Sunteți pe pagina 1din 11

Articles

http://home.earthlink.net/~hsbecker/articles/values.html

Confusions of Value Discussing the French art market of the 50s and 60s, Raymonde Moulin observed, not quite in so many words, that well-developed art markets invariably and necessarily make it difficult, perhaps impossible, for their members to distinguisheconomic from aesthetic value. In a characteristic statement, she says: Le spculateur fait deux paris, troitement solidaires lun de lautre court terme, lun sur la valeur esthtique, lautre sur la valeur conomique des uvres quil achte, chacune des deux valeurs devant garantir lautre. Gagner ce double pari, cest la fois saffirmer comme sujet conomique et sujet culturel. (Moulin, 1967, p. 219.) Although she gives us a detailed gallery of kinds of collectorsincluding le rudit, le dcouvreur, le snob, and le spculateurand an equally detailed list of motives for collectingla singularit, lamour, le jeu, la culture, le sacr, and largentshe eventually summarizes the latter as leading to rational or irrational conduct, the two coinciding to a great degree with economic or aesthetic motives. I dont intend to engage in an explication du texte de Moulin, tempting as that is with a text so rich , but rather to use her remarks as the provocation for further exploration of the phenomenon she draws our attention to. Shared Economic Values Shared economic values form the basis of the economic activity that underlies, in one form or another, all societies. Every society constructs ways of exchanging goods and services, and most develop some sort of standard for determining what constitutes a fair exchange. The most common solution to this prohblem, the one that pervades all modern societies (though it is never the only one, even in such societies) is to develop a money system. By creating a standard unit, in which all objects and services can be valued, we make possible the complicated economic activities that underlie our daily lives: the purchases and sales, borrowings and lendings, and all the rest of it. Art markets operate, in some large part, on the basis of such systems of economic value. Insofar as they are actually markets, they are arenas in which objects are bought and sold on the basis of value expressed in universal, neutral monetary units: dollars, francs, pounds, yen. The exchanges take place in institutions organized for the purpose: in stores (called galleries) and, most usefully for Moulins work because their operations and prices are public, auctions (cf. Smith 1989). These institutions operate on the basis of rules mutually agreed on, or at least accepted, and understood by all participants. Shared Aesthetic Values People create aesthetic value by collectively recognizing some works of art as having it. It is the beauty that I recognize, and simultaneously know that you and other knowledgeable people recognize, that matters in an art world. One can imagine a purely private aesthetic standard. In fact, we need not imagine it. We all have such standards and such preferences. We like things others dont like, and they like things we dont like. Our likes and dislikes of a quasi-aesthetic kind may stem from personal experiences not commonly shared, so that we are fond, like Roland Barthes (1980) as he contemplated the image of his mother, of a photograph of a beloved relative or friend because it reminds us of that person. Objects have all sorts of private meanings that give them great emotional and, we might say, aesthetic valuebut to us alone, not to others to whom they are simply peculiar tchotchkes. (see the

1 de 11

01/09/2012 17:08

Articles

http://home.earthlink.net/~hsbecker/articles/values.html

investigations of Csikszentmihalyi and Rochberg-Halton (1981) on the meanings of household objects). Shared aesthetic standards matter more than those which are private and idiosyncratic because, like other shared beliefs, like the economic rules just discussed, they create the basis for collective action. If we agree on standards, we can agree more easily on what to do in situations in which we have agreed to be governed by those standards. We can act quickly, relying on others to react to our actions in ways we anticipate just because they share those aesthetic judgments. If we all agree on what criteria mark a good painting, then we can admire each others judgment as exhibited in a collection, agree to help finance work of a certain kind, and engage in all the other forms of collective action that make up the routine doings of an art world. If we operate solely with privatized aesthetic standards, we cant act in a coherent or coordinated way with others. Aesthetic rules operate in institutions which define themselves as artistic, as organizations which engage in activities that encourage art or make art possible. In such organizations, aesthetic judgments are paramount and override other considerations. Or, at least, thats the story their participants tell about themselves. Museums say that they choose what to acquire and exhibit on the basis of aesthetic standards, choosing what is most beautiful or most expressive. Or, as Moulin points out, what most exhibits the trend of art history, what has been important to that history, what is important to it now, what will be important in the future: Leurs [les marchands des uvres consacrs] choix artistiques peuvent sappuyer sur la slection dj opr par lhistoire. (Moulin, 1967, p. 100, see also pp. 430-1) Blurred Values To repeat, Moulins key finding is that, in a well-developed art market, none of the actors involved can accurately and consistently distinguish aesthetic from financial value when they judge works of art. I do not mean by this, nor did Moulin mean, that the two systems of value are in conflict. Things are more confused than that. Sociologists say that value conflict occurs when the behavior recommended by one set of values is simultaneously condemned by another set of values. In the classic textbook example, the businessman goes to church on Sunday and learns the value of charity, and on Monday returns to work to practice the value of acquisition and forgets all about the charity. But that example is also one of how temporal or spatial segregation can solve a problem of value conflict. If you can keep the two injunctions in separate situations, so that you never have to obey both of them at once, the conflict is only hypothetical. The trouble starts when they operate in the same place at the same time with respect to the same actions. Moulin meant something more complex than having to serve two masters, hoping not to get caught with both of them in the room at the same time. She alerted us to at least two further consequences of the chronic confusion of aesthetic and financial value in art worlds. The two values may not conflict. In pursuing one you may simultaneously, and without difficulty, pursue the other. Which seems like a fine thing. But it may be, further, that one set of values has a low reputation. People prefer not to be thought to be pursuing that particular goal and would rather be thought to be pursuing the second. Although one would like to appear to be pursuing just the one, that isnt possible. One might even, and in many worlds certainly would, prefer to think about oneself that way, not just create the appearance. Because people are jealous of their self-regard. This is the case with the market in paintings. If a painting is thought aesthetically worthwhile, it is because people who are in a position to knowconnoisseursthink it is more beautiful, more expressive, more whatever it is that their aesthetic system prizes, than most other works. Not only that, it is a unique expression. There will never be another just like it. So it is rare in the nth degree: it is unique. And it is one of a relatively small number of works that have this quality of unique expression, so it is rare, too, by belonging to a class of objects of which there are very few. Even if another is just as good, so that there are many objects with this sort of unique quality and thus substitutability is possible, the class of possible substitutions is very small and, in practice, substitutions seldom occur. (Moulin 1978; 1992, 15-18)

2 de 11

01/09/2012 17:08

Articles

http://home.earthlink.net/~hsbecker/articles/values.html

If something is rare or unique in this way and people want it, it is almost certain, in a market economy, that the ownership will be settled by purchase and, if it is highly valued, by competition among buyers, which will raise the price, the auction being the most visible example of this process. Thus, aesthetic value (the process repeats itself at less rarefied levels, as Moulin explains in her discussion of lesser markets (Moulin 1978; 1992, 34-43)) is mirrored in market value. If an object is beautiful, and standards of beauty are shared (as they must be if there is an art world at all), then price will accurately reflect aesthetic worth. (Heinich, 1991, pp. 149-167, adds considerably to the complexity of this relationship, in her discussion of the enormous prices paid for the works of Van Gogh in recent years.) Turn this equation around. If an art work is very valuable, it must be because knowledgeable actors in the art world think it very beautiful (or whatever they value, letting beauty stand for whatever is taken to be the aesthetic sine qua non). The object has to be beautiful. The aesthetic value accurately reflects the financial. It is often observed that a valuable object has a kind of aura that comes from it being worth so much. Looking at a painting that has just been sold for several million dollars inevitably produces, in people who accept the values of the world in which the transaction occured, an awareness of a special something. It is something, though not exactly, like looking at the money itself, as if several million dollars in banknotes lay before you. Not exactly, because the object is not only the banknotes, it is that rare something worth all those notes. So actors in the art world in which these transactions occur are fundamentally and irremediably confused. They do not, and cannot, know whether the objects around which their world is organized are beautiful or valuable. Why should they worry? If the two coincide, so much the better. Unfortunately not, because the financial motive has a bad reputation in the art world. No one wants to be thought to be acting from such motives. And with good reason. If I am in a position to profit from my judgment, I may be tempted to make the judgment that will profit me rather than the one toward which the standards we all subscribe to impel me. The Personal Problem I can, as an individual member of an art world, worry that this possibility will show itself in my own actions. Suppose I am a critic. Among the tasks I set myself is to find, before others do (thus demonstrating my superior connoiseurship), artists who have already or will soon produce rare works of artistic genius. Suppose further that I am successful in this, and find a few such people other knowledgeable members of the world have overlooked. At the moment, these artists, unknown and without reputation, cannot sell their work for much. No one wants it. But I see that their work is beautiful and expressive, sitting precisely on what will eventually be the main line of the history of painting. I enjoy it for just those qualities. I want these paintings for their intrinsic artistic value. Furthermore, since these painters cannot sell their work, by buying paintings from them I help them out financially. With what I have paid them they can pay the rent, buy food and clothing, buy more supplies with which to make more paintings. Even further, if I (who am a well-known critic) buy their work, this will vouch for its value to other, more timid buyers. Seeing the work in my collection, they will be more willing to take a chance and buy from those artists too. Just at this point, if I am a conscientious member of this world, I begin to have moral qualms. If this happensif others buy work whose artistic value I have recognized ahead of the mobthen the value of the paintings I bought for a few francs will go up. By expressing my critical judgment in the act of buying, I have lined my own pocket. And there is no way I can do the good things I would like to doown beautiful works, help struggling artists without running the risk of being thought to have done them, and the feeling that perhaps I actually havedone them, for low financial motives. The Organizational Problem

3 de 11

01/09/2012 17:08

Articles

http://home.earthlink.net/~hsbecker/articles/values.html

Thats the personal problem. But every personal problem, as sociologists as various as C. Wright Mills and Everett C. Hughes have noted, has an organizational counterpart. If, Mills says, I am depressed because I have no job, that personal problem is the individual version of the whole societys problem of not being able to provide employment for all willing workers. If, Hughes says, the society has created standards for a social status which lead to a contradictionif we expect doctors to be male and white and then allow women or blacks to become doctorsthe women and blacks who have become doctors will experience this as a personal dilemma, as will the patients with whom they come in contact. (Hughes 1984, 141-150) The organizational problem that corresponds to the personal problem of being unable to tell if I am acting from good or bad motives when I acquire works of art is one of trust. If, as members of the art world, we ordinarily assign the responsibility for judgments of aesthetic worth to experts, we expect those experts to act in a disinterested way on behalf of the standards we all share. We expect them to decide that this work is good and that one not so good because the accumulated weight of their knowledge, experience, and sensibility lead them to that judgment. We particularly want to know that they have not made those judgments because it will be financially profitable for them personally or for the institutions they represent. This is perhaps most glaringly a problem with respect to the problem of attribution (Moulin 1992, 18-21). We often have trouble knowing with certainty who painted a particular work, and the decision about that has consequences for the price of the work. A painting by Rembrandt himself is much more valuable than one from the studio or school of Rembrandt (Alpers 1988). The great critic-connoiseurs of the 19th and early 20th centuries made their reputations by pronouncing on such questions, relying in part on their scholarly studies of details of an artists style and partly on a less describable sensibility, an indefinable ability to know that this was a real Titian as opposed to that one which only looks like the real thing. But such connoiseurs often worked closely with dealers, especially dealers who were selling to gullible American millionaires, and there is reason to think that the prospect of a sale would sometimes affect a critical judgment about an attribution. Nor need we prove that such things actually happened. It is enough to know that it could happen for the problem to become an organizational one. In the speculative market for contemporary art (as opposed to the blue chip market in established Old and Modern Masters, to use Moulins important distinction) the problem of attribution is not relevant. But the problem of aesthetic value is. Did this curator choose to have this exhibit because it would enhance the value of his own holdings in the work of that artist or group? Did the curator collaborate with a dealer in assembling this exhibit, knowing that by thus enriching the dealer he would be arranging for the return of a similar favor another day? Collaborations between musuem staff and gallery owners in the organization of exhibits is common and is not in itself frowned on. But it raises these questions, questions to which, because of the confluence of values Moulin described, no one know the answers. The problem is so chronic and so perplexing that it has occasionally led to quixotic acts of self-denial. Thus, the story of Dennis Adrian, a well known critic and adviser to a group of affluent Chicagoans with advanced artistic tastes. (Perhaps I will be forgiven so provincial an example. It is one to which I had better access than many other well-known events.)* The Adrian Gift Dennis Adrian early recognized the artistic gifts of a group of Chicago artists who came to be known first as The Hairy Who and later, more respectably, as the Chicago Imagists. Among the artists involved were Roger Brown, Jim Nutt, Ed Paschke, and others, now well-known , collected, and exhibited internationally. As a result of Adrians championing of their work, and of the concurrent activities of the art critic of a major Chicago newspaper (Franz Schulze of the Chicago Sun-Times), a local gallery owner (Phyliss Kind), and the collectors already mentioned (some of whom were active in the newly formed Chicago Museum of Contemporary Art), whom Adrian advised on their art acquisitions, the work of this group came to be widely exhibited and collected, and consequently rose substantially in

4 de 11

01/09/2012 17:08

Articles

http://home.earthlink.net/~hsbecker/articles/values.html

value. Adrian was quite poor: I have had to form a collection with what are, not to put too fine a point on it, rather less than average means (Adrian 1982, p. 7). He lived simply, had no steady employment (trying to exist as a critic and teacher of art history ibid.), did not deal in pictures privately as so many such critics and advisers do. But Adrian had a large collection of these now valuable paintings, bought at the beginnings of the artists careers for relatively little. It could be thought, and in fact it began to be said in some circles in Chicagos art community, that his championing of the Chicago Imagists was a very clever way of providing for his old age. No one, of course, said this quite as bluntly as I have just put it, although the critic of the rival newspaper in Chicago, Alan Artner (1982) of the Chicago Tribune, came close to it in a malign review published when the collection was first exhibited. And here one must read between the lines and try to unravel the innuendo and metaphor; I will provide some marginal commentary to help with that work:

Artners review

Beckers comments

When [Adrian] began collecting them [the Chicago Imagists]more than a decade ago, the term [maverick] seemed appropriate; they were not yet marked by an accepted style. But in short order many of the young strays were rounded into herds and branded. Then began the campaign aimed at turning homegrown stock into international champions.

This was written in 1982.

Artner uses a ranching metaphor to describe a plot to increase the value of the work of these local artists.

Adrian not only befriended and collected these so-called Imagists, but wrote on their behalf. Scarcely a week went by without a mention in his columns for the Chicago Daily News [a third Chicago newspaper]. A book by a colleague [i.e., Schulze] had given them a corporate name and outlined their milieu. Adrians effort was to provide a distinguished lineage.

Here are some of the deeds that made up the conspiracy: publicity, the invention of a name and a school, and the creation of an artistic lineage that legitimates the value placed on their work.

Everything from folk art to works of the Old Masters was invoked. It was not unusual to find Phil Hanson [an Imagist] compared to Paul Klee or Karl Wirsum [another Imagist] to Paul Klee. The game was merit by association and it characterized several catalogue essays written for the Museum of Contemporary Art.

The conspirators collude to place the paintings in the history of art by reference to accepted modern masters in the essays they prepare for museum exhibits.

5 de 11

01/09/2012 17:08

Articles

http://home.earthlink.net/~hsbecker/articles/values.html

But that was not enough. Just as some of the artists had been recommended to certain dealers, specific works were brought to the attention of collectors. So great was this advocacy that that now, nearly 15 years later, one can trace the Adrian influence in collections from Hyde Park to East Lake Shore Drive to Glencoe. Of course, he had help; the critic is only one link in the nexus that leads to a school of art. But few others on the scene were in a position to give counsel on works-in-progress, urge that they be exhibited, issue written superlatives and provide personal advice for purchase.

As adviser, Adrian can influence collectors whose own actions are highly influential. He alludes here to wealthy areas of the city in which some of the collectors lived, allusions which everyone understood to refer to quite specific people.

Adrian, then, is the artists friend. If their work gave rise to hesitations or doubts, these were never expressed publicly. He maintained a level of enthusiasm that set his writing apart.

Since he never criticizes thework of these artists, his judgments are suspect.

Helpful as it assuredly was for the artists, there nevertheless was a catch. An MCA [Museum of Contemporary Art] staff member, who has tended the collection, estimates that one-quarter of its artworks were presented to the critic as gifts. They bore witness to close association and were tokens anyone with reciprocal feeling would have prized. But a critic is not just anyone. To borrow a famous phrase, the position requires the punctilio of an honor most exact. It dictates an allegiance to principles that friendships, however welcome, cannot help but test. It prescribes the apparent paradox of getting close to the art while remaining distant from the artist. Adrian has preferred to work with proximity all around. His collection includes few pieces by artists he doesnt know and

Here are his reasons for not being critical.

And here is the statement of the moral imperative: to be interested only in aesthetic values, ignoring other motives for appreciating and praising works. By being so close to the artists and others involved, Adrian has rendered his motives suspect.

Finally, a prediction that the untoward behavior

6 de 11

01/09/2012 17:08

Articles

http://home.earthlink.net/~hsbecker/articles/values.html

none by artists he hasnt in some way encouraged. (To have gained the support of so keen-eyed a collector is encouragement in and of itself.) But one must never forget that Adrian is also a tastemaker, a role he has relished, occasionally to his detriment. So if any artist here has escaped the attention of other Chicago collectors, one may rest assured it will not be for long.

will continue in the future.

Adrian , perhaps stung by such talk, then made a great quixotic gesture. Though he needed the money, and could ill afford the gesture, he bequeathed his entire collection to Chicagos Museum of Contemporary Art. The collection had by then become quite valuable. In making this bequest, he assured himself but also, more importantly, the art world, that his judgment was indeed disinterested. Because he would not (unless he changed his will, always a possibility) profit from these works, his acquisition of them was solely an expression of his recognition of artistic worth. This bequest was not enough to satisfy Artner, who commented (the above is quoted from Artners review of the first exhibit of the works given to the Museum) that [t]he museumization of the Adrian collection is, for some, the ultimate confirmation of his judgment. That is one interpretation, that the conspirators put the finishing touches on their work by having it all legitimized by an exhibition in a major museum. Another reading is that Adrian, recognizing that both good and bad motives could be read into the same actionshis collecting and promoting of the work of these artistschose to do the one thing that would prove that he had not profited from his acquisitions and thus that he could not have acted from financial motives, only from aesthetic ones. That was to give the works away. (Pierre-Michel Menger, in a letter to me, suggests that even so grand a gesture has overtones of self-aggrandizement: le collectioneur qui prfre garder ses toiles pltot que les vendre pour payer ses soins mdicaux fait peut-tre un pari symbolique sur la valeur future des oeuvres puisquil sortira personnellement grandi et rput dun choix artistique esthtique payant.) These events were so public that we cannot expect to find straightforward statements of what people intended by what they did. We must interpret what they said in the light of our knowledge of the workings of art worlds. This gives the interpretation Im about to make a circular character: the events to be interpreted are part of the knowledge needed to create the larger understanding of the art world that makes it possible to understand such single events as Adrians gift. This is, of course, methodologically unsound; it is, however, necessary, because the alternative is hopeless naivet. Adrian signalled his intentions not by anything he said about the major gift to the Museum of Contemporary Art, but by what he says in the catalogue about an earlier event. He had begun his career as a collector, he says, with 20th century prints and drawings: Max Beckmann, Louis Corinth, Otto Dix, Joan Mir, Pablo Picasso. He also developed an interest in younger contemporary artists, especially those he had met in Chicago: [T]he increasing prices (and values) of works by modern masters precipitated a kind of unusual crisis for me. It happened that some serious and extremely expensive medical problems left me frighteningly short of money: the things on my walls started to swim in a haze of dollar signs and quite a number of colleagues and friends said Why dont you just sell a few of these things and solve the problem? It was somehow impossible to explain to them that to sell a lot of things would seem like a terrible defeat and loss. I had worked very hard to get them and I wished them to remain works of art, not turn into assets. For this reason, after parting with two things which alleviated the immediate critical pressure, I decided to give my collection of 19th- and 20th-century prints and drawings to the Art Institute of Chicago, to which I had made an earlier gift at the request of the curator of that

7 de 11

01/09/2012 17:08

Articles

http://home.earthlink.net/~hsbecker/articles/values.html

department. It was a step I have never regretted; these 40 or so things remain works of artnot assetsand they remain accessible to me and others interested in them. (Adrian 1982, p. 6) Adrian here puts the point I have been making impersonally. He does not speak of his motives, only of the nature of the objects. By giving his collection to a museumthus, as Moulin has noted, taking them out of the market more or less permanentlyAdrian assured that they would not be assets, that is to say, that they would not, couldnot, be understood as objects of economic acquisition. (Not having a large income, Adrian did not have the economic incentives created by American tax laws, which give substantial tax reductions to donors of valuable objects to public museums.) By giving them away he has foregone the value critics might be accusing him of having created for his own benefit, by manipulating his position as a critic and adviser. Clearly, what was true of a small collection of minor works by well-known artists is even more true of a major collection of what may yet be late 20th-century masters (or perhaps not, since there is no guarantee that Adrians judgment will continue to be honored in the future). That only such dramatic and drastic measures can provide the necessary assurance is a sign of how deeply and irremdiably embedded in the operations of art worlds and markets the confusion of values I am discussing is. The General Problem The phenomenon of conflicting but indistinguishable values, far from being a peculiarity of the world of art, is quite common. My grandmother always told me that it was just as easy to fall in love with a rich girl as a poor girl. I never followed that advice but, if I had, I suppose I might have experienced just this confusion over my motives-its a common enough theme in 19th century fiction, even more so from the point of view of the rich spouses family, who always, in those books, suspected their daughters suitors of being fortune hunters. The existence of such situations, especially if they are as ubiquitous as I think, poses a serious problem for sociological theorists. Typically, theorists have dealt with these situations by talking about conflicting norms or values, cultural contradictions, and the like, and noting how people in such situations of social strain respond. The classic paradigm for such discussions was Robert Mertons theory of anomie Merton, 1957), which took as the archetypal case people who learned to want certain cultural goals, which could only be achieved by certain acceptable means, but were then systematically (or systemically) deprived of those means. Under these circumstances, Merton said, people will engage in various forms of deviance, which he labeled innovation (roughly speaking, crime), ritualism (again roughly, the bureaucrat), and retreatism (the isolate). Merton applied this scheme in its most sophisticated form in his analysis of science, where he saw the institutionally normative emphasis on originality as potentially incompatible with an almost equally strong emphasis on humility and modesty, stemming from the understanding that science was, after all, a communal endeavor in which one achieved results by working in concert with others. Potentially incompatible means that, although not truly contradictory, the two call for opposed kinds of behavior. In this case, although modesty and originality could in principle go together, as scientific institutions are actually organized, originality leads one to insist on priority, on having gotten a result first, while modesty forbids one to mention it. Merton comes near to recognizing what Moulin has made centralthat truly conflicting values can call for the same behaviorbut says little about it. This is, I think, because he is fundamentally committed to the notion that incompatible values really are, after all, incompatible and any attempt to satisfy both must lead to conflict. An extended quotation shows how he approaches and then backs away from the idea:

Mertons statement

Beckers commentary

8 de 11

01/09/2012 17:08

Articles

http://home.earthlink.net/~hsbecker/articles/values.html

[A]ny rewardmoney, fame, positionis morally ambiguous and potentially subversive of culturally esteemed motives.

Here he grasps the possibility of ambiguity firmly,

For as rewards are meted outfame, for examplethe motive of seeking the reward can displace the original motive, concern with recognition can displace concern with advancing knowledge.

Rather than accept the ambiguity, he notes that one motive may displace another, but does not pursue the possibility that they may be indistinguishable and irretrievably confused with one another.

But this is only a possibility, not an inevitability. When the institution of science works effectivelyand like other social institutions it does not always do sorecognition and esteem accrue to those scientists who have best fulfilled their roles, to those who have made important contributions to the common stock of knowledge. Then are found those happy circumstances in which moral obligation and self-interest coincide. (Merton, 1973, p. 399)

He sees the possibility of amalgamation only in the special case when the mixture produces a good result, not as a chronic condition which can produce bad results as well.

For Merton, though both kinds of motives can lead to the same behavior, they are always distinguishable. Thus, science generates a need, in individual scientists, to have ones accomplishment socially validated:

Merton

Commentary

Sometimes, of course, this need [the deep-rooted need for validation of work accomplished] is stepped up until it becomes a driving lust for acclaim (even when unwarranted), megalomania replaces the comfort of reassurance.

Here, Mertons approach takes on a moral tone. The good motive, a socially supported institutional need for validation of real accomplishment can be suppressed by an excess of the bad one, the driving lust for acclaim and megalomania .

But the extreme case need not be mistaken for the modal one. (Merton, 1973, p. 400)

But the case he describes as extreme may in some situations indeed be modal, inevitable, or chronic.

9 de 11

01/09/2012 17:08

Articles

http://home.earthlink.net/~hsbecker/articles/values.html

As elsewhere in his writings, Merton here explains bad behavior by good people by describing it as unusual. But what if what he finds extreme is not only modal but accepted. More to our point, however, what if the two categories, distinguished motivationally, cannot be told apart in practice, because the only way people can tell what they are doing is by seeing what they do, and they do the same thing whether their motives are an institutionally engendered desire for validation or a pathological excess? Merton. a profound and influential theorist, here represents a dominant trend in contemporary academic sociology. Conventional theory requires us to be able to distinguish motives from one another, to know when people are acting from one or the other, and requires social actors themselves to be aware that they have conflicting motives and to know just what they are, and when they are doing one thing or the other. Of course, it is not usually put so crudely. But the underlying imagery of discussions of role conflict and the like is just this: that each action has its socially attached reasons, so that everyone, actors and analysts alike, can see when one or the other is operative. Moulins great contribution, modestly hidden in an analysis of the art market, is to show that the same behavior can seem to arise from quite different and conflicting motives, and that that possibility can cause a chronic and endemic confusion of values in social organizations. Finally, Moulins results show that talk of values, in themselves or as explanations of conduct, is highly suspect, unless that discussion is highly nuanced and qualified. People do on occasion refer to values as they act, but they can never be sure, and thus neither can we, that they know what behavior can be attributed to what values. Not because they are confused or stupid, but because the situations they act in do not give them the resources with which to make such distinctions neatly and clearly. So values, as conventionally conceived, do not help us to understand collective action. We may, at most, understand values as shared understandings to which actors may from time to time appeal, to organize their own behavior or influence that of others. But we must understand also that this is only a beginning on the deeper explanations of collective life so wonderfully embodied in Raymonde Moulins profound explorations of artistic life. REFERENCES Adrian, Dennis. 1982. A Brief Personal History, in Museum of Contemporary Art, Selections from the Dennnis Adrian Collection(Chicago: Museum of Contemporary Art). Alpers, Svetlana. 1988. Rembrandts Enterprise: The Studio and the Market. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Artner, Alan. 1982. MCA rounds up Dennis Adrians maverick herd. Chicago Tribune, Arts and Books section, February 7. Barthes, Roland. 1980. La chambre clair. Paris: Editions de Seuil. Csikszentmihalyi, Mihaly and Eugene Rochberg-Halton. 1981. The meaning of things : domestic symbols and the self. New York : Cambridge University Press. Heinich, Natalie. 1991. La gloire de Van Gogh: Essai danthropologie de ladmiration. Paris: ditions de Minuit. Hughes, Everett. C. 1984. The Sociological Eye. New Brunswick: Transaction Books. Merton, Robert K. 1957. Social Theory and Social Structure. New York: The Free Press. ________. 1973. The Sociology of Science: theoretical and empirical investigations. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Moulin, Raymonde. 1967. Le march de la peinture en France. Paris: Les ditions de Minuit. ________. 1978. La gense de la raret artistique. Ethnologie franaiseVIII (2-3), 241-258.

10 de 11

01/09/2012 17:08

Articles

http://home.earthlink.net/~hsbecker/articles/values.html

________. 1992. Lartiste, linstitution, et le march. Paris: Flammarion. Smith, Charles W. 1989. Auctions: The Social Contruction of Value. The Free Press.

FOOTNOTES (1) I am grateful to Gilda Buchbinder and to Lynn Warren, of the Chicago Museum of Contemporary Art, for helping me with the documentation of this story. (2) Pierre- Michel Menger points out that the problem can appear in reverse; those who think of themselves as primarily economic actors may nevertheless accomplish aesthetic ends as well.: Si vous avez achet des toiles qui ont beaucoup augment, et que vous les revendez pour en acheter dautres que vous prfrez ou que vous pouvez payer plus facilement et qui correspondent votre got profond mais que vous ne pouviez pas satisfaire auparavant faute dargent), comment dire si cest un comportement spculatif et sil est en opposition aven lthique du dsintressement?

11 de 11

01/09/2012 17:08

S-ar putea să vă placă și