control Tactics

    Postcedent Control Tactics

    Direct Escape: Task Challenge (Duration)

    Antecedent Control Tactics

    Postcedent Control Tactics

    Direct Escape: Task Challenge (Difficulty)

    Postcedent Control Tactics

    Direct Escape: Aversive Physical Stimulation

    Antecedent Control Tactics

    Postcedent Control Tactics

    Socially Mediated Escape

    Socially Mediated Escape: Aversive Social Situation

    Antecedent Control Tactics

    Postcedent Control Tactics

    Socially Mediated Escape: Task Challenge (Duration)

    Antecedent Control Tactics

    Postcedent Control Tactics

    Socially Mediated Escape: Task Challenge (Difficulty)

    Postcedent Control Tactics

    Socially Mediated Escape: Aversive Physical Stimulation

    Antecedent Control Tactics

    Postcedent Control Tactics

    CHAPTER 13. MAINTENANCE

    WORKING TOWARD MAINTENANCE

    Generalization Training

    Thinning the Schedule of Reinforcement and Introducing Non-Trainer–Mediated Reinforcers

    Monitoring and Re-intervening When Necessary

    APPENDIX 1. CONTINGENCY MANAGEMENT PROJECT: STEPS

    GLOSSARY

    INDEX

    RESOURCES

    BIBLIOGRAPHY

    INTRODUCTION

    Behavioral Engineering

    This book will introduce the reader to the fundamental laws and principles of the natural science of behavior, behaviorology, and to the technology of behavior it informs. A technology is the application of basic natural science to addressing practical problems and engineering encompasses the practices involved in achieving the necessary changes. In the case of behavior, the behaviorologist or behavior technologist identifies the components of the environment causing the behavior of concern and makes changes to those functionally related environmental events to effect changes in the behavior. This engineering of changes in behavior is more proximally the engineering of those components of the environment that cause the behavior in a way that changes the behavior. The book is designed to be practical and after an introduction to the fundamental laws and principles of behavior, will cover the three phases common to all contingency management plans:

    •  Functional Assessment

    •  Contingency management intervention Contingency management intervention Contingency management intervention

    •  Maintenance

    We begin our coverage with a discussion of behaviorology as a discipline. Readers disinterested in this should skip ahead to Chapter 2.

    CHAPTER 1. BEHAVIOROLOGY

    Behaviorology

    Definition and History

    Put simply, Behaviorology is the natural science and technology of behavior. More accurately, behaviorology is the natural science and technology of environment–behavior functional relations. More elaborately:

    Behaviorology, a comprehensive discipline with philosophical, experimental, technological, analytical, conceptual, and theoretical components, is the natural science among the life sciences, emphasizing the causal mechanism of selection, that discovers, interprets, and applies the single and multiple variables that are in functional relations with the simple and complex, overt and covert behaviors of individual organisms… during their lifetime (and beyond, with respect to cultural practices), and that takes into account the socio–cultural and physical variables from the internal and external environments as well as variables from the biological history of the species (Ledoux, 2014, p. 67).

    Behaviorologists are interested in all behavior, from the simplest forms of reflexes exhibited by very simply structured organisms all the way to the most complex of human behaviors, including the most complex of verbal behavior and even how we behave (some might say perceive) reality itself.

    Behaviorology stretches back to the early 1930s, when Burrhus F. Skinner introduced radical behaviorism, the philosophical foundation of the natural science of behavior discussed in this book. At that time, Skinner was working within a psychology department even though the paradigm he was proposing was incommensurable with psychology, and as a result, it was unfortunately called operant psychology at that time.

    Skinner believed he could transform psychology into a natural science. He likely believed, naively as it turned out, all psychology needed was for someone to demonstrate a natural science of behavior was possible. He was, however, unsuccessful despite an incredibly productive career in natural science. In the 1970s, as it became clear mainstream psychology could not be transformed into a natural science, psychologists of a natural science bent that sought to distance themselves from the rest of psychology, founded behavior analysis. However, organized psychology claimed behavior analysis as a formal division of psychology. Within behavior analysis, philosophical integrity and clarity, and hence credibility, were traded for the political influence that comes with high membership numbers and working within legally protected organized psychology. Behavior analysis allowed a wide range of members with an eclectic set of orientations and perspectives rather than reinforcing a strong dedication to natural science as a membership criterion. As a result of this eclectic distribution of orientations among members, behavior analysis, as a community, put forth little to no objection to psychology’s claim on it and indeed embraced the relation with organized psychology. Attributable to this history and the ongoing association with psychology, many natural scientists believed the behavior analysis label could not now credibly represent a natural science position. As well, they believed that behavior analysis could not justify its separate certification credentials so long as it remained a branch of psychology. It was argued that behavior analysts would always be at risk of needing to be supervised by licensed psychologists, engaging in low level subordinate activities, or trading one half to two thirds of their natural science and behaviorological engineering training with training in mainstream psychology so they may be licensed as psychologists as well (Ledoux, 2014).

    Some natural scientists of behavior supported remaining as a branch of psychology. Under psychology, with its vast resources, career and grant opportunities, and power, not to mention its legally protected right to help the public with behavior issues, one can expect a much easier time of it, career wise. Many of these scientists held the position that the only viable option would be to influence the course of psychology from the inside and/or simply work within organized psychology, but incommensurably with the rest of psychology’s disciplines. It might be argued by some that psychology is merely a banner name for any discipline involving behavior and/or the mind and it is therefore possible, and indeed appropriate, to work within psychology as a natural scientist.

    However, many natural scientists of behavior were dissatisfied with the arrangement of being a division of a decidedly unscientific discipline, because of the credibility problems it poses and being controlled in various ways by an incommensurable disciplinary managing organization. It had become clear to them, in the previous 50 years that: (a) psychology would not, and likely could not, be transformed into a natural science; (b) a natural science of behavior would be more effective and productive than a nonscientific discipline of behavior in solving the many gravely important issues it is tasked with addressing in an acceptable time frame; (c) behavior analysis was now owned by psychology and therefore could not be credible as a full and independent natural science discipline; and (d) the sacrifices and compromises required to work within organized psychology were ethically intolerable and indeed detrimental to the society it served.

    After much debate on the merits of these opposing arguments through the late 1970s and early 1980s, many natural scientists of behavior, recognizing the intolerable and detrimental nature of operating within the organized psychology discipline, agreed that remaining associated with the discipline of psychology would compromise their integrity as natural scientists and preclude their rightful position at the natural science roundtable, as well as hamper their efforts to help resolve immensely important problems. They recognized complete independence was necessary to maintain scientific integrity and behavior analysis was no longer a credible label under which to organize given the previous compromises to its integrity.

    In the 1980s, the entirely independent discipline of behaviorology was founded, with a professional association, educational institution, and peer reviewed journal. Behaviorology is the only comprehensive natural science discipline of behavior that is completely independent of psychology. The professional association managing the discipline of behaviorology and providing educational opportunities is The International Behaviorology Institute (TIBI). Only those with a strong dedication to the assumptions of natural science and who are educated completely in the natural science of behavior may operate as behaviorologists. This requirement means smaller membership numbers, but the maintenance of natural science integrity is always more important than numbers. Credibility does not come from numbers but rather from integrity to natural science and high standards. The TIBI web site is at www.behaviorology.org. The discipline’s fully peer reviewed journal is called the Journal of Behaviorology and is published by TIBI. TIBI members hold positions as professors of behaviorology, work in applied settings and conduct basic research. Within the nonhuman animal field, the Companion Animal Sciences Institute (www.CASInstitute.com) provides technologist level education in behaviorology and the Association of Animal Behavior Professionals (www.AssociationofAnimalBehaviorProfessionals.com) provides certification at the technologist level to animal behavior technologists and publishes a fully peer reviewed journal, the Journal of Animal Behavior Technology. For an excellent and concise description of the development of behaviorology, see Ledoux (2014) and for a more in-depth explanation, see Ledoux (2015).

    Philosophy of Natural Science

    There are different fundamental approaches to studying nature—different methods of knowledge production. Natural science is one such approach, and in this section, this philosophy (i.e. its basic assumptions and tenets) will be elaborated upon.

    Natural Science

    Natural science is an empirical approach to studying the phenomena of nature based on certain philosophical assumptions that together go by the name naturalism. Naturalism is a philosophy of science, utilized by all natural sciences, which holds that only natural events exist, there are no non-real or non-natural events, and all natural events are theoretically measurable in terms of mass, time, distance, temperature, and/or charge. Natural scientists simply do not study proposed non-natural or supernatural events; nor may they postulate them as part of an explanation for natural events. If a supposed event is not at least theoretically measurable, it is not natural, and not an appropriate topic of study. It is only through careful adherence to these assumptions and constraints that natural science can generate such robust, reliable products (such as space shuttles, vaccines, massive skyscrapers and personal computers) when compared to other, less stringently constrained (mystical) methods of studying nature.² Clark (2007) put it eloquently: To be a thorough-going naturalist is to accept yourself as an entirely natural phenomenon. Just as science shows no evidence for a supernatural god up there, there’s no evidence for an immaterial soul or mental agent in here, supervising the body and brain.

    A derivative assumption of naturalism is that of determinism, which states any detectable event represents the culmination of an unbroken and unbreakable natural history—that is, all things are part of a continuous sequence or network of causes and effects and there can be no intrusion into this sequence by non-natural events. In other words, nothing occurs spontaneously, initiatively, or proactively; all events are completely orderly and lawful—that is, caused/reactive. This orderly and lawful characteristic of nature allows us to study it and derive laws and principles that describe these causal relations that we refer to as functional relations.³

    With respect to behavior, naturalism implies that behavior is a passive and completely caused natural reaction of a body to the environment. Behavior is not an exception to the laws of nature. From a natural science perspective, there cannot be a so-called free will, as this would imply a non-natural event, force, or agent within that could spontaneously and initiatively direct the body to act for which there is no scientific support. Natural science disallows mystical, untestable accounts such as the notion of free will. The natural science approach generates a more parsimonious explanation of behavior derived directly from the data, leading to more effective and efficient control over behavior. The naturalistic understanding and acceptance of our fully caused, interdependent nature is directly at odds with the widespread belief … that human beings have supernatural, contra-causal free will, and so are in but not fully of this world. (Clark, 2008)

    Take note these are assumptions. They cannot be proven any more than any other basic or axiomatic assumptions, including mystical ones underlying religion and pseudoscience. The utility of a philosophy, including its basic assumptions, is determined by how effective and efficient it is at generating parsimonious, robust, and reliable products and how well it withstands efforts to refute it. Natural scientists are not required to believe these assumptions are the truth, but rather they are required to operate under the stated assumptions and within these constraints when they carry out scientific work. It happens the assumptions of naturalism result in the most parsimonious, robust, and reliable products (i.e., theories, technologies etc.).

    Psychology, by contrast, does not require the constraints and assumptions required by the philosophy of natural science—naturalism—and that being the case, cannot be a natural science. Psychology emphasizes the explanation of behavior by the actions of a so-called mind, a non-natural thing or force from a mental (nonphysical) dimension that cannot be observed and directly measured, and supposedly directs the actions of the body. Indeed, psychology is the study of mind and behavior. Moreover, there are other disciplines that do not adhere to natural science constraints and assumptions (e.g., astrologists), and as such, they cannot claim the status of natural science either. Mystical assumptions and accounts preclude any discipline from the status of natural science, regardless of whether they also happen to use some scientific methods to study non-natural events as either dependent or independent variables. Non-natural science disciplines, such as theology (religious mysticism—supernatural thing up there), psychology (secular mysticism—supernatural thing in here) etc. are sometimes referred to as sciences to distinguish them from natural sciences, which adhere completely to the philosophical assumptions of natural science. They are referred to as sciences, because they utilize scientific methods. Whether such disciplines deserve the label science is dubious at best, particularly since the general public does not tend to differentiate between science and natural science. These disciplines are also often referred to as soft sciences, which is a soft way of saying the discipline allows for non-natural, or supernatural, events in their accounting for phenomena or they study non-natural phenomena. The most appropriate label for mainstream psychology, and indeed any discipline that uses scientific methods but fails to adhere to the assumptions of natural science, is pseudoscience. A pseudoscience is an activity that may resemble science in some way, including the use of some scientific methods, but which is based on fallacious assumptions (vocabulary.com, n.d.). The proffering of non-natural events is to engage in activities that are based on fallacious assumptions. Within the realm of behavior, theology and psychology fall into this category. The current comprehensive natural science disciplines include biology, geology, physics, chemistry, and behaviorology. Behaviorology is the only natural science of behavior.

    Radical Behaviorism

    Behaviorology was founded on a philosophical framework called radical behaviorism, which was elucidated by Burrhus F. Skinner in the 1930s.⁴ Radical behaviorism is not to be confused with the behaviorisms of the early 1900s. Radical behaviorism is fundamentally different from those other movements commonly clumped together under the name behaviorism (Chiesa, 1994). Radical behaviorism recognizes both respondent and operant behavior and all kinds of behavior, be they public or private. Radical behaviorism simply extends the assumptions of naturalism to the study of behavior. Although Skinner was employed within an academic psychology department, his subject matter and approach were different from that which was (and is) utilized in psychology. Where psychology generally accepts a Cartesian mind-body dichotomy (i.e., dualism) and postulates an inner agent called the psyche or mind to study underlying mental processes, which they considered to be of primary interest, Skinner proposed the study of behavior itself, for its own sake, and from a strictly natural science perspective, without reference to hypothetical (i.e., non-natural) constructs. Taking his inspiration from the Ernst Mach critique of causation, Darwin’s selection causation paradigm in biology, and behavioral work of Ivan Pavlov, Skinner improved vastly upon the behaviorisms that existed at the time. Radical behaviorism is hence a philosophy of natural science and places behaviorology among the natural sciences, along with physics, chemistry, biology, and geology.

    Radical behaviorism is characterized by three fundamental assumptions:

    •  Behavior is an entirely natural phenomenon, respecting the continuity of events in space and time, which accumulates as a natural history of fully caused events.

    •  The emphasis of inquiry is on analyzing environment–behavior functional relations, experimental control over dependent variables, and the application of that control in changing behavior.

    •  Private events such as visualizing, thinking, or emoting are real behaviors occurring in accordance with the same set of laws and principles as more overt public behavior.

    Modes of Causation

    Natural science disciplines study the causal relations between real variables.⁵ The dependent variable refers to the phenomenon to be explained (in our case, behavior) and the independent variable refers to the event that is said to cause or explain it (in our case, environmental stimulation). This is explored further in Chapter 2. Different modes of causation make up the relations between these variables. Physics and chemistry rely heavily on mechanistic causation, which deals with what comes immediately before something else and reliably triggers its occurrence—the second thing depends on the first. For example, I might say sit and that would trigger/cause my dog to sit. Biology and behaviorology rely heavily on selection causation, which deals with selection by consequences—that which comes immediately after something influences the future likelihood of that thing occurring again. For example, because I deliver a treat to my dog every time he sits, upon my saying sit, he is more likely to sit in the future when I say sit, and the consequence that sitting generated causes an increase in the likelihood of future sitting behavior. As you can see, the mechanistic causation paradigm fails to account for this, while the selection causation paradigm does so eloquently. Whereas mechanistic causation deals with contiguous relations, selection causation considers more of the history of the event (the consequences for the behavior in question back through its history). Overcoming the limitations of mechanistic causation with the breakthrough of the idea of selection causation was a turning point in the study of behavior, just as it was in the study of the forms of species.

    Evolutions via Selection by Consequences

    Selection by Consequences

    Mechanistic causation, discovered long ago, is utilized extensively in physical sciences. This model of causation emphasizes a clear chain of causes and then effects. In 1859, Charles Darwin elucidated a different model of causation—that of selection causation. Rather than emphasizing a chain reaction form of causes and effects, Darwin explained the consequences/outcomes that an event generates can influence the future distribution of characteristics of the class of events it preceded. This new model of causation was extremely effective in explaining how the distribution of heritable traits within species evolved over time. The mechanistic model of causation was woefully inadequate to explain this. Later, in the early 1930s, Skinner utilized the same model of causation in the elucidation of radical behaviorism. Selection causation, or put another way, selection by consequences, (as opposed to mechanistic causation) allowed for a very strong means of explanation for, and prediction and control of, the behavior of individual organism. Selection causation is a foundational principle underlying the natural science of behavior. Operant behavior is behavior selected for by the consequences it generates.

    Selection by consequences refers to selection causation, and may broadly be understood as (a) variation in traits or events, (b) interaction with the environment, and (c) differential selection (or replication) of traits. Whether we are talking about physical traits of organisms, the operant behavior of organisms, or even the practices within a culture, there is always variation. These traits (physical structures of the body) or events (behaviors) interact with the environment and the distribution of that trait or event evolves over time, some forms becoming extinct, others becoming highly prominent, and any frequency in between. Selection by consequences provides a vital means of explaining, predicting, and controlling these traits or events, be they cultural practices, like spanking children, physical traits, like eye color, or operants, like walking. Selection by consequences results in three different types of evolution, as alluded to above: biological evolution; repertoire evolution; and cultural evolution.

    Biological Evolution

    Over 150 years ago, Charles Darwin (1859) explained the process of biological evolution. Biological evolution involves the selection of traits by consequences within a population across the span of the existence of the population. Within any population, there is variation in heritable traits among the members of that population. Some traits tend to contribute to greater reproductive rates for members sharing those traits, while other traits do not. (Some can even be counter-reproductive.) This is often characterized as the environment selecting for these traits, however, it is important to recognize that selection simply refers to differential reproductive rates resulting from the contribution of these traits interacting with the environment. There is no purposeful or goal-directed selecting involved in this process and no supernatural being/agent/force doing the selecting.⁶ It is merely a fact that some traits result in higher reproductive rates than others. The environment selects for traits that contribute to reproductive success and selects against traits that do not contribute to reproductive success. Again, by selects, we are simply referring to the fact of the outcome. Thus, the genetic material contributing to reproductively adaptive traits increases in frequency within the population, while genetic material that contributes to reproductively maladaptive traits decreases in frequency—they literally die out along with the members that possess them—within the population over time. This results in the evolution of traits within the population, a continually changing distribution of frequency of that trait. We might refer to these selective pressures as contingencies of reproductive success.⁷ To summarize, there is variation in the distribution of traits, which interact with the environment and differential selection of the trait depending on its contribution to promoting survival and ultimately reproductive success within the environment. As the environment changes over time, the selection forces also change and hence the frequency of traits changes.

    Repertoire Evolution

    About 85 years ago, Burrhus F. Skinner (1938/1991) clarified the process of repertoire evolution, the selection of repertoires of behavior due to consequences it generates within an individual organism across the lifespan of that individual. The phrase repertoire of behavior refers to the full range of behaviors a subject exhibits and can be broken down into convenient categories (e.g., a repertoire of verbal behaviors). An individual’s repertoire of behavior evolves moment-by-moment by way of selection by consequences via contingencies of reinforcement.⁸ Throughout the life of an individual, various behaviors are strengthened by reinforcement, suppressed by punishment, and weakened by extinction on a moment-by-moment basis, as the behaviors are consequated and the relative frequencies of each behavior changes over time. There is variation within the distribution of operants that interact with the environment, which results in differential selection of the operants in the future. As a result of repeated iterations through this cycle, the individual evolves an ever-changing repertoire of operant behavior. This repertoire is established through selection by consequences. Behaviorologists study behavior at this level of analysis and the next.

    Cultural Evolution

    At the cultural level of analysis, selection by consequences involves the selection of cultural practices (e.g., traditions, rituals, norms, ethical rules) within a culture/society/community due to the consequences that the practices generate within the span of existence of the culture (i.e., they outlast the life of individuals). This results in cultural evolution. There is variation within cultural practices within a community, which interacts with the environment, resulting in a differential selection of the practices. Cultural anthropologists study cultures at this level of analysis. Since cultural practices are composed of operant behaviors exhibited by individuals, behaviorologists often study at this level of analysis as well.

    Selection and Causation: Summary and Conclusion

    The unique emphasis Skinner brought to the study of behavior was the selection by consequences mode of causation, known as the selection paradigm. Just as Darwin had explained the perpetuation of genetically heritable traits within a population through generations (phylogeny), Skinner explained the perpetuation of behaviors exhibited by the individual organism within its lifetime (ontogeny). In biology, the evolution of traits within populations is explained by reproductive selection, wherein the environment selects for and against certain genetically coded traits, simply due to the traits that tend to result in greater reproductive success. Similarly, in behaviorology, the environment selects for and against behaviors simply by whether the behavior generates effective, ineffective, or aversive consequences. As mentioned above, cultural selection refers to the selection of cultural practices within a community of individuals. All three of these levels of selection are selection by consequences for the rate of genetic change, behavioral adaptation, and cultural practices, respectively. Fraley and Ledoux (2002, p. 41) described selection by consequences this way:

    The consequences of the past behaviors are said to have selected the behaviors that now occur, and the selection paradigm takes its name from that interpretation. But in each instance of behavior, the body is assumed to behave in the only way that it can behave under the existing circumstances—an assumption that respects the deterministic natural science of philosophy that informs behaviorology. No explanatory appeal is made to a redundant psychological self that would decide or choose the behavior to be exhibited by the body.

    Behaviorology involves the experimental analysis of environment–behavior functional relations, as well as the establishment and application of an efficient and effective technology for controlling behavior. Because of the completely naturalistic character of behaviorology and its emphasis on environment–behavior functional relations, behaviorology is highly effective and efficient in controlling behavior (e.g., training).

    More information about behaviorology is available at www.behaviorology.org. To provide a means to effectively differentiate between other disciplines, branches of disciplines and general approaches that assess behavior are discussed below in detail.

    Psychology

    Psychology is an eclectic aggregate of disparate disciplines, defined as the study of the mind and behavior (American Psychological Association, 2012). In some psychology schools of thought, the mind is the primary emphasis of study, and in others, the activities of the mind are said to explain or elucidate overt behavior.¹⁰ The

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1