Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

Only $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

10 Books that Screwed Up the World: And 5 Others That Didn't Help
10 Books that Screwed Up the World: And 5 Others That Didn't Help
10 Books that Screwed Up the World: And 5 Others That Didn't Help
Ebook290 pages4 hours

10 Books that Screwed Up the World: And 5 Others That Didn't Help

Rating: 3 out of 5 stars

3/5

()

Read preview

About this ebook

You’ve heard of the "Great Books"? These are their evil opposites.

From Machiavelli's The Prince to Alfred Kinsey’s Sexual Behavior in the Human Male, from Karl Marx's Communist Manifesto to Margaret Mead’s Coming of Age in Samoa, these "influential" books have led to war, genocide, totalitarian oppression, the breakdown of the family, and disastrous social experiments.

And yet the toxic ideas peddled in these books are more popular and pervasive than ever. In fact, they might influence your own thinking without your realizing it.

Fortunately, Professor Benjamin Wiker is ready with an antidote, exposing the beguiling errors in each of these evil books.

Witty, learned, and provocative, 10 Books That Screwed Up the World provides a quick education in the worst ideas in human history and explains how we can avoid them in the future.
LanguageEnglish
PublisherRegnery
Release dateMay 6, 2008
ISBN9781596980631
10 Books that Screwed Up the World: And 5 Others That Didn't Help
Author

Benjamin Wiker

Benjamin Wiker, a husband and the father of seven children, holds a Ph.D. in theological ethics from Vanderbilt University. He has taught at Marquette University, St. Mary’s University, and Thomas Aquinas College and is now a professor of political science and the director of human life studies at Franciscan University in Steubenville, Ohio. His twelve books include 10 Books Every Conservative Must Read: Plus Four Not to Miss and One Impostor, The Reformation 500 Years Later: 12 Things You Need to Know, and Worshipping the State: How Liberalism Became Our State Religion.

Read more from Benjamin Wiker

Related to 10 Books that Screwed Up the World

Related ebooks

Language Arts & Discipline For You

View More

Related articles

Reviews for 10 Books that Screwed Up the World

Rating: 2.9253730388059704 out of 5 stars
3/5

67 ratings9 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

  • Rating: 1 out of 5 stars
    1/5
    An absolute dumpster fire. The author clearly didn't understand the content of most of the books he covered and made his outdated worldview very clear. Wrong interpretations, out-of-context quotations, and ethics that are either "good or bad". Morals are far more complex than simply "right or wrong", but the author clearly does not get it. What's even worse is; The author often simply bases his reasoning solely on religion. If religion plays such an important role, and both government and personal life should be dictated by it, then why isn't the bible mentioned? How many wars were caused in the name of Christianity? How many native tribes were enslaved and eliminated because of it?
    How are books about self-improvement, acceptance, and making society as a whole better, worse for the world, than a book that was responsible for countless wars and oppressive regimes?
    I don't know what kind of mental gymnastics the author even did to come up with some of the explanations. Somehow he interpreted the class struggle mentioned by Karl Marx as an argument why Marx wanted to abolish all kinds of families and marriage. I never read something remotely insane than this. He also misses Marx' point, that under capitalism, the proletarian is nothing more than a tool to generate more capital for the capitalist, instead assuming Marx sees people as just objects because of that. Nietzsche's will to power, the driving force of self-growth, overcoming limitations, the author takes as message that survival of the fittest is what Nietzsche meant (which is not).
    The book often comes up with the argumentation "the author was an atheist, therefore the book is evil!" and other religious mumblings.
    This was also the first time I've seen someone spreading hate against pansexuals. According to the author, no one should do sexual experimentation to discover themselves and should strictly stick to one single, heterosexual relationship their entire life. Masturbation is shown as a bad thing, and so is divorce. Unhappy with your partner? Stay with them and be unhappy! That's what the bible wants and you are evil too if you disagree.
    I wish I was joking. To quote the book:
    "their messages: that it would be good to eliminate the “unfit” rather than caring for them charitably; that all evil is caused by one class or race and can be eliminated by the elimination of those people; that we can become geniuses by engaging in sexual bacchanalia; and that easy sex, easy divorce, easy parents, easy standards, and easy religion will cure all that ails us. In each of these cases, it is the cure that kills. "
    If I were to interpret this quote the same way as the author butchered those books, this very book says you are on the same level as Hitler if you think divorce is okay, or if you aren't a radical religious person. Noone would think that way. Well, no one but Benjamin Wiker.


    The book was only good for the totally insane quotes the author brought up. Gave me and my friends something to laugh at. Would have been funnier if it was satire and not something an actual person believes. The book gives a clear image of the author as an unhappy and bitter man, neither happy with his marriage nor sexually pleased generally, one who only finds joy in his life in a fanatical and twisted worldview fueled by radical Christianity that aims to oppress anyone who isn't as unhappy as himself. In Coming of Age in Samoa he made it clear, that he disapproves of teens growing up without any pressure, where they have the opportunity to discover what they like and not, to be with whom makes them happy, the ability to not be with the parents, that perhaps oppress their true self or harm them.

    Kinda ironic that the author created a book that is more dangerous than most of the books it tries to frame as evil. I really wish it was satire. People who live in the 18th century or at least think society should be like that probably like this book, or people who just want to laugh at the crazy, non-sensical, and utterly wrong interpretations of philosophies.
  • Rating: 1 out of 5 stars
    1/5
    Should be titled: 10 books I didn't understand. The only book the author likes is the bible. I regret giving the author the courtesy of finishing this book.

    1 person found this helpful

  • Rating: 2 out of 5 stars
    2/5
    While I agree with a few of the author's book choices, some of the books he choose as corrupting forces seemed to be reflections of their time period rather than written with the intent to corrupt the world around them as Wiker asserts. A few interesting facts were presented here and there, but mostly it was a warning against atheist authors. Not sure what I thought this would be about, but this definitely didn't meet my "expectations".
  • Rating: 4 out of 5 stars
    4/5
    Mr. Wiker looks at Machiavelli, DeCartes, Hobbes, Marx, Darwin, Hitler, Nietsche, Mead, Sanger, and Kinsey and offers, in admittedly 20/20 hindsight, how this books negatively influenced thinking at the time they were published. Then he goes on to explain how these books are still influencing current day ideas, life and values.

    There is no doubt that some of these books, although not necessarily intentionally by the author, have come to be seen as “evil”. Mr. Wiker looks at them individually and as a successive group, one publication sometimes feeding off another in tone and idea. The author makes some good points without preaching. An interesting read, one that made me think and makes me want to delve a little deeper into the books he included.

    2 people found this helpful

  • Rating: 1 out of 5 stars
    1/5
    It's not very often that a book makes me want to go out and commit physical violence on the author, but this book definitely takes the cake. I was seriously pissed off only one chapter in, and the only reason I finished at all is to write a review online and warn people about this sorry excuse for a book.To be fair, the author does a good job of exposing the fallacies in the arguments he writes about, and showing just how ludicrous and/or dangerous the philosophies and theories would be when applied to real life. But his fine use of logic was tainted with bias and his own fallacies.Dr. Wiker equates atheism with immorality, even evil. He doesn't seem to realize that you can be moral and not believe in God. One of the books he names, a book by Freud, is only on his list because it repudiates religion. With almost every book he notes that the author was an atheist or simply rejected Christianity. In fact, Dr. Wiker continuously sneers at anything outside the conservative Christian framework. He has no use for liberal values and even for liberal Christianity -- in fact, he says liberal Christianity is a good tool for dictators because of its "flexibility."I also noticed some glaring misconceptions in Wiker's writing which tie back to his bias against atheists and liberals. For instance, he claims that people who say "I have the right to control over my body" really mean "I want to have an abortion" and people who say "I have the right to privacy" are actually perverts who want to commit nasty sexual practices. That is absolute nonsense. Hasn't he ever heard the catchphrase, "I may not agree with what you say but I will defend to the death your right to say it"? There are plenty of people, myself included, who believe in a woman's right to have an abortion if she chooses, but who have never had an abortion themselves and probably wouldn't even if faced with a crisis pregnancy.This book, I think, could only be liked by people like Wiker himself: that is, conservative evangelical Christians with very narrow minds. I was disgusted by it.

    2 people found this helpful

  • Rating: 1 out of 5 stars
    1/5
    To be short: Benjamin Wiker has no clue what he's writing about.It is hard to take seriously someone who pedantically goes out of his way to state that Descartes wrote his "Meditation on First Philosophy" in French rather than Latin, when, in fact, anyone with half a brain could have checked that Descartes, of course, wrote it in Latin—it was another six years before a French translation was published.It is also hard to take seriously a fool who does not list major religious works at the top of the list of books that caused harm in the world.If you're a rightwing religious nut, this book will be right up your alley.

    1 person found this helpful

  • Rating: 1 out of 5 stars
    1/5
    This is pure conservative/religious right propaganda dressed up as some kind of literary critique. Were this published by a more reputable publisher, I'd say they should be ashamed; as it is, perhaps one should expect no better from an admittedly conservative imprint blissfully free of the ravages of facticity. As for the author, Wiker's bias shows pretty much from page one, and never lets up. Associating atheism (or anything not in line with his seemingly narrow view of 'proper Christian morality'), with a lack of ethics (if not outright evil), Wiker denounces some of the most important, and yes, ethical, books ever written. It's not that Wiker isn't reasonably eloquent or well informed - if he were simply a dullard, as so many of those who quake in fear of Marx, Machiavelli, Darwin and the like tend to be, this book wouldn't be so infuriating. It would just be dumb. Sadly, Wiker seems fairly intelligent generally, just criminally ignorant of his subject matter and fatally biased. Let me take, for example, his view on Machiavelli (I'm sure the others like Marx and Darwin have been argued to death, and Machiavelli is a favorite of mine, with whose work The Prince I am quite familiar). Machiavelli himself Wiker calls "the most profound teacher of evil the world has ever known" (p7), and says of The Prince that it is "a monument of wicked counsel, meant for rulers who have shed all moral and religious scruples and were therefore daring enough to believe that evil—deep, dark, and almost unthinkable evil—is often more effective than good." (p8). If you haven't already gotten a sense for Wiker histrionics, read on; he doesn't ever really dial back on the hand-wringing drama.He does nod to more recent reading of Machiavelli as a sincere and ethical statesman, but tosses such modernity out and chooses (typical of the social movement he seems to represent) to revert to a less informed and older view. The problem is, he is simply wrong. Firstly, Machiavelli favored the Republic above all as the best form of government. However, the reality to which he addressed himself was that of a monarchy. That being the case,The Prince is Machiavelli's way of urging DeMedici to be a strong, effective leader FOR THE SAKE OF THE COMMON GOOD.I cannot emphasize that enough, because Machiavelli makes it clear, over and over again, that the primary, indeed only, concern of the ruler is the good of the state, and thereby its people. Machiavelli was actually deeply ethical, and nowhere does he advise tyranny, greed, violence, or needless cruelty; in fact he is at great pains to condemn them on both political and ethical grounds throughout The Prince. But he understood that a leader, a monarch in particular, if he is to act for the good of the state, must often take actions that a private individual would not want to. And Machiavelli knew full well (a victim of political violence and torture himself) that he did not live in a nation of peaceful, shiny, happy people. He recognized that Individual morality is not a luxury a monarch can afford; if the good of the people requires that the monarch take a personally distasteful action, Machiavelli contended that the ruler had more than his own ethical niceties at stake, and sometimes, rulers have to take lives, imprison dissenters, wage war, even be ruthless. If a ruler shrinks from doing so when the good of the nation is at stake, he's a bad leader. Whether Wiker possesses enough self-reflection to know it or not, I am positive he agrees. After all, we do not think it is ethically right to kill, but when we put a man on the front lines, we sure as heck hope he's ready to set aside his personal ethical concerns and do what he needs to for the common good. If he can't, he's not much good as a soldier (which is why we created the conscientious objector status!) Machiavelli saw the same to be true of the leader of a war-torn country; if he wasn't ready to set aside his personal ethical concerns and do what needed to be done for the common good, he wouldn't be much of a Prince. But Wiker misses this entirely on the way to introducing his own trite and narrowly viewed moralizing. If I've spent too much time on chapter one, I have at least given you a clear idea of how it is that Wiker bludgeons his targets (yes, I believe I can call them such without fear of my own hyperbole), with his 'FOXNews' brand of simplistic and surface morality. I can assure you that he is no less hyperbolic, nor one whit less shallow, in his treatment of any of the intellectual greats at whose assassinations he thankfully fails. Unless you want a laugh (albeit a bitter one, if you love any of the authors Wiker attacks), save your money and a few trees.

    1 person found this helpful

  • Rating: 1 out of 5 stars
    1/5
    I've only read a few of the books mentioned in this one. A couple of them, I did not like at all. However, the author's approach to these books is, in itself, very dangerous and part of the problem with conservatives in this country. The author does not contribute anything intellectually viable or new with his arguments about these "loathsome" books.

    The author thinks that is his Catholicism is a reasonable position to hold and attempts to tie all these books to atheism; hence they are inherently wrong (according to the author). His arguments are fraught with logical fallacies and the only people who would be convinced by them are biased, true-believers like him.

    1 person found this helpful

  • Rating: 1 out of 5 stars
    1/5
    The author's view of literature revolves singularly around how well they agree with his conservative Christian views. If they disagree with them (his views), they are wrong and are "screwing" up the world. It's almost painful to listen to. Example: Descartes' views on skepticism are evil and wrong because they require us to question the world around us and therefore cause undue confusion. I'm assuming the "PhD" suffix Wiker has is not a doctorate of any sciences. It doesn't even offer compelling arguments that ask one to question their own beliefs. Nope, there is no room for argument. I have a feeling if you were to attempt to discuss anything with Wiker on which he disagrees, he would be the type to stick his fingers in his ears and go "lalalala! You're wrong. I'm right. You're wrong. I'm smart. You're stupid."One of the most interesting/annoying aspects of Wiker's arguments is that (by his logic) anything that causes you to think more broadly about the world leads to atheism and atheism is not only devoid of but the antithesis of morality.Finally, he rendered any scholarly aspect of his thesis highly suspect with one glaring oversight tossed out as carelessly as yesterday's garbage; he spoke briefly of the slaves building the pyramids. Slaves had nothing to do with the construction of the pyramids. This is a myth originated by Greeks (long after the construction of the pyramids) and continued by the Old Testament. No sizable population of Jews even lived in Egypt until hundreds of years after the construction of the pyramids. But this disagrees with his Christian views, so he'd probably consider me screwing up the world by trying to educate people on this fact... He also brings up the acceptability of pedophilia in Ancient Greece. Nope. Sorry. Not pedophilia. Pederasty. There's a huge difference. And it wasn't too well accepted throughout Greece and it was VERY rarely penetrative in any way.

    1 person found this helpful

Book preview

10 Books that Screwed Up the World - Benjamin Wiker

INTRODUCTION

Ideas Have Consequences

THERE IS NOTHING SO ABSURD, QUIPPED THE ANCIENT ROMAN philosopher-statesman Cicero, that it can’t be said by a philosopher. Unfortunately, philosophers’ absurdities aren’t limited to classroom sophistry and eccentric speculations. They make their way into print and are thereby released upon the public. They can be, and have been, as dangerous and harmful as deadly diseases. And as with deadly diseases, people can pick up deadly ideas without even noticing. These ideas float, largely undetected, in the intellectual air we breathe.

If we take a good, hard, sober look at the awful effects of such deadly ideas we can come to only one conclusion: there are books that really have screwed up the world, books that we would have been better off without.

This should not come as a shock, except to those who don’t believe that ideas have consequences. Thomas Carlyle, the eminent Scottish essayist and sometime philosopher, was once scolded at a dinner party for endlessly chattering about books: Ideas, Mr. Carlyle, ideas, nothing but ideas! To which he replied, There once was a man called Rousseau who wrote a book containing nothing but ideas. The second edition was bound in the skins of those who laughed at the first. Carlyle was right. Jean-Jacques Rousseau wrote a book that inspired the ruthlessness of the French Revolution (and even more destructive things after that).

Common sense and a little logic tell us that if ideas have consequences, then it follows that bad ideas have bad consequences. And even more obvious, if bad ideas are written down in books, they are far more durable, infecting generation after generation and increasing the world’s wretchedness.

I submit, then, that the world would be a demonstrably better place today if the books we’re about to discuss had never been written. It was possible half a century ago (and even twenty years ago, among the academic elite) to maintain that Marxism was a positive force in history. But since the protective cover has blown off the Soviet Union—and China’s has at least been torn—no one can look at the tens of millions of rotting corpses revealed and conclude anything other than this: if the Communist Manifesto had never been written, a great deal of misery would have been avoided. The same is true of Hitler’s Mein Kampf and the other books on the list, even when the carnage is sometimes of a more subtle and different sort.

What then? Shall we have a book burning? Indeed not! Such a course of action is indefensible, if only for environmental reasons. As I learned long ago, the best cure—the only cure, once the really harmful books have multiplied like viruses through endless editions—is to read them. Know them forward and backward. Seize each one by its malignant heart and expose it to the light of day. That is just what I propose to do in the following pages.

Part I

Preliminary Screw-Ups

CHAPTER ONE

The Prince (1513)

Hence it is necessary to a prince, if he wants to maintain himself, to learn to be able not to be good. . . .

Niccolò Machiavelli (1469-1527)

YOU’VE PROBABLY HEARD THE TERM MACHIAVELLIAN AND ARE AWARE of its unsavory connotations. In the thesaurus, Machiavellian stands with such ignoble adjectives as double-tongued, two-faced, false, hypocritical , cunning, scheming, wily, dishonest, and treacherous. Barely a century after his death, Niccolò Machiavelli gained infamy in Shakespeare’s Richard III as the murdrous Machiavel. Almost five hundred years after he wrote his most famous work, The Prince, his name still smacks of calculated ruthlessness and cool brutality.

Despite recent attempts to portray Machiavelli as merely a sincere and harmless teacher of prudent statesmanship, I shall take the old-fashioned approach and treat him as one of the most profound teachers of evil the world has ever known. His great classic The Prince is a monument of wicked counsel, meant for rulers who had shed all moral and religious scruples and were therefore daring enough to believe that evil—deep, dark, and almost unthinkable evil—is often more effective than good. That is really the power and the poison of The Prince: in it, Machiavelli makes thinkable the darkly unthinkable. When the mind is coaxed into receiving unholy thoughts, unholy deeds soon follow.

Niccolò Machiavelli was born in Florence, Italy, on May 3, 1469, the son of Bernardo di Niccolò di Buoninsegna and his wife, Bartolemea de’ Nelli. It is fair to say that young Machiavelli was born into wicked times. Italy was not a single nation then, but a rat’s nest of intrigue, corruption, and conflict among the five main warring regions: Florence, Venice, Milan, Naples, and the Papal States.

Machiavelli witnessed the greatest hypocrisy in religion, including cardinals and popes who were nothing more than political wolves in shepherds’ clothing. He also knew firsthand the cold cruelty of kings and princes. Suspected of treason, Machiavelli was thrown into jail. To elicit his confession, he was subjected to a punishment called the strappado. His wrists were bound together behind his back and attached to a rope hanging from a ceiling pulley. He was hauled up in the air, dangling painfully from his arms, and suddenly dropped back to the ground, thereby pulling his arms out of their sockets. This delightful process of interrogation was repeated several times.

Machiavelli knew evil. But then, so did many others, in many other times and places. There is no shortage of wickedness in the world, and no shortage of witnesses to it. What makes Machiavelli different is that he looked evil in the face and smiled. That friendly smile and a wink is The Prince.

The Prince is a shocking book—artfully shocking. Machiavelli meant to start a revolution in his readers’ souls, and his only weapons of revolt were his words. He stated boldly what others had dared only to whisper, and then whispered what others had not dared even to think.

Let’s look at Chapter Eighteen for a taste. Should a prince keep faith, honor his promises, work above board, be honest, that kind of thing? Well, Machiavelli muses, everyone understands that it is laudable . . . for a prince to keep faith, and to live with honesty.¹ Everyone praises the honest ruler. Everyone understands that honesty is the best policy. Everyone knows the countless examples in the Bible of honest kings being blessed and dishonest kings cursed, and ancient literature is filled with tributes to virtuous sovereigns.

But is what everyone praises truly wise? Are all good rulers successful rulers? Even more important, are all successful rulers good? Or does goodness, for a ruler, merely mean being successful, so that whatever leads to success—no matter what everyone may say—must be good by definition?

Well, says Machiavelli, let’s see what actually happens in the real world. We see by experience in our times that the princes who have done great things are those who have taken little account of faith. Keeping your word is foolish if it brings you harm. Now, if all men were good, this teaching would not be good; but because they are wicked and do not observe faith with you, you also do not have to observe it with them.

But keeping one’s word is not the only thing that should be cast aside for convenience. The whole idea of being good, Machiavelli assumes, is rather naïve. A successful prince must concentrate not on being good, but on appearing to be good. As we all know, appearances can be deceiving, and for a prince deception is a good thing, an art to be perfected. A prince must therefore be a great pretender and dissembler.

And so, one might ask, should a ruler be merciful, faithful, humane, honest, and religious? Not at all! It is not necessary for a prince to have all the above-mentioned qualities, but it is indeed necessary to appear to have them. Nay, I dare say this, that by having them and always observing them, they are harmful; and by appearing to have them they are useful. So it is much better, more wise, to appear merciful, faithful, humane, honest, and religious, but if you need to be cruel, faithless, inhumane, dishonest, and sacrilegious, well, then, necessity is the mother of invention, and you should invent devious ways to do whatever evil is necessary while appearing to be good.

Let me offer two examples of Machiavelli’s advice in action, the first taken from The Prince, and the other from our own day. A more wicked man than Cesare Borgia—whom Machiavelli knew personally—could hardly be imagined. He had been named a cardinal in the Catholic Church, but resigned so he could pursue political glory (and did so in the most ruthless way). Borgia was a man without conscience. He had no anxiety whatsoever about inflicting great cruelties to secure and maintain power. Of course, this gave him a bad reputation with his conquered subjects, creating the kind of bitterness that soon leads to rebellion. In Chapter Seven Machiavelli sets before his reader an interesting practical lesson on Borgia’s method of dealing with this problem.

One of the areas Borgia snatched up was Romagna, which Machiavelli notes was a province . . . quite full of robberies, quarrels, and every other kind of insolence. Of course, Borgia wanted to reduce it to peace and obedience, because it is hard to rule the unruly. But if he brought them into line himself, the people would hate him, and hatred breeds rebellion.

What did Borgia do? He sent in a henchman, Remirro de Orco, a cruel and ready man, to whom he gave the fullest power. Remirro did the dirty work, but of course this got him dirty. The people hated Remirro for his attempts to crush their rebellious and lawless spirit and make them obedient subjects. But as Remirro was obviously working as Borgia’s lieutenant, Borgia would be hated too.

But Borgia was an inventive man. He knew that he needed to fool the people into believing that if any cruelty had been committed, this had not come from him but from the harsh nature of his minister. And so, Borgia had Remirro placed one morning in the piazza at Cesena [cut] in two pieces, with a piece of wood and a bloody knife beside him. The ferocity of this spectacle left the people at once satisfied and stupefied.

Satisfied and stupefied. The angry people of Romagna were happy to see the agent of Borgia’s cruelty suddenly appear one sunny morning hewn in half in the town square. Borgia himself had satisfied their desire for revenge! But at the same time they were numbed into obedience by a completely unexpected spectacle of ingenious brutality.

The reader’s imagination gropes after an image of the horror. A man sawed in half. Lengthwise or crosswise? A bloody knife. Simply lying beside the body? Thrust into the block of wood? Could a mere knife hack a man in two? And why a block of wood? A butcher’s block?

One thing is certain: Machiavelli does not blame Borgia for his ingenious cruelty, but praises him. He very cleverly appeared to be humane by hiding inhumanity, to be merciful by concealing mercilessness. I would not know how to reproach him, Machiavelli says of Borgia’s lifelong career of similar dastardly actions. On the contrary, it seems to me he should be put forward, as I have done, to be imitated by all those who have risen to empire through fortune.

One does not always need to be as viciously picturesque as Borgia to follow Machiavelli’s advice. As anyone who watches our own political scene well knows, we quite often witness the less bloody (but no less well calculated) spectacle of an underling to a president or congressman immolating himself publicly to take the heat off his boss. Behind the elaborately staged appearances, the underling—like poor Remirro, who was merely carrying out the chief’s orders—is being sacrificed to satisfy and stupefy the electorate.

This brings us to our second example of Machiavellianism in action. A prince should thus take care, notes Machiavelli, returning to his list of virtues, that nothing escape his mouth that is not full of the above-mentioned five qualities so that he should appear all mercy, all faith, all honesty, all humanity, all religion. And nothing is more necessary to appear to have than this last quality. It is most important that rulers—and even more so, would-be rulers—appear to be religious. Everyone sees how you appear, but few touch what you are, and appearing to be religious assures those who see you that, because you appear to believe in God, you can be trusted to have all the other virtues. In politics, some things never change.

But duplicity isn’t the only patrimony of Machiavelli’s The Prince. The damage is much deeper than that. The kind of advice Machiavelli offers in The Prince is only possible for someone to give (and to take) who has no fear of hell, who has discarded the notion of the human soul living on after death as a foolish fiction, who believes that since there is no God then we are free to be wicked if it serves our purposes. That is not to say that Machiavelli ever advises being evil merely for its own sake. He does something far more destructive: evil is offered under the excusing pretext that it is beneficial. Machiavelli convinces the reader that great evils, unspeakable crimes, foul deeds are not only excusable but praiseworthy if they are done in the service of some good. Since this advice occurs in the context of atheism, then there are no limits on the kind of evil one can do if he thinks he is somehow benefiting humanity. It should not surprise us that The Prince was a favorite book of the atheist V. I. Lenin for whom the glorious end of communism justified any brutality of means.

Since this will remain an important connection in most of the subsequent books we cover, we must dwell on the deep connections between atheism and the kind of ruthless advice Machiavelli gives. It is a fundamental principle of Christianity—the religion that defined the culture into which Machiavelli was born, and the religion he rejected—that it is never permissible to do evil in the service of good. You can’t lie about your credentials to get elected to office. You can’t kill an innocent baby to advance your career. You can’t start a war to boost the economy or your approval ratings. You can’t resort to cannibalism to solve the hunger problem. You can’t commit adultery to get a job promotion.

The source of this prohibition is obviously the fact that some actions are intrinsically evil. No matter the circumstances or the alleged or even actual benefits, some acts cannot be committed. Unfortunately, this is not the way we generally think today. When you suggest to someone that there are some intrinsically evil actions—so foul, so unholy, that even to think of doing them leaves a black mark on the soul—the usual response is a smirk, followed by a wildly contrived example that is supposed to force you into choosing some horribly evil deed to avoid even more horrible consequences. What if a terrorist gives you a choice: either shoot and skin your grandmother or we’ll blow up New York. The hidden assumption of the smirker is that, of course, the moral thing to do is save New York by shooting and skinning your grandmother, and that goes to show that there are no moral absolutes.

Of course, smirkers are rarely logical. If there really are no intrinsically evil actions, then it is quite fine to have New York blown up in order to save your grandmother. But the real point, for our purposes, is that the smirker is using precisely the mode of reasoning that Machiavelli uses in The Prince. Machiavelli is the original ends-justify-the-means philosopher. No act is so evil that some necessity or benefit cannot mitigate it.

But how is this all linked to atheism? Again, we must use the religion that historically defines the beliefs Machiavelli rejected. For the Christian, no earthly necessity or benefit can be weighed against eternity. Committing an intrinsically evil act immediately separates us from the eternal good of heaven, whatever the benefit that might accrue to us in the here and now. No good we experience now can possibly outweigh having to suffer eternally in hell. Furthermore, as God is all-powerful, then no seeming necessity or benefit of an evil action in this life can really be necessary or beneficial to anyone from the perspective of eternity. To believe otherwise is only a temptation; in fact, the temptation.

As we shall see in subsequent chapters, yielding to the temptation to do evil in the service of good will be the source of unprecedented carnage in the twentieth century, so horrifying that to those who lived through it, it seemed hell had come to earth (even though it was largely perpetrated by people who had discarded the notion of hell). The lesson learned—or that should have been learned—by such epic destruction is this: once we allow ourselves to do evil so that some perceived good may follow, we allow ever greater evils for the sake of ever more questionable goods, until we consent to the greatest evils for the sake of mere trifles.

Remove God, and soon there is no limit on evil at all, and no good is too trivial an excuse. Consider a report from the British newspaper The Observer three years ago: in the Ukraine, suffering so long under the atheist Soviet foot, pregnant women were being paid about $180 for their fetuses, which the abortion clinics turned around and sold for about $9,000. Why? The tissue was being used for beauty treatments. Pregnant women were and still are being paid to kill their babies so aging Russian women can rejuvenate their skin with fetal cosmetics.

But to return to Machiavelli, our point is this: to embrace the notion that it is not only permissible but also laudable to do evil so that good might come, one must reject God, the soul, and the afterlife. That is just what Machiavelli did, and that is the ultimate effect of his counsel.

Here it might be objected that Machiavelli appeared to be religious in his writings, casting out pious phrases here and there, and speaking with a certain respect (however strained and peculiar) about things religious. So, it is argued, because he appears to be religious, then we must give him the benefit of the doubt.

It is difficult for me to deal with this all too common objection because it shows a frightening woodenness to the obvious (let alone to the subtle) in Machiavelli. Did he not just tell us how important it is to appear to be religious? Who informed us of the necessity, if one is to be a great prince, of being a great pretender and dissembler? Who contrives to be a greater prince—the temporal ruler of a piece of land, or the philosopher who seeks to inform all future princes, to found an entirely new philosophy?

And so we repeat: Machiavelli could not give advice to princes that would mean abandoning any notion of God, the immortal soul, and the afterlife if he himself had not already abandoned all three. That is why he can call evil good, and good evil.

This is seen clearly in the famous Chapter Fifteen. Machiavelli tells the reader quite matter-of-factly that he is departing from the way all others have spoken about good and evil. He will deal with the real world, with how people act in real republics and principalities. While many have imagined republics and principalities that have never been seen or known to exist in truth, we realists shouldn’t take our sights from mere fantasy. We cannot guide our lives by what is good (or at

Enjoying the preview?
Page 1 of 1