Sunteți pe pagina 1din 11

An Ethics of Language

The Archeology of Knowledge and The Discourse on Language by Michel Foucault


Review by: Edward Said
Diacritics, Vol. 4, No. 2 (Summer, 1974), pp. 28-37
Published by: The Johns Hopkins University Press
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/464989 .
Accessed: 24/01/2015 17:13
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

The Johns Hopkins University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
Diacritics.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 142.150.248.14 on Sat, 24 Jan 2015 17:13:19 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

28

Michel Foucault. The Archeology of


Knowledge and The Discourse on Language. New York: Pantheon Books,
1972.
Since the publication of Les Mots et les choses
(the title of its 1971 English translation is The Order of Things) in 1966, Foucault's work has been
revisionist in character and concern. For not only
have his three essays on Nietzsche and Deleuze, his
two later books L'Archdologie du savoir, and
L'Ordre du discours,' all been about thinkers and
thought, revising, reordering, reinterpreting what had
been written, ordered and interpreted differently
from them; but also Foucault now turned his
thought back towards his own previous work. Thus it
appeared in 1969 that The Order of Things and
Madness and Civilization had tried "to measure the
mutations that operate in general in the field of history; an enterprise in which the methods, limits, and
themes proper to the history of ideas are questioned;
an enterprise by which one tries to throw off the last
anthropological constraints [. . .]. These tasks were
outlined [in those two earlier books] in a rather disordered way, and their general articulation was never
clearly defined" (p. 15). Also part of this revisionist
phase has been Foucault's disenchantment with the
idea of an author, a concept he has found grossly
incapable of dealing with the trans-personal authority
of texts and documents. To revise has not meant to
change opinions about which authors are more significant than others, although one can assume that that
too has happened to Foucault. To revise for him has
meant primarily to understand more closely the process of knowledge, its formation, dispersion, transmission and permanence, in terms of "anonymous
rules" that are extremely precise and specialized.
Moreover he has been at pains to show that during
the course of this understanding he has been released
not only from obligations to the history of ideas, but
also from the conventional biography of great men
and the narration of important events. All told then
a good deal of Foucault's revision has been negative,
and his description of those anonymous rules is frequently an itemized list of what they are not. Usually, however, the negatives are pronounced against
what he refers to as anthropology, which is the very
thing that Nietzsche had called anthropomorphism:
the habit of making all knowledge in the image of
man or, worse, making every item of knowledge reducible to an original human act without which the
item would otherwise have no cognitive status.
Foucault's self-revision is theoretically consistent with one of the principal themes of his historical research, the disappearance in contemporary
knowledge of man's role as central subject, author
and actor. But why not also practically consistent?
Because Foucault is, as I have elsewhere said, far
too clearly the unusually impressive author of his
work. This is an unhesitating compliment to him as
a stylist of thought, yet I intend it also as a way of
Edward Said, Professor of English and ComparativeLiterature at Columbia, is teaching at Harvard this year.

Edward Said

JirT(

It0

OF

IL'GQJ(J

making very doubtful his theoretical ambition to


find himself, as he would like, "on the other side of
discourse." An anonymous writer he clearly is not.
Nevertheless the ambition to write as if from the
standpoint of anonymous rules has been worth maintaining since, according to Foucault, he now knows
that discourse "is made up of a limited number of
statements for which a group of conditions of existence can be defined." Among these conditions an
author is not necessarily one of the most important.
To understand this we need only recall that Freud's
account of the Unconscious and its behavior is not
completely dependent for its intelligibility upon the
neurotic patient. The author of neurotic thoughts
does not authorize, except in a limited way, the entire system of coherence by which his thoughts can
be understood. Similarly, Marx's description of ideology envisages no particular individual; as a philosophic idea it has a force (in Marxist discourse) that
need not always be referred back to Marx's biography. "Discourses are composed of signs; but what
they do is more than use these signs to designate
things. It is this more that renders them irreducible
to the language and to speech. It is this 'more' that
we must reveal and describe" (p. 49). The questions
Foucault has been asking himself therefore are as
i These last two works now appear together in English
as The Archeology of Knowledge & The Discourse on
Language. The first, whose French original appeared in
1969, is translated by M. Sheridan Smith, and the second, which originally appeared in 1971, is translated-less carefully-by Rupert Swyer. Unless otherwise noted,
page references appended parenthetically to quotations
from Foucault are taken from this one volume of two
translations.

This content downloaded from 142.150.248.14 on Sat, 24 Jan 2015 17:13:19 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

follows: can one describe intellectual production


without stopping the description at terminals like
author, Zeitgeist, period, texts, ideas or language?
What gives written language a recognizable imprimt
6ver and above the signature of its author? What in
short is the regularity of language in use in relation
to which an author is a kind of eruptive irregularity?
In raising these questions Foucault, I suspect,
would prefer to be called a teacher rather than an
author, because a teacher exposes knowledge directly
before his students, he frees "a coherent domain of
description" for and with his students. The more
Foucault's work increases in volume and authority
the more he has agitated to diminish the author's
prerogatives, the more also he has become a teacher
who stands in "the field of coordination and subordination of statements in which concepts appear,
and are defined, applied and transformed" (pp. 18283). Nowhere does Foucault himself make the explicit distinction between author and teacher, but it
is a very useful one nonetheless. Primarily a teacher
makes explicit what an author hides inside the flowing lines of his language: namely that knowledge is
dispersion, strategy, formation, discontinuity. Moreover the teacher's place of business is the class, a
site of exteriority, whereas the author's locale, a
page, is far less visible as activity (which it is), and
much more his private property. All this is a political
motif running through Foucault's Archeology as he
turns the teacher's openness upon the author's accumulated reserves of power. Class struggle within
knowledge pits man-the-author as historian (whose
security is "the destiny of rationality and the teleo!ogy of the sciences, the long, continuous labor of
thought from period to period, the awakening and
the progress of consciousness, its perpetual resumption of itself, the uncompleted, but uninterrupted
movement of totalizations, the return to an everopen source, and finally the historico-transcendental
thematic," p. 39) against a revolutionary teacher
whose vocabulary replaces history of ideas with
"archeology," documents with "monuments," texts
with "discourses," language with "statements"
(enonces). The teacher's aim
is an attempt to reveal discursive practices in their complexity and density; to show that to speak is to do something-something other than to express what one thinks;
to translate what one knows, and something other than
to play with the structures of a language (langue); to
show that to add a statement to a pre-existing series of
statements is to perform a complicated and costly gesture, which involves conditions (and not only a situation, a context, and motives), and rules (not the logical
and linguistic rules of construction); to show that a
change in the order of discourse does not presuppose
'new ideas,' a little invention and creativity, a different
mentality, but transformationsin a practice, perhaps also
in neighboring practices, and in their common articulation. (p. 209)
Thus the teacher deprives the sovereign subject (or
cogito) "of the exclusive and instantaneous right" to
change discourse.
What has become more clear than ever in
Foucault's revisionist assault upon scholarship is the
particular will to knowledge pushing his work forward. On the one hand, in his most recent series of

lectures at the College de France he has been studying the regular transformations which a "polymorphous" appetite for knowledge can undergo; on the
other hand, the trajectory of his own intellectual
project has re-formed itself to accommodate certain
actualities in research elucidated by his practice. I
think it is imperative to understand that his vocabulary of working terms-monument,
archeology,
statement, discourse, etc.-is not a fussy way of declaring his originality, but is rather a design to meet
the actualities and the desires of will to knowledge
in general, and his own search for knowledge in particular. If his most recent work appears to be more
explicitly political and revolutionary than the work
that brought him great fame, then that is because, I
think, he has only lately apprehended the latent public quality of his historical investigation in Madness
and Civilization and The Order of Things. Probably
the May 1968 events in Paris played a major role in
bringing him out from behind his work: two especially important and extended interviews, in which
Foucault began to draw forth the political meaning
of "archeology," date from that period. One is
"R6ponse 'aune question," Esprit, No. 5 (May 1968),
pp. 850-74; the other is "R6ponse au Cercle d'6pist6mologie," Cahiers pour l'analyse, 9 (Summer 1968),
pp. 9-40.
From then on, I believe that Foucault's interests are dominated by a symptomatic group of pressures on him (one can just as well call them desires
or condititons or obsessions). Taken all together
these pressures have kept him responsible for the
goals and the results of his research, and responsive
to the encroachments on him of the academy, the
community of radicals, the injustices of contemporary society, and his own popularity. The first of
these pressures is the simplest to state and the hardest
to deal with. It is the historian's need to see history
as a mass of historical documents intended, necessitated, by certain condititons, not as chance productions willed into existence by the flukes of genius
or time. An intellectual rejection of the watery rationale usually employed in determining the setting
of a text in time and place, this pressure enables
Foucault to search for rigor in explanation where
none had been possible previously. Yet in order to
resort neither to mechanically determinist explanations nor to simple causal arguments, Foucault redraws the terrain in which, as a historian, he can
function systematically.
To asnwer the question why did X (not A)
say Y (not B) on occasion Z (not W), X, Y, Z,
A, B and W must be re-defined as belonging wholly
to an historically and particularly apprehensible order. This order Foucault calls discourse. Hence:
"The question posed by language analysis of some
discursive fact or other is always: according to what
rules has a particular statement been made, and consequently according to what rules could other similar statements be made? The description of the
events of discourse poses a quite different question:
how is it that one particular statement appeared
rather than another?" (p. 27). Obviously statement
is the key word here, and consequently, as we shall
see, Foucault must make the nature of the statement
coherent both from the standpoint of its retrospec-

diacritics/Summer1974
This content downloaded from 142.150.248.14 on Sat, 24 Jan 2015 17:13:19 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

29

3D

tive historical analysis and of its rationally intelligible method of production. However the place of
discourse, its setting, in which statements occur, is
specified by Foucault as the archive. The retrieval
of the archive from its own time and place in the
past and its description is what, with only the most
unavoidable geological analogy intended, he calls
archeology.
The next pressure has already been implied in
my initial definition of discourse and archive. Paradoxically history no longer can be conceived of as
a domain which is entirely, or even mainly, temporal
(if by time one means, generally, the linear succession of dates and events). Foucault begins The
Archeology of Knowledge with a stocktaking of the
extent to which recent historical research is about
"the great silent, motionless bases that traditional
history has covered with a thick layer of events" (p.
3). To uncover those bases is to admit that an
"epistemological mutation" has overtaken the study.
of history. Its essential point is what Foucault and
others have called decentering, which is fundamentally opposed to anthropological and humanistic attempts to write total history radiating out from man.
For the new kind of history there is no quasi-divine
archi, or telos, no Weltanschauung, no smug continuity, no immobile structures necessarily to be
found in it. The effects of ethnology, linguistics, psychoanalysis, and generally of Nietzschean interpretation have been to dissolve the priority of these
given calendars which supposedly typify time. Rather
the historian must now write general history: "a total
description draws all phenomena around a single
centre-a principle, a meaning, a spirit, a worldview, an overall shape; a general history, on the contrary, would deploy the space of a dispersion" (p.
10). How else is one to deal with such questions as
the "apparently unmoving histories" of "sea routes
[...] of corn or of gold-mining [...] of drought and
of irrigation [...] crop rotation [...] of the balance
achieved by the human species between hunger and
abundance" (p. 3)? No longer is the historian simply
to link events in a causal series; he must now ask
about different sorts of series, new criteria of periodization, differently articulated systems of relation
between series. Dates, by which a sequential calendar
miming the line of a man's life was formerly constructed and given priority, acquire diminished and
qualified significance. Recurrent distributions and
architectonic unities, displacements and transformations-these are the spatial indicators of historical
activity today, and it is Foucault's goal to formulate
a method sensitive to these indicators.
But the linear image of time, based on the sequential calendar of a man's life, is itself abetted by
"two models that have for so long imposed their
image: the linear model of speech (and partly at
least of writing) in which all events succeed one another, without any effect of coincidence and superposition; and the model of the stream of consciousness whose presence always eludes itself in its openness to the future and its retention of the past" (p.
169). It is to break the hold of these models that
Foucault describes discourse and archive, with their
own forms of sequence and succession. Here we
come to the third and the most complex pressure up-

on the new method. For just as history is not temporal sequence, because the birth-to-death span of
man's life is an adequate measure neither of large
units like demographic expansion, of phenomena of
rupture, discontinuity, coincidence, and complementarity, so too the spatial dispersion enacted by history cannot be filled with objects that are analogies
(disguised or not) or direct unmediated representations of human life. Textual evidence, in other
words, is based on historical documents, but these
documents are formed and persist monumentally,
according to their own laws, and not according to a
human image. A text does not simply record-is
not the pure graphological consequence of-an immediate desire to write. Rather it distributes various
textual impulses, regularly and on several axes; what
gives these impulses unity is what Foucault calls a
discursive formation, bound neither by an individual
author, a "period," a "work," nor an idea. A text,
to those who persist in making of a contingent printing device an ontological unit having final value, is a
fundamentally inconstant epistemological judgment.
The background for this more than simply
relativist thought was first sketched in detail by Foucault in the final pages of The Order of Things. He
remarked there how mimetic representation after
such writers as Sade, Mallarm6 and Nietzsche could
convey neither their desires nor their psychological
discoveries. Concurrently the logic of syntax as well
as the linear sequence of printed language in their
work is assaulted (and found wanting) by a wish to
express non-syntactic, non-sequential thought. Together with these writers, Marx, Saussure and Freud
put forward systems of thought for which no image
was adequate. Thus writing could not have a predictive form based either upon biological growth or upon a representative governing image. Instead writing
sought to constitute its own realm, inhabited entirely
by words and the spaces between them. In turn the
relations between this realm and empirical reality
were made possible according to particular strategies
and enunciative functions. What ideas one has about
a text therefore change definitively as one examines
a novel by Virginia Woolf, or a textbook of organic
chemistry, or a political pamphlet, all dating from
roughly the same period.
The Archeology of Knowledge takes the process of defining the realms of language and "reality"
commonly known by all three such "texts" a step
closer to formalization. The vocabulary and the
problematics of that kind of knowledge are articulated by Foucault with the principle negative aim of
avoiding descriptions equivalent to, or understandable in terms of, sense impressions. Since no image
is capable of containing knowledge-formal knowledge cannot be immediately seen, heard, smelled,
felt, or tasted-it can neither be produced nor sought
after (desired) in the simple experiential terms of
daily life. The will to knowledge expresses itself in
what Foucault calls an element of rarity very special
to it. Hence the pertinence of Foucault's choice of
savoir over connaissance (English regrettably translates both as knowledge) for the object of his study:
the former is unthinkable without reference to conditions and appropriations that make it knowledge, the
latter-as Foucault says in a summary of his 1970-

This content downloaded from 142.150.248.14 on Sat, 24 Jan 2015 17:13:19 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

71 course of lectures at the Collkge-is best studied


as something fundamentally subjective and selfish
(interessde), produced as an event of desire (produite
comme evenement du vouloir), and determining
truth by falsification (determinant par falsification
l'eflet de vdritd). Therefore knowledge (savoir)
is that of which one can speak in a discursive practice,
and which is specified by that fact: the domain constituted by the different objects that will or will not acquire
a scientific status (the knowledge of psychiatry in the
nineteenth century is not the sum of what was thought
to be true, but the whole set of practices, singularities,
and deviations of which one could speak in psychiatric
discourse); knowledge is also the space in which the
subject may take up a position and speak of the objects
with which he deals in his discourse (in this sense, the
knowledge of clinical medicine is the whole group of
functions of observations, interrogation, decipherment,
recording and decision that may be exercised by the subject of medical discourse); knowledge is also the field
of coordination and subordinationof statementsin which
concepts appear, and are defined, applied and transformed (at this level, the knowledge of Natural History,
in the eighteenth century, is not the sum of what was
said, but the whole set of modes and sites in accordance
with which one can integrate new statement with the
already said); lastly, knowledge is defined by the possibilities of use and appropriation offered by discourse
(thus, the knowledge of political economy, in the Classical period, is not the thesis of the different theses sustained, but the totality of its point of articulation on
other discourses or on other practices that are not discursive). There are bodies of knowledge that are independent of the sciences (which are neither their historical prototypes, nor their practical by-products), but
there is no knowledge without a particular discursive
practice; and any discursive practice may be defined by
the knowledge that it forms. (pp. 182-83)
Knowledge is specified by discourse, and vice
versa. The tautology does not matter, if only because what it thereby banished is a conception of
knowledge as the free-floating, spontaneous emanation of genius and/or individual hard work. Foucault is not the first modern to attack this romantically humanist vision of knowledge, although I think
he does more to regularize the irregularities of
knowledge, to specify knowledge that is, than most
others. The importance of the attack has gone far
too long unnoticed, however, especially in the United
States. In the first place romantic knowledge (connaissance), signifies property quite narrowly, the
property of the big brain whose inspiration knowledge therefore seems. Secondly it is antidemocratic,
not in any vague counter-culture sense, but rather
in the sense that permits its votaries to wave the banner of science and knowledge and, at the same time
to conceal the privilege-but not the rigor or real
science, which are absent-that entitles them to act
as thought-producers. In March 1972 Foucault began explicitly to speak of an interplay of desire,
power and interest as being the radical intellectual
target in the struggle to uncover the hidden strategies
of social power (L'Arc, number 49, p. 9). The continuity between such a statement and Foucault's attack upon anti-democratic epistemology in The
Archeology is plain. Thirdly, and this realization I
believe is necessitated by the first two, romantic
knowledge is anti-intellectual and anti-rational. Yet

nowhere does Foucault say as a result that knowledge (savoir) is immediately accessible to introspection, to direct questioning, or even to consciousness.
What he does say is that knowledge is produced, disseminated and reformed in ways that can be intelligibly specified and characterized, albeit with difficulty.
In one or two places Foucault carefully distinguishes
between his archeological method and Chomsky's
methods (never mentioned by name) of linguistic
analysis based upon the generative model. While
both theories appear to have a strong libertarian
thrust, archeology,
by seizing, out of the mass of things said, upon the
statement defined as a function of realization of the
verbal performance, distinguishes itself from a search
whose privilegedfield is linguistic competence:while such
a description constitutes a generative model, in order to
define the acceptability of statements, archeology tries
to establish rules of formation, in order to define the condition of their realization. (p. 207)
The opacity of this disclaimer thins out a bit if it is
read with the following, earlier, passage in mind:
"it is vain to seek, beyond structural, formal, or interpretative analyses of language, a domain that is at
last freed from all positivity, in which the freedom
of the subject, the labour of the human being, or the
opening up of a transcendental destiny could be fulfilled" (p. 112).
Positivity and specification: these make up the
tough, almost material, rind of knowledge. Yet like
an archive (as understood conventionally) they are
not wholly corporeal either, for they inhabit a special medium of rarity. Mainly, positive and specifiable knowledge is regular, it absorbs discontinuity
and individual effort, it conceals its structure, it is
eminently capable of being there, even if it is not
visible, and it is repeatable. This is not as unimaginable a constellation of features as its seems. Foucault has assembled together various characterizations made by other writers, some of whom he names
and acknowledges, others he probably did not have in
mind. It is a useful exercise to describe a few of
these correlative discoveries made by others. They
have the virtue of placing Foucault against a relatively familiar background where, if my irony is not
mis-interpreted, the almost oppressively novel vocabulary of his methodology itself seems more regular.
Nevertheless one must note that Foucault's own
thought about originality is highly ambivalent. I
shall return to that critical problem a little later.
One brings Foucault together with Thomas S.
Kuhn, Georges Canguilhem and Michael Polanyi
only with trepidation. Nevertheless I have ventured
to do so and find the attempt instructive. All of
these writers on the structure of scientific knowledge
stress the regularity of that knowledge, that is, the
shared paradigms discussed by Kuhn that comprise a
"research consensus." This consensus enables further
research, accommodates or is radically altered by
anomaly, and always, according to Kuhn, performs
the function of providing in ongoing time "a new
and more rigid definition of the field" of scientific
research. "Men whose research is based on shared
paradigms are committed to the same rules and
standards for scientific practice. That commitment
and the apparent consensus it produces are prereq-

diacritics/Summer1974
This content downloaded from 142.150.248.14 on Sat, 24 Jan 2015 17:13:19 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

31

32

uisites for normal science, i.e. for the genesis and


continuation of a particular research tradition" (The
Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: Univ.
of Chicago Press, rev. ed. 1970; p. 11). If new
problems emerge as anomalies it is because they are
in disharmony with "the background provided by
the paradigm" (p. 65). Within the paradigm, as
Canguilhem showed in a very early study that predates Kuhn's Scientific Revolutions by nineteen
years, criteria are formed in medicine, for instance,
that determine "the normal" and "the pathological."
He concludes that "every empirical concept of illness
retains a disciplined relation with an axiological concept of illness. Consequently it is not an objective
method that characterizes a biological phenomenon
as pathological. It is always the relation between observer and individual patient, mediated by the clinic,
which justifies the label pathological" (Le Normal et
le pathologique. Paris: P. U. F., rev. ed. 1962; p.
156). Canguilhem dispels the subjectivist fallacy by
saying that there is such a thing as objective pathology so long as it is understood first that that objectivity is absolutely tied to a specific biological history
(with its own time, events, sequence, sociology, order) and second, that the object of objective pathological practice "is not so much a fact as a value"
(p. 157).
In 1966 Canguilhem refined this view by saying that within a science like pathology there are
norms that regulate even the concept of error. Thus
"health is a genetic and enzymatic correction of an
error [in the substitution of one molecular arrangement for another: the conceptual structure of biochemistry here is borrowed from informationtheory]. To be sick is to have been wrong, wrong not
in the sense of a counterfeit note in the sense of a
false brother, but in the sense of a mistaken fold of
the page, or of a wrong line of verse" (Canguilhem, p. 208). In Personal Knowledge (Chicago:
which Kuhn reUniv. of Chicago Press, 1958)-to
fers-and in his Lindsay Memorial Lectures, The
Study of Man (Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press,
1959), Polanyi demonstrates that what he calls tacit
knowledge can be incorporated, and is indeed an
important part of what passes for "objective" scientific research. Tacit knowledge need not be immediately formulable in a set of rules; nonetheless it is
consentual and works as a basis upon which scientific research conducts itself. The point is that even
the apparently contradictory status of explicit and
implicit knowledge, as well as the discontinuity between them, does not inhibit the regularity of the
whole body of scientific knowledge at any given
time. Kuhn's brilliant analysis of the role played
by textbooks in contributing to the scientific paradigm stands in a fairly close relation to Foucault's
account of discursive practice "as a body of anonymous, historical rules, always determined in the
time and space that have defined a given period, and
for a given social, economic, geographical, or linguistic area, the conditions of operation of the enunciative function" (p. 117).
Foucault's archeology of knowledge scants the
difference between science, social science and humanities. All of these divisions are subject to the
laws of discursive practice, and the relations between

them are equally a function of these laws. If from


the "archeological" historian's viewpoint, a society
can be studied as a quasi-transcendental form of discourse (I adapt this notion from Angus Fletcher's
theory of a transcendental art-form in his The Transcendental Masque: An Essay on Milton's "Comus."
Ithaca: Cornell Univ. Press, 1972), then the intrasocial exclusions and incorporations that comprise
the penal system, the organization of university curricula, the structure of the political bureaucracy, insofar as these are coherent positivities, are discursive
practices, too. Thus a positvity is that acted-upon
knowledge which can be rationally ascertained and
articulated, no matter how implicit or hidden it may
first appear to be. The more one reads in Foucault
the more one notices the extent to which he is suspicious of, and attracted to, knowledge whose practice conceals the fact of its fabrication. He has this
in common obviously with a number of modern
thinkers, of whom Barthes the structuralist, Lukics
and Adorno, the neo-Marxists, furnish the most
directly relevant analogies. Barthes' anatomy of
myth (in Mythologies) construes the bourgeois habit
of appeals to immutable "reality" as a form of illusionment, by which what is present is falsely given
as not-made and always-there. Lukics' definition of
proletarian class-consciousness also demonstrates
how the bourgeois status-quo masks a discourse or a
theory that denies its own self-preserving activity.
And Adorno, whose philosophical investigations of
contemporary reality play an important role in Frederic Jameson's excellent Marxism and Form (Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press, 1972), equates the socalled autonomy of a work of art in class society
with the class-derived concealment of work:
Works of art owe their existence to the social division
of labor, to the separation of mental and physical work.
In such a situation, however, they appear under the
guise of independent existence; for their medium is not
that of pure and autonomous spirit, but rather that of a
spirit which having become object now claims to have
surmounted the opposition between the two. Such contradiction obliges the work of art to conceal the fact
that it is itself a human construction. (p. 408)
Jameson continues Adorno's argument as follows:
"There is thus given within the very concept of work
-either in the form of the division of labor in general or in the more specialized types of production
characteristic of capitalism-the principle of a censorship of the work process itself, of a repression of
the traces of labor on the product."
Yet if the work process is not to remain occult,
a certain order must be assumed for it. How, if one
does not wish to employ crude sensationalist metaphors, can one depict rational work as a process having significant material consequences? How does one
deal with the problem of showing discourse in its
persistence to be what Foucault has called a materialistic incorporeal? Val6ry's Leonardo comes to mind
here. What interests Val6ry in Leonardo is not his
biography but his constructive power as a mind.
Construction itself has its own logic whose basis is
an "intervention in natural things." The initial step
in a construction is a decision to move away from
nature and into the constructive element. (There is
an interesting study of Leonardo's use of sketches

This content downloaded from 142.150.248.14 on Sat, 24 Jan 2015 17:13:19 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

that develops this theme further than Valry: E. H.


Gombrich's "Leonardo's Method of Working out
Compositions" in his Norm and Form: Studies in
the Art of the Renaissance (London: Phaidon,
1966). Thereafter Val6ry meditates upon Leonardo's
architectural projections for monuments which, although they have no empirical equivalent, nevertheless have a special empirical validity. Leonardo saw
"the air [as being] full of infinite lines, straight and
radiating, intercrossing, and interweaving without
ever coinciding one with another." In this element of
rarity Leonardo puts his monuments:
The monument (which composes the City, which
in turn is almost the whole of civilization) is such a complex entity that our understandingof it passes through
several successive phases. First we grasp a changeable
background that merges with the sky, then a rich texture of motifs in height, breadth, and depth, infinitely
varied by perspective, then something solid, bold, resistant, with certain animal characteristics-organs, members-then finally a machine having gravity for its motive force, one that carries us in thought from geometry
to dynamics and thence to the most tenuous speculations
of molecular physics. (Valkry. Collected Works. Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press, 1972; vol. III, pp. 49-50)
"In our time," says Foucault, "history is that which
transforms documents into monuments" (p. 7). Val6ry's account of the constructed monument corresponds to Foucault's concept of the duration in history of texts as monument: the historian's discipline
is archeology ("the intrinsic description of the monument") which also passes through several successive
phases. A document's monumentality can only
emerge when discourse is not elided with reality.
The time of its construction, the time of monumental duration, the time of its analysis: these three are
correlates that tend differently to repeat each other
without being copies of nature or of an ideal. Monumentality is the general mode of presence of discourse, although in the special sense of the word intended by Foucault (like Valery before him) monumental presence does not exclusively mean empirical
visibility. A library, for instance, is one particular
mode of presence for discourse as monument: as visible objects the books in the stacks are less important
than the infinitely interwined lines that connect the
books to each other and keep the word on the pages.
Moreover in the conception of books and
language as a universe that Borges has made current, each discourse becomes a sort of cross-reference to every other discourse. In such a universe
there is no determinable origin and no final goal,
since repetition underlies cross-reference. Foucault's
philosophical affinity with Gilles Deleuze derives
from this interest in repetition, although recently the
affinity has become political as well. Deleuze's Difference et repetition (Paris: P. U. F., 1968) goes a
very long way towards laying forth a philosophy of
repetition with which Foucault, whose recognition
that there is no Origin is pre-supposed by his interest
in repetition and discourse, has publicly agreed.
What makes such comparative abstractions like difference and repetition clear in Deleuze's otherwise
very complex argument is his way of describing
those things as forms of action. "Repetition [in time]
is a condition of action before it becomes a concept

of reflection" (Deleuze, p. 21). Using examples from


Marx, H61derlin, Vico, and Nietzsche, Deleuze constructs before his reader the drama of repetition that
is capable of producing the absolutely different.
Aside from being an appealingly surprising volte-face,
this argument reveals the extent to which repetition,
as a device or a mode or a philosophic habit, is not
the opposite of originality in the romantic sense of
that word. If as a concept or a description, originality concealed an appeal to some extra-positive "privilege" (the Muse, inspiration, a "raptus") it also
contained an anxiety about the value of what one
was saying. As Vico was one of the first to argue,
all utterance is a form of re-inscription: hence originality is a far more unstable quality. Instead, it and
creativity belong inherently to what Harold Bloom
calls misprision, one of whose signs is parody, the
form of writing relied upon to a great extent by
many of the modern masters like Eliot, Mann and
Joyce. This deliberate mis-taking characterizes inventiveness. Far from being the -realization of an
"interiority" like inspiration, discourse for Foucault
is only misprision and exteriority: "it is a practical
domain that is autonomous" (p. 121). Therefore,
"the time of discourse is not the translation, in a
visible chronology, of the obscure time of thought"
(p. 121). Here we can begin to understand how
repetition produces difference.
Discursive language is like a repertory theatre
that stages numerous spectacles. This figure connects
Foucault with Kenneth Burke's dramatistic analysis
of literature, although Foucault holds that discursive
practice is neither benign nor necessarily artistic:
effectiveness is its main criterion of success. Effectiveness can be judged in several ways but Foucault
is right, I think, not to make effectiveness dependent
upon so fickle a perception as the retrospective critic's. Yet neither is effectiveness passive conformity to
a sort of general will. Discursive practice is modified
constantly by each statement made within it, just as
in Kuhn's discussion of the research paradigm every
research worker re-articulates a special aspect of the
paradigm and extends and refines it further. We
must still ask, however, where discursive practice
actually takes place, how is its effectiveness measured
or realized, and what sort of activity it is really. In
answering these questions in The Archeology of
Knowledge Foucault admits that what he supplies is
not yet a theory but only a possibility (pp. 114-15).
One ought to be willing to accept this qualification
if, in exchange, the possibility provides enough of an
indication that a possibility now is not just an excuse
for the absence of theory. In other words, is a possibility described at length forceful enough to prepare
the ground for a theory? I think it is, in this case.
For Foucault is proposing a method for understanding social behaviour as what it is that people
must do in order to speak and write as contributors
to an ongoing system of the values, discoveries, errors, and institutions that we call knowledge (savoir).
Since knowledge is neither a mysterious jumble of
ideas nor a fact of nature, and since it is not something that one has but something that one does, it is
best conceived of initially as occupying a group of
hypothetical spaces. One of them might be where
one stands in order to speak, another might be from

dkccri IS/Summer1974
This content downloaded from 142.150.248.14 on Sat, 24 Jan 2015 17:13:19 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

3J

where he draws forth the elements he combines to


make a statement, another might be where he puts
his statement, and a fourth might be where his statement is either preserved, modified, accumulated, or
passed on. Surrounding all these places is a set of
general boundaries, or limits, that holds all the other
spaces in. This constraint is the dpistm&e, which,
when it is specified as an actively populated expanse
of knowledge-acts at a given moment in history, is
not an open space but rather a system of distances.
Thus in the eighteenth century, for example, the distance between religion and psychology as discipline is
closer than it is a hundred years later. The whole
map of such relations is what Foucault means by
dpistime. This is very different from describing a
Zeitgeist, or an ideology, or a Weltanschauung. What
distinguishes dpisteme from them is not that all are
unconscious or communal, but that only the episteme
is not an implicit belief-system sometimes projected
by individuals or institutions. Rather the dpistmrne"is
a constantly moving set of articulations, shifts, and
coincidences that are established only to give rise to
others" (p. 192).
The rules collectively governing these movetheir appearance
ments of the dpistem'-governing
as events, for the dpistime is usually described by
Foucault as a set of moving constraints that estabdiscourse
lish an outer limit of knowledge-make
possible. The historical economy of discourse is the
archive:
The archive is first the law of what can be said,
the system that governs the appearance of statements as
unique events. But the archive is also that which determines that all these things said do not accumulate endlessly in an amorphous mass, nor are they inscribed in
an unbroken linearity, nor do they disappear at the
mercy of chance external accidents;but they are grouped
together in distinct figures, composed together in accordance with multiple relations, maintained or blurred in
accordance with specific regularities. ... The archive is
not that which, despite its immediate escape, safeguards
the event of the statement, and preserves, for future
memories, its status as an escape; it is that which embodies it, defines at the outset the system of its enunciability. Nor is the archive that which collects the dust
of statements that have become inert once more, and
which may make possible the miracle of their resurrection; it is that which defines the mode of occurrence of
the statement-thing;it is the system of its functioning.
Far from being that which unifies everything that has
been said in the great confused murmur of a discourse,
far from being only that which insures that we exist in
the midst of preserved discourse, it is that which differentiates discourses in their multiple existence and specifies them in their own duration. (p. 129)
Discourses exist within the archive. They are specialized modes of utterance (clinical discourse, for instance, or sociological discourse) that must not be
confused with simple jargon. A discourse is systematic, and it has epistemological, social, political,
economic and historical relations with other discourses in the archive. Most important, the discourse
is not dialectical-"without flaw, without contradiction, without internal arbitrariness" (p. 114)-and
is made up of statements, which "bear an enunciative function" (p. 115).
We are back to effectiveness, and it now be-

comes possible to see that Foucault is most interested


in defining the statement: the dpisteme', the archive,
even discourse, all these are analytic instruments
more or less invented by the archeologist in order
to approach the statement, in order to provide a
suitable terminology for apprehending the statement,
which is after all the very mode and presence of
effectiveness. For Foucault the statement is not a
sentence necessarily, nor any unit describable by
grammar or logic. Moreover since it is in and of
discourse it cannot be something latent that is realized by discourse. The more Foucault enumerates
what a statement is not, the more it is evident that
a statement is difficult both to make and to describe:
it is rare.
The statement is not just another unity-above or below-sentences and propositions; it is always invested
in unities of this kind, or even in sequences of signs
that do not obey their laws (and which may be lists,
chance series, tables); it characterizesnot what is given
in them, but the very fact that they are given, and the
way in which they are given. It has the quasi-invisibility
of the "there is," which is effaced in the very thing of
which one can say: "thereis this or that thing." (p. 111)
Perhaps a prefiguration of what Foucault means by
a statement is to be found in the smile of the Cheshire cat or, as he himself says in the opening pages of
The Order of Things, in the list of animals given in
a Chinese encyclopedia referred to in "The Analytical Language of John Wilkins" by Borges. "Although the statement cannot be hidden it is not visible either [...] it is like the over-familiar that constantly eludes one" (pp. 110-11). Another important
aspect of the statement is that it is correlative with
a lack: "There may in fact be-and always are-in
the conditions of emergence of statements, exclusions, limits, or gaps that divide up their referential,
validate only one series of modalities, enclose groups
of coexistence, and prevent certain forms of use"
(p. 110). Thus a statement emerging prevents another utterance from emerging; conversely, with regard to a whole series of possibilities, a statement
emerges to be something else, namely, a statement,
but not an idea, or a sentence, or a passing remark.
At all events, one thing at least must be emphasized here: that the analysis of discourse [and of statements in and by discourse] thus understood, does not reveal the universality of a meaning, but brings to light
the action of imposed rarity, with a fundamental power
of affirmation.Rarity and affirmation:rarity, in the last
resort of affirmation[Swyer's translation here is impossibly garbled: Foucault says, "the rarity of affirmation"]
-certainly not any continuous out-pouring of meaning,
and certainly not any monarchy of the signifier. (p. 234)
The peculiar, and I think the crucial, problem
of The Archeology of Knowledge is its attempt to
define effectiveness without theory, that is, to regard
practice not as a cause of effectiveness but as the
main part of it. To affirm with force even as one excludes much else-this is effectiveness. Effectiveness
is also to modify other effective statements, and it is
also to last, to be re-activated (as when a later age
returns to Marx or to Freud), to be consciously excluded (as when The Wasteland excludes Christianity), to be re-appropriated (as in his essay "Kafka

This content downloaded from 142.150.248.14 on Sat, 24 Jan 2015 17:13:19 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

and his Precursors" Borges gives Kafka his forgotten


patrimony).
Lest it be assumed that statements in discourse
during a given epistime make up a unity resembling
either the Great Chain of Being or a Hegelian totality Foucault goes out of his way to show that this
is not what he has in mind. Two of his most complex chapters in The Archeology-"Contradictions"
and "The Comparative Facts"-insist
yet more
strongly on the discontinuous nature of statements
in the archive. To the archeologist discourse is a
space of dissension. Eighteenth-century Natural History, for instance, is essentially a set of "intrinsic
oppositions [... . distributed over different levels of
the discursive formation" (p. 154). These oppositions articulate divergence, incompatibility, and exclusion. "In the case of the systematic analysis of
plants [in eighteenth-century Natural History], one
applies a rigorous perceptual and linguistic code,
and in accordance with a constant scale; for methodical description [during the same period], the codes
are relatively free, and the scales of mapping may
oscillate" (p. 154). When; however, there are no
contradictions-that
is, if one wishes to show, as
Foucault did in The Order of Things, that eighteenth
century General Grammar and Natural History are
related after all-there is "a region of interpositivity," which is tangled but is also a set of fairly wellarticulated correlations.
Everything I have so far said of Foucault interprets, rather than summarizes, his archeology as
simultaneously the expression of radical dissatisfaction and radical affirmation. Let us take dissatisfaction and doubt first. I think he is correct to judge
Western historical understanding as being based very
generally upon two forms of explanation, one vertical, and one horizontal. Both generally work together since both mix the temporal and the spatial
modes. Written historical evidence is judged to be
a trace, which when it is explained vertically is conceived of as the exterior residual expression of an
interior, or underlying, force, rationale, meaning,
image, or idea. When it is explained horizontally it
is conveived of as having been preceded by something that gives it meaning: other events, a successive line of development, an Origin. To Foucault
any form of understanding that sends one away to
given or assumed ontologically prior forms such as
an author, a period, an idea, a source, a world-view
-in short, a genealogy of order-discounts the presence of the evidence, its sheer persistence as event
or as evidence, in favor of deterministic hypostatizations. Moreover these determinisms assume a privilege in the understanding without account being
taken of their very circumstantial nature. When
Nietzsche said that discussions of poets like Homer
(about whom as authors nothing was known) were
judgments made by later generations and not at all
accurate descriptions of reality, he was saying something that Foucault would agree with readily. To say
that Shelley wrote "Adonais" is not sufficiently to
describe the fact that "Adonais" was written. In order to do that one would have to grasp first of all
why to the critic in 1973 it matters that the poem
was written (and this involves an archeological description of literary discourse today), then to grasp

how as writing the poem was received, modified and


preserved in poetico-elegiac discourse in the early
nineteenth century. While one may never to able to
complete such an archeological description-and
Foucault is under no illusion that it is anything but
interminable-its stated requirements are at least a
didactic way of showing that the concept of author
as origin is an unsatisfactory terminal from which
to begin or conclude. So too with Weltanschauungen
and similar ideas of order.
Deleuze has said quite ingeniously that Foucault has rejected horizontal and vertical explanations in favor of "diagonal mobility." This is an
interesting suggestion but it strikes me as too mechanical somehow. An image I prefer is that in his
almost exclusive attention to exteriority and surface
while discussing statements, Foucault is like a man
who runs across rooftops, never descending into the
houses, never going straight, always really moving
from side to side. This perhaps silly picture begins
to get at the combination of realism, freedom and
discipline with which he negotiates the discontinuous
order of knowledge. He is interested in describing
the fact that knowledge is both produced and there,
in knowing, for example, what concatenation of
events (not mere happenings) made it possible for
Linnaeus to produce his system of classification and
one, (I shall permit myself a solecism) not not to
produce it, two, to produce it when he did, three, to
have produced it as it was produced. This is the
aspect of Foucault's work that exemplifies radical
affirmation. Since all knowledge is rarity, which is
the affirmation of a process of exclusion (to know
B is not to know A), then knowledge ("le savoir du
savoir") must also be affirmative. Foucault's lists of
negatives, e.g. archeology is not history of ideas, a
statement is not a sentence, discourse is not made up
of ideas-all these affirm the positive exclusions that
add to knowledge. The will to knowledge therefore
is an effort made to exclude that which is not suitable as knowledge.
This has been one of Foucault's constant
themes, and the extent to which he has shown how
an affirmation exclusion means that what is excluded
is systematically organized and in turn refers to what
it has excluded and organized, is one of the things
that distinguishes him from structuralism and its
more simply appropriated linguistic models. I have
said in another essay that structuralism begins with
linguicity: structuralism assumes that things can be
apprehended by and as signs in a language, and the
pertinent task for the analyst is attention to a system of signs with perpetual, even if theoretic, presence. Foucault's position is that an existing system
of signs is a judgment already made that those particular signs shall be. He investigates the process of
signs being made. In this insistence upon a judgment
made both to exclude and include, Foucault therefore describes language ethically, in the literal sense.
The source or pure origin of language is something
he cannot discuss; however, for every statement in
discourse he can show that there is a beginning made
up of organized exclusions and inclusions, a setting
amidst other permitted statements, a continuity, and
ascertainable transformations.
Discourse is therefore the organized social

1974
diacritics/Summer
This content downloaded from 142.150.248.14 on Sat, 24 Jan 2015 17:13:19 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

35

36

ethic of language: "I am supposing that in every society the production of discourse is at once controlled, selected, organized and redistributed according to a certain number of procedures, whose role is
to avert its powers and its dangers, to cope with
chance events, to evade its ponderous, awesome
materiality" (p. 216). In 1916 Walter Benjamin put
a similar ethical insight into language at the centre
of an essay on language in general and human language in particular. Before the Fall in Eden, Benjamin says, the only knowledge without a name was
the knowledge of good and evil. All things have a
name, all knowledge is nouns. The serpent tempts
man with new knowledge, Good and Evil, which
thereafter
abandons the name. [This new knowledge] is exterior
knowledge, the uncreative imitation of [God's] creative
verb. The name steps away from itself in this knowledge:
the Fall is the moment of birth of man's language (des
menschlichen Wortes), that in which the name no longer
remains intact, that which has left behind a language
that names and the language-one can say-that knew
its own immanent magic, all this in order for language
now to make itself deliberately magical from the outside. The word must communicate something now, outside itself. (Das Wort soll "etwas" ausser sich selbst).
This is really the original sin of the spirit of language.
As it communicates outside of itself the word is something of a parody, by an explicitly mediate word, of the
explicitly immediate word, of God's creative word (das
schaffende Gotteswort); it is the Fall of a fortunate essence of language (der Verfall des seligen Sprachgeistes)
in Adam, who stands in the middle. There is indeed a
basic sameness between the word which, according to the
serpent's promise, perceives good and evil and the word
which on the surface conveys information. The cognition/perception of things/objects is based on the name,
but perception of good and evil is, in the profound
sense in which Kierkegaardconceives this word, idle talk
or chatter, capable only of the purificationand elevation
to which the babbling man, i.e. the sinner, also had to
submit, namely Judgment. (Schriften. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1955; vol. II, pp. 414-15)
Discourse, says Foucault, is things that are said (les
chatter-whose
rarity
choses dites)-profoundly,
(purification and elevation) is the form of judgment
(on what is being excluded and on whomever does
the exclusion), exteriority, and knowledge.
One reason therefore that Foucault seems to
give artists, visionaries, madmen, and deviants
(Hblderlin, Sade, Nietzsche, Beckett) so important
a place in his historical and theoretical studies is
that they, more than the average user of discourse,
exaggerate and make plain in their solitude and
alienation the exteriority of discursive practice by
outdoing discourse. What is heroic about such men
is, paradoxically, their willingness to accept the terrifying freedom that comes from hyper-individuality.
To make "I speak" into what Foucault calls a solitary sovereignty is to be free of all social and psychological limitations: the individual act of speech upon
which all is made deliberately to depend is no longer
communication of something, but the stretchingforth (dtalement) of language in its raw state, as
pure, deployed exteriority. Modern literature in the
main is the result of this exteriority, which is not the
result of signs returning to a point of origin for validation, and not mimetic representation. Modern lit-

erature escapes the mode of being of discourse, but


one result is that the speaking subject who inaugurates the freedom of exteriority has, by the time of
Beckett's work, become a victim of language. Molloy:
"I must go on; I can't go on; I must say words as
long as there are words, I must say them until they
find me, until they say me-heavy burden, heavy sin;
I must go on; maybe it's been done already; maybe
they've already said me; maybe they've already borne
me to the threshold of my story, right to the door
opening onto my story; I'd be surprised if it opened"
(cited by Foucault, p. 215).
But the role of the modern artist, mainly in
the nineteenth century, is in his quasi-madness to
stimulate discourse to change. Many readers of Foucault have been troubled by the seeming absence in
his work of any way of explaining how one epistime
changes into another. I think the answer one finds
is largely symbolic: it is that any alienated man or
group of men, who are hidden beneath discourse as
the insane are hidden in asylums, nevertheless speak
from their own exteriority to society. These bursts
across the fabric of discourse create rents that discourse is forced to repair. I suspect that Foucault
regards Nietzsche and Freud as the most severe and
the most recent of challengers to discourse: as authors he says that they are founders of discourse.
Their work requires so great an adjustment in modes
with Marx, Nietzsche
of interpretation-together
and Freud make interpretation a literally unending
task since they begin by saying that there is no beginning-that interpretation itself becomes a special
discursive formation. It is within the discourse of
interpretation that Foucault's archeology is to be
found, although presumably it is modifying the discourse as it takes its course. The coherence of Foucault's work, despite its visions and revisions, is that
he has always returned to the past in order to release from their silence those utterances blanketted
by discourse. The Archeology of Knowledge constructs, with a terminology that often threatens to
overcome the matter with which it purports to deal,
the skeleton of discourse, archive and statement,
whose ethic is hidden in the exteriority of practice.
Who then is Foucault? To me he typifies, in
a more complex and interesting form than any contemporary writer I know, the problem of modern
beginnings, a predicament to be found lurking everywhere in modern rationalism. He himself seems very
aware of the difficulty of his position. His most important work, his inaugural Legon at the College de
France delivered on December 2, 1970 opens as
follows:
I would like to have slipped imperceptiblyinto this lecture, as into all the others I shall be delivering, perhaps
over the years ahead. I would have preferred to be enveloped in words, borne away beyond all possible beginnings. At the moment of speaking, I would like to
have perceived a nameless voice, long preceding me,
leaving me merely to enmesh myself in it, taking up its
cadence, and to lodge myself, when no one was looking,
in its interstices as if it had paused an instant, in suspense, to beckon to me. There would have been no beginnings: instead, speech would proceed from me, while
I stood in its path-a slender gap-the point of its possible disappearance.(p. 215)

This content downloaded from 142.150.248.14 on Sat, 24 Jan 2015 17:13:19 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

This, he says later, is an expression of anxiety, for


to be an author is to take on the responsibility for
what one says. But what Foucault discovers is that
the order of discourse, and discourse itself, allay
this fear of responsibility. By being the order of
spoken things, organized, controlled, and made to
function by society, discourse reduces the author's
authority. His "real" beginning then is his awareness
of being already inserted in the order of discourse.
And yet Foucault himself in his work says, by almost
any literary standard, original things. His oeuvre
has a unity all its own, and indeed a beginning all its
own in the perceptions he has of history and language. As author then he dramatizes a vacillation between writing as discourse (the author is a function
of the discourse, in this case, of interpretation) and
writing against discourse.
This vacillation I take to be of the greatest interest. For it emphasizes the extent to which writing
is necessarily caught between conflicting pressures
which, in a large, relatively unforced view of them,
are ultimately cultural and political. Every writer, as
he writes, uses other writing, draws upon his ego,
addresses others and his own sense of himself. How
much in his writing is originality, how much repetition and re-combining of "the order of discourse,"
how much exploitation of the discourse, how much
exploitation by the discourse, how much exploitation
of whatever silent voices may be hidden and excluded by discourse? Foucault has recently begun
to devote himself to a study of the penal system,
which is an economic, social and political organization put together, in its operative forcefulness, as a
discourse. What he has already said about discourse
leaves this particular undertaking prey to the doubt
that his decision to study penal laws is a beginning
that may, on the one hand, be a re-assertion of a
discourse concerning crime in contemporary France,
but may, on the other hand, begin a new system of
thought about crime. Similarly, since Foucault has
always explicitly addressed Western discourse, we
must ask whether such an archeological project as
his has not further intensified the ethnocentricity of
Western discourse in its appropriation of the oppressed races everywhere under its domination, or
whether archeology can supply other cultures with
the instruments with which to withstand further
domination?
These problems have everywhere appeared
whenever a method has taken on the task of connecting the most minute particulars of human experience with the most common and universal of
human concerns. Vico, Marx, Nietzsche, Freud are
notable examples. As with most contemporary writers Foucault is saturated with their discoveries and
emboldened by their examples. Yet still more explicitly than they, he acknowledges that their work
places drastic limitations upon the idea of man as
author of his work. So much so that discourse-the
monumentality of man's organized utterance-is an
order of, indeed is, repetition. To begin therefore is
to repeat. If I have understood The Archeology of
Knowledge correctly, however, consciousness of
repetition, as a rational method of understanding, is
a way of beginning to stand openly in the path of
mistaken originality. When a society oppresses its

citizens in the name of an original spirit of laws, or


when a writer masks his opportunism behind a common original "tradition," or, conversely, when revolution is derided as the repetition of hopeless utopianism, then in response one can begin again to
study, act, write-again. Learning and, consequently,
writing, as the author alternates between them, exemplify the cycle of repetition and beginning, but it
is when the distance between them is not made either
into a fetish or a commodity (called, with marketoriented affirmation, originality or creativity) that
they lead to knowledge and freedom.
Much of Foucault's latest work is a kind of
formalized recapitulation of Western historical understanding, done with such complex instruments of
rational exposition as to give that understanding, and
the accumulation of power that it represents, an almost physical presence. For such a presence a recourse to romantic originality is no response, and
neither are dropping out, the recitation of revolutionary-sounding slogans, or empty appeals to a
long-gone past. Although they are very much
his own invention, Foucault's array of "anonymous
rules" binding knowledge together, along with his repeated insistence upon their anonymity, are, I think,
an invitation to the intellectual to see knowledge
practically as a collective responsibility. When he
says that he presents not a theory but a possibility
Foucault is saying also that such a possibility calls
for judgment, analysis, consideration on the part of
other workers in knowledge. That the validation of
the possibility cannot restore what Benjamin calls
the fortunate essence of language should be quite
evident: so long as one recognizes that there is such
a thing as knowledge, alas there is no disinterested
language.
Those observations comprise the rational element of Foucault's relevance to Western cultural
radicalism and also to the radical nationalism of the
non-Western world. Foucault's support of these two
disparate movements has been unstinting, but he has
never, and hopefully will never, take the step of substituting agitation dominated by undigested philosophies of unrepeatable revolution for study and
analysis conceived of as making differences within
the order of repetition. Notwithstanding Sartre's
profoundly ill-considered attack on Foucault (in
1966) for his alleged anti-historical attitude, Foucault has been concerned with what men have made
with what they have. If what they have is "doxological" there is no reason whatever for saying consequently that because a doxology is maintained on a
level of its own (the archive), it is therefore outside
of history. Quite the contrary. Archeology has sought
to describe systematically the systematic exchanges
between knowledge and the historical conditions
which gave rise to it. If system here is repetition, we
can be expected to examine first the need for repetition (in laws of exclusion that society has always
employed), and then we can go on to investigate
whether what has been excluded has impoverished
a large part of society justly or unjustly. One can
work rationally on this basis, and historically as well,
for to be concerned with knowledge is to be of history without being uniformly subject to its repeated
illusions.

diocritics/Summer 1974
This content downloaded from 142.150.248.14 on Sat, 24 Jan 2015 17:13:19 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

31

S-ar putea să vă placă și