Sunteți pe pagina 1din 22

I N T . J. S C I . E D ec .

1 9 9 2 , V O L . 1 4 , '>0 . 5 , 5 4 1 - 5 6 2

In search of a meaningful relationship: an


exploration of some issues relating to
integration in science and science education

Derek Hodson, The Ontario Institute For Studies in Education,


Toronto, Canada
The long-running debate about the desirability of separate courses in biology, chemistry and physics
versus the merits of integrated science, co-ordinated science or combined science, the case for 'balanced'
science within a Science for All programme, and the unresolved question of 'process' versus 'product'
orientation in science curriculum design each relates to fundamental philosophical problems concerning
the nature of science and scientific practice and to issues concerning the goals and practice of science
education. This article examines the philosophical validity of claims for the conceptual and methodo
logical integration of the sciences and explores the possibilities for constructing coherent science courses
based on alternative integrating elements rooted in educational theory.

Is there unity within and among the sciences?


Elsewhere, I have advocated the adaptation of the familiar 'Objectives Model'
of curriculum to provide a simple conceptual model of science for the purpose
of focusing the attention of curriculum developers, teachers and students more
explicitly on issues concerned with learning about the nature of science and
scientific activity (figure 1) (Hodson 1990). This model also provides a means of
addressing questions concerned with the unity of science. The rhetoric of many
integrated science courses is underpinned by claims that science constitutes a
single, coherent Form of Knowledge (to use Hirst's [1974] expression) with
common purposes, content, method and criteria of evaluation (Adeniyi 1987, Frey
1989). To what extent are these claims sustainable? Are the purposes of physics and
biology the same? Does scientific knowledge have the same role and status in all
branches of science? Are the methods of all scientists the same? Is there a single
criterion or common set of criteria by which claims to scientific knowledge
(,scientific truth'?) can be judged?

The purposes of science

At the simplest level, the purpose of science is to accumulate scientific knowledge.


Of course, this immediately raises questions about the status of that knowledge and
the reliability of the methods employed in reaching it, and serves to illustrate the
inter-relatedness of the four elements in figure 1 (b). Leaving aside, for the moment,
the dispute between realist and instrumentalist views of scientific knowledge, it can
be argued that all scientists seek knowledge that renders the world more intelligible,
comprehensible and predictable. In other words, scientific knowledge is sought and
0950-0693/92 $300

1992 Taylor

&

Francis

Ltd.

542

D . HOOSO:\

Aims &

(oo>ct'\

'

)'

Purposes

'Conceptual

;> ,C"&'"\
Appraisal

Validation.. 6:.

!-.h g rallon '

for

Figure 1.

Scientific

Knowledge

.
ienllfiC
Methods & Prcx::-esses

Teaching/Learning
Methods

(a)
Model
Rational
Curriculum Planning.

Publication

Figure L
Adapting a Model from
Curriculum Planning.

(b)
ModeJ for Teaching and
Learning about Science.

Adapting a model from curriculum planning.

constructed not 'for its own sake' (as in the stereotypical textbook image of science),
but for its value in solving problems. Problems may arise with respect to insufficient
data, conflict between theory and observational evidence, dispute between rival
theories, failure of an otherwise promising theory to generate predictive knowledge,
and so on. The precise nature of the problems depends on the current stage of
theoretical development of the science or, in Kuhn's (1970) terms, on whether the
science is in a preparadigmic, normal, extraordinary or revolutionary phase.
In passing, it is interesting to note that Laudan's (1977) view of science as a
problem-solving activity points to a decreasing stock of problems, as scientists
become more successful at 'coping with the world', whereas Knorr-Cetina's (1983)
'constructivist' view points to an increasing stock of problems, because the 'knO\vn
world' that science addresses is created by scientific practice and so is continuously
expanding. In both cases, problems are solved (if at all) by the modification of
existing knowledge or the creation of new knowledge generated via a mix of
experiment, observation and critical argument (an issue to be addressed later).
It is also worth noting that industrialization, commercialization and militarization
of contemporary science increasingly determines the direction of the scientific
endeavour and, therefore, the kind of problems that scientists have to confront-a
matter to be raised with students if we are serious in our desire to present an
authentic view of science (Martin et al. 1990).
It has been argued by Smolicz and :"Junan (1975) that much of the rhetoric of
science education assumes that the purpose of science is to gain control of the
environment and, therefore, that the aims of science education should be to give
students confidence in the capacity of science and technology to manipulate, alter
and control events. The extent to which this essentially Western (or orthern) view
of science is any longer an acceptable (let alone desirable) vie,v for those engaged in
the practice of science is discussed at length by Maxwell (1984). He argues that
many urgent social problems, including poverty, disease and malnutrition, are not
caused by lack of scientific knowledge or technological expertise, but by a mis
understanding or misappropriation of the purpose of science. \Vhilst he believes
that individual scientists cannot be blamed, he insists that the scientific community
should be held collectively accountable for the fact that science is pursued in a way
that is dissociated from a concern with sound human values. He urges a radical shift

I N TEGRATI O N 1,\ S C IENCE A!\O S C IENCE EDCCAT IO,\

543

from a 'philosophy of knowledge', with its emphasis on the disinterested search for
knowledge, to what he calls a 'philosophy of wisdom', which prioritizes what is
personally and socially desirable and worthwhile.
Given that we are faced with unprecedented levels of environmental degrada
tion, it is perhaps even more urgent that Maxwell's 'philosophy of wisdom' includes
a more sensitive appreciation of environmental issues and a greater determination
to re-order human activity (and scientific and technological activity, in particular)
in line with sounder environmental values. Unfortunately, far from the community
of scientists being united in a search for wisdom and environmentally sustainable
technology, it is fragmented and disparate in its purposes. This is not to say,
however, that science education should ignore the desirability of seeking to establish
a social climate that will promote and sustain such unity.
Scientific knowledge

Many science textbooks present a simplistic view of the origin and development of
scientific knowledge. Often, theory generation is seen as no more than a process of
looking for regularity in nature, and theory testing is regarded as simple
confirmation or refutation, usually based on a single observation or critical experi
ment. A more appropriate and sound view is that theories are complex structures
that stand or fall on their ability to describe, explain and predict observable
phenomena, without being dependent on any single observation. In practice, no
theory can accommodate all observations within its domain; there will nearly always
be some observations that cannot satisfactorily be explained. It is when these
anomalies are long-standing, socially significant and strike at the fundamental
assumptions of the theory that it comes under threat of falsification. History shows
us that scientific theories grow and develop in order to accommodate observational
evidence more fully. Hence, if we are to be faithful in our teaching to actual
scientific practice, theories will undergo a process of refinement, development and
replacement throughout a student's science education, and the degree of theoretical
sophistication at any particular stage will be determined by the capacity of the
theory to explain the phenomena the learners will encounter and the kind of
enquiries they will undertake. It need not go further.
Once it is accepted that theories grow and develop, it is necessary to consider
their status. As far as school science is concerned, there have traditionally been two
extreme positions: nai've realism and instrumentalism. In naive realism ; scientific
theory is believed to provide a true description of the world, whereas in instrumen
talism the real world is considered to be described by means of imaginary scientific
models. A major problem in science curriculum design is deciding which of these
two positions to adopt. Sole use of either extreme position has serious limitations
when compared with the actual practice and history of science, and so a critical
realist position, able to accommodate both perspectives, may be more appropriate
(Jacoby and Spargo 1992).
Critical realists assert that scientists sometimes aim at a true description of the
world and a true explanation of observable events. However, because they cannot
know for certain that their findings and explanations are true, they regard them as
conjectures about reality that are subject to critical scrutiny and test and, possibly,
rejection. On other occasions, a 'true' description of the world may not be sought.
Rather, a convenient predictive instrument is all that is required. Thus, critical

544

D. HOD SO"l

realists can be realist about some theories (those that they believe to be true, or to
be the 'current best shot at truth') and instrumentalist about others (those that they
find useful, but do not accept as true). These latter are more appropriately termed
theoretical models. From a critical realist position it is not illogical to retain a falsified
or superseded theory in an instrumental capacity, provided that its status is recog
nized and acknowledged. It may be that within a restricted domain of application,
and this applies particularly to school science which necessarily is more restricted
than science itself in its theoretical needs, a theory that was once accepted but has
now been falsified (and hence reduced to the status of a model) may be more useful
than a 'true' (currently accepted) theory because it is simpler to use. Nor is it
illogical to use alternative (even seemingly incompatible or contradictory)
instrumental models for different aspects of the same phenomenon-for example,
wave and particle models of light.
\Vhat is confusing to students is that the role and status of theories and models
are not made explicit. We leave students to form their own views from the
classroom experiences we provide, many of which have not been planned with
epistemological considerations in mind. At the very least, we need to be more
careful in our use of the terms theory and model, and we need to make it clear that
conceptual structures are designed with particular purposes in mind (see also Gilbert
1991). Those purposes are either realist (an attempt to describe and explain the
world) or instrumentalist (an attempt to gain an increased measure of control and
predictive power). Role and status are inextricably linked. Moreover, the variety of
specific purposes that motivate theory building and model building within the
sciences ensures that the precise meaning attached to a concept will depend on the
specific role that it has within a particular knowledge structure. Hence, attempting
to integrate the sciences via 'large' concepts such as energy and force are fruitless.
Moreover, it could even be argued that significantly different purposes of knowl
edge building -in physics and biology, for example -lead to conceptual structures
that are qualitatively different in kind (see, for example, Hull 1974, Mayr 1982,
Rosenberg 1985, Ruse 1973, 1988).
The view that the conceptual structures of science are subject to growth,
development and modification has striking parallels with contemporary views in
constructivist psychology, holding out the prospect of a degree of harmony between
the philosophical and psychological principles underpinning the curriculum
(Duschl 1990, Duschl et al. 1990, Nersessian 1989, Villani 1992). It is interesting
that concept development in children seems to follow certain well-characterized
'learning histories', largely because of the common influences of everyday
experience (Head 1986, Solomon 1987), and that these often reflect the concept's
historical development (Clough et al. 1987, Driver et al. 1985). Hence, encouraging
students to reflect on their own developing ideas is a way of illuminating the way
in which scientific knowledge itself develops (Baird et al. 1991).
However, acceptance of the legitimacy and pedagogical value of children's alter
native frameworks runs counter to the notion that science and, therefore, science
education can be integrated by means of a few powerful concepts. Such unifying
concepts may exist, but only in the minds of experienced scientists. For children,
concepts are still very much context bound and are often at variance with scientists'
views. Many who hold theories of domain-specific knowledge claim that 'experts'
have both more and different relations between concepts than do novices, and that

545

INTEGRATION IN SCIENCE A"ID SCIEI'\CE EDCCATIO:\l

experts organize their knowledge in terms of conceptual structures that do not exist
for, or are not readily accessible to, novices (Vosniodou and Brewer 1987).
Holton (1978, 1986) has pointed to the existence of certain interdisciplinary
themes (such as randomness, reductionism/holism, concern with the nature of time)
that transcend subject boundaries and serve, periodically, to unify the work of
scientists in seemingly disparate fields. These themes may have some integrative
power within an interdisciplinary science programme at university level (Jordan
1989), but at school level they operate at too sophisticated a level (but see Smith

et al. 1990). Of greater potential as integrative themes are what Smolicz and Nunan
(1975) refer to as the prevailing 'ideological pivots' of Western science and science
education: anthropocentric views of the world, 'positivistic faith' and concern for
analysis and quantification. However, the desirability of continuing to promote
such values has already been called into question in the discussion of scientific
purpose.

Scientific method
Perhaps the most significant feature of science curriculum change during the past
quarter century has been the shift away from the teaching of science as a body of
established knowledge towards the experience of science as a method of generating
and validating such knowledge. Science teachers have been encouraged to provide
courses with exemplify scientific method and put the learner in the position of __
'being a scientist', and scientific method has come to be regarded as the major
integrating feature of the sciences. Underlying these changes is the assumption that
there is such a thing as a distinctive scientific method, and that it can be character
ized and taught.
Consideration of the extensive literature in the philosophy of science fails to
identify a single, universally accepted description of scientific method. Far from
being dismayed by such lack of agreement, White (1983) regards it as an inevitable
consequence of the complexity of the scientific enterprise, the myriad of possible
starting points, and the differences in knowledge, experience and personality among
individual scientists. Interestingly, children also regard it as inevitable. It is

teachers

who create the expectation of a single method through their continual reference to

the scientific method (Hodson 1990).


However, our failure to identify a single, simple method does not mean that
scientists have no methods. Feyerabend's (1975) famous assertion that 'anything
goes' implies the absence of a prescribed method, the absence of an algorithm, rather
than the absence of methods. It should not be taken too literally. Science does
have methods, but the precise nature of those methods depends on the particular
circumstances: on the matter under consideration, on the theoretical knowledge the
scientist chooses to employ, and on the investigative techniques and instrumen
tation devices a\ailable. By making a selection of processes and procedures from
the range of those available and approved by the community of practitioners,
scientists choose a 'method' they consider to be contextually appropriate. There
are no universal decision criteria for what to do and how to do it. All decisions
are 'local' - determined by the particular circumstances of individual investiga
tions-and, therefore,

idiosyncratic. As in games playing, success comes to those

who can improvize and exploit opportunities, rather than to those who slavishly
seek to follow strict guidelines. In Percy Bridgham's (1950) words, 'the scientific

546

D . H O D SO:-.J

method, as far as it is a method, is nothing more than doing one's damndest with
one's mind, no holds barred'.
The goal of a science curriculum integrated through a common method is
unattainable- except at a very elementary level. Biologists, chemists and physicists
approach problems and conduct investigations in ways that are sufficiently distinc
tive to warrant the attention of students being drawn to the differences (and their
causes) as much as to their similarities. Moreover, in making their selections
and in implementing their chosen strategies, scientists utilize an additional kind
of knowledge and understanding, often not well articulated or even consciously
applied, that can be acquired only through the experience of doing science and
that constitutes the central core of the art and craft of the creative scientist.
This knowledge combines conceptual understanding with elements of creativity,
experimental flair, the scientific equivalent of the gardener's 'green fingers' and a
complex of affective attributes that provide the necessary impetus of determination
and commitment. With experience, it develops into what Polanyi (1958) calls
connoisseurship. In practice, scientists proceed partly by rationalization (based on
their theoretical understanding) and partly by intuition rooted in their tacit knowl
edge of how to do science (their connoisseurship).
Because the ways in which scientists work are not fixed and not predictable, and
because they involve a component that is experience-dependent in a very personal
sense, they are not directly teachable. That is, one cannot learn to do science by
learning a prescription or set of processes to be applied in all situations. The only
effective way to learn to do science is by doing science, alongside a skilled and
experienced practitioner who can provide on-the-job support, criticism and advice.
The implications of this for science education will be addressed later in this article.
Assessment and evaluation

By tradition, reproducibility of experimental results and consistency with


'observable facts' are held to be the criteria by which scientific theories are
appraised. As a consequence, school science curricula invariably invest enormous
faith in the capacity of observation and experiment to provide reliable data for
making unequivocal decisions concerning the validity of theories. Even at a level of
sophistication appropriate to the school curriculum it can be pointed out to students
that there are some major problems associated with this position. First, 'consistency
with the facts' does not confer any increased truth status on a theory. Such
consistency simply means that the theory may be true (Duhem 1962). But so may
lots of other theories that might also correspond with the observations. Second,
observation statements are fallible and theory-dependent, so any conclusions based
on them are also fallible and theory-dependent. Third, experiments are messy and
uncertain things that have to be interpreted using theoretical insights. They do not
provide reliable and unambiguous data, because evidence can often be interpreted
in a variety of ways, depending on the theory employed. Indeed, as Feyerabend
(1975) asserts, a well-designed theory creates its own supporting evidence, thereby
insulating it from attempts to falsify it. In practice, it is rarely possible to devise an
experiment that represents a decisive test of a theory, and we seriously mislead
students when we pretend to do so in class ( Koertge 1969, Millar 1987).
If it is not possible to perform critical experiments capable of furnishing theory
independent data, it follows that there are no purely logical criteria (in the familiar

547

E,TEGRATION IJ'\ SCIE"ICE AND SCIENCE EDCCATIOJ'\

usage of the term) for establishing the superiority of one theory over another. In
other words, theories are empirically under-determined. Empirical adequacy is
not enough in itself to establish validity. In practice, empirical inadequacy is
frequently ignored by individual scientists fighting passionately for a well-loved
theory (Mitroff and Mason 1974), and is often considered subordinate to the
'context of discovery' by the community-appointed validators

(Knorr-Cetina

1983). Additional factors that may play a part in decision-making include:

elegance and simplicity (the aesthetics of science);

similarity and consistency with other theories;

'intellectual fashion', in the sense of compatibility with trends in other disciplines;

social and economic considerations;

cultural considerations;

the status of the researchers;

the views of 'significant others' (influential and powerful scientists, journal


editors, publishers);

priorities of research funding agencies.

In other words, knowledge is

negotiated within the community of scientists by

a complex interplay of theoretical argument, experiment and personal opinion.


Criteria of judgement include social, economic, political, religious, moral and
ethical factors as they impact (sometimes unconsciously) on the decision makers
(Latour and \Noolgar 1979). In other words, science is not propelled exclusively by
its own internal logic. Rather, it is shaped by the personal beliefs and political
attitudes of its practitioners and reflects, in part, 'the history, power structure and
political climate of the supportive community' (Dixon 1973). So much for unity of
the sciences through a common means of theory appraisal!

Towards a unified science education


Whilst there may be little in the literature of philosophy and sociology of science to
support the notion of a

science integrated through its purposes, conceptual struc

tures, methods and criteria of judgement, there may still be compelling arguments
for an integrated science

education. In her review of integrated science curricula,

Brown (1977) declares that it is incumbent on curriculum developers to state both


the nature and justification of their integrative principles. The second part of this
article is devoted to that task.
In his Presidential Address to the ASE, Black (1986) warned us of 'the temptation
to

invent a unifying philosophy for integrated science' (emphasis added) and

advised us to 'be wary of any attempt to unify science... that does not draw on the
views of scientists or philosophers of science'. \Nhat follows is not an attempt to
unify

science. Rather, it is an attempt to unify science education. For that purpose,

an integrating principle (or principles) rooted in educational theory, rather than


philosophy of science, is necessary. Meeting Brown's challenge requires that we
ignore Black's demand or, at least, the literal interpretation of it. Indeed, as I
tried to argue in the first part of this article, arguments rooted in philosophy and
sociology of science

cannot provide integrative principles.

The familiar 'Objectives Model' of curriculum (figure 1 (a)) can be used to


remind us that unity of science education may be sought in terms of coherence and

548

D . H O D SON

consistency among the goals (aims and objectives), content (knowledge, skills and
attitudes), teaching/learning experiences and assessment/evaluation procedures of
science education. For example, otherwise disconnected content can be integrated
through the use of unifying contexts, themes or topics (Kirkham 1989, Linjse et al.
1990) or through students' particular interests, as expressed in their choices within
a modular course (SSCR 1987). When the curriculum is focused on a problem
solving approach there is a sense in which teaching and learning methods provide
integration and, insofar as they impact significantly on classroom activities, a
similar case can be made for the integrative potential of assessment procedures.
:Many of the more significant educational differences between curricula are less to
do with traditional subject classification into biology, chemistry and physics than
with the educational intent (aims and objectives in figure 1 (a)), or what Roberts
(1982) calls the 'curriculum emphasis' of the programme. Any one of seven
major curriculum emphases- Everyday Coping; Structure of Science; Science,
Technology and Decisions; Scientific Skill Development; Correct Explanations;
Self As Explainer; Solid Foundations- could be used as the basis of a coherent
science education programme. Of interest here is the Alberta Ministry of
Education's (1990) current promotion of the STS curriculum emphasis as the means
of achieving balance and integration in science education.
The STS (science , technology and society) concept of curriculum .. . is an opportunity to
organize and p resent all the goals of science education in a coherent p ackage .

Although I have considerable empathy with this view, it does sidestep the problem
that STS itself is by no means a coherent, consistent and unproblematic curriculum
emphasis (Heath 1992, Hurd 1991, Rosenthal 1989, Solomon 1988, Zuga 1991).
A range of curriculum emphases is included in the umbrella term 'scientific
literacy', a term that has recently become a rallying call for those who seek to render
science more meaningful and more accessible to all students. The following section
explores the potential of scientific literacy as a focus for integration.

Integration through scientific literacy

Whilst scientific literacy is neither a new concept (Roberts 1983, Shen 1975) nor a
well-defined one (Bodmer 1989, Jenkins 1990, Lewis and Gagel 1992, Mayer and
Armstrong 1990, Shahn 1988), its multidimensionality does have the potential to
provide a kind of integrated science curriculum or, at least, a balanced and coherent
science education. However, there is much dispute about whether science education
programmes can, simultaneously, prepare some students for careers as scientists
and technologists and ensure that all students become scientifically literate (Carter
1991, Fensham 1988). It is my view that these goals are compatible and achievable,
provided that emphasis is placed on the personalization of learning (Bentley and
Watts 1989, Burbules and Linn 1991, Martin and Brouwer 199 1, Newton 1986,
Reid and Hodson 1987).
For convenience, the multidimensionality of scientific literacy can be described
in terms of three major elements:
1. Learning science- acquiring and developing conceptual and theoretical
knowledge.

549

ITEGRATIO:'\ I SCIE)JCE AND SCIE:--JC E EDCCATIO"I

2.

Learning about science - deyeloping an understanding of the nature and


methods of science, and an awareness of the complex interactions between
science and society.

3.

Doing science - engaging in and deyeloping expertise in scientific inquiry and


problem solying.

With respect to these three elements, 'personalization of learning' means ensuring


that (i) learning is rooted in the personal experiences of indiyidual learners, (ii)
science is seen as more person-oriented and science education is infused with sound
human and enyironmental yalues, and (iii) eyery student has the opportunity to
pursue scientific inyestigations of their own choosing and their own design. Over

prioritization
of the affective: ensuring that the curriculum meets the emotional and spiritual

arching all three aspects is what Hodson and Reid (1988) refer to as
needs of all students.
In attempting to meet the

learning science goal, we need to take cognizane of

what recent research into children's understandings in science has revealed about
concept acquisition and concept deyelopment, principally that learning is an active
process in which learners construct and reconstruct their own understanding in
the light of their experiences (Driver and Bell 1986). This entails (i) creating
opportunities for students to explore their current understandings and evaluate
the robustness of their models and theories in meeting the purposes of science, and
(ii) providing suitable stimuli for development and change. Unfortunately, many of
the so-called process-oriented science curricula seriously misjudge the nature of
this enterprise. First, by attempting to draw clear distinctions between the various
processes of science. Second, by insisting that they are independent of context and
content and, therefore, are generalizable and transferable to other situations. In
practice, employing the processes of science involves using concepts and theories,
and inyolyes using other processes. Because all processes are theory-impregnated,
and are inextricably linked with other processes, it is not possible to engage in
theory-free investigations or to deyelop skills of observation, data collection,
classification, inference, and so on, in isolation. Since one's capacity to use the
processes of science effectively is dependent on one's theoretical understanding, it
follows that teaching for process skill development is inseparable from teaching for
concept development (Hodson 1992a).
Given the inter-dependence of processes and concepts, it is reasonable to
suppose that engaging in the processes of science

changes one's conceptual

understanding and that process skills play a crucial role in the development of
understanding. In other words, encouraging students to deploy the processes of
science (in conducting investigations and solving problems) is a way of developing

(a) the interrelatedness of con


(b) the exploration and development of

their conceptual understanding. In its emphasis on


ceptual and procedural knowledge and

personal understanding, this argument is markedly different from those used by


advocates of discovery learning and process-oriented teaching ( Swatton 1990).
A theory-driven approach to investigation, in which students

use the processes

and methods of science to inyestigate phenomena and confront problems as a means


of enhancing and developing their understanding, provides a powerful integrative

At the same time, students acquire a deeper under


et al.
[1990] call it) becomes a method both for learning science and learning about science.

element for the curriculum.

standing of scientific activity, and investigation (or 'exploration' as Qualter

5 50

D . H O D SO;';

Further progress in learning about science can be made by encouraging students to


reflect on the personal learning progress that has been made. For example, when
students reconsider and reinterpret laboratory activities conducted earlier in the
course, they are able to draw meaningful parallels between the development of their
personal understanding and the growth of scientific knO\vledge.
However, if it is to be effective, learning about science has to be afforded a much
more explicit role in curriculum planning than has been common in the past
(Hodson 1990, Kirschner 1992). In criticizing much of our contemporary approach
to laboratory work, "'Toolnough and Allsop ( 1985) make a case for regarding
practical \vork as having three major aspects: exercises-to develop skills and tech
niques; experiences-to 'get a feel for phenomena'; investigations-to gain experience
of doing science. Clearly, this last one is a major contributor to children's under
standing of the nature of science. However, a case can be made for a fourth category
of practical work: \vhat we might call 'getting a feel for scientific practice' (see
Kirschner [ 1992] for a thorough and incisive discussion of this notion). 'Practical
\vork' in this context is not restricted to bench work. Rather, it includes all manner
of other active learning experiences designed to bring about a clearer understanding
of the nature of scientific activity- among them, the use of historical case studies,
simulations and dramatic reconstructions (Brush 1989, Burdett 1989, Bybee et al.
1991, Solomon 1989, Solomon et al. 1992, Wandersee 1990), role playing and
debating (Loving 199 1, van der Valk 1989), purpose-built 'nature of science' units
(Carey et al. 1989), activities focused on topics where theoretical explanation is still
controversial (Benson 1989a, Millar 1989), utilization of socio-economic issues
(Aikenhead 1991, 1992), use of computer-based activities (Freidler et al. 1990,
Hodson 1992b) and 'paper-and-pencil' problem solving (Gil-Perez et al. 1990), and
the elegant 'epistemological disturbance' strategy described by Larochelle and
Desautels ( 199 1a).
Of course, investigation/exploration is also the means by which students do
science-use the methods and processes of science to investigate phenomena, solve
problems and follow interests that they have chosen for themselves. It is here that
I wish to take further issue with those who promote the so-called process approach
to doing science. The principal claim of this approach is that doing science can be
analysed into a set of discrete activities, each of which can be clearly and unambigu
ously described, taught as theory-free, generalizable and transferable skills, and
systematically assessed. I regard such a claim as philosophically unsound and
pedagogically mistaken (Hodson 1992a). As I argued earlier, doing science is a
context-dependent and idiosyncratic activity. In approaching a particular situation,
scientists refine their approach to a problem, develop greater understanding of it
and devise more appropriate and productive ways of proceeding all at the same time.
As soon as an idea is developed, it is subjected to evaluation (by observation,
experiment, comparison with other theories, etc.). Sometimes that evaluation leads
to new ideas, to further and different experiments, or even to a complete recasting
of the original idea or reformulation of the problem. Thus, almost every move that
a scientist makes during an inquiry changes the situation in some way, so that the
next decisions and moves are made in an altered context (see Stewart and Hafner
[1991] for an extended discussion). Consequently, doing science is a holistic and
fluid activity, not a matter of following a set of rules that requires particular
behaviours at particular stages. Science is an organic, dynamic, interactive activity,
a constant interplay of thought and action.

I:'-!TEGRATI O C\! Ic\! S C IE:\CE A :\ D S C IENCE E D C CATIO:'-!

5 51

Moreover, in doing science one also increases both one's understanding of what
constitutes doing science and one's capacity to do it successfully. Just as you
'think your way into new ways of acting', so you 'act your way into new ways of
thinking'. In other words, doing science is a reflexive activity: current knowledge and
expertise informs and determines the conduct of the inquiry and, simultaneously,
involvement in inquiry (and, crucially, reflection on it) refines knowledge and
sharpens procedural expertise. Cheung and Taylor (1991) provide further insight
into this 'double spiral of knowing', as they call it, and outline ways in which a
developmental series of investigative tasks sensitive to the relationship between
conceptual knowledge and procedural knowledge can be planned.

Integration via task

In arguing that learning science, learning about science and doing science are
mutually reinforcing activities, and that doing science is itself a reflexive activity,
I have been moving towards the notion that the most powerful integrating factors
for science education are the learning tasks each student undertakes. When an
investigative approach to learning science is adopted, there is integration through the
dynamic interaction of the processes of science and the conceptual understanding
of each individual learner. When students have adequate experience of doing science,
there is integration through the interaction of observation, experiment and theory.
In addition, because of the reflexive nature of scientific activity, there is integration
between doing science, learning science and learning about science: students develop
their conceptual understanding and learn more about scientific inquiry by engaging
in scientific inquiry, provided that there is sufficient opportunity for and support of
reflection.
If scientists enhance their professional expertise through practice, it seems
reasonable to suppose that students will learn to do science (and to do it better) by
doing science-simple investigations at first, probably chosen from a well-tried list
of 'successful' investigations designed and developed by the teacher, but whole
investigations none the less. Then, as confidence, skill and knowledge grow,
progress can be made to more complex, more challenging and more open-ended
investigations. There is some evidence (Schauble et al. 1991) that it may be more
productive to begin with 'engineering type problems' (where the goal is to optimize
desired or interesting outcomes) and then to make a transition to 'science type
problems' (in which the goal is to identify and understand causal relationships
among variables) because, as the authors argue, the former more closely match
children's intuitive problem-solving strategies and their everyday ways of thinking.
Eventually, students can proceed independently: choosing their own topics, and
approaching them in their own way. In this way, they experience the whole process,
from initial problem identification to final evaluation. Also, as Brusic (1992)
reminds us, they experience 'the excitement of successes and the agony that arises
from inadequate planning or bad decisions'. However, the teacher's role is still a
crucial one: role model, learning resource, facilitator, consultant and critic. As
Ravetz (1973) has commented, learning to do science occurs 'almost entirely within
the interpersonal channel, requiring personal contact, and a measure of personal
sympathy between the parties. What is transmitted will be partly explicit, but partly
tacit; principle, precept, and example are all mixed together'.

552

D . HODSON

Before these kinds of activities can take place, however, it is important for
students to acquire a rich background of what White (1991) calls 'episodes' or
'recollections of events'. There are two senses in which these early experiences are
crucial. First, it is important for students to have first-hand experience of pheno
mena and events. It is not enough for them to read about blue crystals and forces
of magnetic attraction and repulsion; they need to see them and experience them
directly (Woolnough and Allsop 1985). Second, students need direct experience of
laboratory apparatus and procedures in order to develop both the confidence and
the capacity to use equipment appropriately and skilfully. This is not an argument
for an intensive bench skills training programme. Rather, it is a suggestion that the
adoption of some kind of 'familiarization programme' may be a necessary precursor
to successful scientific inquiry.
Once attention shifts to problem-solving exercises, investigative tasks and,
ultimately, to open-ended scientific inquiry, students are enabled to enhance
their conceptual understanding, build up more 'episodes' and acquire first-hand
experience of the procedures of science -especially those that relate to the structure,
purpose and conduct of experiments- all at the same time.
Within this overall constructivist epistemology and psychology of learning,
there are two major and closely related difficulties that have to be overcome if a
satisfactory degree of integration is to be established:
1. Avoiding the trap of relativism, where any conclusion that students arrive at,
for reasons that satisfy them, is deemed acceptable.
2. Ensuring that practical activities incline students towards currently accepted
knowledge (in curriculum terms) without implying that knowledge is
absolute or 'out there, waiting to be discovered'.
In both cases, the solution to the difficulty lies in a more explicit consideration
of the ways in which scientific knowledge is constructed and social acceptance is
negotiated, and in ensuring that such considerations are prominent in the design of
laboratory activities. In many classrooms, serious mismatches occur between the
professed 'philosophic stance' of the teacher and the curriculum experiences
provided (Hodson 1992c, Linder 1992). For example, in teaching about science
teachers may promote the view that scientific knowledge is socially constructed,
yet fail to acknowledge the social construction of scientific knowledge in the design
of laboratory activities. In school laboratories, an 'experiment' is usually designed
to lead students to a particular view; it is regarded by teachers as a way of
convincingly revealing meaning, rather than constituting an element in the
negotiation or construction of meaning. As a consequence, the implicit curriculum
message is that scientific theory is a body of authoritative knowledge revealed and
authenticated by observation and systematic experimentation. In other words,
students come to believe that certainty about knowledge resides in the method of
science. For an extended discussion of these matters, and of the resulting confusions
that students encounter, see Benson (1989b), Cheung and Taylor (1991), Duschl
and Gitomer (1991), Larochelle and Desautels (1991a, b), Nersessian (1989),
Russell and Munby (1989), Songer and Linn (1991).
As noted earlier, when students are engaged in conducting their own investi
gations, under their own direction, they refine their conceptual knowledge and
develop their procedural skills concurrently. Most importantly of all, they use their
developing knowledge and expertise in real contexts. In such circumstances, there

]:'-:TEGRATIO:'-: IN S C I E:'-:CE A:'-:O S C IENCE E DCCATIO:'-:

553

is much to be said for the use of an Investigator's Logbook, in which students reflect
on the progress of their investigation: '\Vhere am I going?' 'Where do I go next?'
' Do I need to rethink, replan?' It is reflections like these, and the requirement to
discuss them with the teacher, that gives students insight into the idiosyncratic and
reflexive nature of scientific investigation. Requiring students to be responsible for
discussing their own learning provides an opportunity for critical self-reflection and
helps to develop the sense of ownership and personal involvement that underpins
the integrative nature of the learning task.
Integration through issues

Another sense in which learning tasks based on investigation/exploration can


provide an integrative element for a science curriculum designed to achieve
universal scientific literacy is through the confrontation of issues. A mix of local and
global issues focusing on the seven priority areas identified by the Bangalore
Conference on 'Science and Technology and Future Human Needs' (Tendencia
1987) might suffice:

food and agriculture;


energy resources;
land, water and mineral resources;
industry and technology;
the environment;
information transfer;
ethics, and social responsibility.

The claim for integration resides in the belief that knowledge development and
utilization is a socially situated activity (Lave 1988). By grounding content in
socially and personally relevant contexts, an issues-based approach can provide the
motivation that is absent from current abstract, decontextualized approaches and
can form a base for students to construct understanding that is personally relevant,
meaningful and important.
Of course, it is possible to engage in an issues-based approach at several levels
of sophistication. At the simplest level, case studies of the societal impact of
inventions such as the steam engine, the printing press or the computer can be used
to bring about an awareness that science and technology are powerful forces
that shape the lives of people and other species, and impact significantly on the
environment as a whole. Part of this awareness includes recognition that the
benefits of scientific and technological innovations are often accompanied by
problems: hazards to human health, challenging and sometimes disconcerting
social changes, environmental degradation and major moral-ethical dilemmas.
iVluch of STS and environmental education is currently pitched at this level.
At the second level of sophistication, students recognize that scientific and
technological decisions are taken in pursuit of particular interests and are justified
by particular values. As a consequence, the advantages and disadvantages of
scientific and technological developments often impact differentially on society.
Being critically literate involves recognizing that science and technology serve
the rich and the powerful in ways that are often prejudicial to the interests and
well-being of the poor and powerless, and serve to increase further the inequalities
and injustices of the world (Carter 1990, 1991). Within a more global context, it

5 54

D . H O D SO:-;

includes recogmzmg that material benefits in the \Vest (:-.Jorth) are sometimes
achieved at the expense of those living in the Third 'World (Brophy 1991). By
addressing issues such as the infringement of Aboriginal land rights and the
destruction of the Amazonian rainforest in the pursuit of financial gain and
economic growth, students recognize that critical considerations in science and
technology cannot be divorced from concern with the distribution of wealth and
power, or from consideration of the root causes of environmental degradation.
\Vhen the goal is critical scientific literacy, it is not enough to view environ
mental problems merely as matters of careless industrialization and inexpert
management of natural resources, because this ignores the underlying causes of
the problems- the values underpinning industrialization and the exploitation of
natural resources- and sees their solution as a technical problem, for which we
need a quick 'technological fix'. In that sense, the approach depoliticizes the issues,
thereby removing them from the 'realm of possibility' within which ordinary
people perceive themselves as capable of intervention. As a consequence, dealing
with environmental problems is left to the 'experts' and the holders of office, and
ordinary citizens are disempowered. Education for empowerment requires that
science education is much more overtly political in flavour, which entails
recognizing that the environment is not just a 'given', but a social construct. It is
a social construct in two senses: (i) we act on and change the natural environment,
and so construct and reconstruct it through our social actions, and (ii) we perceive
it in a way that is dependent on the prevailing socio-cultural framework. Thus, our
concept of 'environment' itself is a social construct, and so could be different.
Indeed, many indigenous peoples do perceive it in significantly different ways
(Knudtson and Suzuki 1992).
By encouraging students to recognize the ways in which the environment is
socially constructed, we can challenge the notion that environmental problems are
'natural' and inevitable. If 'environment' is a social construct, environmental
problems are social problems, caused by societal practices and structures and
justified by society's current values. It follows that solving environmental problems
means addressing and changing the social conditions that give rise to them and the
values that sustain them. This realization shifts questions of environmental
improvement from the technical domain into the socio-political domain. The
solution to environmental problems does not lie in a quick 'technological fix', but
in socio-political action. In other words, scientists cannot be relied on to put
everything right whilst the rest of us maintain our current profligate lifestyle.
Thus, an essential step in pursuit of critical scientific literacy is applying a social
critique capable of challenging the notion of technological determinism- the idea
that technological change is inevitable and irresistible. \Ve can control technology
and its environmental and social impact or, more significantly, we can control the
controllers and redirect technology in such a way that adverse environmental impact
is reduced (if not entirely eliminated) and issues of freedom, equality and justice are
kept in the forefront of discussion during the establishment of policy (May 1992,
Hodson 1992d).
Students who have progressed this far will already have begun to formulate
their own opinions on important issues and to establish their own value positions.
The third level of sophistication focuses much more overtly on values clarification,
personal decision making about 'where one stands' on important local and global
issues, developing strong feelings about issues and actively thinking about what

I'lTEGRATI O N 1:,\ S C I EN C E A:,\D S C I E K C E EDCCATIO'l

555

it means to act wisely, justly and 'rightly' In different social, political and
environmental contexts. This phase has much in common with the goals of Peace
Education (Hicks 1988).
The final (fourth) level of sophistication in the issues-based approach is helping
students to prepare for and take action. Preparing students for action means
ensuring that they gain a clear understanding of how decisions are made within
local, regional and national government, and within industry and commerce. With
out knowledge of where and with whom power of decision making is located, and
awareness of the mechanisms by which decisions are reached, intervention is not
possible. At level one of an issues approach, students can be made aware of the
societal and environmental impact of science and technology and alerted to the
existence of alternative practices. At level two, students can be sensitized to the
socio-political nature of scientific and technological practice. At level three, they
may become committed to the fight to establish more socially just and environ
mentally sustainable practices. But only by proceeding to level four can we ensure
that students acquire the knmvledge and skills to intervene effectively in the
decision-making processes and ensure that alternative values are brought to bear on
policy decisions. Of course, the likelihood of students becoming active citizens will
be enhanced by encouraging them to take action now. Suitable action might include
conducting surveys, making public statements and writing letters, organizing
petitions and consumer boycotts of environmentally unsafe products, publishing
newsletters, working on environmental clean-up projects or assuming responsi
bility for environmental enhancement of the school itself (Hodson 1992e).
What I am arguing here is that education for critical scientific literacy is
inextricably linked with education for political literacy and with the ideology of
education as social reconstruction, and that these orientations provide the most
powerful means of integrating and unifying science education. The integrative
element is each student's progress towards a personal frame\vork of under
standings, points of view and values, and its expression through personal action.
A similar argument, leading to a curriculum proposal based on a five-phase
'responsibility spiral', has recently been developed by Waks ( 1992):
By moving through the phases of the spiral, learners of all ages can be guided in
forming their convictions and commitments, their life- style choices and values, as
these bear upon the technology dominated issues facing our society. As they move
through these phases, on issue after issue, confronting and thinking through science
and technology dominated issues of increasing complexity, learners can make p rogress
toward mature social responsibility.

Questions of research, curriculum development and teacher


education
In conducting my personal search for a more meaningful relationship among the
sciences, and in exploring possibilities for integration in science education, I began
by seeking my own answers to four series of questions, commencing with the
following:
1. What view of science is it desirable for students to hold?
2. Is it possible to 'translate' this model of science into learning experiences that
adequately 'convey the message'?
3. What view of learning in science should be employed?

556

D . HODSO:\l

4. Can this model of learning be 'translated' into suitable and effective learning
experiences?
5. Is it both possible and desirable to establish a degree of harmony between
preferred models of knowledge construction in science and preferred models
of learning science and, therefore, between activities that focus on learning
about science and those that focus on learning science?
It goes without saying that other curriculum researchers might answer these
questions differently. For example, Loving ( 1992) provides a detailed discussion of
questions 1 and 2, and some interesting and important comments on questions 3,
4 and 5 can be found in recent work by Burbules and Linn ( 199 1), Giannetto et al.
( 1992), Gil-Perez and Carrascosa-AIis ( 1992), Matthews and Davson-Galle ( 1992).
A second series of questions concerns the possibility of using scientific, techno
logical and environmental issues as an integrating principle, and the extent to which
an issues-based curriculum that involves social critique and education for political
literacy is desirable. Again, others might answer these questions differently.
Inevitably, there will be those who would seek to maintain science education's
current preoccupation with abstract, theoretical knowledge and with pre-profes
sional preparation, and some will regard the reformulation of science education in
terms of more overtly political goals as undesirable. As McElroy ( 1986) comments:
' It is ironical that the very success of political literacy education is what draws the
most opposition. Politically literate students are seen as a threat to the established
order of power and control. Hence potentially successful political action may be
vigorously resisted while ineffective participation...is lauded.'
Restriction of an issues-based curriculum to the level of scientific and techno
logical considerations (level one in the earlier discussion) would be seen by many as
'politically safe', because of its supposed 'neutral' stance. In reality, it is not neutral.
Indeed, it implicitly supports current social practices, current institutions and
current values. Insofar as it fails to address underlying socio-political and economic
issues, excludes consideration of social alternatives, sustains a 'technocratic'
approach to the confrontation of problems and fails to equip students with the
capacity to intervene, the so-called 'neutral' approach actually reinforces the societal
values that created the problems and so has to be regarded as education for social
reproduction (Hodson 1992d, May 1992).
A third series of questions concerns the most appropriate approach to
curriculum development and teacher education. What is not in dispute is that
an investigative approach to learning science, learning about science and doing science
will only work with teachers whose professional expertise includes awareness of
what constitutes good scientific investigation, how students can be brought to a
similar understanding (in kind, if not level) and how they can be encouraged and
supported in their scientific investigations. What may be in dispute is how that state
of affairs can be achieved. However, if we have learned anything from previous
excursions into science education reform it is that centre-to-periphery styles of
curriculum development and directive styles of teacher education are nearly always
unsuccessful. For the kinds of curriculum changes envisaged here, an alternative
approach would need to be adopted.
The constructivist epistemology assumed in the investigative approach seems to
demand a constructivist approach to curriculum development, teacher education
and professional development. Teachers need to articulate their views about the

THE U N IVERS!TY OF WAI KATO


EDUC,I"TION UGRARY
I :\TEGRAT IO:"l I"l S C I E);CE A"lD S C I E :-.i C E EOCCAT I O );

5 57

nature of science and the nature of teaching and learning, they need to explore them
and critique them, they need opportunities to consider alternatives, and to model,
test and evaluate them in action. In effect, what is being described here is an action
research spiral in which teachers plan, act, observe and reflect ( Kemmis and
:vlcTaggert 1982). Just as scientists and students develop expertise in doing science
by doing science (because of the reflexive nature of scientific practice), so teachers
develop expertise in supporting and encouraging students' scientific investigations
by supporting and promoting students' scientific investigations (because of the
reflexive nature of educational practice).
These arguments can be extended to the issues-based approach to integrated
science education, where anxieties over unfamiliar content and teaching/learning
style make a centralist approach to curriculum development even more inappro
priate (Bybee 1991, :VIitchener and Anderson 1989). The purpose of confronting
students with issues is to develop the critical thinking and decision-making skills
that constitute critical scientific literacy. It is absurd and contradictory- even
perverse-to deny teachers that same opportunity to develop their critical thinking
and decision-making skills in relation to their professional practice. Educational
practice should be educative and empowering for teachers as well as for students.
Because of its critical and reflexive nature, the issues approach is empowering
for teachers and engagement in it is, in itself, a major stimulus for professional
growth, provided that teachers are given sufficient autonomy. Under these condi
tions, educational practice has many of the characteristics of the kind of critical
action research envisaged by Carr and Kemmis (1986) as the route to enhanced
professionalism. In other words, the issues-based approach to science education has
a commitment to and a procedure for professional growth built into it. Similar
arguments concerning curriculum development and professional development are
presented at greater length by Hart and Robottom (1990) and Rubba (1991), with
respect to STS education in general. In a modest way, this approach to curriculum
development is exemplified in two recent Canadian initiatives: 'Science Plus'
(McFadden 1992) and 'LoRST' (Aikenhead 1991, 1992). Research into the
effectiveness of the more radical approach advocated by May (1992) is urgently
needed.
A fourth set of questions concerns assessment and evaluation procedures. There
is no doubt that assessment procedures, and public examinations in particular, exert
a significant influence on the curriculum and can promote or hinder the adoption
of particular classroom activities (Kempa 1986). If it is accepted as inevitable that
both teachers and students will put most value on that which is examined, and for
which academic credit can be gained, ways will need to be found for recognizing and
rewarding quality in investigative inquiries (Hodson 1992a) and for monitoring and
rewarding students' abilities to confront complex issues in a critical way (Cheek
1992, Zoller 1990). However, such concerns fall outside the scope of this article.

References
AOE:\ I Y I ,

E. O . ( 1 9 8 7 ) . Curriculum development and the concept of ' integration ' in


science - some implications for general education. Science Education , 71 , 5 2 3-5 3 3 .
A I KENIIEAD , G . S . ( 1 9 9 1 ) . Transposing STS Science Curriculum policy into a High School
Textbook. Paper p resented at the Annual 'VIeeting of the Canadian Society for the
Study of Education, Queen ' s University , Kingston .

558
A I K E:\I H E A D ,

D . H O D S O :'\

G . ( 1 9 9 2 ) . The integration of STS into science education. Theory in to Practice,


3 1 , 27-3 5 .
ALBERTA yI I N I STRY O F EDCCATIO:\l ( 1 990) . S TS Science Educa tion Unifying the Goals of
Science Education . Alberta, Ministry of Education .
B A I R D , J . , FENSHA:\I , P . , GU:"JSTO:"J E , R and '-"' B I T E , R ( 1 9 9 1 ) . The importance of reflection
in improving science teaching and learning. Journal of Research in Science Teaching,
28, 1 6 3-1 8 2 .
B E '\ S O N , G . D . ( 1 989a). Epistemology and science curriculum . Journal of Curriculum Studies,
2 1 , 3 29-344.
B E N S O :\l , G . D . ( 1 9 8 9 b ) . The m isrepresentation of science by philosophers and teachers of
science . Synthese, 80, 1 07-1 1 9 .
BE,\TLEY, D . and WATT S , M ( 1 9 8 9 ) . Learning and Teaching in School Science : Practical
A lternatives . M ilton Keynes, Open University Press .
B O D M E R , W. ( 1 9 8 9 ) . Scientific literacy for health and prosperity . School Science Review , 70,
9-2 0 .
B L A C K , P . ( 1 9 8 6 ) . I ntegrated or co-ordinated scienc e ? School Science Review, 67, 669-6 8 1 .
B R J D GHA:\J , P . W . ( 1 9 5 0 ) . The Reflections of a Physicist . New York, Philosophical Library .
B ROPHY, M . ( 1 99 1 ) . Global Science . School Science Review , 73, 5 9-66 .
B ROW:,\ , S . A. ( 1 977) . A review of the meanings of, and arguments for , integrated science .
Studies in Science Educa tion, 4, 3 1 -6 2 .
B R U S H , S . G . ( 1 9 8 9 ) . History o f science and science education . In terchange, 20, 60-7 0 .
B R U S I C , S . A. ( 1 9 9 2 ) . Achieving S T S goals through experiential learning. Theory into Practice,
3 1 , 44-5 1 .
B U R B U L E S , N . C . and L I :"J l\ , M . C . ( 1 99 1 ) . Science education and philosophy of science :
congruence or contradiction ? In ternational Journal of Science Educa tion , 1 3 , 227-24 1 .
B URDETT, P . ( 1 9 8 9 ) . Adventures with N - rays : an approach to teaching about scientific theory
and theory evaluation . I n R. Ylillar (ed . ) , Doing Science : Images of Science in Science
Education (pp . 1 80-204) . Lewe s , Falmer Press.
BYBEE, R W . ( 1 99 1 ) . Science-technology-society in science curriculum : the policy-p ractice
gap . Theory into Practice, 30, 294-3 0 2 .
BYBEE, R . W . , POWE L L , J . C . and E L L I S , J . D . ( 1 9 9 1 ) . Integrating the history and nature o f
science and technology into science and society studies curriculum . Science Education,
75, 1 43-1 5 5 .
CAREY , S . , E VA 0i S , R , H O ,\ D A , M . , J A Y , E . and U'\GER, C . ( 1 9 8 9 ) . ' An experiment i s when
you try it and see i f it works ' : a case study of grade 7 students' understanding of the
construction of scientific knowledge . Interna tional Journal of Science Educa tion, 1 1 ,
5 1 4- 5 2 9 .
CARR, \\! . and KE:\IM I S , S . ( 1 9 8 6 ) . Becoming Critical. Levie s , Falmer Press.
C A R T E R , C . ( 1 9 9 0 ) . Gender and equity issues in science classroom s : values and curricular
discourse. I n D. E. Herget (ed . ) , More History and Philosophy of Science in Science
Teaching ( p p . 1 2 2-1 3 2) . Tallahassee, Florida State University.
CARTER, C. ( 1 99 1 ) . Science-technology-society and access to scientific knowledge . Theory
into Practice, 30, 273-279.
C H E E K , D . W . ( 1 9 9 2 ) . Evaluating learning in STS education. Theory into Practice, 3 1 , 64-7 2 .
C H E U :'\ G , K . C . and TAYLOR, R . ( 1 99 1 ) . Towards a humanistic constructivist model of
science learning: changing perspectives and research implication s . Journal of
Curriculum Studies , 23, 2 1 -40.
C L O C G H , E . E . , D R I V E R , R . and W o o D - Ro B I :"J S O N , C . ( 1 9 8 7 ) . How do chil d ren ' s scientific
ideas change over time ? School Science Review, 69, 2 5 5-267 .
D IXO:,\ , B . ( 1 9 7 3 ) . What is Science For ? London , Collin s .
D R I V E R , R a n d B E L L , B . ( 1 9 8 6 ) . Students' thinking a n d t h e learning of science: a construc
tivist view . School Science Review, 6 7, 443-4 5 6 .
D R I V E R , R , G U E S =" E , E . and T I BERGH I E N , A . ( 1 9 8 5 ) . Children 's Ideas i n Science . 1VIilton
Keynes, Open University Press.
D U H E :vr , P . ( 1 962) . T h e A im a n d Structure of Physical Theory , tran s . P . P . Weine r . New York ,
Atheneum Press.
DUSCHL, R A . ( 1 9 9 0 ) . Restructuring Science Educa tion . New York , Teachers College Press .
D U S C H L , R A. and GI'fO;'I1ER, D . H . ( 1 99 1 ) . Epistemological perspectives on conceptual

l:-JTEGRATIO:-J 1:\ S C IEl'iCE A :-J D S C I E :\ C E E D C C A T I O N

559

change: Implications for educational p ractice. Journal oj Research in Science Teaching,


28, 8 3 9-8 5 8 .
D C S C H L , R . A . , HA:vI I LTO"l , R. and GRA:\D Y , R. E. ( 1 9 9 1 ) . Psychology and epistemology:
match or mismatch when applied to science education ? International Journal oj Science
Educa tion, 1 2 , 2 3 0-243 .
FEKSHA:VI , P . J . ( 1 9 8 8 ) . Familiar but different: some dilemmas and new directions in science
education. In P. Fensham (ed . ) , Developments and Dilemmas in Science Educa tion
( p p . 1-26) . Lewes, Falmer Press .
FEYERABE:\D , P . K . ( 1 9 7 5 ) . Against Method. London , New Left Books.
F RE I D LE R , Y., N A C H NI I A S , R . and L I N '\; , M. C. ( 1 9 9 0 ) . Learning scientific reasoning skills
in microcomputer-based laboratories . Journal oj Research in Science Teaching, 2 7,
1 7 3- 1 9 1 .
FREY, K . ( 1 9 8 9 ) . I ntegrated science education: 20 years on. International Journal oj Science
Education, 1 1 , 3-1 7 .
G I AN'lETTO , E . , TARS I TAN I , C . and V I C E NT I :\ I :\I[ I S SO N I , M . ( 1 9 9 2 ) . The relations between
epistemology, history of science and science teaching from the p oint of view of the
research on mental representations. In S. Hills (ed . ) , The History and Philosophy oj
Science in Science Education, Vol . 1 , Proceedings of the 2nd I nternational Conference ,
Kingston (pp . 3 5 9-3 74) . Kingston , Queen ' s Vniversity .
G I LBERT, S . W . ( 1 99 1 ) . :.vIodel building and a definition of science . Journal oj Research in
Science Teaching, 28, 73-7 9 .
G I L-PEREZ , D . a n d CARRASCOSA-A L I S . J . ( 1 9 9 2 ) . Approaching pupils' learning to scientific
construction of knowledge : some implications of the history and philosophy of science
in science teaching. I n S. Hills (ed . ) , The History and Philosophy oj Science in Science
Educa tion , V o l . 1 , Proceedings of the 2nd International Conference , Kingston
(pp. 3 7 5-3 8 9 ) . Kingston , Queen ' s University .
G I L -PERE Z , D . , D U NIAS-CARRE, A . , C A I LLOT, M . and :\I[ART I K E Z - ToRREGROSA, ] . ( 1 9 90 ) .
Paper and pencil problem- solving in the physical sciences as a research activity .
Studies in Science Education, 1 8 , 1 3 7-1 5 1 .
HART, E . P . and ROBOTTO :VI , I . M . ( 1 990) . The science-technology-society movement in
science education: a critique of the reform p rocess. Journal oj Research in Science
Teaching, 2 7, 5 7 5-5 8 8 .
H E A D , J . ] . ( 1 9 8 6 ) . Research into alternative frameworks : p romise and problems. Research in
Science & Technological Education, 4, 203-2 1 1 .
HEATH , P . A . ( 1 9 9 2 ) . O rganizing for STS teaching and learning: the doing of STS . Theory into
Practice, 3 1 , 5 2-5 8 .
H I C K S , D . ( 1 9 8 8 ) . Educa tion Jor Peace : Issues, Principles and Practice . London , Routledge .
H I R S T , P . H . ( 1 974) . Knowledge and the Curriculum London, Routledge & Kegan Pau l .
H O D S O N , D . ( 1 990) . Making t h e implicit explicit: a curriculum planning m o d e l for
enhancing childre n ' s understanding of science . I n D. E. Herget (ed . ) , More History
and Philosophy oj Science in Science Teaching (pp. 2 9 2-3 1 0) . Tallahassee , Florida State
Vniversity .
H O D s O K , D . ( 1 9 9 2 a ) . Assessment of p ractical work : some considerations in philosophy of
science . Science & Educa tion , 1 , 1 1 5-1 44.
HODSON, D. ( 1 9 9 2 b ) . Redefining and reorienting practical work in school science . School
Science Review, 73, 6 5-7 8 .
H O D S O "l , D . ( 1 9 9 2 c) . Philosophic stance, curriculum experiences and children ' s under
standing of science : some p reliminary findings . Paper p resented at the 2nd
I nternational Conference on the History and Philosophy of Science and Science
Teaching, Queen ' s University, Kingston .
H O D S O N , D . ( 1 9 9 2 d ) . Towards a framework for multicultural science education. Curriculum,
1 3, 1 5-28 .
H O D S O "l , D . ( 1 992e) . Politicizing environmental education . Crucible (in p ress) .
H O D S O "l , D . and R E I D , D . ( 1 9 8 8 ) . Changing p riorities in science education. School Science
Review , 70, 1 0 1 - 1 0 8 , 1 5 9-1 6 5 .
H O LTo"l , G . ( 1 9 7 8 ) . The Scientific Imagina tion : Case Studies . Cambridge , Cambridge
University Press .

560
H O LTON , G .

D . HODSON

( 1 9 8 6 ) . The A d'vancemen t of Science and its Burdens. Cambridge , Cambridge


University Press .
H U L L , D . ( 1 974) . The Philosophy of Biological Science . Englewood Cliffs , :--1 1 , Prentice Hal l .
HURD , P . D . ( 1 99 1 ) . Closing the educational gaps between science, technology , and society .
Theory into Practice, 30, 2 5 1 -2 5 9 .
JACOJlY, B . and SPARGO , P . ( 1 9 9 2 ) . A n appropriate science education for Africa: Deweyan
instrumentalism or critical realism ? I n S. Hills (ed . ) , The History and Philosophy of
Science in Science Education, Vol . 1 , Proceedings of the 2nd I nternational Conference,
Kingston (pp . 545-5 5 7 ) . Kingston, Queen ' s University .
J E:--I K I N S , E . ( 1 990) . Scientific literacy and school science education. School Science Review ,
71 , 43-5 1 .
J ORDAX, T . ( 1 9 8 9 ) . Themes and schemes: a philosophical approach to interdisciplinary
science teaching. Synthese, 80, 63-7 9 .
KEl\I.\JI S , S . and J\lI cTAGGERT, R . ( 1 9 8 2 ) . The A c tion Research Planner. Geelong, Deakin
Vniversity Press.
KE.\IPA, R . ( 1 9 8 6 ) . Assessment in Science . Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
K I R KIIA!\I , J . ( 1 9 8 9 ) . Balanced science : equilibrium between context , process and content. In
J. Wellington (ed . ) , Skills a n d Processes i n Science Education (pp. 1 3 5- 1 5 0 ) . London,
Routledge .
K I RSCHNER, P. A. ( 1 9 9 2 ) . Epistemology, p ractical work and academic skills in science educa
tion. Science fj Education, 1 , 27 3-299 .
KXCDTSON, P . and S U ZU K I , D . ( 1 9 9 2 ) . Wisdom of the Elders . Toronto, Stoddart.
KOERTGE , )J. ( 1 9 6 9 ) . Toward an integration of content and method in science education.
Curriculum Theory Network, 4, 26-44 .
KNORR-CETI:--I A , K. D . ( 1 9 8 3 ) . The ethnographic study of scientific work: towards a
constructivist interpretation of science . In K. D . Knorr- Cetina and :.vI . :Vlulkay (eds) ,
Science Observed (pp. 1 1 5-1 40 ) . London, Sage .
KUI-I !\ , T. S . ( 1 970). The Structure of Scientific Revolu tions . Chicago , University of Chicago
Press.
LATOU R , B. and W O O L G A R , S. ( 1 9 7 9 ) . Laboratory Life : The Social Construction of Scien tific
Facts. London , Sage .
LARO C H E L L E , M . and D E SAUTE L S , J . ( 1 9 9 1 a) . The epistemological turn in science education :
the return of the actor. Paper presented at the I nternational Vvorkshop ' Re search in
Physics Learning. Theoretical I ssues and Empirical Studies ' , I nstitute of Physics
Education , Gniversity of B remen .
LAROCHELLE, M . and D E SAL'TE L S , J . ( 1 9 9 1 b ) . ' O f course , it's j ust obvious ' : adolescents '
ideas of scientific knowledge . International Journal of Science Education , 1 3 , 3 7 3-3 8 9 .
LACDAX , L . ( 1 9 7 7 ) . Progress and its Problems . Berkeley , University o f California Press.
LAVE, J. ( 1 9 8 8 ) . Cognition in Practice : Mind, Ma thematics and Culture in Everyday Life .
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
L EW I S , T . and GAGE L , C. ( 1 9 9 2 ) . Technological literacy : a critical analysi s . Journal of
Curriculum Studies, 24, 1 1 7- 1 3 8 .
L I :--I D E R , C . J . ( 1 9 9 2 ) . I s teacher- reflected epistemology a source o f conceptual difficulty i n
physics ? International Journal of Science Education, 1 4 , 1 1 1 -1 2 1 .
L I N] S E , P . L . , KORTLAND , K . , E I] K E L H O F , H. M . C . , VAN GE"iDERE:\, D . and HOOY.\IAYER S ,
H . P . ( 1 990) . A thematic physics curriculum: a balance between contradictory curricu
lum forces . Science Education, 74, 9 5-1 0 3 .
L OV I N G , C . C . ( 1 99 1 ) . The scientific theory profile: a philosophy of science model for science
teachers. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 28, 8 2 3-8 3 8 .
L O V I N G , C . C . ( 1 9 9 2 ) . From constructive realism t o deconstructive anti-realism : helping
science teachers find a balanced philosophy of science . I n S. Hills (ed . ) , History and
Philosophy of Science in Science Education, Vol . I I ( p p . 45-7 0 ) . Kingston, Queen ' s
University .
MART I i' , B . and BROUWER, W . ( 1 99 1 ) . The sharing of personal science and the narrative
element in science education . Science Education, 75, 707-7 2 2 .
MART I N , B . , KAS S , H . a n d BROCWER, \\7 . ( 1 9 9 0 ) . Authentic science: a diversity of meanings.
Science Education, 74, 5 4 1 - 5 5 4 .
MATTHEW S , M . R . a n d DAVSON- GALLE , P . ( 1 9 9 2 ) . Constructivism and science education :

L'\TEGRAT I O N IN S C I E :\ C E A:'-rD S C I ENCE EDl'CATIO'\

561

some cautions and comments. In S . Hills (ed . ) , History and Philosophy of Science
Educa tion, Vol . I I ( p p . 1 3 5- 1 4 3 ) . Kingston, Queen ' s University .
:VIAXWE L L , X

( 1 984) . From Knowledge to Wisdom . Oxford, Basil Blackwell .


W . T . ( 1 9 9 2 ) . What are the subj ects o f sTs-really ? Theory in to Practice, 3 1 , 73-8 3 .
MAYER, V . J . and AR:\ISTRO K G , R . E . ( 1 9 9 0 ) . What every 1 7 -year old should know about
planet Earth : the report of a conference of educators and geoscientist s . Science
Education, 74, 1 5 5- 1 6 5 .
MAYR, E . ( 1 9 8 2 ) . The Growth of Biological Though t . Cambridge , :\IA, Harvard University
Press.
McELROY, B. ( 1 9 8 6 ) . Geography ' s contribution to political literacy . I n J. Fien and R . Gerber
(eds) , Teaching Geography for a Better World. Brisbane, J acaranda Press.
wl c FAD DEN , C. F . ( 1 9 9 2 ) . Author-publisher-educator relationships and curriculum reform .
Journal of Curriculum S tudies, 24, 7 1 -8 7 .
M I LLAR, R . ( 1 9 8 7 ) . Towards a role for experiment in the science teaching laboratory. Studies
in Science Education, 1 4 , 1 09-1 1 8 .
I\I I LLAR, R . ( 1 9 8 9 ) . Bending the evidence : the relationship between theory and experiment
in science education . I n R. M illar (ed . ) , Doing Science : Images of Science in Science
Education (pp. 3 8-6 1 ) . Lewes , Falmer Press.
M I TCHE:\ER, C. and A:\DERSO:'-r, R. ( 1 9 8 9 ) . Teacher ' s perspective : developing and imple
menting an STS curricul um. Journal of Research i n Science Teaching, 26, 3 5 1 - 3 6 9 .
M ITRO F F , I . I . a n d M A S O N , R . O . ( 1 974) . On evaluating the scientific contribution of the
Apollo lVloon mission via information theory : a study of the scientist-scientist relation
shi p . Management Science : Applica tions, 20, 1 5 0 1 - 1 5 1 3 .
E R S E S S I A :\ , . J . ( 1 9 8 9 ) . Conceptual change in science and i n science education. Synthese,
80, 1 6 3-1 8 3 .
NEWTO:\ , D . P . ( 1 9 8 6 ) . Humanized science teaching and school science textbook s .
Educational Studies, 12, 3-1 5 .
PO LA:'-rY I , :VI. ( 1 9 5 8 ) . Personal Knowledge. London , Routledge & Kegan Paul .
QCALTER, A . , STRA :'-r G , J . , S\\'ATTO:'-r , P . and TAYLOR, R. ( 1 990). Exp lora tion : A Way of
Learning Science . Oxford, Basil Blackwell .
RA VETZ , J . R. ( 1 9 7 3 ) . Scientific Knowledge and its Social Problems . Harmondsworth , Penguin .
REI D , D . J . and H O D s o :\ , D . ( 1 9 8 7 ) . Science For A l l : Teaching Science in the Secondary
School. London , Cassell.
ROBERTS, D. A. ( 1 9 8 2 ) . Developing the concept of ' curriculum emphases' In SClence
educatio n . Science Education, 60, 243-260.
ROBERT S , D. A . ( 1 9 8 3 ) . Scientific Literacy . Ottawa, Science Council of Canada.
ROSE'-JBERG, A. ( 1 98 5 ) . The Structure of Biological Though t . Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press .
ROSE:'-rTH A L , D . ( 1 9 8 9 ) . Two approaches to science-technology-society ( S-T-S) education.
Science Education , 73, 5 8 1 - 5 8 9 .
RCBBA, P . A . ( 1 9 9 1 ) . I ntegrating S T S into school science a n d teacher education: beyond
awarenes s . Theo ry in to Practice, 30, 3 03-3 0 8 .
R C S E , M . ( 1 9 7 3 ) . The Philosophy of Biology . London, Hutchinson .
R C SE , :.\1. ( 1 9 8 8 ) . B u t is it Science? Buffalo , Prometheus Books.
RUSSELL, T . and :.\lu:\BY, H. ( 1 989) . Science as a discipline, science as seen by students and
teachers' p rofessional knowledge . I n R . lVIillar (ed . ) , Doing Science : Images in Science
in Science Education (pp. 1 07-1 2 5 ) . Lewes, Falmer Press.
SCHAUBLE, L . , KLOPFER, L . E . and RAGHAVA '-J , K . ( 1 99 1 ) . Students' transition from an
engineering model to a scientific model of experimentation . Journal of Research zn
Science Teaching, 28, 8 5 9-882 .
S H A H N , E . ( 1 9 8 8 ) . On science literacy. Educational Philosophy (5 Theory , 20, 42-5 2 .
S H E X , B . ( 1 9 7 5 ) . Science literacy: the public need s . The Sciences, 24, 42-46 .
S :\I I T H , H . A., P I LC H , D. R . and W E L C H , G . R . ( 1 9 9 0 ) . Holism vs. reductionism: a model for
introducing philosophy into biology. In D. E. H erget (ed . ) , Afore History and
Philosophy of Science in Science Teaching (pp. 3 5 3-3 7 2 ) . Tallahassee , Florida State
University .
S :\I O L I C Z , J . J . and NCNAN, E. E. ( 1 9 7 5 ) . The philosophical and sociological foundations of
:VIAY,

562

I C\TEGRAT I O ;\l I C\ S C I EC\ C E AC\D S C IE C\!CE E DUCAT I O :\,

science educati on: the demythologizing of school science . Studies i n Science Education,
2 , 1 0 1 -1 4 3 .

SounIO C\ , J . ( 1 9 8 7 ) . Social influences on t h e construction of p u p i l s ' understanding of


science . Studies in Science Education, 14, 6 3 -8 2 .
S O LO:\IO)'! , J . ( 1 9 8 8 ) . The dilemma of science , technology and society education . I n
P . Fensham (ed . ) , Developments and Dilemmas in Science Education ( p p . 2 6 6-2 8 1 ) .
Lewes, Falmer Press.
S O LO:\IO C\ , J . ( 1 9 8 9 ) . T h e retrial of Galileo . I n D . E . Herget (ed . ) , The History and Philosophy
of Science in Science Teaching (pp . 3 3 2-3 3 8 ) . Tallahassee, Florida State University .
S O Lo:'IIO)'!, J . , DCVEE)'!, J . , S C O T , L . and M C CARTHY , S. ( 1 9 9 2 ) . Teaching about the nature of
science through history: action research in the classroom . Journal of Research in Science
Teaching, 29, 409-4 2 1 .

N . B . and L I )'! 'l , :YI. C . ( 1 9 9 1 ) . How do students' views of science influence knowl
edge integration ? Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 28, 7 6 1 -7 8 4 .
S S C R (Secondary Science Curriculum Review) ( 1 9 8 7 ) . Better Science : How to Plan and
A1anage the Curriculum, Curriculum Guide 5 . London , Heinemann/AsE.
STEWART, J . and H A F :'\i E R , R . ( 1 9 9 1 ) . Extending the conception of ' p roblem' in p roblem
solving research. Science Education, 75, 1 0 5- 1 2 0 .
S\YATTON , P . ( 1 9 9 0 ) . Process and content in the national Science Curriculum . School Science
SONGER,

Review , 72, 1 9-28 .


T E C\ D E 'l C I A ,

C . (ed . ) ( 1 9 8 7 ) . Science and Technology : Towards Informed Citizenship .


Proceedings o f the fifth ACASE-A S I AC\! symposium. Penang, :Yl alaysia, RECSA:\1 .
VAc\! DER VALK, T. ( 1 9 8 9 ) . vVaves or particles ? The cathode ray debate in the classroom . I n
R . Millar (ed . ) , Doing Science : Images of Science in Science Education (pp . 1 60- 1 7 9 ) .
Lewes, Falmer Press.
V I LLAN I , A . ( 1 9 9 2 ) . Conceptual change in science and science education. Science Education,
76, 2 2 3-2 3 7 .

S . and B REWER, \\7 . F . ( 1 9 8 7 ) . Theories o f knowledge restructuring in develop


ment . Review of Educational Research , 5 7, 5 1 -6 7 .
\\-AI( S , L . J . ( 1 9 9 2 ) . The responsibility spiral: a curriculum framework for STS education .

VO S 'l I O D O U ,

Theory into Practice, 3 1 , 1 3- 1 9 .


VVAN DERSE E , J .

H . ( 1 990) . O n the value and use of the history o f science i n teaching today ' s
science : constructing historical vignettes . I n D . E . Herget (ed . ) , More History and
Philosophy of Science in Science Teaching ( p p . 2 7 7-2 8 3 ) . Tallahassee , Florida State
Cniversity .
\V H I T E , F. C . ( 1 9 8 3 ) . Knowledge and relativism I I I : the sciences . Educational Philosophy &5
Theory , 1 5 , 1 -2 9 .
WII I T E ,

R. T. ( 1 9 9 1 ) . Episodes, and the purpose and conduct of practical work . I n B . E .


Woolnough (ed . ) , Practical Science (pp . 7 8-8 6 ) . :YI ilton Keynes, Open University
Press.
\VOO LC\O U G H , B . and A L L S O P , T . ( 1 9 8 5 ) . Practical Work i n Science . Cambridge , Cambridge
University Press.
ZOLLER, L'. ( 1 9 9 0 ) . The individualized eclectic examination ( I EE) : an innovative strategic
model for science and S-T-E-S [science-technology-environment-society] teaching for
all . Journal of College Science Teaching, 1 9, 2 8 9-2 9 1 .
Zl;GA, K. F. ( 1 9 9 1 ) . The technology education experience and what it can contribute to STS .
Theory into Practice, 30, 2 6 0-2 6 6 .

S-ar putea să vă placă și