Sunteți pe pagina 1din 15

Apparent, Implied, and Postulated Authors

Robert Stecker

Philosophy and Literature, Volume 11, Number 2, October 1987, pp. 258-271 (Article) Published by The Johns Hopkins University Press DOI: 10.1353/phl.1987.0033

For additional information about this article


http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/phl/summary/v011/11.2.stecker.html

Access provided by McGill University Libraries (5 Nov 2013 18:40 GMT)

Robert Stecker

AND POSTULATED AUTHORS

APPARENT, IMPLIED,

"Things inanimate cannot be aumors ..."


Thomas Hobbes

justify the distinction, i.e. , establish diat diere really is a need for it? These are the questions I want to answer in this article.

variously called die apparent, implied, or postulated author (or artist). What motivates making this further distinction? Does the motivation

Boodi diat we distinguish, not only between die writer of a work of fiction and its narrator, but distinguish bodi of these from something else

ANUMBER OF writers have recendy revived a suggestion of Wayne

Kendall Walton makes die distinction not only with respect to literature but across the arts.1 For him, speaking of apparent artists and their apparent acts is merely a convenient way of referring to what appears to be
the case widi or in a work of art. However, not every way a work appears pens to appear green under certain unusual conditions of light need not

makes it appropriate to speak of an apparent artist. That a painting hap-

make appropriate talk of an apparent artist. It is appropriate to speak of an apparent artist when a work appears to be made in a certain way or with a
diemselves in die work.

certain intention, or under die influence of certain beliefs and emotions in short, whenever acts or states of a maker of the work appear to manifest

apparent artists. Works of art do often appear to be made in certain ways, with certain intentions, and so forth. Often, we are not tempted to attrib258

Given diis usage, it is certain that there is often license for speaking of

Robert Stecker259

us formal license to speak of apparent artists, it does not so far give us good reason to. We would have a good reason to so speak only if the appearances picked out by such talk were important for understanding or appreciating works of art. reality and if die focus of critical inquiry is the way a work really is, the in-

ute such acts of making to the narrator (if any) of the work. Sometimes they do not, in fact, belong to die real artist. While Walton's usage gives

If we are concerned widi appearances simply as our initial estimate of

tentions an artist really had, etc., dien Walton's usage will prove more

is or ought to be on the appearances themselves, men Walton's usage will help us maintain that focus and not confuse it with die alternative just
"From the point of view of art criticism and appreciation, how works appear to have come about is important for its own sake, and not as an indimentioned. Walton indeed thinks diat it is die latter focus that is correct.

cumbersome man useful. On die odier hand, if the focus ofcritical inquiry

cation of how it did come about" (p. 65). It is mis claim that really justifies

talk of die apparent artist. The question now becomes whether Walton's claim about what is important is itself correct.

pears to be made and of apparent intentions in such a way as to acknowledge diat we see works of art as essentially made, essentially die product of
intentional acts.

actual intentions, seem not to be. On the odier hand, die range of appearances usually recognized is extended by speaking of die way the work ap-

One point that might be regarded in its favor is that it preserves the widely held view diat a proper appreciation of a work of art ought to find its source in the direct experience of it. (Call this "the direct experience requirement.") Appearances are well suited to such appreciation while "external facts," like the way the work is actually made and die real author's

quirement:

In die following passage, Walton appeals to die direct experience reOne must examine "The Love Song of J. Alfred Prufrock" to ascertain that in it Eliot portrayed die hero compassionately. But if Eliot did not write die poem, he did not perform diis act, no matter what die poem is

the act of portraying die character compassionately. The words of the poem are, to be sure, good evidence diat someone wrote it, but it is conceivable diat other evidence ("external" evidence) should show no one wrote it. (p. 53)

like; and if the poem was "written" by a computer . . . , no one performed

260Philosophy and Literature

Walton's point, I take it, is that if what is really important were the acts and intentions of die real artist, we would not rest content with our experi-

ence of the poem. Since we do rest content with our experience in deciding whedier Prufrock is compassionately portrayed, it is die appearance of

compassionate portrayal that is important. I find unconvincing bodi Walton's claim about what is important for understanding/appreciating works of art and die reason given in support of the claim. Let us begin with his remarks about "Prufrock." I believe that we might often rest content with our experience of the poem to find out how a character is portrayed. This, however, does not show that we are not interested in how die real author portrayed die character. Certainly this is not shown by pointing out mat it is conceivable that Eliot did not write "Prufrock* and die words of die poem might still exist having been produced in die right order by a computer, or by a monkey or by the action of waves on a cliff face. Though these possibilities are conceivable,

they are not possibilities we have to dispose of before attributing the act of portrayal to Eliot because none of these are possibilities there is any reason to take seriously. We know who wrote "Prufrock" so we can take for granted diat the words of the poem are evidence of his acts and intentions. we would be expected to seek if we were really concerned to discover the
Walton claims diat there is more direct evidence of these diings which acts and intentions of die real artist. However, this is false on a number of counts. First, a work often provides as good evidence of die artist's acts

and intentions as possible. A record of how Eliot felt or what he was thinking before, during and after writing "Prufrock," or of a general disposition to compassion or lack thereof, would not be better evidence of how he portrayed Prufrock than die evidence of die text. It would in fact be worse

evidence. We cannot, widi equal confidence, say die same about how Eliot intended to portray Prufrock, but it remains true mat professions of intention are not necessarily better evidence of intentions man products of intention. In die case of arts like painting and sculpture, there can be better

the work provides adequate evidence or that, although such evidence is conceivable, it is unavailable.

evidence of how a work is made man the work itself, e.g., a photographic record of die work being made. But diis would not give us more direct access to odier artistic acts performed by die artist or to his intentions. Second, even if more direct evidence is conceivable, it may be felt that

It may be diought mat all diis misses Walton's point in introducing die possibility that die words of "Prufrock" have a nonhuman source. Perhaps he is suggesting that the way Prufrock appears to be portrayed would be

Robert Stecker261

main fixed on this appearance. It is this that shows only the appearance is
important.

die same whatever the cause of die "poem" and diat our interest would re-

However, it is not clear that the appearance would remain the same if we knew of the poem's strange genesis nor is it Walton's view that it which a work was created" (p. 56). So it is not true, in general, that die
would. "Even when what is relevant to criticism is merely with what intention a work appears to have been made or how ... it seems to have come about, it still may be crucial to consider die actual historical context in work itself is all we need for understanding it or that the way it appears is independent of external fact. Walton, like other proponents of apparent artists, discriminates between diose appearances that give us a correct

perception of a work and diose mat do not. He claims that considering historical context is among the ways of pinning down die former class of appearances. However, once we discriminate among appearances in this way, the claim that only appearances are important to criticism collapses.
We will see that, not only does it collapse, but we are driven to regarding die acts and intentions of actual artists as important. We can see this by looking at an example Walton uses to illustrate the importance of historical context in altering appearances. The example is an imaginary one borrowed from Borges's story, "Pierre

Menard, die audior of Don Quixote.'" Menard, in Borges's story, writing in radically different due to the difference in historical context in which die

me early twentieth century, produced a text diat is identical in wording widi certain chapters of Cervantes' Don Quixote. The narrator of the story suggests that, afthough die words are identical, dieir interpretation will be

history . . ." are mere historical eulogy to history coming from Cervantes's pen, but are an expression of the pragmatic theory of truth coming from the pen of Menard, a contemporary of William James. Walton approves of the interpretation of the narrator with die proviso diat it should be taken
texts rather than as an account of what die real Cervantes and the "real" Menard had in mind.

words were produced. Thus die words, "truth, whose mother is

to state how die words appear to a reader aware of die two historical con-

pearances and why should we want to view a work from the perspective of question. First, why does historical context create different appearances? "The information that makes Cervantes's Don Quixote seem not to have been writ-

But exactly why does die historical context create these differing ap-

its historical context? Walton does not have a satisfactory answer to eidier

262Philosophy and Literature

before William James, and hence diat it is unlikely diat its audior would it was written with pragmatism in mind because historical context makes

ten widi pragmatism in mind is . . . mat ... it was written . . . long

have had in mind die doctrines of pragmatism" (p. 64). By parity of reasoning, one would expect Menard's Quixote to give die impression diat
Menard's text . . . seems to have pragmatism in mind, it does so in a sense diat does not provide die slightest support for the claim mat

it likely that die audior had it in mind. Walton surprisingly denies diis. "If

Menard . . . did have pragmatism in mind." (p. 65). If historical context (combined perhaps with Menard's words in his Quixote) made it likely that he had pragmatism in mind, it would provide not slight but strong support for the claim he did have it in mind. On the odier hand, if Walton is right, and it provides no support for this claim, we have been given no reason, comparable to die one given for Cervantes's text, for saying mat Menard appears to have had pragmatism in mind. So Walton has no satisfactory
explanation why placing a text in its historical context creates different im-

pressions. Or rather, he does suggest such an explanation (in his remarks about Cervantes), viz., that historical context makes attributions to the real author probable or improbable, but he recoils from it because it not only makes important for criticism historical context but the acts and intention of real artists.

written in die seventeenth century; to construe it as a product of die twentiedi century would be to misconstrue it . . ." (p. 57-58). Walton tries to justify a historical perspective by citing the (external) fact diat works are

Second, why do we want to view a work from its historical perspective? According to Walton, "I diink we can agree that it is correct ... to read Cervantes's Don Quixote as a seventeenth-century work, since it was in fact

twentieth-century philosophies. It is only by linking Menard to one of diese (eidier through his text or otherwise) diat we would make it likely to produce the appearance diat he had pragmatism in mind. To take anodier example, suppose we discover a manuscript by an Irishman from the eigh-

produced in a historical context. In the same way we canjustify the importance of the artist's acts and intentions by citing die fact diat works are produced by such acts and intentions. We can also point out that if ignorance of historical context leads to misconstrual, there is as much reason to suppose that ignorance of the historical author does so as well. To return to Menard's Quixote, we should stop pretending diat historical context alone could make it likely or produce die appearance diat die audior had pragmatism in mind. Such a context would only give us an array of early

Robert Stecker263

teendi century. That the Irishman is Berkeley would lead us to interpret it one way, mat he is Swift would lead us in quite a different direction. concerned with historical context that is not also a reason for being con-

The argument so far only shows mat Walton gives no reason for being

cerned widi historical author. There may still be a way of showing why we should regard the former but not die latter as important for criticism. I will look at another attempt to do so in die next section. It may be worth pointing out now die implausibility of any such attempt. Walton unintentionally pinpointed why we would ordinarily be interested in historical con-

bitrarily confines a critic to only some historical information out of die


total information, but deprives him of an obvious reason for being interested in historical information.

text. Since it is the context in which die artist worked, information about the historical context renders probable or improbable hypotheses about what die artist was doing, or intending to do, in a work. Cutting off an interest in historical context from an interest in historical audior not only ar-

II

According to Alexander Nehamas, the object of critical understanding is die postulated audior, an agent hypothesized to explain die features of a text.2 According to Nehamas, this agent is not die historical writer. Nevertheless, the postulated author has to be understood as occupying die hisapparent artist but the postulated audior is a rather different creature. In constructing the postulated audior, we are by no means confined to how a text appears to us against a background of common historical knowledge. All sorts of information, including biographical information about die writer, no matter how esoteric, can be relevant to the enterprise which Nehamas compares to the construction of a scientific theory to explain natural phenomena. I find Nehamas's conception of the enterprise of interpretation attractive. I agree mat much interpretation consists in forming and defending hypotheses about what die author meant, though some interpretation consists in accounting for divergences between what the audior evidendy did
and what he might have meant. torical context of the historical writer. So far this sounds just like Walton's

construct ... a complete, historically plausible audior" ("PA," p. 147)

author and historical writer. Nehamas's description of the enterprise "to

I find puzzling, however, Nehamas's distinction between die postulated

264Philosophy and Literature

sounds like it is concerned with die actual writer. In Nehamas's first article

on me subject, "The Postulated Audior," he only offers a few hints of his motivation. Unfortunately none of these really justifies the distinction. At one point, Nehamas distinguishes die postulated audior from the ac-

tual writer's selfunderstanding. As Nehamas says, such self-understanding (e.g., of die writer's intentions) is fragmentary. If we were to identify die could be distinguished from the postulated author. But of course, such an The other hint we are given is diis: "The author is postulated as die
actual writer with his self-understanding, we could see how die former
identification is incorrect. The intentions that a writer is unaware of or misconstrues are still his.

agent whose actions account for the text's features; he is a character, a hypothesis which is accepted provisionally, guides die interpretation, and is in turn modified in its light. The audior, unlike die writer, is not a text's identical with it" ("PA," p. 145). The formal cause of a diing is its essence, and, since a text is essentially a production of someone, I do not see how the efficient/formal distinction is supposed to work here. Earlier in the

efficient cause, but, so to speak, its formal cause, manifested in diough not passage the postulated audior is identified widi a hypodiesis which die actual writer certainly is not. But the identification cannot plausibly be taken literally, or else it conflicts with the characterization of the postulated audior as an agent. "Hypodiesis" must be loose for "hypothetical agent."

Taking "hypodiesis" this way, die passage goes on to suggest diat die identity of diis agent is constandy changing (while die real writer does not

change with every change in our interpretation). However, our changing hypodieses are more plausibly construed as changes in belief about the audior rather than changes in the identity of die audior. In that case they
can be construed as hypotheses about die actual writer. Nehamas has recendy made a more elaborate attempt to justify the dis-

tinction between postulated audior and historical writer.3 The background of diis attempt is Foucault's critique of the audior in "What is an Audior?" Nehamas accepts two points that Foucault makes: (A) Rather man a person, the author is a figure, function or role which implies the appropriateness of certain questions about the text and the expectation of certain

answers. (B) The audior has been a repressive principle used to force texts
to undergo certain operations and to exclude odiers. I will return to B at the end of diis section. For the time being I will concentrate on A.

Let us first examine Nehamas's main argument for distinguishing writers and audiors. It is found in the following passage which harks back

Robert Stecker265 efficient and formal cause of a work:

to and clarifies the passage in "The Postulated Audior" distinguishing die


Writers are extrinsically related to their texts. This is reflected in the

possibility mat Henri Beyle, for example, never wrote the works mat are commonly attributed to him. ... It is, so to speak, not necessary for Henri Beyle to ... to have been Stendhal. But notice how we must construe the expression "to have been Stendhal" in this context: it is not a reference ... to die actual person. This, in turn, reflects die essential connection between Stendhal and the texts of which, necessarily, he is the
author. Stendhal is whoever can be understood as the author of these

texts. ("WTAW," p. 272)

audior of these texts. (4) Therefore, S. is essentially (noncontingendy) related to diese texts. (5) Therefore, S. is not H.B. (6) Therefore, die necessary that H. B. wrote S.'s works. First, it is logically or metaphysically possible that H.B. did not write them: it is not contradictory to assert
audior is not the writer. I diink we can admit that there are at least two senses in which it is not

The argument of mis passage can be stated as follows: (1) it is not necessary that H. B. wrote S.'s works. (2) Therefore, H.B. is only contingendy related to S.'s works. (3) S. is whoever can be understood as die

he did not, and we can imagine a possible world in which someone else wrote them. Second, it is epistemically possible that H. B. did not write them: we might discover that someone else wrote diem. I am also willing to grant that (2) follows from (1) and diat (3) is true except that I find obscure the phrase "can be understood as" in (3). What I certainly would accept is: (3') S. is whoever is the author of these texts. The argument goes wrong at the next step. It seems to me that (3') can be construed in two ways, neidier one of which implies (4). On one consumai of (3'), "whoever" is a pronoun that refers to the person who wrote

the texts without specifying who diat person is. On this construal, (4) not whoever he may be, who wrote these texts, (3^ in conjunction with (2) would imply not (4). On the odier construal, "whoever" is a variable, and die expression "whoever is the author of diese texts" would be a predicate
or open sentence. On this construal, "whoever" does not refer to the only does not follow, but, since (3') would mean mat S. is the writer,

writer. Nehamas may have inferred (4) because, construing (3^- or

(3) this way, he supposed diat "whoever" still referred to somediing and

266Philosophy and Literature

diis construal of (3'), "whoever" does not refer to anything. (3^ would mean that the predicate "x is die audior of diese texts" is true of S. This too does not imply (4). I know of no way of construing (3^ or (3) on which (4) does follow. So I conclude diat Nehamas's argument is invalid. figure invites, it becomes as puzzling as it was in his earlier article why the audior is not die historical writer. According to Nehamas, to interpret a work (which for him is the same as supposing it to have an author) is to construe it as the product of action by an agent and to ask questions appropriate to the understanding of actions and products of agents ("WTWA," p. 277). If diis is what interpretation is, why in die world is it not concerned with die writer. He is die agent whose actions brought about the product we are interpreting as the product of actions of an agent! Nehamas answers this question in many ways: (A) "the agent postu-

that whatever is referred to is essentially related to die text. However, on

Furthermore, when Nehamas specifies the questions that die audior

What else could we be talking about?

the audior. Only (B) seems to imply that we are not talking about the writer. However, even (B) can be accommodated with die identification of

p. 281); (B) "a plausible historical variant of the writer" (p. 285); (C) "a character the writer could have been" (p. 285); (D) "what any individual who [produced die text] must be like" (p. 286). Not all diese come to the same diings. (A) is precisely where we began and would normally be construed to refer to the writer, the actual agent. (D) surely implies that we are describing die writer; he did produce die text and so, if anyone who produced die text must answer to our description, die writer must. (C) at least leaves open mat die writer coincides with

lated ... to account for construing a text as the product of an action"

audior and writer. After all, our hypotheses about what the agent (i.e. , die writer) was doing in producing a text will usually be just diat: hypotieses rather than highly confirmed dieories. To that extent, it is likely diat die agent we describe will be a plausible variant of die actual agent. That is
simply a way of saying that our hypotheses will fall short of die truth. As in

"Authors, not being persons, do not have psychological states diat might

his original article, it is not clear why Nehamas prefers to think of hypodieses as constructing characters rather than imperfectiy characterizing the writer. There are other things Nehamas says about audiors which do clearly distinguish diem from writers, but at the same time they undermine his account of interpretation. One (crucial) example will have to suffice here.

determine in advance what texts mean" ("WTWA," p. 286). If diis is so,

Robert Stecker267

audiors are indeed not writers, but it is not clear how diey can be regarded as die agents postulated to explain die features of a text. Agents do have psychological states and it is precisely in terms of such states as intention, desire and belief diat die actions of agents are understood. ciple. This is a claim mat Nehamas takes very seriously. Another motive that he has in distinguishing between writers and authors is to avoid die
accusation involved in the claim. However, I do not think that Nehamas's condemning was a conception of reading texts which forces texts to undergo some operations and exclude odiers. Nehamas's conception of interpretation certainly does diis. Finally, I return to Foucault's claim mat die audior is a repressive prin-

audior figure would escape Foucault's condemnation. What Foucault was

project of constructing hypodieses about what a writer is doing in a work,

On the odier hand, die audior, even construed as the writer, needn't be invoked as a repressive principle. It would be repressive if regarded as die only principle diat determines legitimate interpretations. However, die

can be regarded as one of many possible projects all equally deserving the name "interpretation." To so regard it would be to abandon die critical

monism it was Nehamas's original purpose to defend, but given die state
abandoned.

of contemporary criticism, I believe that such monism has to be


Ill

It seems wrong to think of the acts and intentions of actual audiors as unimportant for criticism. It may still be true that die apparent author should be important too. While I don't want categorically to deny diis, I

do want to argue diat apparent authors are harder to come by man is comapparent audior between die narrator and die real audior.

monly thought. The reason for this is diat it is harder to find room for the

This notion is harder to pin down dian diat of Walton's apparent artist

Wayne Booth tries to make room widi his notion of an implied audior.*

intellectual perspective. In fact, a novel may have many such perspectives belonging to die various characters including narrators. But there will be a more fundamental perspective that may not belong to anyone in die novel. It is from this perspective that die novel can be said to pass, or refuse to pass, judgment on its characters. The perspective determines how much knowledge characters have of themselves, odiers, and die

and Nehamas's postulated audior though it has more affinities with die former. The basic idea seems to be mis. A novel has an ethical, emotional,

268Philosophy and Literature

world. It determines die moral significance, or lack thereof, of the situations of die novel, and characteristic ways of reacting to them. It proposes,

or refuses to propose, an attitude toward diese reactions.

compatible with what I have been arguing: that the actual writer's acts and audior to attribute this perspective to. While I do not deny that such per-

it is not necessarily his. It is necessarily the implied author's. This claim is intentions are important in understanding a work including die perspective of die implied audior, but it claims that we still need die implied

According to Boodi, diis perspective is created by die actual writer, but

spectives exist in novels, I question whedier we need any categories other than narrator and actual writer to account for such perspectives. Very often, die role of implied audior is filled by die narrator of a work. of Emma and of Anna Karenina. (Actually, if an undramatized narrator suggests, however, that whenever we have a dramatized narrator, the implied audior should be distinguished from the narrator. His practice, unBooth acknowledges this is so whenever the narrator is undramatized, i.e., stands wholly outside die world of die fiction. Such are the narrators

turns out to be unreliable, and I do not see why diis is impossible, we would not identify his perspective with the perspective of die novel.) Boodi fortunately, does not follow diis suggestion. For a class of narrators, called TomJones, Booth's practice is to constandy shift between maintaining and

"reliable spokesmen for the implied audior" (p. 211) such as die narrator of ignoring the distinction.5 Since his substantive remarks ignore the distinction necessarily, since whatever can be said of die implied audior can be said of die reliable spokesman I infer mat once again die category of
narrator does all die work.

If there is reason to introduce a new category the implied audior it ought to be found in diose works with a narrator or narrators who are not also include narrators whose perspective is more limited dian die audior's. In such works, we are particularly anxious to find a perspective that transcends diat of die narrator, but why shouldn't we say diat die one we are looking for is simply the actual writer's? Though the perspective we seek is created by die audior, it is not neces-

reliable "spokesmen." Such narrators need not be unreliable; they may

I have already mentioned one reason Booth gives to think odierwise.

himselfhas suggested diat there is some doubt whether die actual Fielding held some of the moral beliefs diat are part of me perspective of TomJones.

querulous and intolerant the actual Tolstoy may have been, the implied audior of Anna Karenina is full of compassionate understanding." 6 Boodi

sarily held by him. Thus one follower of Booth has suggested, "however

Robert Stecker269

(Ignore the fact diat neimer of these works contains an unreliable narrator.) A minor point about such claims is that they are often simpleminded, as is me one just given about Tolstoy. Just because someone has a ten-

dency toward intolerance does not mean diat he is not also full of compas-

sionate understanding. When understanding is acute, a person often vacillates between compassion and intolerance. There is much evidence diat Tolstoy was just such a person and even his novels display both tendencies, though in these diey are directed to different characters, the tendency
to intolerance usually only to minor ones.

reader's judgment of die narrator and die events he narrates without it being anyone's in this sense and widiout die reader attributing it to anyone. In another sense, however, the perspective is the actual audior's.

The main problem with such claims is mat, even if the perspective of a novel is not the actual writer's, in the sense diat he firmly holds every belief and has every disposition constituting it, it is not necessary to posit an implicit author who does. Such perspectives can exist and guide die Let me try to explain these two senses. Just as die world of die novel is

resemblance it bears to the real world) but is presented as something to be


entertained in die imagination, so die perspective a novelist adopts in

not asserted by its actual audior to be the real world (no matter how much

ing this; it is in diis sense diat die perspective is his, not an implied audior's. But die moral perspective from which the writer judges characters, etc. , is one he may not unequivocally affirm (though he can unequivocally be said to present it to us). The writer may be exploring it, trying to

presenting this world may itself only be entertained. From the point of view of a certain moral perspective, say, characters are judged, situations are given ediical significance, and so forth. It is the real audior who is do-

imagine what it would be like to actually hold it, but he does not hold it. sense it does not have to be anyone's in or out of die novel.

This is die sense in which die perspective is not the writer's, but in this

This is not to say diat perspectives are not sometimes held in the strong sense of affirmed by writers or that it is never worth asking whedier a perspective is affirmed or merely entertained by its writer. It may be part

of understanding a work to understand diis.


IV

It may be that die idea of an apparent or implied artist does not have a useful general application, but it may still have an application in certain

270Philosophy and Literature

For example, Mozart's "Musical Joke" at one level appears to be written by an incompetent composer, diough at a deeper level it appears, and in fact is, written by a composer of genius. And Jackson Pollock's paintings at one level appear to be painted in a haphazard and spontaneous manner, though at a deeper level they appear, and in fact are, carefully planned and executed. I diink it is significant diat diese examples come tendy "at one level" but not at a deeper level, die incompetence would probably be attributable to die novel's narrator. Similarly if it appeared to be produced in a haphazard and spontaneous manner at one level but not at a deeper level. I am inclined to think diat the notion of an apparent artist has genuine, significant application in diese cases. In die "Musical Joke," Mozart establishes the fiction diat die piece was composed by an incompetent composerjust as novelists can establish the fiction diat a story is written by an incompetent writer. But while we already have die notion of a narrator
to handle die latter case, we need some other notion like that of apparent artist to handle die "Musical Joke." I would be less inclined to say mat Pollock establishes a fiction, but no less inclined to endorse the usefulness from arts other dian literature. If a novel appeared to be written incompe-

special cases. Walton provides several special cases where this is plausible.

of die notion of apparent artist in understanding his paintings, at least if Whether the notion of apparent artist has any useful application to literature the art to which it was thought to have die most obvious application I do not know. Central Michigan University Walton's account of diem is correct.

1 . Kendall Walton , "Style and die Products and Processes of Art" in The Concept ofStyle, ed. Berel Lang (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1979). Ideal," Critical Inquiry 8 (1981): 133-149; hereafter abbreviated "PA." 3.Alexander Nehamas, "Writer, Text, Audior, Work," in Literature and the Question of Philosophy, ed. A. J. Cascardi, (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1987), pp. 267-91; hereafter abbreviated "WTAW." 4.Wayne Boodi, The Rhetoric of Fiction (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1961).
2.Alexander Nehamas, "The Postulated Audior: Critical Monism as a Regulative

Robert Stecker271

5.Ibid.; see especially pp. 71-73 for a passage where die distinction is ignored. 6.Jenefer Robinson, "Style and Personality in die Literary Work," The Philosophical Review 94 (1985): 234. It may be noted that philosophers are particularly fond of finding
compassion in implied audiors.

S-ar putea să vă placă și