Sunteți pe pagina 1din 21

A Japanese View of Theatricality 73

The Structure of Theater :


A Japanese View of Theatricality

Mitsuya Mori

The Western concept of “theater” did not exist in pre-modern Japan.


Engeki was the word chosen to translate “theater” when it was introduced
to Japan in the second half of 19th century.1 It still sounds a little foreign to
Japanese people. Traditionally Japan had a word shibai, which was almost
equivalent to “theater,” but was, and still is, applied only to Kabuki and
Bunraku (puppet theater) and not to Noh. The modern westernized theater
is not usually called shibai, either, for this sounds too colloquial or too non-
literal. The adjective forms of shibai, shibai-jimita or shibai-gakatta, imply
“pretentious” or “insincere” behavior, a definitely pejorative nuance,
equivalent to the negative meaning of the English term “theatrical.”
“Theatricality,” on the other hand, is rendered in Japanese as engeki-sei.
The suffix -sei makes an abstraction of the preceding noun. The foreignness
of engeki is reinforced by this suffix, for the abstraction of theatricality is also
a Western way of thinking, imported into Japan only in modern times.
Grammatically, it would be possible to add -sei to shibai as well, but shibai-sei
sounds odd and is not in common usage. This means that there is no Japanese
word that is exactly equivalent to the slightly pejorative “theatricality.”
Instead, engeki-sei (theatricality) is used to mean the spectacular quality of
theater, or the qualities unique to theater—i.e. particular qualities that
construct the kind of performance we could call theater. It is in this sense
that the word was often uttered to describe the new trend of Japanese theater
since the late 1960s. But some representatives of this “underground” theater
would like to call their activities shibai rather than engeki, as a revolt against
“modern theater.” They have even declared themselves to be closer to the
old conception of performance art in Japan, geinoh.
Geinoh (“gay-noh”) is another Japanese word, fairly equivalent to
“theater” but covering the broader or narrower realm of performance arts,
depending on the context. (I will return to this issue later.) Though the word
itself first appeared in literature in the 10th century,2 much earlier than shibai,
today the word is also commonly used, and obviously intersects with engeki-
sei. The distinction between engeki, shibai and geinoh is not a clear-cut one,
© Board of Regents, University of Wisconsin System, 2002 73
SubStance # 98/99, Vol. 31, nos. 2 & 3, 2002
74 Mitsuya Mori

and it becomes almost meaningless to attempt to define the words at all.


(Such confusion is an inevitable result of modernization, and is seen in many
fields of culture in Japan.) But if our goal is not simply defining terms, but
understanding what theater is, then we need to move beyond the definition
of concepts. Our understanding of the topics will be deepened in the course
of discussing them. Our topics are theater and theater-like performances,
which still exist in abundance in Japan.
There are many ways to analyze theater. I will limit my arguments here
to the structural analysis of theater events—i.e. basic characteristics of theater
to be distinguished from other performative activities, in order to clarify
“theatricality” to some degree.

From Creator to Audience


Theater is play and so is music. As an art form, theater and music have
some structural similarities. In the aesthetic classification of art forms, theater
and music are put into the same category—performing arts.
A composer writes a piece of music, which is perceived by someone
else. This “someone else” is usually a musician who plays the score to be
perceived by the audience. This sequence can be schematized as follows:

Composer —> Musical Composition —> Score reader

Musician—> Musical performance —> Audience

The upper and the lower levels have a similar structure in the way they are
produced. For this reason, music is called an art form of “double
productions.”
Different musicians may play the same score differently, but it would
not be unreasonable to say that what the composer composes and what the
musician plays are almost the same. In a competition of musical composition,
the nominated works are performed in front of the judges. What the audience
finally perceives is supposed to be the same as what the composer originally
had in mind. The audience and the composer share the same artistic
experience. We can modify the diagram to the cyclic structure as follows:

Composer —> Musical Composition —> Score reader

Audience <— Musical performance <— Musician

SubStance # 98/99, Vol. 31, nos. 2 & 3, 2002


A Japanese View of Theatricality 75

The second production repeats the first one but in reverse.


Theater is also an art form of double productions. Therefore, on the
surface, the analysis of its structure is similar to that of music.

Dramatist —> Drama —> Drama reader

Actor—> theater performance—> Spectator

However, unlike music, the second production does not repeat the first one
in reverse. A theater performance onstage is quite different from a drama on
paper, and what the spectator conceives is not at all the same as what the
dramatist had in mind. It used to be said that the dramatist imagines the
stage production as he writes, so that one can read in the drama—provided
it is a good one—every detail of the stage production. Obviously this is
wrong. Even the realist Ibsen would not possibly have imagined the way A
Doll’s House or Ghosts might be performed today. This is because a theater
production is a combination of two different aspects: drama and play. I have
detailed these aspects elsewhere (Mori, 1997), but it is primarily the play
aspect that makes the difference between what the dramatist writes on paper
and what the actor performs onstage.
If what the musician plays is fairly much the same as what the composer
composes, the above written diagram of the music structure could be as
simple as this:

Composer —> Musical Piece (Score-Musician-Playing) —> Audience

But the diagram of theater structure cannot be shortened. It remains:

Dramatist—> Drama —> Actor —> Playing —> Audience

Structurally speaking, the musician is a mediator between the composer


and the audience or an interpreter of the score (a musical performance is
sometimes called an interpretation), while the actor is a creator of a kind of
art form that is different from a written drama. This is another way of saying
that music depends only on our sense of hearing, but theater on both hearing
and sight. True, we enjoy the pianist’s passion-filled bodily movements, but
the sight is not supposed to affect our evaluation of his or her musical
performance.

SubStance # 98/99, Vol. 31, nos. 2 & 3, 2002


76 Mitsuya Mori

Actor Plays Character for Audience

The unique feature of theater lies in its process of performance. Hence


any discussion of theater tends to focus on the performance level. Peter Brook
says in the opening passage of his The Empty Space, “A man walks across
[...the] empty space whilst someone else is watching him, and this is all that
is needed for an act of theater to be engaged” (9). This statement is rather
misleading. The man who crosses the empty space may be an actor and the
man who watches him a spectator, but Brook mentions no character that the
actor plays. Nevertheless, the man’s action of crossing the empty space
implies his playing something or somebody else. Therefore, we can find
even in Brook’s statement three basic elements of theater: Actor plays
Character for Audience.
Admittedly, this formula has been challenged in the second half of the
20th century, and various theaters, which seemingly lack one of those
elements, have been advocated and practiced. But it seems that no one has
proposed more than these three as the primary agents composing a theatrical
event. So, this formula can still be a good point of departure.
First, the relationship between these three elements is to be seen not as
linear but as triangular. The diagram can be drawn thus:

A(ctor) —————— C(haracter)

Au(dience)

This kind of triangular relationship is meaningless in art forms other than


theater. The impossibility of technological reproduction of a theater
performance also derives from this structural relationship.
This triangular diagram may be viewed in two ways: either from each
corner point, or from each line between the two corners. The latter view is
preferred here, for in this way we have a chance to grasp a theater production
as a whole without cutting it up into pieces to be examined one by one. If we
look into the triangle from the line between A and C, for example, we see Au
beyond the line so that Au is not at any moment excluded from our view of
the A-C relationship. In this way the whole theatrical event could be viewed,
if not in its completeness, at least adequately enough.
Each line of the triangle—i.e. the relationship between each two of the
three agents—is closely related with each of the three basic aspects of theater:
playing, drama, theatrical space. The relationship between Actor and

SubStance # 98/99, Vol. 31, nos. 2 & 3, 2002


A Japanese View of Theatricality 77

Audience transforms a physical place, where they simultaneously exist, into


a theatrical space. The aspect of playing stands in the relationship between
Actor and Character, and Drama is not something Actor presents to Audience,
but something formed between Audience and Character. The triangular
diagram, therefore, can be enriched as follows:

playing

A ——— C
space —> <— drama
Au

Creating a Theatrical Space

When and how is a physical place transformed into a theatrical space?


Peter Brook refers to empty space as if it exists before a man crosses over it.
But “empty space” does not exist in this world. In both an open-air theater
and a proscenium-arch theater, many things have been in existence before
the man crosses over the space. In fact, it is the man’s crossing it that makes
the place into the “empty space” for the one who watches. The actor’s action
makes every pre-existing thing (except those set up for his action) invisible
to the audience.
This is apparent particularly in the indoor theater, which became
common in the 18th century, both in Europe and in Japan. Before that, most
theatrical performances took place in open- or semi-open-air theaters,
surrounded by nature. In some Greek theaters the audience could have a
view of a natural landscape or townscape beyond the skene (Carlson, 62).
One of the oldest Noh stages in Japan stands in seawater, and the audience,
sitting in another building, can notice the sea-level change as the performance
proceeds. Even the Shakespearean theater, already encircled by walls, must
have made best use of the effect of the movement of the sun during the
performance. I would like to call this characteristic of the theatrical place
“field” in contrast to empty “space.” It is an interesting coincidence that
both European and Japanese theater history had a transition from “field” to
“space” in the 16th and 17th centuries. In Europe in this period, the tradition
of medieval drama lost its vigor and modern secular drama came to be
formed, while in Japan, the long-established Noh drama made room for the
newly-emerging Kabuki theater form. Apparently, on both sides, this change

SubStance # 98/99, Vol. 31, nos. 2 & 3, 2002


78 Mitsuya Mori

was reinforced by a new type of dramatic character on the stage—a type


that was more realistic than in previous dramas.
The “space” characteristic of the stage is closely related to realism in
theater. Realism demands that the audience ignore the pre-existing
decorations and forms of the stage and see characters as if they were really
living there. The more realistic the drama becomes, the more the stage is
required to be “space,” and vice versa. The “space” also cosmopolitanizes
drama, because a drama’s “space” can be transferred to any other theater
without essential alterations. This was not possible for Shakespearean drama,
for example, which still retained the “field” aspect to a considerable degree.
Nevertheless, a physical place cannot transform itself into a theatrical
place without acquiring aspects characteristic of “space.” An absolute “field”
will remain a natural place of daily life. Thus the question, “When and how
is the physical place transformed to theatrical space?” can be modified to,
“When and how is field transformed into space?”

Field and Performance

The “field” aspect of the performing place is nowhere more apparent


than in folkloric rituals, which still today are regularly seen in Japan and
other Asian countries. The place can be a rice field, the area around a shrine,
a village market place, etc. Every ritual must be performed in its particular
“field” and cannot be moved to any other place.
However, the “field” of the ritual is not a mere natural, everyday field.
An actual rice field, which is chosen for the rice ritual on a specific day of
the year, is decorated in a special way for the performance by girls selected
in the village for this occasion. This is no longer an ordinary rice field, but
the one devoted to a divine being in a wish to have a good harvest, not only
for this particular field, but for all the fields in the village. The “space” aspect
already creeps in here. The selected girl performers and the surrounding
village people have a special relationship with each other in their wishes,
which transforms this rice field into a ritual space or, we may say, a theatrical
space.
Let us take another example. A ritual performance at the Nigatsu-do
Hall of the Todaiji Temple in Nara is called Todaiji-shunie and takes place in
the middle of March. The climax comes after dark. Monks carry eight or
nine burning torches (ca. 10 meters long and half a meter in diameter), each
held by several monks, up to the wooden veranda of the Hall, about 20
meters above ground level. They are laid side by side on the edge of the

SubStance # 98/99, Vol. 31, nos. 2 & 3, 2002


A Japanese View of Theatricality 79

floor, the burning heads being thrust in the air. Hundreds of thousands of
people come to watch this performance, standing on the ground below, so
that sparks of fire fall upon them. This is truly a spectacular sight. While the
torches are burning on the veranda, a group of monks conducts a special
rite in a small room inside the Hall. They continue the rite all night long,
sometimes sitting on the floor, sometimes walking or jumping around an
altar, but all the time chanting prayers. At around three o’clock in the
morning, a monk brings another burning torch into this small room and hits
the wooden floor with full force. Sparks of fire spread out and monks jump
over them. This is an incredible performance, even more spectacular than
the performance outside. Only those who have obtained special permission
from the Temple are allowed to witness this rite from a side room. No women
are allowed. They must remain outside, but may watch through a grill. The
monks completely ignore the spectators, the rite being conducted first and
foremost for themselves. I cannot deny the great excitement I felt when I
saw the enactment of this rite. And yet I had no personal feeling toward the
monks, but rather an impression of a great panoramic picture, like an erupting
volcano or an awesome ocean wave. It was an event completely of another
world, so to speak, which we were peeping into; similar to a cinematic
experience rather than a theatrical one. No definite theatrical relationship
between the performers and the spectators was formed.
It was different in the case of the ritual that I once experienced in the
region of Kofu, in central Japan. The performance took place inside curtain
walls set up around the village shrine, so that the performance was totally
hidden from the spectators. Nevertheless, we, standing outside, clearly felt
related to those performers inside. I say “we” because I could sense the
festive atmosphere prevailing among us while waiting for the end of the
performance. This feeling, I assume, came from the fact that we had talked
with the village performers and had walked behind them to the shrine before
the performance. The whole process was a ritual, only a part of which was
the performance inside the curtain walls. So we were participating in the
ritual not only by having followed them to the shrine, but also by waiting
outside the curtain walls. It was odd indeed that we had a feeling of being
related to the performers whom we could not see—a kind of feeling one did
not have for the other performers whose spectacular action had made an
awesome impression. Although I did not share the belief of the village people
in their divine being, I at least could understand their belief. Herein lies the
crucial point of our relationship. Both I and the village people perceived
something existing outside our relationship, or better said, something that

SubStance # 98/99, Vol. 31, nos. 2 & 3, 2002


80 Mitsuya Mori

assured our close relationship. Even if it is doubtful that this “something”


could be called Character in our diagram of the theater structure, it was,
without doubt, because of this “something” that the area of the village shrine
became a theatrical space, which the small room for the rite in the Nigatsu-
do Hall was not. I had been struck by the sight of the monks’ performances,
but almost completely alienated from their belief.
Without at least a glimpse of C, the relationship will be reduced to that
of Player-Spectator. I mean by “Player” the performer who performs for
him/herself, and by “Spectator,” the one who watches the performance as a
mere bystander. The Player—Spectator relationship is, in fact, no relationship.
This is the case with sports, games or music. Some sports, and certainly
music, are played for spectators (or listeners), and some may claim that
musical performers are influenced by the audience’s responses. This is true
especially in popular music concerts, but these come close to being theater
performances. Spectators are not essential for players of music, nor are
players necessary for “spectators.” We enjoy recorded music as a substitute
for live performances, even if it is not a completely satisfactory one. This is
not the case with theater, as anyone knows.

Actor and Character

The relationship between Actor and Character is the most problematic


one in the triangular structure of theater. We say that an actor plays a character,
but this activity is called acting. The difference between playing and acting
corresponds to the distinction between Player and Actor, respectively. Acting
implies “playing a character,” but the “play” element, being situated between
Actor and Character, stands independent of both. In actuality, A, p and C
are combined together in a person acting in front of the audience, but in
theory these three can be separately examined. I have done so in some detail
on another occasion, basing my arguments on the following schema (Mori,
1997):

A(ctor) —— p(lay) —— C(haracter)

Au(dience)

As is easily understood, realistic theater tends to hide p, or tries to make


p unseen to Au. In non-realistic, or stylized, theater, p is emphasized rather
than hidden, and when a certain pattern or form of p is repeated by one

SubStance # 98/99, Vol. 31, nos. 2 & 3, 2002


A Japanese View of Theatricality 81

actor or one generation of actors after another, what is called kata in Japanese
is born. This is the case with the stylized movements in Kabuki and Noh.3
And the traditional puppet theater in Japan, today called Bunraku, is an
interesting example by which we can illustrate each element of this scheme—
A, p and C—not in theory, but in actuality.
Any puppet theater consists of three basic elements: the puppeteer, the
puppet, and the narrator. The puppeteer manipulates the puppet according
to the dialogue or narrative spoken by the narrator. In most puppet theaters
the puppeteer and the narrator are the same person who hides himself from
the audience so that they see only the puppet. But in Bunraku, all three
elements are in sight. The narrator chants the story with the shami-sen (three-
stringed instrument) musical accompaniment, played by a shami-sen player.
Both narrator and musician sit side by side on the small platform, stage-left.
A puppet is two-thirds the size of an actual human being, and is operated
by hand by three puppeteers; the main puppeteer handles the head and the
right hand, the second the left hand, and the third, the legs. Usually
puppeteers cover their heads and bodies in black so as not to distract the
audience’s attention from the puppets, but curiously enough, the main
puppeteer shows his face in important, dramatic scenes of the play.
These three elements of Bunraku—puppeteer, puppet and narrator (with
music player)—correspond to the above-schematized three structural
elements of acting, A, p and C, respectively. This rare case of Bunraku reveals
that C cannot be a theatrical element without being bodily expressed by p,
and that p could not be theatrical p, no matter how stylized it may be, without
being framed by C. But the most interesting thing to see is that A and p are
indeed two separate entities in acting. The Audience can see p without paying
attention to A, or even both A and p at the same time but separately. The
audience can see all the structural elements of theater performance
independently. In this respect Bunraku manifests the most basic structural
characteristic of theater performance.
Of course this manifestation is not possible in an ordinary theater. But
what is really revealing in Bunraku for the present argument is the fact that
A does not play C in the sense that A’s movements represent C to Au. Au
watches p, or A and p together, but C is given independently from a different
side. In Bunraku, what the narrator chants is not only the dialogue of the
characters but the whole narrative story. It can be appreciated as a free-
standing form of literature. Herein lies a key to the everlasting question
concerning acting: is it the actor or the character that the audience is watching
on the stage?

SubStance # 98/99, Vol. 31, nos. 2 & 3, 2002


82 Mitsuya Mori

Actor/Character
Our perceptive organs can perceive only one object at a time, never two
or more. It is not possible for us to watch both the actor and the character at
the same time. Some think that we watch them alternately. But this is absurd,
for then the character is split into pieces, and each member of the audience
may have entirely different portions of the character. Some also think that
the actor is a real person and the character an imaginary one, so that both
are compatible. But real or imaginary, we cannot perceive two objects at the
same time. What is wrong about the above-asked question is the
presupposition that character is a “person,” real or imaginary. For in fact, a
character is not a person but a conception, which is formed in the audience’s
mind.
When a person appears on the stage, we notice him, of course, but do
not know if he is an actor playing a character or not. He may be the man we
call Hamlet, but he may turn out to be the man who is going to apologize for
the delay of the performance. Even a man who we suppose is playing Hamlet
can take off his pretence at any moment and come back to himself as an
actor. This means that we cannot be sure of having a complete character
until the final curtain falls. We have a character only when the play ends.
But when the play ends, the character is gone. He remains only in our minds,
as a conception. Therefore, we may say that, watching the movements of the
actor and hearing his lines, we build up the conception of the character little
by little. Sometimes he may surprise us by an action, which his previous
behavior had not led us to expect from him, but we adjust our hitherto built-
up character to that new behavior and amend the conception accordingly.
No matter how much his behavior confuses us at a certain moment in the
play, we get a total conception of the character at the end. If we do not, we
feel that the character is incomprehensible.
Although everything in theater is pretense, a pretense that the audience
is well aware of all the time, the audience can believe in the character all the
same. This belief is supported by the fact that a man on the stage is a real
human being, which is not the case in cinema or the novel. So, coming back
to the question of actor-character confusion, the audience’s illusion of
character is based on the reality of the actor’s being. And if Character is a
conception that we complete only at the end of the play, it is to be understood
in the genuine sense of the word “character”—ethos in Greek.
Aristotle put the primary importance on mythos rather than ethos, in his
analysis of Greek tragedy in the Poetics. Mythos, usually rendered into English
as plot, is a series of actions. Hence his definition: “Tragedy is a representation

SubStance # 98/99, Vol. 31, nos. 2 & 3, 2002


A Japanese View of Theatricality 83

of an action.” But we humans have the amazing ability to discern the plot of
a play that consists only of dialogues. In a theater, we hear only actors’ lines,
with no explanations by the author or any one else, but we can still discern
the story of the play as if it were narrated. This ability is obviously related to
our ability to understand language. In the same way that we conceive the
meaning of a sentence in a linear sequence of words, we weave the texture
of the story little by little as we see actions going on. The story grows bigger
and bigger from the series of small stories within each scene, until we get
the whole story—the plot of the play—at the final curtain.
If the series of actions does not form a plot, everything we see is on the
level of bare reality, and there is no formation of character, either. If one
were to diagram the formation of both character and plot, they would be the
same, since character and plot are actually one and the same thing. A
character cannot stand alone, but can exist only in relation to other
characters.4 That a character is complete at the end of the play means that all
the relationships between characters are completed, which is nothing but
the plot of the play. We make up a character, little by little, in our minds, as
we gradually make up the plot. Here arises the question of Drama. But before
pursuing this question, I would like to take a couple of examples to illustrate
how reality and fictionality intersect on the stage.

Reality and Fictionality


There is a scene in a Noh play, Dojoji, where an actor seems to step out
of the realm of the fictional world into reality. In this scene, called ran-byoshi,
the shite (main role) makes stamping movements in accord with the drum
music, played by one of the four musicians sitting on the floor upstage. The
shite of this play is a female entertainer who has been infatuated with, but
deserted by, a young priest, and who chases after him to the temple where
he hides himself. At the temple, the celebration of the completion of a new
bell is held, but the female entertainer’s jealous passion makes the bell fall
down. She transforms herself into an evil snake inside the bell and comes
out only to be soothed by a priest. The scene ran-byoshi takes place right
before the fall of the bell. When the play reaches this scene, the player of the
small drum changes his posture so that he directly faces the shite, who is
standing beside the right pillar, downstage. Usually the musicians, facing
toward the main auditorium, pay no attention to the players. In this scene,
subtle movements of the shite’s feet, stamping on the floor, and sporadic
sounds of the small drum are in accord and discord with each other, as if
both players were engaged in a battle of life and death. Each of them is

SubStance # 98/99, Vol. 31, nos. 2 & 3, 2002


84 Mitsuya Mori

concentrating greatly, the actor on the timing of his movements and the
musician on the beating of the drum. The fictional plane of the play
disappears for several minutes of this scene, and the audience senses both
players existing on the plane of reality.
A sudden stepping out of the fictional world happens more often in
Kabuki, and in a more festive mood. The typical one is koh-joh, a scene where
actors on stage pay the audience ceremonial greetings on the occasion of the
succession of a big actor’s name by a junior one.5 A koh-joh scene sometimes
takes place in the middle of the play; that is to say, all the actors on the stage
at the moment, who are usually the young one’s family and relatives, stop
acting all of a sudden and sit in a horizontal line on the stage to greet the
audience one by one. After the greetings are finished, they resume acting
and the play continues. It is even more obvious here than in ran-byoshi of
Noh, that we see actors in reality rather than characters in fiction.
However, if, as we have discussed, character is not a person but a
conception that the audience conceives in the course of the performance,
and if character is in fact the same as the plot, these scenes of Noh and
Kabuki, which seem to be carried out on the plane of reality in the middle of
the play, should also be included in the conception of character and plot.
Indeed, in these scenes actors do not change their costumes, and their
actions—stampings or greetings—are still very stylized. They are definitely
in kata. Therefore, the plane of reality that suddenly manifests itself in these
scenes is not everyday reality, but reality in fiction, one may say. It is a
theatrical device to make the audience realize that in theater, reality and
fiction are interwoven in a complicated fashion. And it is at this moment
that the audiences of Noh and Kabuki have the feeling of utmost theatricality
(engeki-sei), a feeling that we rarely get from any other art form.6

Drama
Audience builds up Character, which is identical to Plot. This
identification of Character and Plot forms Drama. Drama here is not the
drama the playwright writes. In my definition, Plot and Drama are the same
as Story, but Drama is an expression of a view of life, while Plot is a series of
actions. Drama emerges from Plot and yet is a larger world than Plot. We
can get a plot out of what the playwright writes (what a playwright writes
is also a series of dialogues, and the reader composes the plot of the play in
the same way that the audience does it from the lines spoken by the actors),
but Drama must be formed in theater—that is, from actual actions on the
stage.

SubStance # 98/99, Vol. 31, nos. 2 & 3, 2002


A Japanese View of Theatricality 85

Drama has been the subject of elaborate discussions among literary


critics, and we do not need to go through them. But a few observations on
Japanese theater may be of some use for our discussion on theatricality.
When drama was invented as the form of Noh in Japan, it was not the
same as Greek Tragedy or any later Western drama. Noh consists not only of
dialogues, but—more important—of narrative and lyric forms. Lines include
explanatory descriptions (or stage-directions) and the words of the chorus
(ji-utai) of eight chanters, sitting stage-left, who speak sometimes as pure
narrator and sometimes in unison with the main character, shite, who also
partly narrates his actions by himself. Therefore Plot is not formed by, but
given to, Audience as in an epic. Nevertheless, an abyss lies between the
participatory role of Audience in Noh, and that of the earlier performative
forms of narrative and lyric (both were performed in all countries in pre-
modern times). While the latter could be totally passive in perception of the
narrative story or lyrical poetry, the former (Audience in Noh) is supposed
to conceive the extended world of poetry, only a small portion of which is
enacted or narrated on the stage. This world is Drama in Noh. In typical
Noh plays (though the present repertories of about 220 plays contain many
different kinds), the shite is a dead person appearing in this world from an
old literary world such as The Tale of Genji or The Tales of Ise, or from an
historical epic of major battles such as The Tale of the Heike or Taihei-ki. The
play is enacted in the present tense (otherwise it would not be drama), but
the story is given in the past tense because it is about a world from the past.
The shite, therefore, exists in both worlds, present and past, at the same time.
We conceive beyond the episodic story of the shite the entire world of the
tales or historical epics. When, for example, the wife of Narihira, the shite of
the most famous Noh play, Izutsu, looks down into the well and sees the
reflection of herself, whom she sees as her beloved husband (she is now
wearing Narihira’s clothes, in her yearning for him), we feel beyond her
longing the whole world of The Tales of Ise, a story about Narihira. More
than that, we sense the long tradition of Japanese poetry, for Narihira was
one of the best and most representative figures in Japanese poetry. In this
sense Noh calls for an active audience, which no performance art in Japan
did before.
Greek or European drama is primarily enactment of an action, which
looks forward to the future. Noh drama is enactment of a feeling, which
looks backward in the past. Or, better said, Noh makes no clear distinction
between the past and the present; characters come and go between the two
worlds. It has been pointed out that the Buddhist way of thinking lacks the

SubStance # 98/99, Vol. 31, nos. 2 & 3, 2002


86 Mitsuya Mori

sense of history, which the Christian tradition clearly holds. In the Kamakura
Era, the period preceding the formation of Noh, new schools of Japanese
Buddhism emerged one after another. One of them was Japanese Zen, under
the influence of which Zeami was culturally educated. This may have
something to do with the above-stated characteristic of Noh drama.
When new forms of theater emerged around 1600 as Kabuki and
Nin’gyo-joruri (the original name of Bunraku), they did not have a pure
drama form, either. To be more precise, Kabuki did develop a drama form
of dialogue during its early stage, but in time it came under the dominance
of the Puppet Theater and adapted the puppet drama form to human actors;
actors play in part according to the narrative chanting. Most of the famous
Kabuki plays in the present repertories are of this type. Kabuki, though closest
to Western theater among the traditional theaters, acquired a pure drama
form in dialogue only in the second half of the 18th century. Before long,
however, it succumbed to the temptation of performing only some scenes
extracted from a long play, which originally had been performed from dawn
to twilight. Bunraku, too, follows this custom today.
Kabuki’s Plot, like Noh’s, is not identical with Character, but is composed
of dialogue and narrative (stage directions). In a sense, the story has been
given to the Audience beforehand. Most audiences know the play; if you do
not know the story of the play, you do not understand the scene. The primary
enjoyment results from the appreciation of the acting. And yet, just as the
Audience of Noh conceives a larger world beyond the shite, the Audience of
Kabuki appreciates the manifestation of a long tradition in the acting styles.
This larger world, Drama, keeps the Audience’s interest within the realm of
the Actor, rather than having it dispersed into mere interest in the Player.

Actor Plays Character for Audience


Having circumnavigated the triangle corners and lines of the theatrical
structure, we come back to the original formula: Actor plays Character for
Audience. But we have said that Character is only an abstract conception
that Audience completes at the final moment of the play. Is it not odd,
therefore, to say that Actor plays Character? However, when we say that an
actor plays, for example, Hamlet, what we actually mean is that he plays the
role of Hamlet. This “Hamlet” is no character in the sense we have discussed,
but a generally accepted image of a man called Hamlet in Shakespeare’s
Hamlet. Different actors play the same role of Hamlet but the audience
conceives different characters of Hamlet in different actors. The role of Hamlet
is a sort of stock character, like Pantalone, Arlecchino, or Dottore in commedia
dell’arte. He is not someone we conceive at the end of the play, but perceive
SubStance # 98/99, Vol. 31, nos. 2 & 3, 2002
A Japanese View of Theatricality 87

from the beginning. Roles are recognized in appearances and patterns of


movements and behaviors. In everyday life, we recognize Student, Teacher,
Priest, Fireman, etc. or more fundamentally, Man, Woman, Youth, Old Man,
etc. as roles. When small children play Father and Mother, these are roles,
too, not characters. As is commonly said, we are all playing roles of our own
in life.
Stock roles are common not only in commedia dell’arte or ancient Roman
comedy, but in most traditional Asian theaters. Each role has a distinct
appearance and its own patterns of behavior and movement, that is, kata. In
fact we are all behaving according to the kata most suitable to ourselves in
everyday life. Without this custom, the convention of female impersonation
in Kabuki or Elizabethan theater would be impossible. Role is an outer
feature, and Character is an inner quality. Role is a physical appearance,
and Character is a conceptual idea. In life and on the stage, Role and Character
are inseparable and together give us the complete person. Thus, we should
now amend our original triangle diagram as follows:

A —— C, R(ole)

Au
Note that Role or kata is nevertheless on the plane of abstraction, though
based on the level of everyday life. Different young men have different
patterns of behavior, but a certain typical pattern is abstracted from them
and called the role of the handsome young man. Character and Role are two
sides of a coin, a conception; they are not inseparable in actuality.

However, Character is equated with Plot, as we have seen, but Role is


not. Role is more on the side of reality, or, one may say, abstraction in reality.
It is possible that an actor plays the role of Hamlet without knowing the
character of Hamlet, or plot, only by moving as he was told to move, for the
patterns of his movement are decisive factors in the performance, out of
which Audience will compose Character and Plot. A famous Noh actor, who
had been greatly admired, confessed one day that he did not know the story
of the play he was playing on the stage. In Kabuki productions in the old
days each actor was given a script in which only his lines were written so
that he had no knowledge of the whole plot before the dress rehearsal. When
Role is the dominant factor in the C-R element, Plot tends to be fragmented;
it stands for the manifestation of Role rather than for Drama, the view of
life. This is exactly what has happened in Kabuki; today the usual Kabuki

SubStance # 98/99, Vol. 31, nos. 2 & 3, 2002


88 Mitsuya Mori

repertories for an evening consist of three or four famous scenes taken from
long plays. When children are playing Father and Mother, it is of this type,
too; the important thing is being Father or Mother and not the story that
they play.
C is split into C and R in the new diagram. But this is nothing peculiar.
A and Au also have double faces. As was mentioned before, A contains a
“Player” aspect in itself and Au is endorsed by “Spectator.” So, the triangle
structure should be like this:

A(ctor), P(layer) ———— C(haracter), R(ole)

Au(dience), S(pectator)

The double faces of each corner element are inseparable, but the one
stands on the plane of fictionality and the other more on the side of reality.
Apparently Actor is related to Audience, which composes C, but Player is
seen by Spectator as a person who plays Role. The triangle of three pairs is
in fact two triangles, (a) and (b):

(a) (b)
P(layer) ———— R(ole) A(ctor) —— C(haracter)

S(pectator) Au(dience)

Any theatrical performance must have both structural triangles of (a)


and (b) together. Triangle (a) is more on the level of reality and (b) is more
on the level of fictionality. Because of its slant toward reality, triangle (a)
tends to exclude R, which is by nature not real but conceptual.

However, when (a) is reduced to a mere P-S relationship, it will be sports


or music. Player and Spectator do not necessarily communicate with each
other.
By the same logic, triangle (b) tends to ignore the existence of Actor,
which is on the plane of reality as a real human being. But when (b) comes
to be only a C-Au relationship, it will be a narrative or a novel. It needs
Actor’s performative aspect to be theater. Character is Character only by
being conceived by Audience as Plot, and Actor must be present in order to
make Plot theatrical.

SubStance # 98/99, Vol. 31, nos. 2 & 3, 2002


A Japanese View of Theatricality 89

To endorse the element of R in triangle (a), (a) needs (b), and (b) needs
(a) to assure A’s performative function. One may say that triangle (a) is a
triadic relationship—that is, we must look at the triangle from each corner
element, while triangle (b) is a tri-linear relationship—that is, we must look
at the triangle from each line between the corners. The ran-byoshi or koh-joh
scene seems to put more emphasis on (a) than (b) and makes the Player
aspect come forward because the fictional level is stripped away in these
scenes. But the Audience is never lost, for in the koh-joh scene in Kabuki, the
actors are directly addressing the Audience, and in the ran-bryoshi of Dojoji
everything is meant for the Audience. Noh actors look absolutely indifferent
to the audience when performing, but the goal of Noh is the satisfaction of
the audience, which Zeami called “making hana (flower) bloom.”
Being aware of the double triangle schemes of theater structure, we
may be able to clear away confusions that sometimes occur in theater
performances. When the Actor element is supposed to be emphasized, it
may, in fact, be the Player aspect that comes forth because of the lack of
Character. Or, when the Actor attempts to emphasize Plot, the emphasis
may actually be on Role, not on Character at all. New experimental theaters
are often entangled in two kinds of triangle relationship—the triadic and
the tri-linear—without being conscious of it.

Theatricality
Now we finally come to our main issue, theatricality. Theatricality is by
definition “being theater-like.” If theater is conceptually based on the
structural relationship between A-C-Au, it is the physical relationship of the
above-diagramed (a) that concretizes the conceptual (b) into an actual or
physical event, which is truly what we call theater. In short, it is the (a)
triangle that makes a performance of the (b) triangle. However, if the aspect
of (a) is too much in front, theater tends to be broken because of the loss of
fictionality. The less apparent the (a) is in a performance, the more we believe
in the plot in the (b), and it may be praised as a good theater of realism.
It seems that theatricality emerges when the (a) breaks into, and yet
does not destroy, the (b), that is, the (a) and the (b) are combined in the
stylized performance, which actually stands on the edge of ficitionality. A
spectacular scene or an acrobatic performance in theater, for example, gives
us a feeling of theatricality because of its manifestation of the (a) in the realm
of style, which actually is the (b).7 If traditional Japanese theater appears
rich in theatricality, it is because Japanese theater essentially appreciates the

SubStance # 98/99, Vol. 31, nos. 2 & 3, 2002


90 Mitsuya Mori

aspect of (a) in style, as in the case of ran-byoshi in the Noh play, Dojoji, or the
koh-joh scene of Kabuki, discussed above.
This is the characteristic of what we call geinoh in Japanese, which I
mentioned in the beginning of this essay.
Geinoh or geinoh-jin (geinoh people) has in some contexts a pejorative
sense because it implies vulgarity or low artistic status. Modern theater would
refuse to be called geinoh. Geinoh covers traditional Japanese music
performances but never Western music (whose reviews in daily newspapers
usually appear in the culture section rather than geinoh section).
However, geinoh is often used in scholarly research works as a concept
to cover all the theatrical genres and performative activities, including the
tea ceremony and Sumo wrestling.8 Following the structural analysis we
have developed so far, we may say that geinoh includes every kind of
performance that contains the above schematized triangular structure of (a),
but that it needs even the slightest hint of the triangle of (b). Rituals have a
definite tendency to base themselves mainly on (a). But if they give us an
impression of geinoh, they always have certain aspects of (b). In the case of
the ritual performance, which was executed inside the curtain walls and out
of sight, we felt a definite relation to the performers, which means that we
were transformed from mere Spectator to Audience by something outside
us that we shared with the village people. This ritual performance definitely
falls into the category of geinoh. The rite in the Nigatsu-do Hall of the Todaiji-
Temple, on the other hand, refuses to let us be Audience. True, the monks in
the small room are no longer ordinary monks. They are playing sacred roles
that are quite different from their everyday roles. Nonetheless, they do not
go further to be totally characterized as Actor, and the rite remains on the
border between a geinoh and a purely religious rite.
Conventional theaters that hold a clear structural relationship of (b)
may dislike being classified as geinoh. But since triangle (b) could not stand
for a theatrical performance without (a), they, too, are categorized as geinoh.
Thus, geinoh requires: (1) the triangular structural relationship of (a),
Player-Role-Spectator, but (2) that at least one of these elements be lifted up
to the plane of the fictional relationship of triangle (b), Actor-Character-
Audience. Both traditional Japanese performances and Western experimental
ones tend to step out of the fictional plane of (b), but while the former still
keep the triangular structure with regards to the aspect of Audience, the
latter seem to put more emphasis on Actor in their own structure. Both share
the same intersection of reality and fictionality. Therefore, these Western
experimental performances give us a definite impression of being in the

SubStance # 98/99, Vol. 31, nos. 2 & 3, 2002


A Japanese View of Theatricality 91

realm of the geinoh even if they are rigorously trying to get rid of the
traditional structure of theater.
Thus, geinoh and theatricality go together, side by side. And whenever
the Western concept of “theater” suffers from narrowness and ambiguity,
the term geinoh may be recommended. Adopting this term, it will be possible
to denote the broader implication of theatricality as well as to make
distinctions between different kinds of performance, theatrical and non-
theatrical. Perhaps we need a new discipline of geinoh studies in order to
further explore the issue of theatricality.
Seijo University, Tokyo

Notes

1. Sino-Japanese characters for engeki did exist early in the 19th century, but labeled not as
engeki but as kyogen (see, Mori 2001).
2. The meaning of geinoh, which originally came from Chinese usage, first meant “skill,”
but went through a considerable degree of change from the 10th to 14th centuries (see
Moriya, 1981).
3. Kata is described in the New Kabuki Encyclopedia as follows: “Kata essentially are fixed
forms or patterns of performance and, while the term most commonly refers to acting,
may be found in all production elements, such as the arrangement of a program, of
scenes, and the traditions of scenery, props, wigs, makeup, music, and costumes.[...] A
kata may be said to have been born when an actor created an appropriate interpretation
of the spirit of a play and his role in it (in terms of movement, speech, appearance, and
so on) and this interpretation was transmitted as a convention to the next generation of
actors...” (Leiter, 289)
However, in my opinion, kata in Kabuki is more a pattern, while kata in Noh is
more form, or Form in the sense close to the Platonic idea. Kata as pattern can be changed,
as we see in the history of Kabuki, but kata of Form cannot, since Noh will no longer be
Noh if its kata is changed (See Mori, 1997, II).
4 Bert O. States holds a similar view of character: “All characters in a play are nested
together in ‘dynamical communion,’ or in what we might call a reciprocating balance of
nature: every character ‘contains in itself’ the cause of actions or determinations, in
other characters and the effects of their causality… Hamlet is made of Gertrude and
Claudius, Osric and Horatio, Rosencrantz and Guildenstern, et cetera and vice versa.
Seen from the characterological viewpoint, Hamlet is a collection of relationships”(146-
48).
5. A Kabuki critic and scholar, Tamotsu Watanabe, claims that the koh-joh scene presents
the essence of Kabuki in various aspects (see Watanabe, 1989).
6. The intersection of reality and ficitionality is most clearly seen in the convention of
Kabuki’s onnagata, a female impersonator. As is well known, this convention was
practiced in Elizabethan theater, too. But the comparison of both cases would show the
differences of theatrical sensibility between the East and the West. To take examples
from Shakespearean comedies, Viola and Rosalind disguised as men do not conceal
their true selves from the audience, and the audience knows everything and enjoys the
various layers of philosophical implications in their ironic situations. In contrast, Kabuki’s
disguise hides the true self of the character not only from other characters in the play
but also from the audience, so that the revelation of the real self is a surprise for both. A

SubStance # 98/99, Vol. 31, nos. 2 & 3, 2002


92 Mitsuya Mori

typical example is the Hamamatsu-ya scene in the play Benten the Thief. The thief is a
handsome young man and played by an actor who can be an onnagata. When he appears
on the stage, disguised as a young princess, the audience naturally takes him as an
onnagata—that is, a genuine princess who is not disguised. He even uses some theatrical
gimmicks to maintain that illusion with the audience. It is in the climactic scene that he
is detected as a man. He suddenly takes off his kimono and identifies himself with a
long and melodiously narrated monologue.
7. This characteristic of theatricality in theater will become clear when we consider cinema.
Cinema has, on the surface, a similar structural relationship between actor, character
and audience. In a movie house an audience is watching an actor playing a character,
but on the screen. The essential difference between theater and cinema is often expressed
by the phrase, “the theater audience confronts a real person on the stage while the
cinema audience watches only a shadow of a person on the screen.” Structurally speaking,
this means that cinema is based solely on the conceptual relationship of (b), not at all on
the physical one of (a), though this may sound the other way round at first. A movie
actor looks just like himself on the screen, that is, the same as in his actual life. But this
is so because there is no gap between Actor and Player. If what we are watching must be
either a real person or a fictional character, it must be a character, for otherwise we
could not enjoy the fictional world there. When we see Laurence Olivier playing Hamlet
on the stage, we never imagine that Hamlet actually looks like Olivier. But when he is
playing Hamlet on the screen, Hamlet is no one but he. This is another way of saying
that cinema is totally realistic. Therefore, a movie, even a spectacular type, does not
give us a feeling of theatricality. Anything on the screen does not appear artificial (not
theatrical in every sense of the word) to our eyes; if it does, it must be a miserable
failure.
8. It may be difficult to imagine that Sumo wrestling was in the old days regarded as
geinoh. But it was geinoh not because it was something like today’s pro-wrestling—a
kind of show entertainment—but because it was a performing competition dedicated
to divine beings. If this sounds odd to us today, it is because we have lost the ability to
sense the transformation of Sumo elements to those of triangle (b). In contrast, the tea
ceremony gives us a clear feeling of geinoh. Here Player and Spectator easily transform
themselves to Actor and Audience. Despite the fact that no shadow of Character appears
in the performance, the feeling for a larger world clearly emerges. Actor and Audience
constantly exchange their roles during the performance, and yet the host is the host and
the guests are the guests; the triangle structure remains.

Works Cited

Brook, Peter. The Empty Space. London: MacGibbon & Kee Ltd., 1968.
Carlson, Marvin. Places of Performance: the Semiotics of Theater Architecture. Ithaca & London:
Cornell University Press, 1989.
Leiter, Samuel L. New Kabuki Encyclopedia, a Revised Adaptation of Kabuki Jiten. Westport,
Connecticut & London: Greenwood Press, 1997.
Mori, Mitsuya, “Thinking and Feeling.” In Stanca Scholz-Cionca & Samuel L. Leiter (eds),
Japanese Theater & the International Stage. Leiden, Boston & Köln: Brill, 2001.
——. “Noh, Kabuki and Western Theater: An Attempt at Schematizing Acting Styles.”
Theater Research International, Spring Supplement, Oxford University Press, 1997.
——. “Koten-geki to gendai-geki (Classical and Modern Theater).” Iwanami Koza, Kabuki,

SubStance # 98/99, Vol. 31, nos. 2 & 3, 2002


A Japanese View of Theatricality 93

Bunraku, Vol.1, Tokyo: Iwanami, 1997.


Moriya, Tsuyoshi. “Introduction”, Nihon Geinoh-shi (The History of Japanese Geinoh). Vol. 1,
Tokyo: Hosei University Press, 1981.
States, Bert O. Great Reckonings in Little Rooms. Berkeley, Los Angeles, London: University
of California Press, 1985.
Watanabe, Tamotsu. Kabuki: kajonaru kigo no mori (Kabuki: A Forest of Signs). Tokyo: Shin-
yoku-sha, 1989.

SubStance # 98/99, Vol. 31, nos. 2 & 3, 2002

S-ar putea să vă placă și