Sunteți pe pagina 1din 43

CONTENTS

Copyright © 1970, 1974 by Edmund Leaeh


Al! rights reserved
Original!y published in 1970
Revised edition published in 1974 in a hardbound and
paperbound edition by The Viking Press, Ine.,
625 Madison Avenue, New York, N.Y. 10022
SBN 670-22515-0 (hardbound)
670-01980-1 (paperbound) Biographical Note ix
Library of Congress eatalog eard number: 74-1122
Printed in U.S.A. /// The Man Himself 1
ii
vii
ivv
vi Oysters, Smoked Salmon, and Stilton
iii Cheese 15
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

Hill and Wang, Ine., and ]onathan Cape Ltd.: From The Human Animal and His Symbols 35
The Elements of Semiology by Roland Barthes.
Translated by Dr. Annette Lavers' and Dr. Colin The Structure of Myth 57
Smith. Translation © 1967 by ]onathan Cape Ltd.
Reprinted by permission. Words and Things 93
The University of Chicago Press and GeorgeWei- The Elementary Structures of Kinship 105
denfeld & Nicolson Ltd.: From The Savage Mjnd by
Claude Lévi-Sh'auss. English translation © 1966 Machines for the Suppression of Time 125
by George Weidenfeld & Nieolson Ltd. Al! rights
reserved. Reprinted by permission. Short Bibliography 137
lndex 143
·..,. ""'T r

",t.,:

•••
The Human Animal and His Symbols

111 Lévi-Strauss' central intellectual puzzle is one


to which European philosophers have returned
over and over again; indeed, if we accept Lévi-
Strauss' own view of the matter it is a problem
which puzzle s all mankind, everywhere, always.
Quite simply: What is man? Man is an animal,
a member of the species Horno sapiens, closely
related to the great apes and more distantly to
all other living species past and presento But
man, we assert, is ahuman being, and in saying
that we evidently mean that he is, in some way,
other than "just an animal." But in what way
is he other? The concept of humanity as distinct
from animality does not readily translate into
exotic languages, but it is Lévi-Strauss' thesis
that a distinction of this sort-corresponding to
the opposition culture/nature-is always latent
in men's customary attitudes and behaviors
CLAUDE LÉVI-STRAUSS 36 The Human Animal and His Symbols 37
\

even when it is not explicitly formulated in words. The . '" ; infancy to be self-centered and individualistic, to fear
human Ego is never by himself; there is no ''1'' that is • the impurity of foreign things-a doctrine which we
not part of a "We,"l and indeed every ''1'' is a member of embody in the formula "Hell is the others" (1'enfer,
many "We"s. In one sense these we-groups stretch out c'est les autres)-but primitive myth has the opposite
to infinity in all directions to embrace everybody and moral implication, "Hell is ourselves" (l' enfer, e' est
,1 nous-meme)." "In a century when man is bent on the
everything. "Man is not alone in the universe, any more
. ~ than the individual is alone in the group, or any one destruction of innumerable forms of life," it is neces-
society alone among other societies" (Tristes Tropiques, sary to insist, as in the myths, "that a properly ap-
p. 398), but in practice we cut up the continua. My pointed humanism cannot begin of its own accord but
.\' particular "we," the people of my family, my com- must place the world before lHe, life before man, and
munity, my tribe, my class-these are altogether special, the respect of others before self-interest." (Mytholo-
they are superior, they are civilized, cultured; the others giques IIl, p. 422) But, the puzzle remains, what is a
/d
are just savages, like wild beasts. human being? Where does culture divide off from
~.j
~t-,~ Lévi-Strauss' central preoccupation is to explore the nature?
'~'l
...J dialectical process by which this apotheosis of ourselves Lévi-Strauss himself takes his cue from Rousseau,
as human and godlike and other than animal is formed though he might equally well have followed Vico or
and re-formed and bent back upon itself. Adam and Hobbes or Aristotle or a dozen others. It is language
Eve were created as ignorant savages in Paradise in a which makes man different: "Qui dit homme, dit lan-
world in which animals talked and were helpmeets to gage, et qui dit langage dit société." (Tristes Tropiques,
man; it was through sin that they gained knowledge p. 421) But the emergence of language which accom-
and became human, and different, and superior to the panies the shift from animality to humanity, from
animals. But are we really "superior"? God made man nature to culture, is also a shift from affectivity to a
in his own image, but are we so sure that in achieving state of reasoning: "The first speech was all in poetry;
humanity (culture) we did not separate ourselves from reasoning was thought of only long afterwards."3
God? This is the note on which Lévi-Strauss ends Tristes Rousseau's thesis, as elaborated by Lévi-Strauss, is
Tropiques, the book which first brought him interna- that man can become self-conscious-aware of himself
tional renown outside the narrow world of professional as a member of a we-group-only when he becomes
anthropology-to discover the nature of man we must capable of employing metaphor as an instrument of
find our way back to an understanding of how man is contrast and comparison:
related to nature-and he comes back to the same
theme in the closing paragraph of Mythologiques IlI. e The reader is expected to recognize that ¡'enfer c'est les
We (Europeans), he comments, have been taught from autres is a quotation from Jean-Paul Sartre's play Huis dos
(Paris, 1944).
1 Tristes Tropiques (Paris, 1955), p. 448: "Le moi n'a pas de Jean-Jacques Rousseau,
:1 "Essai sur l'origine des langues"
place entre un nous et un rien." (Geneva, 1783).
CLAUDE LÉVI-STRAUSS 38 The Human Animal and His Symbols 39

It is only because man originally felt himself identi- ,do this not so much because of any instinct but because
cal to all those like him (among which, as Rousseau ".~ the architecture of the human mouth and throat and its
explicitly says, we must incIude animals) that ,he .associated musculature makes this the natural way to
carne to acquire the capacity to distinguish himself' go about it.Lévi-Strauss asks us to believe that category
as he distinguishes them, i.e. to use the diversity of formation in human beings follows similar universal
species as conceptual support for social differentia- "natural" paths. It is not that it must always happen
tion. (Totemism, p. 101)
the same way everywhere but that the human brain is
so constructed that it is predisposed to develop cate-
,
Rousseau's insight can be held to be "true" only in a gories of a particular kind in a particular way.4
strictly poetic sense, for the thought processes of proto- All animals have a certain limited capacity to make
lr
!\ man are even less accessible to us than those of apes category distinctions. Any mammal or bird can, under
ff1 and monkeys. But the phylogenetic form of the argu- appropriate conditions, recognize other members of its
t~
ment is mixed up with Lévi-Strauss' search for human own species and distinguish males from females; some
lii
:~
universals. Verbal categories provide the mechanism can further recognize a category of predator enemies.
through which universal structural characteristics of Human beings, in the process of learning to talk, extend
human brains are transformed into universal structural this category-forming capacity to a degree that has no
.characteristics of human culture. But if these universals para11el among other creatures, but nevertheless, at its
exist, they must, at some rather deep level, be consid- very roots, before the individual's language capacity
ered innate. In that case, we must suppose that they has become elaborated, category formation must be
are patterns which, in the course of human evolution, animal-like rather than human-like. At this basic level
have become internalized into the human psyche along the individual (whether animal or human) is con cerned
with the specialized development of those parts of the only with very simple problems: the distinction between
human brain which are directly concerned with speech own species and other, dominance and submission,
formation through the larynx and mouth and with sexual availability or lack of availability, what is edible
speech reception through the ear. And why not? After and what is not. In a natural environment distinctions
all, although the human infant is not born with any of this sort are a11 that are necessary for individual
innate language, it is born with an innate capacity to survival, but they are not sufficient within ahuman
learn both how to make meaningful utterances and how environment. For human (as distinct from animal) sur-
to decode the meaningful utterances of others. vival every member of society must learn to distinguish
Not only that but, if Jakobson's argument is correct,
all human children will learn to master the basic ele- 4It should be stressed, however, that unlike Piaget Lévi-
ments of their phonemic inventory by making the same, Strauss does not speculate about the ontogenetic or philo-
or very nearly the same, initial series of basic dis- genetic development of category systems; he simply relies
on this style of argument to explain the otherwise surpris-
criminations-consonant/vowel, nasal consonant/ oral ing fact that he is able to discover strikingly similar
stop, grave/ acute, compact/ diffuse. They presumably "structures" in widely different cultural contexts.
The Human Animal and His Symbols 41
CLAUDE LÉV1-STRAUSS 4°
his fe110w men according to their mutual social status., ..that elements of "totemic" behavior occur even in
But the simplest w,ay to do this is to apply transforma: :sophisticated cultures, but the earlier writers interpreted
tions of the animal-Ievel categories to the social classifi: 'thesedetails as archaic residues which had somehow
cation of human beings. This is the key point in: . survived into our own day from the remo te past. In the
Lévi-Strauss' structuralist approach to the classic an- more general primitive case "totemism" was thought to
thropological theme of totemism. pose a basic problem of rationality.
It is a fact of empirical observation that human Why should sane human beings indulge in the "super-
beings everywhere adopt ritual attitudes toward the stitious worship" of animals and plants? How can
animals apd plants in their vicinity. Consider, for ex- men come to imagine that they are descended from
ample, the separate, and often bizarre, rules which kangaroos, or wallabies, or white cockatoos? A great
govern the behavior of Englishmen toward the creatures variety of possible answers to such guestions were pro-
which they classify as (1) wild animals, (2) Eoxes, (3) posed. A. Van Gennep, in L'Etat actuel du probleme
game, (4) farm animals, (5) pets, (6) vermin. Notice totémique (1920), was able to distinguish forty-one
further that if we take the seguence oE words (la) different "theories of totemism," and more have accumu-
strangers, (2a) enemies, (3a) friends, (4a) neighbors, lated since then. Broadly speaking they fa11 into two
(sa) companions, (6a) criminals, the two sets of terms types: (1) universalist explanations implying that
are in some degree homologous. By a metaphorical totemic beliefs and practices indicate a "childish" men-
usage the categories oE animals could be (and some- tality which had once been characteristic of a11 man-
times are) used as eguivalents for the categories of kind; (2) particularist explanations resting on the
human beings. One oE Lévi-Strauss' major contributions functionalist proposition that any totemic system will
to our understanding has been to show how very wide- serve to attach emotional interest to animal and plant
spread is this kind of socialization of animal categories. species which are of economic value to the particular
The facts themselves are we11 known, but, in Lévi- human society concerned and will thereby tend to pre-
Strauss' view they have been misunderstood. serve these species from total destruction by human
The conventions by which primitive peoples use depredation.
species of plants and animals as symbols for categories After the publication of A. Goldenweiser's "Totemism,
of men are not rea11y any more eccentric than our own, an Analytical Study" (1910) theories of the first kind
but, in a technologically restricted environment, they were barely tenable, and thereafter down to 1962 the
be come much more noticeable, and to scholars of Sir more worth-while contributions to the subject were
J ames Frazer's generation they seemed altogether ex-
concerned with particular ethnographies-Australia,
traordinary-so much so that any social eguivalence Tikopia, Tallensi-rather than with universal truth.
But Radcliffe-Brown's "The Sociological Theory of To-
between human beings and other natural species came
to be regarded as a kind of cult (totemism), a proto- temism" (1929) is a special case because it attempts to
religion appropriate only to people at a very early stage generalize the functionalist position; "totemism" is here
treated as a near universal and is seen as the ritual
of development. It was recognized right Erom the start
e L A U DEL É VI - S T H A U S s I 42 The Human Animal and His Symbols 1 43
, l' "', ..-
expression of interdependence between social order and. , unconscious "human mind"; the empirical evidence is
the natural environment. In a later essay, "The Gom.i, merely an example of what is possible. This same pref-
1 parative Method in Social Anthropology" (1951), Rad.•
cliffe-Brown carried this universalist thesis a good deal
•erence for the generalized abstraction as compared with
the empirical fact occurs again and again throughout
further, drawing special attention to the classificatory." ·Lévi-Strauss' writings. Mind you, that is not how Lévi-
nature of totemic systems. Some features of this latter Strauss himseIf sees the situation. He conceives of the
paper are so markedly "structuralist" in style that it "human mind" as having objective existence; it is an
provided the trigger for Lévi-Strauss' own contribution,' ·attribute of human brains. We can ascertain attributes
Le Totémisme aujourd'hui (1962). of this human mind by investigating and comparing its
., Lévi-Strauss takes the view that the anthropologists cultural products. The study of "empirical phenomena"
}t
\ who have tried to isolate "totemism" as a phenomenon is thus an essential part of the process of discovery, but
);;1
sui generis have deluded themselves; considered as a it is onl y a means to an end.G

religious system "totemism" is an anthropological But let us go back to Rousseau's vision of man as a
mirage; even so, the subject deserves our close atten- talking animal. Until a few years ago it was customary
tion because totemic beliefs and practices exemplify a for anthropologists to draw a very sharp distinction
universal characteristic of human thought. between culture, which was conceived of as exclusively
Lévi-Strauss' account does not add anything of sig- human, and nature, which was common to a11animals,
nificance to our understanding of Australian totemism induding mano This distinction, according to Leslie
but his reappraisal of Radcliffe-Brown's arguments White, "is one of kind not of degree. And the gap be-
makes it much easier to understand how the seemingly tween the two types is of the greatest importance ....
bizarre thought categories of the Australian Aborigines Man uses symbols; no other creature does. An organism
are related to category systems with which we are more has the ability to symbol or it does not, there are no
familiar. The crux of his argument is that totemic intermediate stages."7 In his earlier writings, though
systems always embody metaphoric systems of the sort less emphaticalIy in his later ones, Lévi-Strauss reiter-
indicated above (pages 39-41 )." IncidentalIy it was with ates this view. The special marker of symbolic thought is
reference oto "totemism" that Lévi-Strauss came up with the existence of spoken language in which words stand
his Own summary of what constitutes the essence of for (signify) things "out there" which are signified.
structuralist method, which I have quoted already (see
page 20). Note in particular his seeming contempt for GIt is the constant refrain of Lévi-Strauss and his close
the "empirical phenomenon." The "general object of disciples that all his Anglo-Saxon critics, the present author
analysis" is conceived as a kind of algebraic matrix of included, are erude empiricists. Empiricism here seems to
mean the doctrine that truth must be verifiable by reference
possible permutations and combinations located in the to observable facts; it stands opposed to "rationalism,"
which reaches to a deeper form of truth by means of
operations of the intellect.
'This metaphoric formatio:l is discussed in greater detail 7 Leslie White, The Science of CultuTe (New York, 1949),
below, pages 46-50.
p. 25·
e L A U DEL É v 1- S T R AU S s 44 The Human Animal and His Symbols I 45
i
Signs must be distinguished from triggers. Animals oí •. and the forbidden. Furthermore, in society as it actually
all kinds respond mechanically to appropriate signals; '. : exists individuals are social persons who are "in rela-
this process does not entail "symbolic thought."· In . tion" to one another-e.g., as father to son or as em-
j order to be able to operate with symbols it is necessary ployer to employee. These individuals communicate with
first of all to be able to distinguish between the sign one another by "exchange"; they exchange words; they
and the thing it signifies and then to be able to recog- exchange gifts. These words and gifts communicate
nize that there is a relation between the sign and the information because they are signs, not because they
thing signified. This is the cardinal characteristic which are things in themselves. When an employer pays out
distinguishes human thought fram animal response-,. wages to an employee, the action signifies the relative
.\ the ability to distinguish A from B while at the same status of the parties to the transaction. But, according
I'.
(! time recognizing that A and B are somehow interde- to Lévi-Strauss (if 1 understand him correctly), the
pendent. ultimate basic symbolic exchange which provides the
This distinction can be put in another way. When an model for a11 the others is sexual. The incest taboo
individual acts as an individual, operating upon the (which Lévi-Strauss erroneously claims to be "uni-
world outside himself-e.g., if he uses a spade to dig versal") implies a capacity to distinguish between
a hole in the ground-he is not concerned with symboli- women who are permitted and women who are for-
zation; but the moment some other individual comes bidden and thus generates a distinction between women
onto the scene every action, however trivial, serves to of the category wife and women of the category sister.
communicate information about the actor to the ob- The basis of human exchange, and hence the basis of
server-the observed details are interpreted as signs, symbolic thought and the beginning of culture, lies in
because observer and actor are in relation. From this the uniquely human phenomenon that aman is able to
~ point of view the animals in any human environment establish relationship with another man by means of
serve as things with which to think (bonnes a penser). an exchange of women.8
When Lévi-Strauss poses for himself the seemingly But let me take up once more my earlier point that
quite unanswerable puzzle of how this faculty for sym- Lévi-Strauss seems to be more interested in an algebra
bolic interpretation carne into being, he finds his answer of possibilities than in the empirical facts. His justifi-
in an adaptation of ideas borrowed from Durkheim and cation is this: in actual social life individuals com-
his immediate pupils. Certain binary concepts are part municate with one another a11 the time by elaborate
of man's nature-e.g., men and women are alike in combinations of signs-by words, by the clothes they
one sense yet opposite and interdependent in another; wear, by the food they eat, by the way they stand, by
the right hand and the left hand are, likewise, equal the way they arrange the furniture of a room, and so on.
and opposite, yet related. In society as it actually exists In any particular case there wi11 be a certain discover-
we find that such natural pairs are invariably loaded able consistency between behaviors at these different
with cultural significance-they are made into the prato-
8I shall come back to this again. See below, Chapter VI,
type symbols of the good and the bad, the permitted pages 105 ff·
CLAUDE LÉVI-STRAUSS 46 The Hll1nan Animal and His Symbols 47
..
levels; e.g., in England, members of the upper micjdle : .; ábove, and the information-theory
.
distinction of code
class living in Kensington will adopt, for each of the.. ..and message. If we, in fact, think of a spoken language
"codes" l have mentioned, quite a different style from ,; ;.as acode, then it is a particular kind of code-namely,
members of, say, the working class in Leeds. But any . . acode made up of sound elements. But there are many
particular empirical case is only one alternative from a other kinds of possible codeso As I suggested just now,
whole set of possibilities, and, according to Lévi-Strauss we use clothes as acode, or kinds of food, or gestures,
and his folIowers, we shall gain additional insight into or postures, and so on. Each such code is "a language"
the empirical cases that we have observed by consider- (in de Saussure's sense), and the sum of all such codes
ing their relationship to the possible cases that we have (Le., the culture of the individual actor) is also "a
not observed. language."
At this point it is necessary to make something of a Now, the verbal boxes which l have used in this
digression. Lévi-Strauss' ideas about how human beings argument-e.g., "sound elements," "clothes," "kinds of
are able to communicate through symbols are a develop- food," etc.-Iump things together because they are
ment from arguments originalIy developed by specialists associated in our minds as somehow similar in func-
in structural linguistics and semiology (the theory of tion or "meaning," whereas when l make a verbal utter-
signs). But the latter have used a very varied and con- ance and transmit a message-"the cat sat on the mat"
fusing terminology and it may help if l try to sort out -the elements are brought together in a chain as a re-
some of the equivalents. sult of the rules of the language and not because they
The first basic distinction is that of de Saussure be- are in any way similar in themselves. This is what I
tween language (langue) and speech (paTOle). "The D mean when I refer later to "syntagmatic chains" -they
English language" denotes a total system of words, are chains formed by the application of rules of
conventions, and usages; from the point of view of any syntax.
particular individual speaker it is a "given"; it is not In the same way, we need to distinguish the mental
something he creates for himself; the parts of the association which tells us that roast turkey and boiled
language are available for use, but they do not have to chicken are both "kinds of food" (and therefore parts
be used. But when 1, as an individual, make an utter- of one language) from the rules of particular whole
ance I use "speech"; I select from the total system of languages (cultures) which may specify, for example,
"the language" certain words and grammatical con ven- that in England roast beef should be eaten with York-
tions and tones and accents, and by placing these in a shire pudding or, to be more complex, that a menu of
particular oTdeT I am able to transmit information by roast turkey followed by flaming plum pudding and
my utterance. mince pies probably indicates that it is December 25·
Thcre is a close but not exact equivalence between Many readers are likely to find this use of the word
the distinction of language and speech, as specified "language" to refer to nonverbal forms of communica-
v F. de Saussure, COU1'S de linguistique générale (Paris,
tion somewhat confusing, and matters are not made
1916). any easier by the fact that Roland Barthes, who in
) -)JL The Human Animal and His Symbols 49
CLAUDE LÉVI-STRAUSS 48 1

Syntagm and System11


Elements of Semiology (1968) presents the general. ~I" A B
structuralist argument with relative clarity, uses yet' Syntagm
System [Parts of speech:
another terminology. On page 49 1 give a modified :'1, nouns, verbs, etc.] [Sentence.]
version 01' a table which Barthes employs to explain Juxtaposition in
Garment Set of pieces, parts,
the relationship between metaphoric (paradigmatic) "system" or details which the same type of
and metonymic (syntagmatic) uses 01' nonverbal signs. [language, cannot be worn at dress of different
In the original Barthes uses the term "system" in twa cade] the same time on the elemen ts: skirt,
different senses-first, to denote what 1 have re1'erred same part of the blouse, jacket.
body, and whose
to above as "a language" and, second, to denote the variation corre-
"parts 01' speech" 01' such a language-i.e., the sets of sponds to a change
objects which correspond to the sets 01' words which, in the meaning of
in a verbal language, we would distinguish as nouns, the clothing: toque,
verbs, adjectives, etc. (I have modified his diagram by bonnet, hood, etc.
writing the first 01'these usages "system" and the second Faod Set of foodstuffs Real sequences of
"system" which have affinities dishes chosen
system). The term "syntagm," as applied to an assem-
[language, or differences, within during a meal,
blage 01'nonverbal signs, here corresponds to "sentence" which one chooses the menu."
cade]
in a verbal language. a dish in view of a
The distinction between columns A and B in this certain meaning:
diagram is very important for any understanding of entree, roast,
Lévi-Strauss' writings, but he himself does not use this sweet, etc. "
terminology. Where Barthes opposes "system" and Furniture Set of "stylistic" Juxtaposition of
"syntagm," the corresponding contrasts in Lévi-Strauss "system" varieties of a single different pieces of
[language, piece of furniture: furniture in the
are "metaphor" and "metonymy" or sometimes "paradig- bed, etc. same space: bed,
cade] i¡
matic series" and "syntagmatic chain" (see, for example, wardrobe, table, l;f


page 101). Although the jargon is exasperating, the prin- etc.
cipIes are simple. As J akobson puts it, metaphor (sys-
tem, paradigm) relies on the recognition 01' similarity,
Architecture
"system"
Variations in style of
a single element in
Sequence of the
details at the level l
+'1

[language a building: types of the whole


and metonymy (syntagm) on the recognition 01' con- r'
cade] of roof, balcony, building.
tiguity.]O
hall, etc.
Lévi-Strauss maintains that in the analysis 01' myth
and 01' primitive thought generally, we need to dis-
11 From Roland Barthes, Elements of Semiology (New York, I
]968), p. 63. The words in square brackets have been added. }:

tinguish between these two poles. For example, if we * A restaurant menu actualizes both planes: a horizontal
reading of the entrees, for instance, corresponds to the
system; a vertical reading of the menu corresponds to the
10R. Jakobson and M. Halle, Fundamentals of Language syntagm.
(New York, 1956), p. 81.
"
CLAUDE LÉVI-STllAUSS 5° The Human Animal and His Symbols 51

imagine another world peopled by supernatural'b~ing;.' '.~.• , , " ..


then we can represent this other world in any numbel" ,.ph9nc/metonym1c d1stmctlOn, and the fact that Frazer
of ways: as a society of birds, or of fishes, or of wild •.• ' and Lévi-Strauss should agree that this kind of dis-
animals, or even 01'beings "like" men, and in each 'case' crimination is highly relevant for an undersanding of
we shall be using metaphor. That is one kind of symboll_"prímitive thought" seems very significant. ¡~
zation. But there is also another kind in which we r~l - But how does a11this tie in with Lévi-Strauss' general
¡,\
on the fact that our audience, being aware of how ~ ' attitude to the process of symbolizatíon? f', \
partícular syntagm (sentence) is formed out of the We11, first of a11 ít needs to be appreciated that
elements of the "system" (language, code), ís able to these two dimensions-the metaphoric-paradigmatic- .\
.
fL:,..

~ecognize the whole by being shown only a parto Thís harmoníc-símilaríty axis on the one hand, and the meto- ¡I
t·,j

1S metonymy. For example, when we use the formula nymíc-syntagmatíc-melodíc-contagíous axís on the other
l· \
"The Crown stand s for Sovereignty" we are relying on -:correspon~ to, the logical fra.mework within which
¡ \
t~e fact that a crown is uniquely associated wíth a par- Lev1-Strauss v~nous structu.ral tnangles are constructed.
tlcular syntagmatic chaín of items 01' clothíng which For example, 1.f v:e take F1g~re 3. (page 27), the cul- ( l'
l. \.

together form the uníform of a particular officeholder ture/nature aX1SIS metaphonc whlle the normal/ trans- L... "
,
the King, so that, even when removed from this con: formed axís is metonymic. But it ís more immedíately
text of proper use, it can still be used as a signífier fol' relevant in, the present co~text that, for Léví-Strauss,
t~e v:hole co~plex, This metaphor/metonymy opposí- thlS s,ame f,ramew~rk provldes the clue .for our u~de~-
tlOn 1Snot an elther/or distinction; there is always some s~andm? oí' totem1sm and m~th. Cons1dered as md1-
element of both kinds of association in any communí- v1dual ltems of culture totem1C ntuals or myths are
cative discourse but there can be marked differimces of syntagmatic-they consist of a sequence of details
emphasis, As 1 have said, "The Crown stands for linked together in a chain; animals and rrien are ap-
Sovereígnty" is primarily metonymic; in contrast; the parently interchangeable, culture and nature are con-
concept of a "queen bee" is metaphoric. fused. But if we take a whole set of such rituals or
All this link s up with a much earlier style of anthro- myths and superimpose one upon another, then a para-
pological analysis. Frazer started his classic stud of digmatíc-metaphoríc pattern emerges; it becomes ap-
prímítíve magicl~ wíth the thesís that magícal beiíefs pa~ent that the variatíons of what happens ~o, the
depend on two types of (erroneous) mental association: a~lmals are algebrmc transformatlOns of the vanatlOns
homeopathi.c magic, depending on a law of similarity; of what h~ppens to the men.
and contaglOus magic, depending on a law of contact. Alternanvely we can operate the other way round.
Frazer's homeopathic/ contagious distinction is practi- If we start wíth a particular sequence of customary
cally identical to the J akobson-Léví-Strauss meta- behavior we should
case of ordered regardamong
relations it as aa set
syntagm, a special
of cultural odd-
ments which, ín itself, is just a residue of history. If
1" James G. Frazer, The Galden Baugh (London; abridged we take such a special case and consider the arrange-
edition, 1922), p. 12,
ments between íts component parts algebraically we can
CLAUDE LÉVI-STRAUSS
~. The Human Animal and His Symbols \ 53
52
l;Ús endeavor sometimes leads him to make sta te-
arrive at the total system, a theme and variations-a
ments which suggest that the mind has an autonomy of
set of paradigms (metaphors) of which our special casé l',\
is just one example. This will bring to our attention all its O\yn which operates independently of any. human
individual. For example, "Nous ne prétendons done pas \-1
sorts of other possible variations, and we can then take . \\.
montrer eomment les hommes pensent dans les mythes
another look at our ethnographic data to see if these i\ \

mais comment les mythes se pensent dan s les hommes,


other variations actually occur. If they do, then we
et ii leur insu." (Mythologiques 1, p. 20) Native speakers
shall have confirmed that our algebra corresponds to
of French disagree as to just what this is in tended to
some deep-rooted organizational principIe in hurnan'
mean; and there are two published English versions
brains everywhere.
of this passage. One reads, "We are not, therefore,
This sounds plausible in theory, but there are two
clairning to show how men think the myths, but rather
practical difficulties which turn out to be of major im-
how the myths think themselves out in men and with-
portance. The first is that, in the final stage of tbis
out men's knowledge."I:{ The other reads, "1 therefore
process, it is easy to make it appear that the theory
claim to show, not how men think in myths but how
and the evidence fit together, but the contrary is difficult
to demonstrate. Logical positivists can therefore argue myths operate in men's minds without their being aware
of the fact."14
that Lévi-Strauss' theories are more or less meaningless The French is ambiguous. "Comment les mythes se
because, in the last analysis, they cannot be rigorously
tested. pensent dans les hommes" might be translated "how
The second difficulty is to understand just what is myths are thought in men," which would reduce the
degree of autonomy implied. The issue of autonomy is
meant by the total system, "the general object of analy-
'sis," the ultimate algebraic structure of which particular important. Lévi-Strauss appears to regard cross-cultural
variations of cultural phenomena, especially myth, as
culture products are merely partial manifestations.
self-generated topological distortions of a common struc-
Where is this structure located? This is a question
ture. As illustration, he refers to D'Arcy Thompson's
which may be asked about all cultural systems. Where
discussion of the shapes of fish,15 The presumed au-
is "a spoken language" -in de Saussure's sense-Io-
cated? The language as a whole is external to any par-
ticular individual; in Durkheim's terrninology, it is part 1" In Jacques Ehrmann, ed., StructU1'alism, a double issue of
of the collective consciousness (eonseienee eolleetive) Yale French Studies, Nos. 36-37 (1966), p. 56; the Intro-
duction to Mythologiques 1 is reprinted there in English
of all those who speak it. translation.
But Lévi-Strauss is not much concerned with the 1-1 In John and Doreen Weightman, trans., The Raw and the .
Coohed (New York, 1969), p. 12. ".
',o
collective consciousness of any particular social system; 1,
le, See Mythologiques IV, p. 606. The last chapter of D'Arcy
his quest rather is to discover the collective uneonseious Thompson, On Growth and Form (Cambridge, 1961), is
of "the hurnan mind" (l'esprit humain), and this should highly relevant for an understanding of Lévi-Strauss' struc-
apply not merely to speakers of one language but to turalism (Chapter XVII, "On the theory of transformations,
or the cOlnparison of related forms").
speakers of all languages.
C L A U DEL É VI - S T R A U S s 54 .The Hmnan Animal ancl His Symbols I 55

tonomy implies that Lévi-Strauss can ignore the cultural,. 'l\'e can therefore postulate that the human brain oper-
context of particular variants; the mechanism that" ates in much the same way when it uses nonverbal
, I
generates the observed differences is not that of adap-~ lele~ents of culture to form a "sign language" and that
tive evolution 01' functional relevance, but simply mathe- • • tbe ultimate relational system, the algebra itself, is an
matical permutation. The nature of the "human mind," • . attribute of human brains everywhere. But-and this
which functions as a kind of randomising computer to is where the metaphors and the metonyms come in-
generate these permutations "without bcing aware of we also know, not only from the way we can decode
the fact," is left obscure. The heresy of Lévi-Strauss' speech but more particularly from the way we appre-
Anglo-Saxon critics is that they start off by assuming hend music, that the human brain is capable of listen-
that any local variation of a structured form, whether ing to both harmony and melody at the same time. Now
in biology 01' in culture, is functionally adapted to the the associations of sounds in harmony-an orchestral
local environment, so that we can only claim to under- score read vertica11y up and down the page-is meta-
stand the local peculiarities after we have taken into phoric. In terms of the table on page 49 the notes belong
account the local environmental circumstances. For to the system of sounds which can be made by a11the
such critics, playing tic-tac-toe with topological dia- assembled orchestral instruments. But the sequence of
grams is not enough. sounds in a melody-an orchestral score read hori-
However, Lévi-Strauss firmly repudiates the sugges- zontally acrosS the page-is metonymic. In terms of
tion that he is an idealist, so we have to assume that the table, the notes form a syntagmatic chain derived
the somewhat mysterious operations of the "human in sequence from one instrument at a time. So it is
mind" which he postulates are processes that take place Lévi_StrauSS, bold proposition that the algebra of the
in the ordinary substance of the brain. The implica- brain can be represented as a rectangular matrix of at
tions of his argument seem to be something like this: least two (but perhaps severa!) dimensions which can
In the course of human evolution man has developed be "read" up and down or side to side like the words of
the unique capacity to communicate by means óf lan- a crossword puzzle. His thesis is that we demonstrably
guage and signs and not just by means of signals and do this with sounds (in the way we lis ten to words and
triggered responses. In order that he should be able to music); therefore it is intrinsica11y probable that we
do this it is necessary that the mechanisms of the also do the same kind of thing when we convey mes-
human brain (which we do not yet understand) embody sages by manipulating cultural categories other than
certain capacities for making plus/minus distinctions, sounds.
for treating the binary pairs thus formed as related This is an extreme reductionist argument, but on the
couples, and for manipulating these "relations" as in a face of it, it should help to explain not only how cul-
matrix algebra. We hnow that the human brain can do tural symbols convey messages within a particular
this in the case of sound patterns, for structural lin- cultural milieu but how they convey messages at all.
guistics has shown that this is one (but only one) essen- The structure of relations which can be discovered by
tial element in the formation of meaningful speech; analyzing materials drawn from any one culture is an
e L A U DEL É VI - S T R A U S s I 56
algebraic transformation of other possible stru~tútes
belonging to a common set, and this common set consti-'· <

tutes a pattern which reflects an attribute of the mech- ".1)


anism of all human brains, It is a grand conception;
whether it is a useful one may be a matter of opinion.

The Structure of Myth



IV Lévi-Strauss on myth has much the same fas-
cination as Freud on the interpretation of
dreams, and the same kind of weaknesses too,
A first encounter with Freud is usually per-
suasive; it is all so neat, it simply must be right.
But then you begin to wonder. Supposing the
whole Freudian argument about symbolic asso-
ciations and layers of conscious, unconscious,
and preconscious were entirely false, would it
ever be possible to prove that it is false? And if
the answer to that question is "No," you then
have to ask yourself whether psychoanalytic
arguments about symbol formation and free as-
sociation can ever be anything better than clever
talk.
Lévi-Strauss' discussions about the structure
of myth are certainly very clever talk; whether
they are really any more than that still remains
to be seen.
The StTuctuTe of Myth \ 59
CLAUDE LÉVI-STRAUSS I 58 , .-
.. -,

Myth is an ill-defined category. Some people use ~, .~d conceive of time present as a straightforward per-
word as if it meant fallacious history-a story about tbe" 'petuation of time pasto In Lévi-Strauss' usage, myth
past which we know to be false; to say that an event is haS no location in chronological time, but it does have
"mythical" is equivalent to saying that it didn't happen.; .certain characteristics which it shares with dreams and
The theological usage is rather differen t: myth is a fairy tales. In particular, the distinction between nature
formulation of religious mystery-"the expression of and culture which dominates normal human experience
unobservable realities in terms of observable phe- largely disappears. In Lévi-Straussian myth men con-
nomena."l This comes close to the anthropologist's usual verse with animals or marry animal spouses, they live
view that "myth is a sacred tale." in the sea or in the sky, they perform feats of magic as
If we accept this latter kind of definition the special a matter of course.
quality of myth is not that it is false bu t that it is Here, as elsewhere, Lévi-Strauss' ultimate concern is
divinely true for those who believe but fairy tale for with "the unconscious nature of collective phenomena."
those who do noto The distinction that history is true (StTUcwral Anthropology, p. 18) Like Freud he seeks
and myth is false is quite arbitrary. Nearly all human to discover principIes of thought formation which are
societies possess a corpus of tradition about their own universally valid for all human minds. These universal
past. It starts, as the Bible starts, with a story of the principIes (if they exist) are operative in our brains
Creation. This is necessarily mythical in all senses of just as much as in the brains of South American In-
the termo But the Creation stories are followed by dians, but in our case the cultural training we have
legends about the exploits of culture heroes (e.g., King received through living in a high-technology society and
David and King Solomon), which might have some through attending school or university has overlaid the
foundation in "true history," and these in turn lead on universal logic of primitive thought with all kinds of
to accounts of events which everyone accepts as fulIy speciallogics required by the artificial conditions of our
historical because their occurrence has been independ- social environment. If we are to get at the primitive,
ently recorded in some other source. The Christian New universal logic in its uncontaminated form, we need
Testament purports to be history from one point of view to examine the thought processes of ver y primitive,
and myth from another, and he is a rash man who technologically unsophisticated peoples (such as the
seeks to draw a sharp line between the two. South American Indians), and the study of myth is one
Lévi-Strauss has evaded this issue of the relation be- way of achieving this end.
tween myth and history by concentrating his attention Even if we accept the general proposition that there
on "societies with no history"-that is to say, on peoples must be a kind of universal inbuilt logic of a nonrational
such as the Australian Aborigines and the tribal peoples kind which is shared by a11humanity and which is made
of Brazil, who think of their own society as changeless manifest in primitive mythology, we are still faced with
many methodological difficulties. Mythology (in Lévi-
].l. Schniewind, "A Reply to Bultmann," in Kel'ygma and Strauss' sense) starts out as an oral tradition associated
Myth, ed. I-I.W. Bal'tsch (London, 1953), p. 47. with religious ritual. The tales themselves are usually
CLAUDE LÉVI-STRAUSS 60 The Structure of Myth 6r

transmitted in exotic languages at enormous len'gth. a message in codeo In other words he assumes with
J .Fr'eud that a l11yth is a kind of collective dream and
By the time they become available to Lévi-Strauss or to;.
¡
J

'.'that it should be capable of interpretation so as to


I any other would-be analyst, they have been writteri ~
down and transcribed, in abbreviated form, into one . reveal the hidden l11eaning.
or other of the common European languages. In the Lévi-Strauss' ideas about the nature of the code and
process they have been completely divorced from their the kind of interpretation that might be possible have
original religious context. This is just as true of the several sources.
stories which Lévi-Strauss discusses in Mythologiques The first of these comes from Freud: myths express
as it is bf the myths of Greece and Rome and ancient unconscious wishes which are somehow inconsistent
Scandinavia with which we are more familiar. Even so, with conscious experience. Among primitive peoples the
Lévi-Strauss asserts that the stories will have retained continui ty of the polítical system is dependent upon
the essential structuTaI characteristics they possessed in the perpetuation of alliances between sl11all groups of
the first place, so that if we go about it in the right way kin. These alliances are created and cemented by gifts
a comparison of these emasculated stories can still be of women: fathcrs givc away their daughters, brothers
made to exhibit the outstanding characteristics of a give away their sisters. But if men are to give away
universal primitive nonrationallogic. their women to serve social-political ends they must
Our valuation of such an improbable credo can only refrain from keeping these women to themselves for
be assessed in operational terms. If, by applying Lévi- sexual ends. Incest and exogamy are therefore opposite
Strauss' technigues of analysis to an actual body of sides of the same penny, and the incest taboo (a rule
anthropological materials, we are able to arrive at in- about sexual behavior) is the cornerstone of society (a
sights which we did not have before, and these insights structure of social and political relations). This moral
throw illumination on other related ethnographic facts principie implies that, in the imaginary initial situation,
which we had not considered in the first instance, then the First Man should have had a wife who was not his
we may feel that the exercise has been worth while. sister. But in that case any story about a First Man or a
Letthis
of say at once that in many cases there is a pay-off
me kind. First Woman must contain a logical contradiction. For
íf they were brother and sister then we are all the out-
The problem, as Lévi-Strauss sees it, is roughly this. come of the primeval incest, but, if they were separate
If we consider any corpus of l11ythological tales at their creations, only one of them can be the first human being
face value we get the impression of an enormous variety and the other must be (in some sense) other than
human: thus the biblical Eve is of one flesh with Adam
of trivial incident, associated with a great deal of repeti-
tion and a recurrent harping on very elementary themes and their relations are incestuous, but the nonbiblical
Lilíth was a dCl110n.~
-incest betwcen bl'othcr ancl sistcr or mother ancl son,
parricicle and fratricide, cannibalism .... Lévi-Strauss "This representation of the incest argument is altogether
postulates that behind the l11anifest sense of the stories too "empi11cist." For Lévi-Strauss the importance of the dis-
there must be another non-sense (see above, page 29), tinction exogamy /incest is that it marks the establishment
"',

The StructuTe of Myth 63


CLAUDE LÉV1-STRAUSS 62

Another contradiction of a comparable kind 1s that' :in.consistencies are lost sight of even when they are
the concept of life entails the concept of death. A living . . openly expressed. In "La Geste d'Asdiwal" (1960),
thing is that which is not dead; a dead thing is that" .'which is, for many people, the most satisfying of all
which is not alive. But relígion endeavors to separate Lévi-Strauss' essays in myth analysis, his conclusion
these two intrinsically interdependent concepts so that is that:
we have myths which account for the oTigin of death or
which represent death as "the gateway to eternal life." All the paradoxes conceived by the native mind, on
the most diverse planes: geographic, economic, socio-
Lévi-Strauss has argued that when we are considering
logical, and even cosmological, are, when all is said
the universalist aspects of primitive mythology we sha1l and done, assimilated to that less obvious yet so real
repeatedly discover that the hidden message is con-
cerned with the resolution of unwelcome contradictions paradox which marriage with the matrilateral cousin
attempts but fails to resolve. But the failure is
of this sort. The repetitions and prevarications of admitted in our myths, and there precisely líes their
mythology so fog the issue that irresolvable logical function. ("The Story of Asdiwal," pp. 27-28)

of a social dichotomy order/ disorder. The key myth of But the "admission" is of a complex kind, and even Lévi-
Mythologiques l, M. 1 (pp. 43 ff.) and the key myth of Strauss needs two pages of close argument to persuade
Mythologiques IV, M. 529/30 (pp. 25 ff.; 564) are both
manifestly "about" incesto They are also both manifestly the reader (who is already in possession of all the rele-
"about" bird nesting. The bird-nesting element entails sus- vant evidence) that this is what in fact the myths are
pension in a void between this world and the other, regres- saying.
sion to infancy, deprivation from cooked food. Although
most of the other details are quite different, Lévi-Strauss The second major source of Lévi-Strauss thinking on
declares that the two myths are identical but inveTse. In this topic comes from arguments taken over from the
M. 1 a naked adolescent boy commits incest with his field of general information theory. Myth is not just
mother, acquires clothing, and, after adventures, kills his
father; in M. 529/30 the father of a richly clothed adult fairy tale; it contains a message. Admittedly, it is not
son strips the son of his clothing and commits incest with very clear who is sending the message, but it is clear
one of the son's many wives. In the course of adventures who is receiving it. The novices of the society who hear
the son is reborn in an abnormal manner. The father is
again destroyed by the son. It is only after extended analysis the myths for the first time are being indoctrinated by
that these stories can be shown to be concerned with the the bearers of tradition-a tradition which, in theory
beginning of society because they are also concerned with at any rate, has be en handed down from long-dead
the beginning of time, the beginning of order, the beginning ancestors. Let us then think of the ancestors (A) as
of culture. For Lévi-Strauss, the most persistently recurrent
"opposition" in mythology is that between order and dis- senders and the present generation (B) as receivers.
order, but it takes on endless permutations of empirical Now let us imagine the situation of an individual A
formo To illustrate this point he places near the end of
Mythologiques l (p. 318) a series of myths which move who is trying to get a message to a friend B who is
from "noisemaking to eclipses, from eclipses to incest, from almost out of earshot, and let us suppose that communi-
incest to unruliness, and from unruliness to the coloured cation is further hampered by various kinds of inter-
plumage of birds." The transformations I offer in the fol-
lowing pages are of a more pedestrian kind. ference-noise from wind, passing cars, and so on.
CLAUDE LÉVI-STRAUSS 64 The StTuctuTe of Myth 65

What will A do? If he is sensible he will not be satisfl,ed pCiges to the analysis of a single complex of myths pre-
with shouting his message just once; he will shout it ,'cisely located in a particular cultural region, and the
several times, and give a different wording to the rr¡e~~' result is entirely fascinating. But when, like Frazer, he
sage each time, supplementing his words with visual, ,roams about among the ethnographies of the whole
signals. At the receiving end B may very likely get the world picking up odd details of custom and story to
meaning of each of the individual messages slightly reveal what he presumes to be a single unitary message
wrong, but when he puts them together the redundan- inherent in the architecture of the human mind, most
cies and the mutual consistencies and inconsistencies of his British admirers get left behind. Here is an ex-
will make· it guite clear what is "really" being said. ample of this latter procedure: "As in archaic China and
Suppose, for example, that the in tended message con- certain Amerindian societies there was until recently
sists of eight elements, and that each time that A a European custom which entailed the ritual extinction
shouts across to B different parts of that message are and subseguent rekindling of domes tic hearths preceded
obliterated by interference from other noises; then the by fasting and by the use of instruments of darkness
total pattern of what B receives will consist of a series [instruments des tenebTes]." (Mythologiques II, p. 351)
of "chords" as in an orchestra score, thus: "Instruments of darkness" refers to a twelfth-century
European custom in which, between Good Friday and
1 2 78 4 6 8
7 5
8 Easter Eve, the ordinary church bells were silent and
1 1 234
2 345 6
were replaced by various other noise-producing devices,
the din from which was supposed to remind the faithful
of the prodigies and terrifying sounds which accom-
panied the death of Chris t. (M ythologiques II, p. 348)
Lévi-Strauss' postulate is that a corpus of mythology In the cited guotation Lévi-Strauss has given this
constitutes an orchestral score of this sort. The collec- medieval European Christian category a world-wide ex-
tivity of the senior members of the society, through its tension by using it to include any kind of musical in-
religious institutions, is unconsciously transmitting to strument which is employed as a signal to mark the
the junior members a basic message which is manifest beginning or end of a ritual performance. He then draws
in the score as a whole rather than in any particular attention to the use of such signals in various situations
myth. where lights and fires are extinguished and rekindled
Many social anthropologists of the more usual Anglo- at the beginning and end of a period of fast. And finally
American sort-the functionalists of whom Lévi-Strauss he comes back to Europe and notes that "instruments
is so critical-are prepared to go along with him this of darkness" are used in contexts of the latter kind.
far, but they find his method far less acceptable when- The whole argument is circular, since the universality
ever he ignores the cultural limitations of time and of the conjunction of "instruments of darkness" and
space. fasting is already presupposed in the operational defini-
In "The Story of Asdiwal," Lévi-Strauss devotes forty Hon of the terms employed.

J
CLAUDE LÉVI-STllAUSS 66 The St1"uctu1"e of Myth 67
Very substantial sections of aIl four volumes of which run paraIlel to those of Lévi-Strauss in quite a
Mythologiques are open to objections of this kind, ánd, l1umber of ways. But the latter has carried the theoreti-
to be frank, this grand-scale survey of the mythology.· cal analysis of what he is up to much further than any
of the Americas, which extends to two thousand pages of the others.
and gives details of eight hundred and thirteen different In Lévi-Strauss' first essay on this topic4 he uses, as
stories and their variants, often degenerates into a one of his examples, an abbreviated analysis of the
latter-day Golden Bough, with aIl the methodological structure of the Oidipus story. This is one of the very
defects which such a comment might imply. Lévi- few cases in which he has so far applied his method to
Strauss is, of course, weIl aware that he is open to a myth which is likely to be familiar to an English 01'
criticism of this kind, and in Mythologiques III (pp. American reader, so let us start with that. I have fol-
11-12) he goes to some lengths to justify an astonishing lowed Lévi-Strauss fairly closely, introducing modifica-
claim that a Tukuna myth which is "impossible to in- tions only at points where his argument seems particu-
terpret" in its native South American context becomes larly obscure.
comprehensible when brought into association with a He first assumes that the myth (any myth) can
"paradigmatic system" drawn from the myths of North readily be broken up into segments 01' incidents, and
America. It seems to me that only the most uncritical that everyone familiar with the story will agree as to
devotees are likely to be persuaded by this argumento what these incidents are. The incidents in every case
But, even so, the structural analysis of myth deserves refer to the "relations" between the individual characters
our serious attention. Just what does this expression in the story, 01' to the "status" of particular individuals.
mean? These relations and statuses are the points on which we
I shaIl try to explain by demonstration, but I must need to focus our attention; the individual characters,
emphasize two preliminary points. First, a fuIl exposi- as such, as often interchangeable.
tion of the method requires a great deal of space; my In the particular case of the Oidipus" myth he takes :1
",IJ,
skeletal examples give no indication of the subtleties the foIlowing segments of a syntagmatic chain:
of the technique. Second, Lévi-Strauss' method is not i. "Kadmos seeks his sister Europe, ravished by
entirely new. In England, Hocart and Lord Raglan made Zeus."
gropings in the same direction over forty years ago; ii. "Kadmos kiIls the Dragon."
so did the Russian folklorist Vladimir Proppa Rather
-,Claude Lévi-Strauss, "The Struetural Study of Myth," I
la ter, Georges Dumezil, one of Lévi-Strauss' senior col-
leagues at the CoIlege de France, began to develop ideas ]ou1'11al of AmeTiean Vol. 68, No. 270 (1955).
FolhloTe, ,1

o In this and subsequent stories I use an anglicized Greek "


1I

(rather than a Latin) spelling of personal names in the I


,
"See Claude Lévi-Strauss, "La Strlleture et la forme. Ré- form in which they appear in the Index of H. ]. Rose, A
flexions sur un ouvrage de Vladimir Propp," in Cahie'/"s de Handbooh of G-reeh Mythology (1959). A summary of the
l'Inst'itut des Sciences économiques appUqllées (Paris), leading features of the Theban myth cyc1e is given below,
1960. pages 78 ff.

~
The Stmctme of Myth 69
CLAUDE LÉVI-STRAUSS 68
. But where should we stop? In another version Haimon
iii. "The Spartoi (the men who are born as a result is 'killed by the Sphinx; in another Antigone bears
of sowing thé dragon's teeth) kill one another." Haimon a son who is killed by Kreon, and so on.
iv. "Oidipus kills his father Laios." • So let us stick to Lévi-Strauss' own skeletal version.
v. "Oidipus kiUs the Sphinx." (But in fact, in' the He puts his eleven segments into four columns, thus:
story, the Sphinx commits suicide after Oidipus
has answered the riddle.)
vi. "Oidipus marries his mother Jokaste." I II III IV
(ii) Kadmos/
vii. "Eteokles kiUs his brother Polyneikes." (i) Kadmos/
Dragon
viii. "Antigone buries her brother Polyneikes despite Europe
(iii) Spartoi
prohibi tion." (ix) Lame
(iv) Oidipus/ Labdakos
Lévi-Strauss also draws our attention to a peculiarity of Laios
three of the names: (vi) Oidipus/
(v) Oidipus/
ix. Labdakos (father of Laios)= "Lame" Jokaste Sphinx
(x) Left-sided
x. Laios (father of Oidipus) = "Left-sided" (vii) Eteokles/ Laios
Poly-
xi. Oidipus = "Swollen-foot" neikes
Lévi-Strauss admits that the selection of these char~
(viii) An ti- (xi) Swollen-
acters and these incidents is to some extent arbitrary, gone/ footed
but he argues that if we added more incidents they Poly- Oidipus
would only be variations of the ones we have already. neikes
This is true enough. For example: Oidipus' task is to
kill the Sphinx; he does this by answering the riddle: He then points out that in each of the incidents in
the answer to the riddle, according to some authorities, Column I there is a ritual offense of the nature of incest
was "the child grows into an adult who grows into an -"an overvaluation of kinship." This contrasts with
old man"; the Sphinx then commits suicide; Oidipus the incidents in Column Il, where the offenses are of
Cthe child grown into an adult") then marries his the nature of fratricide/parricide-"an undervaluation
mother, Jokaste; when Oidipus learns the answer to of kinship." In Column III the common element is the
this riddle, Jokaste commits suicide and Oidipus puts destruction of anomalous monsters by men, while Col-
out his own eyes to become an old mano So also, if we umn IV refers to men who are themselves to some extent
were to pursue the fortunes of Antigone, we should note anomalous monsters. Here Lévi-Strauss introjects a
that, having "buried" her dead brother in defiance of
general proposition based on grand-scale comparative
the command of her mother's brother (Kreon), she is
ethnography of the Frazerian kind: "In mythology it is
in turn herself buried alive by Kreon; she commits a universal characteristic of men born from the Earth
suicide; her suicide is followed by that of her betrothed that at the moment they emerge from the depth they
cousin Haimon and also that of Haimon's mother
either cannot walk or they walk clumsily. This is the
Eurydike.

~
CLAUDE LíéVI-STHAUSS 70 The S tmctme of Myth 71

case 01' the chthonian beings in the mythology 01' the tion 01' this type, "the overrating 01' blood relations"
Pueblo ... [and 01'] the Kwakiutl." This, so he says, is to the "underrating 01' blood relations" as "the
explains the peculiarity 01' the names. attempt to escape autochthony" is to the "impossi-
Anyway, the nature 01' the anomalous monsters in bility to succeed in it." Although experience contra-
Column 111 is that they are half man-half animal, and dicts theory, social life validates cosmology by its
similarity 01' structure. Hence, cosmology is true.
the story 01' the sowing 01' the dragon's teeth implies a
eStructural AnthTOpology, p. 216)(;
doctrine of the autochthonous origin 01'man; the Spartoi
were oo1'n 1'rom the earth without hum::m aid. In con- Those who think that aIl this is vaguely reminiscent 01'
trast, the story 01' Oidipus' being exposed at birth and an argument from Alice through the Looking Glass will
staked to the ground e this was the origin 01'his swollen not be far wrong. Lewis CarroIl, in his alter ego as
foot) implies that even though born 01' woman he was mathematician, was one 01' the originators 01' the
not fuIly separated from his natural earth. And so, says peculiar kind 01'binary logic upon which Lévi-Straussian
Lévi-Strauss, Column 111, in which the monsters are discourse and modern computer technology are alike
overcome, signifies clenial of the autochthonous origin constructed.
of man, while Column IV signifies the persistence of the It must be admitted that, emasculated in this way,
autochthonous origin of mano So IV is the converse 01' the argument almost ceases to be comprehensible, yet
III just as II is the converse 01' I! even so, the reader may suspect that behind the non- "

By this hair-splitting logic we end up with an sense there is a sense. The reason why Lévi-Strauss has j

eguation; not pursued his explorations 01' classical Greek my- ,1

1111 ; ; III/IV i
thology any further seems to be that, in the somewhat .j! lit,.
But Lévi-Strauss maintains that there is more to this bowdlerized form in which these stories have come I
than algebra. The formal religious theory 01' the Greeks down to us, there are too few parameters. The South
was that man was autochthonous. The first man was 1
American mythology, which has provided the main
half a serpent; he grew from the earth as plants grow arena 01' his explorations, has many more dimensions. ,1

from the earth. Therefore the puzzle that needs to be


"

In particular he is there able to show that:


solved is; i
l. sets 01' relationships among human beings in l' ,

how to find a satisfactory transition between this ,11

11"
theory and the knowledge that human beings are "Compare al so the following quotations; "The purpose of I(
actuaIly born from the union 01' man and woman. myth is to provide a logical model capable of overcoming a If.';i
1;;
Although the problem obviously cannot be solved, contradiction (an impossible achievement if, as it happens, !l
1:
the Oidipus myth provides a kind 01' logical tool the contradiction is real)." And, "The inability to connect :í
two kinds of relationships is overcome (01' rather replaced)
which relates to the original p1'oblem-born from one by the assertion that the contradictory relationships are Ij
or born from two-to the derivative problem: born identical inasmuch as they are both self-contradictory in a
from different or born from the same. By a correla- similar way." (StTuctlLml Anthropology, pp. 229, 216) .:[
i',
,i,
"

}; "

It
i
CLAUDE LÉVI-STRAUSS 72
The StTuctll7'e of Myth I 73
terms of relative status, friendship and hostility,' In his' original articIe Lévi-Strauss remarks at the end
sexual availability, mutual dependence
of his brief discussion of Oidipus:
may be represented in myth, either in direct or trans.
po sed form, as
If a myth is made up of all its variants, structural
2. relationships among different kinds especies) of' analysis should take them alI into account. After
men, animals, birds, reptiles, insects, Supernatural' analyzing alI the known variants of the Theban ver-
beings sion, we should thus treat the others in the same
3· relationships between categories of food and way: first the tales about Labdakos' colIateral line
incIuding Agave, Pentheus, and ]okaste herself; the
modes of food preparation and the use or non-use
of fire eabove, page 27) Theban version about Lykos with Amphion and Zetos
as the city founders; more remote variants concern-
4· relations between categories of sound and silence ing Dionysos eOidipus' matrilateral cousin) and
prod1,lced either naturalIy as animal cries or arti. Athenian legends where Kekrops takes the place of
ficialIy by means of musical instruments Kadmos. For each of them a similar chart should be
5· relations between categories of smelI and taste- drawn and then compared and reorganized according
pleasantlunpleasant, sweetlsour, etc. to the findings. eStructural AnthTOpology, p. 217)
6. relations between types of human dress and un.
The methodological program applied to American ma-
dress and between the animals and plants from
which the cIothing is derived terials in Mythologiques is a modification of this plan.
Volume 1 starts with a Bororo myth from South America
7· relations between body functions: e.g., eating, (M. 1) and explores variants and permutations. There ./

excretion, urination, vomiting, copulation, birth,


menstruation

8. relations between categories of landscape, sea-


is recurrent emphasis on the theme that "culinary oper-
ations are viewed as mediatory activities between heaven
¡
~: .
and earth, life and death, nature and society." Volume
sonal change, cIimate, time alternations, celestial
bodies II examines more convoluted versions of the same com-
plex, and Volume III pursues the chase into North
01' combinations of any of these. The main purpose of America. Volume IV leads us the other way round:
his South American analysis is not merely to show that
starting with a myth from the American Northwest
such symbolization occurs, for Freud and his folIowers
eM. 529), variants eventualIy take us back to South
have already cIaimed to demonstrate this, but to show
America. The emphasis on cooking as an agent of trans-
that the transformations folIow strictly logical rules.
formation persists, but the title Naked Man draws atten-
Lévi-Strauss displays quite extraordinary ingenuity tion to the recurrent equivalence: nakedl clothed =
in the way he exhibits this hidden logic, but the argu- Nature/Culture. At the end of the day Lévi-Strauss
ment is extremely complicated and very difficult to
evaluate. cIaims to have demonstrated that the whole vast agglom-
eration of stories forms a single system. In principIe,
Is it possible to present a reduced model of such a .such an operation might be expanded indefinitely so
system of analysis and still convey the general sense? .
there can be nothing heretical about applying the rules
CLAUDE LÉVI-STHAUSS 74 The Str1.Lcture of Myth I 75

of the game to the mythology of Classical Greece. There brother Demophoon nearly achieves immortality be-
are indeed striking American parallels for some well- cause he eats nothing in this world but is instead
known European themes.7 anointed with ambrosia, a food of the gods related
In particular, Orpheus, being heavily laden with to honey. He fails to achieve immortality because his
binary anrithE:SE:s, SE:E:msposiri\'E:ly to inÚte a Le vi- real mother (Metaneira) drags hiro from fire in which
Straussian im'bri-:;arion: he is being cooked by Demeter, who is seeking to
burn away his mortality. Persephone is lured to her
H,; ¡., ó. ::/,[j (,i SéfltlE: :\V-,llr, r,ul ::. idlC¡.';E:r úf "ild doom by the fragrant smell of fresh ftowers.
Diúnysús, with \vhom hE:bE:C:úmE:S idE:nrified.
Already 1 have started enough hares to fill a whole
He rescues his wife hom the land of the dead by volume of Lévi-Strauss' magnum opus, and our author
means of music but loses her because of silence-
"nol hearing her footsteps behind him." himself is undoubtedly aware of the possibilities (see,
He is a devoted husband yet the originator of male e.g., Mythologiques II, p. 347). But the ordinary reader
homosexuality; his orac1e was located on Lesbos, the who is unfamiliar with the details of classical mythology
traclitional source of female homosexuality. or the permutations and combinations in Mythologiques
can hardly be expected to decipher such a rigmarole. j
Furthermore, the Orpheus-Euridike story is a structural I
permutation of the Demeter-Persephone story:
1 shall attempt something much more modesto By fol-
lowing through a very restricted version of Lévi-Strauss'
original plan, 1 shall try to give the reader some feeling
i
~
Euriclike the wife and Persephone the Virgin
Daughter are both carriecl off to rule as Queen of the of how, in a structuralist analysis, the contrasted pat-
Unclerworlcl. terns of superficially different stories can be seen to fit
Orpheus the hllsbancl fails to rescue his wife and together. It needs to be realized, however, that in any
is sterile; Demeter the mother partially rescues her such trllncated illustration we necessarily forfeit many
c1aughter ancl is fertile. of the subtler nuances of the technique.
Euridike dies in consequence of being bit ten by a Within these limitations the analysis which follows,
snake while evading the sexual embraces of Aristaios, which discusses eight stories in outline and mentions
half-brother to Orpheus. The punishment of Aristaios several others in skeletal form, is in tended to illustrate
is that he loses his bees and hence his honey. He certain key features in Lévi-Strauss' procedure. The
recovers his bees by finding a swarm in the carcass
various stories are all summarized in the same way so
of a sacrificed animal which has been specially that the roles of the various dramatis peTsonae can be
allowed to go putrid instead of being cooked and
bumed for the gods in the usual way. Persephone easily distinguished. King, Queen, Mother, Father,
fails to achieve immortality beca use she eats raw Brother, Sister, Daughter, Son, Son-in-law, Paramour,
pomegranate seeds in the other world; her foster etc., are seen to exhibit permutations of a single "plot."
The comparison rests on a basic underlying hypothe-
See A. Hultkrantz, The North American Indian OrphelLs
sis to the effect that Greek mythology as a whole con-
Tmdition (New York, 1958). 'stitutes a single "system" (language) and that each
CLAUDE LÉVI-STRAUSS 76 The Structure of Myth 77
individual story is a syntagm of that system (pages 48- in a fuller account it would be seen that this issue also
50). The system as a whole presupposes a certain meta- appears in other guises transposed onto other planes.
phorical apprehension of the relative positions of l11en Just how this works cannot be shown in brief space,
and animals and deities in a matrix formed by the 'but the í'ollowing generalization by Lévi-Strauss derived
oppositions:
from his American material may well apply to the
Greek data also:
ABOVE/BELOW, TI-lIS WORLD/OTI-IER WORLD,
CULTURE/NATURE [There is] an analogy between honey and menstrual
blood. Both are transformed (élaborée) substances
This schema is summarized below in Figure 5. Other resul ting from a sort of infm-cuisine, vegetal in the
factors which are presupposed in my analysis (this one case. , . animal in the other. Moreover, honey
would be more evident if my description oí' the myths may be either healthy 01' toxic, just as a woman in
were more complete) are the transformational rules her normal condition is a "honey", but secretes a
hinted at in my remarks about the Orpheus story (page poison when she is indisposed. Finally we have seen
74)· The Greek deities were supposed to eat only fresh that, in native thought, the search for honey repre-
sents a sort of return to Nature, in the guise of erotic
uncooked foods-ambrosia, nectar, honey-but they
delighted in the smell of burnt offerings. Thus BURNING/ attraction transposed from the sexual register to that
of the sense of taste which undermines the very
PUTRm :: SKY/ UNDERWORLD. In my versions of the
foundations of Culture if it is indulged in for too
myths the issue is blatantly about sex and homicide; long. In the same way the honey-moon will be a
PRESUMED SCHEMA menace to public order if the brida! paír are allowed
MEN ANIMALS to extend their priva te game indefinitely and to neg-
GODS
lect their duties to society. (Mythologiques III, p.
~
..;¡ 340)
Zeus sky
Eagles And if the relevance of all this to what follows seems
J +
Men In - Domestic Animals _ Wild Animals
obscure 1 can only remark that one of the unmentioned
Gods In
Cities I In Fanns Monsters the Wild characters, Glaukos, son of Minos and brother-in-law
(SkY-Mounta:J.n)
~ Serpents (dragons) Underworld to Dionysos, was "drowned in ajar of honey" and re-
1-<

< born from a tomb.


!:l
Poseidon ~~es
•• (sea) (ow Finally, 1 should point out that the ultimate conelu-
ground) I
THIS WORLD ~ • OTRER WORLD sion of the analysis is not that "all the I?yths say the l'
.. CULTURE
same thing" but that "collectively the sum of what all ¡
----------- NATURE • ¡:
the myths say is not expressly said by any of them, and 11

that what they thus say (collectively) is a necessary 1,

Figure 5
poetic truth which is an unwelcome contradiction." It 1I

11

!
¡(- ,',{ C'. (( ~. t .. /
>t.-,...J\ ..A
11,'
._~_
~ ¡ :. ) ,. l... ).~. l l ,.,.,
./ • " o" .~, ~ ( •• ' _ , • ('

I '.J ~. , •• , I ,~
'1
' , ¡. ~~¡'(( '...t· ,I l' l' r
I . ( ( \. r,/, (: (.: 'í
The StructuTe of Myth 79
CLAUDE LÉVI-STRAUSS I 78
is Lévi-Strauss' thesis that the 1'unction 01'mythology iS daughter Harmonia. The gods give Harmonia a
to exhibit publicly, though in clisguise; ordinariiy un- magical necklace as dowry, which later brings dis-
conséious paradoxes of this kincl (cf. page 63 The r aster to everyone who possesses it. At the end of
the story Kadmos and Harmonia change into
underlying assumption throughout the analysis is that
\ this '2:~duc~~ ~1:9_cJ~!;:_.which
arranges various _.-.~
pairs of dragons.
: -. _ ...
Comment: The story specifies the polarity Na-
ture : Culture :: Gocls : Men and affinns that the
,A
,,\tt.'\
i'
(-

V
,;:
".~
I .
~Iicit in t~e-'whoJe s~stem of mythology of whichll1e
hsted stonesin are
~~g9..E~~_s
~._._.-
partIcular
binary examplcs.
opposition along . two axes, is im-
relationship between gods and men is one of am-
biguous ancl unstable al!iance-exemplifiecl by
¡ l •• 1 ~ ( , ¡
marriage fol!owed by feucl followed by marriage
accompanied by poisoned marriage gifts. There is
THE STORIES
also the ambiguity of autochthony/nonautoch-
thony. Kadmos, who slays the dragon from whom
1 I Kadmos, ElIrope, and the Dragon's Teeth are born the Spartoi, is himself the clragon and
StOTY: Zeus (Gocl) in the 1'orm of a tame wild ancestor of the Spartoi.
bul! (mecliator between wild and tame) seduces
and carries off ahuman girl, Europe. 2 I Minos and the Minotaur
Europe's brother, Kadmos, and mother, Tele-'
phassa, search for her. The mother dies and is StOTY: Minos is son of Zeus and Europe (s tory
buried by Kaclmos. Kadmos is then told to fol!ow a 1) and husband to Pasiphae, daughter of the Sun.
particular cow (domestic animal: replacement of Poseidon is brother to Zeus but his counterpart,
the sister ancl the mother). Where the cow stops, god of the sea instead of god of the sky.
Kaclmos must found Thebes, having first sacrificed Poseidon sends Minos a beautiful bull which
the cow to Athena. (Cow 1'orms link between man should be sacrificed; Minos retains the bull. In
and gocls just as bul! formecl link between gods punishment Poseidon causes Pasiphae to lust after
and man.) In seeking to pro vicie water for the the bull. By the ingenuity of Daidalos, Pasiphae is
sacrifice Kadmos encounters a clragon (monster) changed into a cow ancl has sex relations with the
guarding a sacrecl pool. The dragon is a son of bul!, of which union is born the monster Minotaur,
Ares, gocl of war. Kaclmos ancl the clragon engage who annually devours a tribute of living youths
in battle. Having killed the dragon, Kadmos sows and maidens.
Comment: This is the inverse of story 1, thus:
the dragon's teeth (a clomestic action appliecl to
wilcl m aterial ). The crop is men (the Spartoi) (a) Kadmos veTsion: Bul! (Zeus) carries away
without mothers. They kill one another, but the Europe, who has ahuman chilcl, Minos.
survivors coopera te with Kaclmos to found Thebes. Europe has ahuman brother, Kadmos, who
Kadmos makes peace with Ares and marries his is required to sacrifice a cow, sent from the
CLAUDE LÉVI-STRAUSS 80 The Structure of Myth 81
gods, and in the process he kills a monster cause of the treachery of the daughter, who loves
from whose remains come live human the enemy; but the victorious enemy then punishes
beings. But Kadmos is himself the monster. the daughter by desertion 01' murder. Thus:
(b) Minos version: Bull (Poseidon) cohabits (a) Minos is at war with Nisos, King of Megara,
with Pasiphae, who has a monster child, a descendant of the autochthonous Kekrops.
Minotaur. Pasiphae has ahuman husband, Nisos is preserved from death by a magic
Minos, who is required to sacrifice a bull, lock of hair. Skylla, daughter of Nisos, cuts
sent from the gods (which he fails to do). off the hair and presents it as a love token
The bull is replaced by a monster who con- to Minas. Minos kills Nisos but abandons
sumes human beings. But the monster = Skylla in disgust. Nisos is then turned into
Minotaur = Minos-Bull is himself Minas. a sea eagle in perpetual pursuit of his errant
In effect, the two stories have almost identical daughter in the form of another sea bird
"structures"; one story is con verted into the other (keiris ).
by "changing the signs" -Le., bulls become cows, (b) Perseus, son of Zeus by the human Danae,
brothers become husbands, and so on. is founder-King of Mycenae. The kingdom
The implication is the same as before. Again we passes to Perseus' son Alkaios and then to
have a polarity Gods : Men :: Wild : Tame :: Elektryon, brother of Alkaios, who engages
Monsters : Domestic Animals, with the Divine Bull in feud with Pterelaos, grandson of Nestor, ~
an ambiguous creature linking the two sides. Again another brother of Alkaios. Amphitryon, son , 'lf

sexual relations between gods and men and the of Alkaios, is betrothed to Alkmene, J

sacrifice of divine animals expresses the highly daughter of Elektryon (his father's brother).
equivocal alliance in which the friendship of the Elektryon gives Amphitryon the kingdom
gods is bought only at enormous cost. but binds him by oath not to sleep with
Alkmene until vengeance against Pterelaos 1
has been achieved.
3 / Theseus, Ariadne, and the Minotaur
In the course of the feud the sons of :¡
Story: Theseus, son of Poseidon by ahuman Pterelaos drive off Elektryon's cows and are 11

mother, is ranged against Minos, son of Zeus by a counterattacked by the sons of Elektryon.
human mother. Ariadne, daughter of Minos and One son from each side survives. Amphit-
Pasiphae (story 2), loves Theseus and betrays her ryon redeems the cattle but, as he is driving
father by means of a thread. Theseus kills the them home, one of the cows runs aside.
Minotaur and elopes with Ariadne but deserts her. Amphitryon flings a stick at the cow but the
C01J11nent: This is one of a group of closely re- stick hits Elektryon, who is killed. Pterelaos
lated stories in which a father 01' the father's double is, like Nisos, preserved from death by a
(here Minos-Minotaur) is killed by his enemy be- magic hair. Komaitho, daughter of Ptere-
The StTuctuTe of Myth 83
CLAUDE LÉVI-STRAUSS 82

laos, in love with Amphitryon, betrays her problem of exogamy ancl feud ("the overrating of
affinal relations" -treachery by the errant daughter
father [as in (a)]. Amphitryon kiUs Ptere-
laos but also kills Komaitho for her -and "the unclerrating of affinal relations"-
murder of the potential father-in-law by the poten-
treachery.
tial son-in-law).
Notice, first, that the killing of Elektryon on
account of an errant cow is metaphoric of the
killing of the other fathers on account of an errant 4 I Antiope, Zethos, and Amphion
daughteT, and, second, that in each case there is a
StoTY: Kaclmos is succeeded as King of Thebes,
clash of loyalties, since the daughter must betray
the father in seeking to gain a husband. In the first by a daughter's son, Pentheus, then by his
own son, polydoros, then by Labdakos, son of Poly-
first two cases (Theseus, Minos) the potential hus-
doros. Pentheus and Labdakos both be come sacri-
band rejects the sinful daughter, but in the third
fices to Dionysos-their womenfolk in a frenzy
case the "contradiction" is resolved by a duplication
of roles. Pterelaos is the double of Elektryon, mistake them for wilcl beasts and tear them to
Komaitho is the double of Alkmene. Amphitryon pieces. Laios, the next heir, is an infant, and the
throne is usurped by Lykos, Labdakos' mother's
kills both the fathers, but his killing of Komaitho
father's brother. Antiope, daughter of Nykteus, is
allows him to marry Alkmene.
brother's claughter to Lykos. She becomes pregnant
(c) Alkmene now becomes the prototype of the
faithful wife. Nevertheless she is faithless, by Zeus. Nykteus, clishonored, commits suicide,
,1
since she becomes the mother of Herakles and the duty of punishing Antiope for her liaison
as the result of sexual union with Zeus, falls on Lykos. Lykos and his wife, Dirke, capture
and imprison Antiope, but not before she has given
who had impersonated her husband Amphit-
birth to twins, Zethos (a warrior) and Amphion (a I
ryon. musicían), who as infants are exposed on a moun- L
tain and (like Oiclipus) rescued by shepherds. In .¡
These stories add up to a variation of Lévi-
due course the twins discover their mother and
Strauss' gene'ralization cited on page 69. The hero I!I
avenge themselves on Lykos and Dirke and reign
who is left on stage (Theseus in the. one case, 1'.
jointly in Thebes.
Herakles in the other) is the son of ahuman
mother by adivine father and therefore the oppo-
si te of the autochthonous beings (such as Kekrops)
Comment: This story combines features from
story 3 with those of the better-known Oiclipus
storíes (6 and 7 below). The role of Amphitryon
l
¡

who are born of the earth without reference to I 'H


in 3 (b) is taken over by Zeus. The suicide of
women. Yct Lévi-Strauss' formula still applies, ex-
Nykteus is, in effect, a slaying of the father-in-law
cept that the problem of incest ("the overrating of
by the son-in-law. Zethos ancl Amphion are sons of
blood relations") and parricide/fraticide ("the
Zeus by ahuman mother; their opponent, Lykos,
underrating of bloocl relations") is replacecl by the
!r
·1
CLAUDE LÉVI-STRAUSS 84 The Structure of Myth 85

is son oE the autochthonous Chthonios. In other of Minas, is wife to Theseus and step-mother' to
respects Antiope is a sort oE Antigone-Jokaste. Hippolytos. Phaidra falls in lave with Hippolytos,
Antiope, like Antigone, is imprisoned by her unde, who rejects her advances; Phaidra then accuses
but where Lykos is father's brother of Antiope, Hippolytos of having tried to rape her. In revenge
Kreon is mother's brother of Antigone. Amphion Theseus appeals to Poseidon to slay Hippolytos,
and Zethos resemble Oidipus in that they are ex- and Hippolytos dies. Phaidra commits suicide.
Theseus discovers his error and suffers remorse.
posed on a mountain in childhood and seize the
Cornrnent: This is very clase to being the inverse
throne after killing the king. But they kill the king
. after discovering their true parentage, whereas of the Oidipus story (7). Here the father kills the
Oidipus kills the king first. They al so resemble son instead of the son killing the father. The son
Eteokles and Polyneikes in that they are twins who does not sleep with the mother, though he is accused
of doing so. The mother commits suicide in both
both claim the throne, but they rule together in
amity, one as a warrior and one as a musician, cases; the surviving father-son suffers remorse in
both cases. It will be observed that the failure oE
whereas the Argives, both being warriors, kill one
another. Like Oidipus, Amphion and Zethos are Hippolytos to commit incest with his estep-) mother
"mediators" between the sky gods and the under- Phaidra has an even more negative outcome than
world in that their mother Antiope is in the line the actual ineest of Oidipus with Jokaste.
of Chthonios and their father is Zeus. Notice further that Phaidra is sister to Ariadne
So far as the succession principIe is concerned e story 3). The roles are now reversed. Ins tead of
Amphion and Zethos are the opposites of the the son-in-Iaw killing the father-in-Iaw because of
Spartoi. The Spartoi are the autochthonous sons of the treachery of the daughter, the father kills the
a Chthonian man-monster, Kadmos; Amphion and son because of the treachery of the mother.
Zethos are the sons of ahuman mother by a sky-
deity, Zeus. But the final outcome is disaster. Am- 6 / Laios, Chrysippos, and Jokaste
phion marries Niobe, by whom he has many chil-
dren, but Niobe boasts of her fertility and the Story: During the reign of Lykos, Amphion, and
Zethos, Laios goes into banishment and is be-
whole family is destroyed by the wrath of the gods.
Moral: Amity between brothers (Amphion-Ze- friended by Pelops. He falls in lave with Pelops'
thos) is ultimately no more fruitful than fratricide son, Chrysippos, whom he teaches to drive a
(Eteokles-Polyneikes) . chariot. After returning to the throne of Thebes he
marries Jokaste but avoids sleeping with her be-
eause of the prophecy that her son will kill him.
5 / Thesells, Phaiclra, ancl Hippolytos
The conception which results in the birth of Oidipus
')
Story: Hippolytos is the son of Theseus by follows a bout of lust when Laios has got drunk
Antiope, Queen of the Amazons. Phaidra, daughter at a religious feast. On the occasion when he en-
86 The Structure of Myth 87
CLAUDE LÉVI-STllAUSS

countered Oidipus "at the crossroads," Oidipus was punishment she is walled up alive in a tomb, where
she commits suicide. Later the sons of the dead
a "young man driving a chariot." •
Cornrnent: The myth establishes an equivalence heroes lead another expedition against Thebes and
between Chrysippos and Oidipus, and the incest are triumphant.
Cornrnent: Lévi-Strauss' own treatment of stories
between Oidipus and his mother is matched by
homosexual incest between Laios and his son. 7 and 8 in conjunction with story 1 has already
been given on pages 67-71.
7 / Oidipus It will be seen that if we proceed in this way there
never comes a point at which we can say that we have
Story: The lOng (Laios) and the Queen (Jokaste) considered "all the variants," for almost any story drawn
rule in Thebes. The son (Oidipus) is exposed on a from the general complex of classical Greek mythology
mountain with his ankles staked and thought to tums out to be a variant in one way or another. If, for
be dead. He survives. The son meets the King- example, we take as our central theme the Oidipus
father "at a crossroads" and kills him. The Queen's
complex as understood by Freud-the story of a son
brother (Kreon) acts as regent. Thebes is beset by who kills his father and then becomes the paramour
a monster (Sphinx: female). The Queen's hand in of his mother-we shall find that the fol!owing well-
marriage is offered to anyone who will get rid of known stories are all "variants." Thus:
the monster by answering its riddle. Oidipus does "
, ",

so. The monster commits suicide. The son assumes Oidipus: son kil!s father and becomes paramour.
al! aspects of the deceased father's roleo On dis- Agarnernnon: paramour kills father inviting venge-
covery, the Queen commits suicide; son-King (Oidi- ance from the son.
pus) blinds himself and becomes a seer (acquires Odysseus: father merges with son and destroys the
supernatural sight). would-be paramours. Odysseus has no descendants.
Menelaos: paramour (P aris) is destroyed by a third
8 / Argives (Antigone, Eteokles, and Polyneikes) party and there is no heir (son).
Hippolytos (story 5): innocent son, falsely accused
Story: Oidipus has two sons, Eteokles and Poly- of being paramour, is killed by father.
neikes, who are also his half-brothers, since they ;1

are sons of Jokaste. Oidipus having abdicated, What emerges from such a comparison is that each

Eteokles and Polyneikes are supposed to hold the story is seen to be a combination of relational themes, I~I I
throne alternately. Eteokles takes the throne first that each theme is one of a set of variations, and that ¡
I

I
and refuses to give it up; Polyneikes is banished what is significant about these relational themes is the 1,

~I
and leads an army of heroes from Argos against contrast between the variations. l.

Thebes. The expedition fails. Eteokles and Poly- The message contained in the whole set of stories-
neikes kill each other. Antigone, in defiance of the ones 1 have spelled out at some length and the ones
Kreon, performs funeral rites over Polyneikes. In I have mentioned only by title-cannot readily be put
·--- •••••••

The Structure of Myth I 89


e L A U DEL É v 1- S T H A U S s I 88 ..' -~U
,.
~.~
_

into words; otherwise there would be no need for such and sexual misdemeanor. In Lévi-Strauss' own examples ¡,.
circumlocution. But, roughly, what it amounts to is these ultimate confiicts are usually transformed into a
simple enough: if society is to go on, daughters must language code of some other kind.
be disloyal to their parents and son s must destroy (re- For example, in his American case material many of
place) their fathers.8 the most perceptive of Lévi-Strauss' comparisons derive
Here then is the irresolvable unwelcome contradic- from analogies between eating and sexual intercourse.
tion, the necessary fact that we hide from consciousness Clase paraIlels are not easily found in classical my-
because its implications run directly counter to the thology, but the stories relating to the ancestry of Zeus,
fundamentals of human morality. There are no heroes which are themselves in certain respects duplicates of
in these stories; they are simply epics of unavoidable the Oidipus myth, wiIl serve as a partial illustration:
human disaster. The disaster always originates in the
Gaea, Earth, first produces Uranos, Heaven, by spon-
circumstances that ahuman being fails to fulfill his or
taneous generation. Then Uranos copulates with his
her proper obligations toward a deity or a kinsman, and mother. She bears the Titans. Uranos, jealous of his
this, in part at least, is what Lévi-Strauss is getting at sons, thrusts them back into the body of their mother.
when he insists that the fundamental moral implication Gaea, unable to tolerate this state of permanent
of mythology is that "Hell is ourselves," which I take to gestation, arms the last of her sons, Kronos, with a
mean "self-interest is the source of all evil." sickle with which he castrates his father. The drops
But I must again remind the reader that this whole of blood faIl to earth and turn into the Furies, the
example is Leach imitating Lévi-Strauss and not a sum- Giants, and the Nymphs; the castrated member itself
mary of a Lévi-Strauss original. It has been necessary falls to the sea and is transformed into Aphrodite,
to go to this length in order to display the "theme and the goddess of love. Kronos then rules and is in turn
told that he will be overthrown by his son, but where
variations" aspects of a typical Lévi-Straussian analysis,
Laios tried to save himself by abstaining from hetero-
but in all other respects the material is thin and atypical.
sexual intercourse (story 6 above) Kronos indulges
There is a paucity of magical happenings and a monoto- himself but swaIlows his children as fast as they are
nous concentration on the bed-rock issues of homicide
born. When Zeus is born the mother, Rhea, gives
Kronos a phallic-shaped stone instead of the newborn
s Cf. Lévi-Strauss' own formula, cited on page 69. In my babe. Kronos then vomits up the stone along with
extended analysis Incest : Fratricide-Parricide : : Murder of
potential father-in-Iaw : Exogamy : : "born from one" : all the children previously consumed.
"born from two" : : Society in which there is no succession
(Odysseus) : Society in which there is succession (Oidipus). In this story, the ordinary act of sexual intercourse is
That the Odyssey has this static implication is confirmed by
consideration of a post-Homeric supplement which unsuc- transposed. Where in reality the male inserts a phallus
cessfully attempts to resolve the puzzle by splitting the into the female vagina and thereafter children are born
various roles: Telemachos, son of Odysseus and Penelope, through the vagina, in the myth the female inserts a
has a half-brother, Telegonos, son of Odysseus and Kirke;
Telegonos accidentally kills Odysseus and marries Penelope; phaIlus into the male mouth as a form of food and
Telemachos marries Kirke. thereafter the children are born through the mouth in
CLAUDE LÉVI-STRAUSS 90 The Structure of Myth 91
the form of vomit. A erude nursery imagery, no doubt, verse would be "an answer for whieh there was no
but in Lévi-Strauss' view this exemplifies a very general question." In the Oidipus stories disaster ensues beeause
principle-"In the language [plan] of myth vomit is someone answers the unanswerable question; in another
the eorrelative and inverse term to eoitus and defeea- class of myths of world-wide distribution, disaster ensues
tion' is the eorrelative and in verse term to auditory beeause someone fails to ask the answerable question.
communication" (Mythologiques II, p. 2Io)-and by Lévi-Strauss cites as examples the death of Buddha
the time he has finished with it, he has linked up this beeause Ananda failed to ask him to remain alive and
symbolism with modes of eooking, methods of making the disasters of the Fisher-King which are the eonse-
fire, ehanges in the seasons, the menstrual periods of quenee of Gawain-Pereival's failing to ask about the
young women, the diet of young mothers and elderly nature of the Holy Grail.
spinsters, and Lord knows what else. To discover just This kind of verbal juggling with the generalized
how one thing leads to another, however, the reader formula is quite typieal of Lévi-Strauss' hypothesis-
must pursue some inquiries on his own. Having started forming proeedure, but sueh methods eannot show us
at Mythologiques II (pp. 210-12), he will be led back the truth; they only lead into a world where all things
to various other Lévi-Straussian references, but notably are possible and nothing sure.
to Mythologiques 1 (p. 344) and "The Struetural Study
of Myth," from whieh we started out. The journey is
well worth while, though the traveler will not neces-
sarily be all that the wiser when he comes to the end
of it.
Let me say again that even among those who have
found it extremely rewarding to apply Lévy-Strauss' 1I
!,
structuralist techniques to the detailed study of particu-
lar bodies of ease material, there is widespread skepti-
cism about the reckless sweep with which he himself
is prepared to apply his generalizations. For example,
consider the following:
With regard to the riddle of the Sphinx, Lévi-Strauss
claims that it is in the nature of things that a mythical
riddle should have no answer. It is also in the nature of
things that a mother should not marry her own son.
Oidipus eontradicts nature by answering the riddle; he
also eontradiets nature by marrying his mother.
Now if we define a mythical riddle as "a question
which postulates that there is no answer" then the eon-
CLAUDE LÉVI-STRAUSS 100 WOTCIsand Things 101
municate with them by acoustic means recalling Now the names given to cattle belong to a different
articulated language. series from birds' or elogs'. They are generally de-
Conseguently everything objective conspires to make scriptive terms referring to the color of their coats,
us think of the bird world as a metaphorical human their bearing or temperament: "Rustaud," "Russet,"
society: is it not after a11 litera11y para11el to it on "Blanchette," "Douce," etc.; these names have a meta-
another level? There are countless examples in my- phorical character but they differ from the names
thology and folklore to indicate the freguency of this given to dogs in that they are epithets coming from
mode of representation. the syntagmatic chain while the latter come from
The position is exactly the reverse in the case of the paraeligmatic series; the former thus tend to
dogs. 'Not only do they not form an independent derive from speech, the latter from language. (The
society; as "domes tic" animals they are part of human Savage Mind, p. 206)
society, although with so low a place in it that we Here again, the Englishman is out of line, though he L.......\rf~.
should not elream of ... elesignating them in the does better when it comes to racehorses! The trouble is
same way as human beings .... On the contrary, we that Lévi-Strauss always wants to force his evidence
a110t them a special series: "Azor," "Méelor," "Sultan,"
into completely symmetrical molds:
"Fielo," "Diane" (the last of these is of course a
human christian name but in the first instance con- If therefore birds are metaphoTical human beings and
ceived as mythological). Nearly a11 these are like dogs metonymical human beings, cattle may be
stage names, forming a series para11el to the names thought of as metonymical inhuman beings and race-
people bear in ordinary life or, in other words, meta- horses as metaphoTical inhuman beings. Cattle are
phorical names. Conseguently when the relation contiguous only for want of similarity, racehorses
between (human and animal) species is socially similar only for want of contiguity. Each of these two
conceived as metaphorical, the relation between the categories offers the converse image of one of the two
respective systems of naming takes on a metonymical other categories, which themselves stand in the rela-
character; and when the relation between species is tion of inverted symmetry. (The Savage Mind, p. 207)
conceived as metonymical, the system of naming But supposing the English evielence doesn't really fit?
as sumes a metaphorical character. (The Savage Well, no matter, the English are an illogical lot of bar-
Mind,pp. 204, 205) barians in any case.
Don't misunderstand me. The Savage Mind taken as
The catch, of course, as any pet-Ioving Englishman or a whole is an entrancing book. The exploration of the
American will immediately recognize, is that these way we (primitives anel civilizeel alike) use elifferent
broad French generalizations do not holel up as soon as kinds of language for purposes of classification, and of
one crosses the Straits of Dover! A great many English the way that the categories which relate to social (cul-
dogs have names identical with those of their human tural) space are interwoven with the categories which
frienels. Be that as it may, Lévi-Strauss then goes on to relate to natural space is packed with immensely stimu-
make further learned generalizations about the names lating ideas. But you should not always believe what is
French farmers give their cows: said! When, for example, Lévi-Strauss claims that the
e L A U DEL É v 1- S T R A U S s 1 104

so that hearing and sight and smell and taste and


touch, etc., seem all to be giving the same message. The
problem then is simpl y to devise a means of breaking
the codeo Lévi-Strauss thinks he has solved this problem;
even those who have doubts can hardly fail to be
astonished by the ingenuity of the exercise.
1', The ninth chapter of La Pensée sau'Uage is of a differ-
ti
f' ent kind from the rest and I have already made some
II remarks about it (see pages 6-8). Here I will do no more
,1
\, than repeat that what Lévi-Strauss seems to be saying

-'1

<

11
is that Sartre attaches much too much importance to
the distinction between history, as a record of actual
events which occurred in a recorded historical sequence,

The Elementary Structures of Kinship

and myth, which simply reports that certain events


;/
1
occurred as in a dream, without special emphasis on
chronological sequence. History records structural trans-
formations diachronically over the centuries; ethnog-
raphy records structural transformations synchronically
across the continents. In either case the scientist, as
VI And so at last we come to Lévi-Strauss' con-
tributions to kinship theory. This is technical
observer, is able to record the possible permutations and
anthropological stuff, and readers who prefer a
combinations of an interrelated system of ideas and diet of souffié to suet pudding must mind their
behaviors. The intelligibility of the diachronic trans- digestion.
formations is no greater and no less than the intelligi- This part of Lévi-Strauss' work was mostly
bility of the synchronic transformations. By implícation, publíshed before 1949. I have ignored the
the only way to make sense of history would be to apply chronology because, in this area of study, I am
to it the method of myth analysis which Lévi-Strauss quite out of sympathy with Lévi-Strauss' posi-
has exhibited in his study of American mythology. tion, but I must now try to explain what the
Whether such an argument could possibly have any argument is all about. One long-establíshed
appeal to professional historians or philosophers of anthropological tradition, which goes back to the
history it is not for me to sayo Certainly it líes far off publícation of Morgan's Systems of Consan-
the beaten track of conventional anthropology, which
for nearly half a century has paid líttle attention either
guinity and Affinity of the Human
(1871), is to attach especial importance
Family
to the">"./.
,
to grand philosophy or to speculative interpretations of
way words are used to classify genealogically )) "
the nature of history. related individuals. Although there are thou-
So let us go back to some conventional anthropology. sands of different human languages, all kin-term
~'---:-'j
CLAUDE LÉVI-STRAUSS I 106 The ElementaTY StTuctUTes of Kinship 107 /-- t. r',,'/ f

f II~J.-..
v--
systems belong to one or other of about half a dozen and' not biological facts, and the two sets of data are vv"'" ¿/;./
"types." How should we explain this? Lévi-Strauss does often so widely discrepant that it is often convenient
not follow Morgan at aIl closely, but he assumes, as we to discuss kinship without any reference to biology, AIl
might expect, that any particular system of kin terms is the same, any action which is labeled "kinship behavior"
í a syntagm of the "system" of aIl possible systems, which must in the last analysis have some tenuous link with
Uis, in turn, a precipita te of a universal human psy- biology-it must trace back to the self-evident fact that
chology. This line of thought is consistent with the a mother is "related" to her own child and that brothers 1:'

"formal ethnography" of Lounsbury and others in the and sisters (siblings) of the same mother are related
United States,J but is quite incompatible with the posi- to one another,
I tion of most British functionalist anthropologists. If Most kinship facts present themselves to the field
'.pressed, the latter will argue that the different major anthropologist in two ways. In the first place, as 1 have
-'i')·' types of kin-term system are a response to different
.,J . i i patterns of social organization rather than to any uni- said,
such hisas informants
father, mother,
use auncle,
~~shipaunt,
terminology-words
cousin, etc.-to :'/) l.
1
, ',:. 1" \,
1, l' . (. i\ "versa
/'. 1') attn 'b ute of' th e h uman mIn
. d
. s9.!~ out the people in their vicinity into sign.!ficant
,',,,'))" i / AIl the same, despite their contempt for kinship i:.?,~'ps; in the second place it emei-ges that !E_~!~_3\re ,
\:-",/

\/ .'
,) ,1: ..words, the functionalists attach great importance to
the study of kinship behavior. There is no mystery about
various sets of behaviors and attitudes which are con-o
si~~-d .espeéi~lly- ~pprop:date o~ in:~pproprÚte)ietween\c.:,
l)
this. Anthropologists are usuaIly observing human a~.Y,t":V<?:in9iviquals
deel11ed to be .r~lat~d in ap~~ti_~uEr
beings in situations where the facilities for transport w¿}-e.g., it may be 'said that aman should never
and communication are, by modern standards, very speak in the presence of his mother-in-law or that it I
.bad. Most of the individuals under study spend their would be a good thing if he were to marry a girl who
whole lives within a few miles of the locality in which faIls into the same kin-term class as his mother's

they were born, and in such circumstances most neigh- brother's daughter,
bors are biological kin. This do es not mean that the If we are trying to understand the day-to-day behavior
people con cerned wiIl always recognize one another as of people living in close face-to-face relationship, facts
kin or that they must inevitably attach special value to
ties of kinship, but they may do so, and the anthro- such as these are clearly of great s.!g!1jfLc.anc~and a
pologist's experience is that this is very likely. good deal of the l~~.!rªE.~hropo~? __
ª-~'.s,_r~,s.~~E:?.-''ti~eis --~,---?t}
_t~k.~J1.Ul?
with discovering Nsfhow theseS~~_?_.~~!l:~_~\ofí ~ ..
The general background of kinship theory lies out- x:.~e!~~~_~ the _~Y~!~!l1.?i::~:Y~~.!?,~~:~:~~~~~.5-~. the'
side the scope of this book, but there is one key point ..\ar.~..H1teF;Qg!,!~~~~~
¡~liystem of~~~~:'_lOral att~~~_d.~~, ~ut
which must be understood. When anthropologists talk ~A'or·the chau-borne 'anthropologrst, whether he be an In·
about kinship they are concerned with social behaviors experienced student or a senior professor, the data of
kinship offer delights of quite another kind,
1 See H. W. Scheffier, "Structuralism in Anthropology," in
Jacques Ehrmann, ed., StTuctll7'alis11l, a double issue of In its original context a kinship terminology is just
Yale FTench Studies, Nos. 36-37 (1966), pp. 75 ff. a part of a spoken language; nothing particular sepa-
CLAUDE LÉVI-STRAUSS I 108 The Elementary Stmctures of Kinship I 10g

rates kinship words from other words-indeed m6st 'My disagreement he re is basic. Lévi-Strauss has said
kinship words have non-kinship meanings. Here are somewhere that he considers that social anthropology is\
two examples: If you address someone as "Father'
, atral'concern
"branch of is
semiology," which would imply
with the internallogical that itsof cen-\.\\
structure the,¿>}; ,l T"il
O'Brien" you probably believe that he is both celibate
1
and childless, and in the English East Anglian dialect
the word "mother" used to mean an unmarried girlt matter
meaningsof social
of setsanthropology
of symbols. But
always
for me
remains
the real
the subjed~ e ¡=.;,:~;;t...~
actual )(1("
!l
However, if we ignore context and rely exclusively on social behavior of human beings. Whether or not kin- ·)i~::t'J·.J
orthodox dictionary definitions the words of any kin- ship nomenclatures can be regarded as "authentic ob- -
\:' ship' vocabulary can be treated as a closed set-the jects of scientific research" is perhaps a matter for
,:';11' elements of an algebraic matrix which refers exclusively
debate, but most emphatically the logical analysis of
these term systems cannot be used to determine
':.,\'\'\ /to genealogical connections. Once the words have been
\.~~,",'1",.'(,• isolated in this way the investigator is tempted to be- whether any particular body of documentary material
is or is not "reliable."
"~' ",\'~,: ¡' lieve that this set of terms is logically coherent, and
'\ '

u jf' " ", that other sets of terms, derived in a similar way from Anyway, despite these later tendencies, Lévi-Strauss'
main contribution to kinship theory has not been con-
, \) 'other languages, must have a comparable coherence.

(~).:\"_./ In this way the analysis of kinship terminologies be- cerned with the
the structure of trivialities
conventionalof rules
kin-term This ~''''''.:>
logic but with
of marriage. /)
work is of interest to all anthropologists even though
)'b \:the ground are related only as a tiresome and perhaps
its details are open to the same kind of objection as
(".
\ \ ).¡",.y~ misleading
\comes irrelevance.
an
end in itself, to which the original facts on
before-namely, that Lévi-Strauss is liable to become
\: \ \<,.;r In ~i.s earlier pap~rs, Lévi-Str.auss display~d a healthy
so fascinated by the logical perfection of the "systems") •......
;..
\i
I Dj'~J
T~
,
skeptiCIsm about thIS sort of thmg, but as hIS own field
experience recedes further into the background he has
become more and more obsessed with his search for
he is describíng that he disregards the empirical facts.//
The orthodox tradition of functional anthropology is
universals applicable to all humanity, and increasingly to start any discussion of kinship behavior with a refer-
contemptuous of the ethnographic evidence. In a recent ence to the elementary family. A child is related to both
paper he has remarked, with regard to the analysis of its parents by ties of filiation and to its brothers and
kinship terminologies: sisters by ties of siblingship. These links provide the
basic bricks out of which kinship systems are built up.
F. G. Lounsbury and 1. R. Buchler have pro ved that Other discriminations depend on whether or not either \
these nomenclatures manifest a kind of logical per- parent has children by another spouse, whether or not l', ¡ .., t.r

fection which makes them authentic objects of affinal kinship (established by m arriage ) is or is not
scientific study; this approach has also permitted treated as "the same" as kinship based in filiation and
Lounsbury to expose the unreliability of some of the siblingship, and so on.~
documentary material we are accustomed to handling
without ever questioning its value. ("The Future of 2 A. R. Radcliffe-Brown, Structure and Function in Primitive
Kinship Studies," p. 13) Society (Glencoe, m., 1952), p. SI.
CLAUDE LÉVI-STRAUSS 110
The Elementary Structures of Kinship I 111
, ;' Lévi-Strauss puts the emphasis elsewhere. Admittedly, relationships between me'mbers of A and members of e
y in the vast majority of societies, a child needs to have
.~ must in some sense be the "opposite of the relationships
'JLJ ~ two recognized parents before it can be accepted as a between members of B and the members of C.
~ \" fully legitimate member of society, but the legitimacy A complete analysis of this superficially simple situa-
,0l' , .of the child depends upon the relationship between the tion woulcl require consideration of a wide variety of
J parents rather than the relationship between the parents "types" of relationship-e.g., brother/brother, brother/
and the child. So Lévi-Strauss would claim that the
sister, husband/wife, father/son, father/daughter,
conventional analysis starts at lhe wrong place. mother/ son, mother/ daughter, mother's brother/ sister's
The ~verage young aclult is a member of a group of son, mother's sister/sister's son, mother's brother/sister's
siblings (A) and, as a consequence of marriage, will be

..
daughter, mother's sister/sister's daughter, father's
brought into a new (affinal) kind of relationship with sister/brother's son, father's brother/brother's son,
another group of siblings (B). (See Fig. 6) The relation- father's sister/brother's daughter, father's brother/
brother's claughter-ancl already the possible permuta-
+ / / + tions and combinations are enormous.
I I I I But Lévi-Strauss concentrates his attention on the

A
- • B ••
much more restricted set of alternatives available for
two pairs of oppositions-namely, the contrast between
brother/sister and husbancl/wife, on the one hand, and
that between father/son and mother's brother/sister's
I son on the other. Let us represent the alternatives
I I offerecl by the first opposition (X) by the words "mu-
tuality" (+) and "separation" (-), and the alternatives
.• e •
offered by the second opposition (Y) by the words
Figure 6 "familiarity" (+) and "respect" (-). Then we can
draw up a matrix of possibilities of the same kind as
that discussed on page 20. Thus in Figure 7, +/ _ in
ship of siblingship and the the relationship of affinity are Column X stands for "mutuality/separation," but +/_
thus structurally contrasted as: +/-. As a result of the in Column y stands for "familiarity/respect."
marriage, a third group of siblings (C) will be gener-
According to Lévi-Strauss' rather one-sided reading
ated, and this new group will be related to each of the of the ethnographic evidence all four possible combina-
previous groups, but how it will be related will clepend tions actually occur, and he claims, on grouncls which
on a variety of circumstances. All that one can say at do not seem very substantial, that this total system of
this stage is that if the system is one of unil-ineal descent, possibilities is a human universal: "this structure is the v"-/
eithe1' pat1'ilineal (C~ A) 01' mat1'ilineal (C~ B) then the most elementary form of kinship which can existo It ,/ .../ i
I

!/1/1:'''' ()::l.·(··
l\./ ¡.. ~, t' 1!
" .:',' >lo ••• \

,
A>, ...
CLAUDE son
---- -
+sister's
++
son
father/ + brother/
wife
brother/
sister
band/
(Tribal
Grollp) Y
LÉVI-STRAUSS hus-112 +
Siuai
Dobu
Cherkess
Tonga
The Elementary Structures of Kinship I 113
7 mother's
X
women,
."In and society
human not viceit versa,"
is the (Structural
men who Anthropology,
exchange the) \í{,.~J,l'
G u
p. 47)

To the nonanthropologist all this must seem highly


artificial, but for Lévi-Strauss it is a step in the direction
of making the study of apparently freakish custom a
problem for scientific investigation; or, to put it differ-
ently, it repres'ents the establishment of a generalization
fram diverse particulars.
In the history of anthropology the empirical facts
emerged the other way round. Lowie, in his early text-
book Primitive Society, gives a long series of examples
of the "avunculate," a term which he applies somewhat
indiscriminately to almost any special '~7lationship link- !jl
1,

ing a m~the(~ h~o!hé' with his siste(s son. a That such


' is properly speaking the unit of kinship," and he then
..
goes on to say that "in order for a kinship structure to special relationships existed in apparently random
!,!

:I / exist, three types of family relations must always be world-wide distribution has been known to ethnog-
\ ,,' raphers for nearly a hundred years and the most diverse
\ present: a relation of consanglliptty, a relation of
¡; ./ \affinity and a relation of descent." explanations have been offered to account for such
, ",
fñ my view, this argument is fallacious for a variety customs. Some of these explanations seem to fit very
"

:1

of reasons, the most important being that Lévi-Strauss well with particular sets of local factS,4 but the apparent 1,

merit of Lévi-Strauss' approach is that he offers a gen- ¡'


here confuses the notion of descent, a legal principIe
\, governing the transmission of rights from generation eral theory which should apply wherever there is any
\J ~" ~deology of unilineal descent.
>'~- f to generation, with the notion of filiation, the kinship
1; ;~

.y, ;'l' link between parent and child. It is the same kind of Unfortunately, we must at once draw a caveat. As
.,/ .~
confusion which leads him to suppose that the incest may be seen from Figure 7, Lévi-Strauss originally
\\i.>' taboo is simply the converse of exogamy. Another point offered six positive examples to illustrate his thesis, but "-'¿l.
'''-'., ," \ on which the argument appears vulnerable is that it is he never considers the possibility of negative cases 5; ,
~,
• I , ':(• ','; male-centered, but here Lévi-Strauss finds his J'ustifica- which do not fit his logical schema. Moreover, the argu- .---VI.'! (
t;¡ tion in the ethnography. He claims that his point of ment, as presented, presumes that unilineal descent " ~ ,l. ,) ,)
t.,L y\I . {
~J .. : ..
J Lo,' .,l,l. {l'
",\: departure, the transaction by which a sister changes her
./ \.1 ~ role to that of wife, is preferable to its inverse, the 3 R. H. Lowie, Primitive Society (New York, 1920), p. 78.
4 See Radcliffe-Brown, Structure and Function in Primitive
transaction by which a brother changes his role to that Society, Chapter 1; and J. Goody, "The Mother's Brother and
of husband, on empirical rather than logical grounds: the Sister's Son in West Africa." ]ournal of the Royal An-
thropological Institute, No. 89 (1959), pp. 61-88.
CLAUDE LÉVI-STRAUSS 114
... ' The Elementary Structures of Kinship I 115 f./"i7<!..
systems are universal, which is wholly untrue, and,:be- the difference many anthropologists get them confused."G (.- ....j ..
cause it is untrue, Lévi-Strauss' final grandiose ftourisB
The fact is that in all human societies of which we have Ij~-" ,t
-"the avuncular relationship, in its most general forro; .• '. detailed knowledge, the conventions governing sex re- S,';;, ¡u·Y
is nothing but a corollary, now covert, now explicit, lations are quite different from the conventions govern- rs: .I'D~,)J~·' I ,.1' J
of the universality of the incest taboo" (Structural
ing marriage, so there is no case for saying that in the :;.~,'1 ,.!~. f"'
Anthropology, p. 51) -seems to be reduced to nonsense. beginning the latter must have been derived from the (j
However that may be, Lévi-Strauss' major kinship former,
treatise, Les Stnlctures élémentaires de la parenté Once past this initial hurdle, Lévi-Strauss goes on to
(1949) is no more than an enormously elaborated and discuss the logical possibilities of systems of exchange
convoluted version of this general proposition, and it and then to consider certain rather specialized forms
suffers throughout from the same defects. Logical argu- of marriage regulation as examples of these logical
ments are illustrated by means of allegedly appropriate possibilities,
'\() ,..ethnographic evidence, but no attention whatever is The argument about exchange, as such, is pretty
¡. /, paid to the negative instances which seem to abound. much in line with Mauss' Essai sur le don (1924) and
i' ", • I The big book starts off with a very old-fashioned re- with the views of the British functionalists (for ex-
í ,'., view of "the incest problem" which brushes aside the
substantial evidence that there have been numerous ample, Firth), The conventions of gift-giving are in- ¿ IfT-
historical societies in which "normal" incest taboos did terpreted as symbolic expressions of something more (, I v>'l'H~
not prevaiL This allows Lévi-Strauss to follow Freud in
abstract, ~~twor~_~trel~ti~!2.~.!:I.~E~ .._~~ich.J!l!.k_s.,to- ~;~!:
....
y,i- • ¡
gether members orIbé society.!n quesu.0n. fli'é giving of (d •.i;.
___ ._w_. __ .. u_". ~ _. __ ..~
declaring that the incest taboo is the cornerstone of womeñ--íninarriage añd the consequent forging of a
human society. His own explanation of this allegedly special form of artificial kinship-that is to say, the
universal natural law depends upon a theory of social creation of the relationship between brothers-in-Iaw-
Darwinism similar to that favored by the English nine- is seen as simply a special case, an extension in the
teenth-century anthropologist Edward Tylor. The latter converse direction of the process whereby gifts of food
maintained that, in the course of evolution, human are habitually exchanged on ceremonial occasions to ex-
societies had the choice of giving their wo.menfolk away press the rights and obligations of existing ties of kin-
to create political alliances or of keeping their womoo- ship and affinity. In the jargon of Barthes' semiology,
folk to themselves and getting killed off by their nu- "gift exchange" constitutes a "system," a general lan-
merically superior enemies, In such circumstances, guage code for the expression of relationships. "Ex-
natural selection would operate in favor of societies en- change of women" is one system within that "system";
forcing rules of exogamy, which Tylor equated with the "exchange of valuable¡; other than women" is another.
converse of the incest taboo. So also does Lévi-Strauss, The routine sequence of exchanges which occurs in the
The error is rudimentary: "The distinction between in- context of a particular marriage in a particular society
cest and exogamy , , , is really only the difference be-
tween sex and marriage, and while every teenager knows "R. Fox, Kinship and Marriage (London, 1967), p. 54.

(l" I u/.

' . , {.' I~ !.,'.
• J J
I -'.'
.... - I'
" I ¡) ¡' ~ y.
!'-! •.j' .... ".
,.' P" 1.1 I -. e.. 1'" T'l
1,. (; .7'
r
u." . ,
J\..'
{,O

ll, r( .'! ',/'.,..~\. \ • ~ / I I ,. f" J J ." J ' I ;'\


"1 f ~ " f•• , ( .) . o{ f!
~
r. e t.? .l t.
I¡f'
t (.0, f '(;. j. f"4 ~. !! ,~ ');
~

CLAUDE LÉV1-STRAUSS II6 Th~ Elementary Structures of Kinship II7

is a syntagm of the "system." The methoclology b: societi.es (e.g., Congo Pygmies and Kalahari Bushmen)
not have systems of unilineal descent.
breaking the cocle is the same as that which has beeJl '.dQ

clescribecl in earlier chapters. The marriage.~y,stems However, let me try to expound Lévi-Strauss' thesis.
....----..,.".of
--
clifferent".§OGi~ties
--.--, ' ..
are '" treatecl-'as
".
...... ,,
' " ,."

paraclign.!~tic;;trans-
formations of an unclerlying common logical structure.
. ----...
First let us consider Figure 8 as an elaborated form of
Figure 6 (page 110) in which two unilineal descent
Ho;;~~~r,' Lévi~Strauss cloes not regarcl ~ar~i~ge(i.e .• groups are represented as three generations of sibling
the exchange' of women between men) as just one pairs: Al, A2, A3 on the one hand, and Bl, B2, B3 on
alternative system of exchange among many; it is the other. Let us suppose that Al and Bl are allied by
primary. He claims that because, in the case of women. marriage, either because the Al male is married to the
-:.h
-- th~ relationship symbolized by the exchange is also Bl female 01' vice versa, 01' because both of these
constituted by the thing exchanged, the relationship marriages have taken place. Then, in the jargon of
and its symbol are one and the same, and the giving anthropology, the B2 siblings are classificatory first
\ Ix.. of women in marriage must be considered the most cross-cousins of the A2 siblings, while the B3 siblings
elementary of all forms of exchange. It must be deemed are classificatory second cross-cousinsG of the A3 sib-
C)U'·\
c' ¡tJ >-., to have preceded (in evolution) the exchange of goods, lings. Lévi-Strauss first of all considers various kinds of
!> \. \,
\,"y
i' j, where the sign and the relationship that is signifiecl are hypothetical marriage conventions which would have
.~.,, .•1,¡.,,/ distinct. the effect of perpetuating an alliance between the A
., •
( ;1.' \"
As with the case of the earlier avunculate argument, group and the B group once it had been established.
Lévi-Strauss' discussion of marriage rules in Les Struc-
tures élémentaires de la parenté (1949) was distorted Lineage A Lineage B
by his erroneous belief that the great majority of primi- I I I I
tive societies have systems of unilineal descent By now
• Al ..A x • BI ••.
he has come to realize that this was a mistake, and there
is an interesting contrast between pages 135-36 of the I . unl I I
first edition and pages 123-24 of its 1967 successor. In • B2 ••
• A2 .•
the latter he weakly concludes: "Nevertheless, since
this book is limited to a consideration of elementary I I I I
structures, we consider it is justifiable to leave proví- • A3 •••. • B3 •.
sionally on one side examples which relate to undiffer'
Figure 8
entiated filiation." [!] Incidentally, as time goes on, it
becomes increasingly difficult to understand just what
Lévi-Strauss really means by "elementary structures." A crass-causin is a causin af the type "mother's brother's
ti

child" al' "father's sister's child" as distinct fram a parallel


The reader nceds to appreciate that the great majority causin, wha is a causin af the type "mather's sister's child"
of what are usually considered to be "ultraprimitive" al' "father's brather's child."
CLAUDE LÉVI-STRAUSS 118 .' The Elementary Structures of Kinship II9

If, for example, the exchange were directly r~cipr~31, that systems of the first type will tend to evolve into the
so that the A males always exchanged sisters with the' "second type, rather than vice versa, or alternatively that
B males, this would be the equivalent of a marriage rule harmonic systems of "restricted exchange" provide the
expressing preference for marriage with a mother's base from which have emerged harmonic systems of
brother's daughter or a father's sister's daughter. But a "generalized exchange." These terms need further ex-
different kind of over-all political structure would result planation.
if the rules required an exchange of sisters with a Lévi-Strauss classes all varieties of directly reciprocal
second cousin, so that, for example, aman marries bis sister exchange as falling into one major category
mother~s mother's brother's daughter's daughter or bis échange restreint (restricted exchange) which he dis-
mother's father's sister's daughter's daughter. tinguishes from his other major category échange
As a further complication he suggests that very simple généralisé (generalized exchange). In res tricted ex-
organizations of this kind can be usefully distinguished change, so the argument goes, aman gives away a sister
as "harmonic" or "disharmonic." He recognizes only two only if he has a positive assurance that he will get back
types of descent-patrilineal and matrilineal-and two a wife; in generalized exchange he gives away his sister
types of residence-virilocal and uxorilocal. (In anthro- to one group but gambles that he will be able to get
pological jargon a virilocal residence rule requires a back a wife from some other group. The poli tic al alli-
wife to join her husband on marriage, an uxorilocal rule ance is widened-the individual gets two brothers-in-
requires a husband to join his wife.) Systems which are law where previously he had only one-but the risks
patrilineal-virilocal or matrilineal-uxorilocal are har- are greater. Asymmetrical arrangements of this kind
monic; systems which are patrilineal-uxorilocal or are equivalent to marriage rules in which marriage
matrilineal-virilocal are disharmonic. with one cross-cousin is approved and marriage with
All these arguments are highly theoretical. By some the other forbidden, e.g.:
stretching of the evidence some parts of the discussion
can be illustrated by ethnographic facts which have been mother's brother's daughter
approved but
reported of the Australian Aborigines, but the latter are father's sister's daughter maniage rule"
in no sense typical of primitive societies in other parts forbidden ] "matrilateral cross-cousin
of the world, and there is no justification for Lévi-
Strauss' apparent postulate that once upon a time all father's sister's daughter
approved but
ultraprimitive human societies operated in accordance mother's brother's daughter marriage rule"
with an Australian structural model. On the contrary, forbidden 1 "patriLHeral cross-cousin
there are good grounds for supposing that they did not.
However, for what it is worth, Lévi-Strauss maintains, Rules of the second kind have just the same practical
on logical grounds, that harmonic structures are un- consequence as rules based on a reciprocal exchange of
stable and that disharmonic structures are stable, so sisters, so they are of no serious interest, though Lévi-
e L A U DEL É v 1- S T R A U S S 120 The Elementary Structures of Kinship I 121

Stiauss devotes much attention to their aIleged óccur- Either the X group give their sisters to the Z group
rence and they have been the source of much anthro- .direct, 01' else through several intermediary groups of
pological argument. Rules of the first type ("matrilateral similar kind: in any event the women whom the Zs
cross-cousin marriage") are much more common, and' e take in as wives are the equivalents of the women whom
though Lévi-Strauss was by no means the first person the Xs give away as sisters.
to bring them into serious discussion, he did manage Lévi-Strauss recognizes that the difficulties in the
to make a number of theoretical observations which
proved te)be of considerable practical significance. way of maintaining such a system of "circulating con- I ~ (j
nubium" for any length of time must be very consider- a'lc:ll~e
A matrilateral cross-cousin marriage rule, if it were able, and he claims that, in practice, the marriage 1.,J(J (
strictly enforced, would produce a chain of lineages in circles will always break down into hierarchies such ;:;1.(:' y ,
a permanent affinal alliance of wife givers and wife that the intermarrying lineages wiIl be of different (v;~/<' e'
, .
receivers (Figure 9). status. The resulting marriage system would then be .,~;;; .-
hypergamous, with the groups at the top receiving .1",.:,,!~t>!¡): ~

y z women as tribute from their social inferiors. "'{;,


--
_~:~ ..
~~.I
x
Starting out on this fragile base, échange généralisé ti oo."'"
I---~ ,-
•,--- -1
.....=. A= •.•.
I is then developed into a principIe which explains the
evolution of egalitarian primitive society into a hier-
archical society of castes and classes.
I ------¡ I I I I Thus reduced, the theory sounds preposterous, and
• A.=. A=. A even when presented at fulllength it is still open to all I
kinds of criticism of the most destructive sort, and yet
I H~ I I r-- ---- 1
there is an odd kind of fit between some parts of the / j I
• A=. .....
=. A theory and some of the facts on the ground, even ..,j''¡" ~t:
Figure 9 though, at times, the facts on the ground perversely
turn Lévi-Strauss' argument back to front! For example,
the systems in which hypergamous hierarchy is carried
Such diagrams seem to contain a paradox: where will to the wildest extremes are associated with dowry rather
the men of Group Z get their wives? Where will the than bride-price, while the systems in which matrilateral
sisters of the men of Group X find their husbands? cross-cousin marriage is the rule mostly take the form
Lévi-Strauss discusses this puzzle at enormous length. in which the wife givers rank higher than the wife
Any summary of the argument, let alone of the rival receivers.7
arguments produced by other authors, would be pre-
posterously misleading, but perhaps the heart of the 'In the 1967 and 1969 editions of his book Lévi-Strauss 1 ••.

attempted to mask the fact that he had ever made this I


matter is this: the system illustrated in Figure 9, as it ethnographic error but the resulting patchwork in his text
works out in practice, must be in some sense circular. only leads to inconsistency. See Leach (1969).
CLAUDE LÉV1-STRAUSS
122
~ . , The Elementary Structmes of Kinship

. . someone else by making a speech utterance, 1 do not


123

Lévi-Strauss himself seems inclined to argue that if.•


there are any ethnographic facts which are consistf¡lnt deprive myself of anything at a11; having shared my
information with one lis tener 1 can repeat the operation
with his general theory, then this alone is sufficient to • and share it with another.
prove that, in its basic essentials, the general theory is
Certainly there is some kind of analogy between the
right, but even his most devoted fo11owers could hardly
two frames of reference-a collectivity of lineages
accept that kind of proposition.
Elsewhere Lévi-Strauss has claimed that the superi- which intermarry forms a "kinship community" in a
sense which is, up to a point, comparable with the
ority of his method is demonstrated by the fact that a
vast multiplicity of types and subtypes of human society "speech community" formed by any collectivity of indi-
is here reduced to "a few basic and meaningful princi- viduals who habitua11y converse with one another. But,
as Lévi-Strauss himself has pointed out in a different
pIes" (Mythologiques 1, p. 127), but he fails to point out
that the vast majority of human societies are not covered context, the concept
r~~o.~rces-is of !!!::.~tl1~lit'y-of
in important respects diametrically op- /fiJ)
sharing cº,~rrlOn ~
by his basic and meaningful principIes at a11!Moreover,
there seems to be a major fa11acy at the very root of his posed to the concept of recipTociYi-the exchange of
argument. According to Lévi-Strauss we need to think of di~~i.!lc::tbut :equivalent resoúr'ces.¡ (Structural Anthro-
pology, p. 49)
marriage rules and kinship systems as a sort of However, irrespective of the merits of the particular
case, the reader should note that Lévi-Strauss' over-all
1_ ~ .•. language that is to say a set of operations designed procedure for the analyses of marriage alliances is just
-./ (' r d to insure, between individuals and groups, a certain the same as that which we have discussed elsewhere
, ¡l< l' ( , ,,' ..{ í, type of communication. The fact that the "message"
_".~~,).'I ' would here be constituted by the women of the group in the context of myth and totemism and the categories
of cooking. He treats the possible preferences for mar-
.,~'? }"J 11 who ciTCtLlate between clans, lineages or families
L "Ir " (and not, as in the case of language itself, by the riage with a cousin of such and such a category as
J Í' )l'l\¡ .!¡lv ,- words of the group circulating between individuals) forming a set of logical alternatives, adherence to
l.,;,~: . /' in no way alters the fact that the phenomenon con- which will result in different over-all patterns of social
1;'" ,,'''' ¡'- sidered in the two cases is identica11y the same. solidarity within the total society. These different kin- /4'/1 dLJP
y¡v .;; 1; i' (Anthropologie structurale, p. 69; cf. Stmctural An- ship systems, superimposed, constitute a set of para- ';>,/"';
thropology, p. 61, where a different and much less
literal translation is offered) digms e in the sense discussed on pages 48-50) which ·.9 i,/., ••L-
are manifested ea) in sets of kinship terms and (b) in e·,·, /V"'''''f (

But of course, there is no such identity. If 1 give an institutions of marriage and exchange. Taken a11 tO-c2)f~ f:t, j
gether the paradigms will provide us with clues as tO(iY)k¡.,'.'(
object into the possession of someone else, 1 no longer
the internalized structurallogic of the human mind ... j}~·, ~ '
possess it myself. Possibly 1 sha11 gain something else
The argument is systematic: first we consider so- <." "'Ie
in exchange and possibly 1 retain some residual c1aim
on the original object, but 1 have limited my previous cieties with two intermarrying groups, then four, then
eight, then a sequence of more complex asymmetrical
rights. If, on the other hand, 1 transmit a message to
e L A U DEL É v 1 - S T R A U S Sil 24

types. It is all so elegantly done that even the most


skeptical professional may find some difficulty in de-
tecting the precise point at which the argument runs
off at a tangent. In my view the end product is in large
measure fallacious, but even the study of fallacies can
prove rewarding.

••
Machines for the Suppression of Time

VII Let us go back to the beginning and try to pull


the argument together. Lévi-Strauss' quest is to
establish facts which are universally true of the
"human mind" (esprit humain). What is uni-
versally true must be natural, but this is para-
doxical because he starts out with the assumption
that what distinguishes the human being from
the man-animal is the distinction between cul-
ture and nature-Le., that the humanity of man
is that which is non-natural. Again and again in
Lévi-Strauss' writings we keep coming back to
this point: the problem is not merely "in what
way is culture (as an attribute of humanity)
distinguishable from nature (as an attribute of
man)?" but also "in what way is the culture of
Homo sapiens inseparable from the nature
of humanity?"
Lévi-Strauss takes over from Freud the idea

--------- ...------------

S-ar putea să vă placă și