Sunteți pe pagina 1din 8

6/9/2015

Noumenon - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Noumenon
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

The noumenon (/numnn/) is a posited object or event that is known (if at all) without the use of the
senses.[1] The term is generally used in contrast with, or in relation to "phenomenon", which refers to anything that
appears to, or is an object of, the senses. In Platonic philosophy, the noumenal realm was equated with the world
of ideas known to the philosophical mind, in contrast to the phenomenal realm, which was equated with the world
of sensory reality, known to the uneducated mind.[2] Much of modern philosophy has generally been skeptical of
the possibility of knowledge independent of the senses, and Immanuel Kant gave this point of view its canonical
expression: that the noumenal world may exist, but it is completely unknowable to humans. In Kantian philosophy,
the unknowable noumenon is often linked to the unknowable "thing-in-itself" (Ding an sich, which could also be
rendered as "thing-as-such" or "thing per se"), although how to characterize the nature of the relationship is a
question yet open to some controversy.

Contents
1 Etymology
2 The concept in pre-Kantian philosophy
3 Kant's usage
3.1 Overview
3.2 Noumenon and the thing-in-itself
3.3 Positive and negative noumena
3.4 The noumenon as a limiting concept
3.5 The dual-object and dual-aspect interpretations
4 Criticisms of Kant's noumenon
4.1 Pre-Kantian critique
4.2 Schopenhauer's critique
5 See also
6 Notes
7 External links

Etymology
The Greek word noumenon (o), plural noumena (), is the middle-passive present participle of
(noein), "I think, I mean", which in turn originates from the word "nous" (from , , perception,
understanding, mind). A rough equivalent in English would be "something that is thought", or "the object of an act of
thought".

The concept in pre-Kantian philosophy

http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Noumenon

1/8

6/9/2015

Noumenon - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Platonic Ideas and Forms are noumena, and phenomena are things displaying themselves to the
senses. [...] that noumena and the noumenal world are objects of the highest knowledge, truths, and
values is Plato's principal legacy to philosophy.
The Oxford Companion to Philosophy [3]

Kant's usage
Overview
Noumenon came into its modern usage through Immanuel Kant. Its etymology derives from the Greek noomenon
(thought-of) and ultimately reflects nous (intuition), but not emotion. Noumena is the plural form. Noumenon is
distinguished from phenomenon (Erscheinung), the latter being an observable event or physical manifestation
capable of being observed by one or more of the human senses. The two words serve as interrelated technical
terms in Kant's philosophy. As expressed in Kant's Critique of Pure Reason, human understanding is structured
by "concepts of the understanding", or innate categories of understanding that the mind uses in order to make sense
of raw unstructured experience.[4]
By Kant's account, when we employ a concept to describe or categorize noumena (the objects of inquiry,
investigation or analysis of the workings of the world), we are in fact employing a way of describing or categorizing
phenomena (the observable manifestations of those objects of inquiry, investigation or analysis). Kant posited
methods by which human beings make sense out of the interrelationships among phenomena: the concepts of the
transcendental aesthetic, as well as that of the transcendental analytic, transcendental logic and
transcendental deduction.[5][6][7] Taken together, Kant's "categories of understanding" are descriptions of the sum
of human reasoning that can be brought to bear in attempting to understand the world in which we exist (that is, to
understand, or attempt to understand, "things in themselves"). In each instance the word "transcendental" refers to
the process that the human mind uses increasingly to understand or grasp the form of, and order among,
phenomena. Kant asserts that to "transcend" a direct observation or experience is to use reason and classifications
to strive to correlate with the phenomena that are observed. By Kant's view, humans can make sense out of
phenomena in these various ways, but can never directly know the noumena, the "things-in-themselves", the actual
objects and dynamics of the natural world. In other words, by Kant's Critique, our minds may attempt to correlate
in useful ways, perhaps even closely accurate ways, with the structure and order of the various aspects of the
universe, but cannot know these "things-in-themselves" (noumena) directly. Rather, we must infer the extent to
which thoughts correspond with things-in-themselves by our observations of the manifestations of those things that
can be sensed, that is, of phenomena.[8][9]
According to Kant, objects of which we are sensibly cognizant are merely representations of unknown somethings
what Kant refers to as the transcendental objectas interpreted through the a priori or categories of the
understanding. These unknown somethings are manifested within the noumenonalthough we can never know
how or why as our perceptions of these unknown somethings are bound by the limitations of the categories of
the understanding and we are therefore never able to fully know the "thing-in-itself".[10]

Noumenon and the thing-in-itself

http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Noumenon

2/8

6/9/2015

Noumenon - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Many accounts of Kant's philosophy treat "noumenon" and "thing-in-itself" as synonymous, and there is textual
evidence for this relationship.[11] However, Stephen Palmquist holds that "noumenon" and "thing-in-itself" are only
loosely synonymous in as much as they represent the same thing but viewed from two different perspectives,[12][13]
and other scholars also argue that they are not identical.[14] Schopenhauer criticised Kant for changing the meaning
of "noumenon". Opinion is far from unanimous.[15] Kant's writings show points of difference between noumena and
things-in-themselves. For instance, he regards things-in-themselves as existing:
...though we cannot know these objects as things in themselves, we must yet be in a position at least
to think them as things in themselves; otherwise we should be landed in the absurd conclusion that
there can be appearance without anything that appears.[16]
..but is much more doubtful about noumena:
But in that case a noumenon is not for our understanding a special [kind of] object, namely, an
intelligible object; the [sort of] understanding to which it might belong is itself a problem. For we
cannot in the least represent to ourselves the possibility of an understanding which should know its
object, not discursively through categories, but intuitively in a non-sensible intuition.[17]
A crucial difference between the noumenon and the thing-in-itself is that to call something a noumenon is to claim a
kind of knowledge, whereas Kant insisted that the thing-in-itself is unknowable. Interpreters have debated whether
the latter claim makes sense: it seems to imply that we know at least one thing about the thing-in-itself (i.e., that it is
unknowable). But Stephen Palmquist explains that this is part of Kant's definition of the term, to the extent that
anyone who claims to have found a way of making the thing-in-itself knowable must be adopting a non-Kantian
position.[18]

Positive and negative noumena


Kant also makes a distinction between positive and negative noumena[19]
If by 'noumenon' we mean a thing so far as it is not an object of our sensible intuition, and so abstract
from our mode of intuiting it, this is a noumenon in the negative sense of the term.[20]

But if we understand by it an object of a non-sensible intuition, we thereby presuppose a special mode


of intuition, namely, the intellectual, which is not that which we possess, and of which we cannot
comprehend even the possibility. This would be 'noumenon' in the positive sense of the term.[21]
The positive noumena, if they existed, would roughly correspond with Plato's Forms or Ideasimmaterial entities
which can only be apprehended by a special, non-sensory, faculty: "intellectual intuition".[22]
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Noumenon

3/8

6/9/2015

Noumenon - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Kant doubts that we have such a faculty, because for him intellectual intuition would mean that thinking of an entity,
and its being represented, would be the same. He argues that humans have no way to apprehend the meaning of
positive noumena:
Since, however, such a type of intuition, intellectual intuition, forms no part whatsoever of our faculty
of knowledge, it follows that the employment of the categories can never extend further than to the
objects of experience. Doubtless, indeed, there are intelligible entities corresponding to the sensible
entities; there may also be intelligible entities to which our sensible faculty of intuition has no relation
whatsoever; but our concepts of understanding, being mere forms of thought for our sensible intuition,
could not in the least apply to them. That, therefore, which we entitle 'noumenon' must be understood
as being such only in a negative sense.[23]

The noumenon as a limiting concept


Even if noumena are unknowable, they are still needed as a limiting concept,[24] Kant tells us. Without them, there
would be only phenomena, and since we have complete knowledge of our phenomena, we would in a sense know
everything. In his own words:
Further, the concept of a noumenon is necessary, to prevent sensible intuition from being extended to
things in themselves, and thus to limit the objective validity of sensible knowledge.[25]

What our understanding acquires through this concept of a noumenon, is a negative extension; that is
to say, understanding is not limited through sensibility; on the contrary, it itself limits sensibility by
applying the term noumena to things in themselves (things not regarded as appearances). But in so
doing it at the same time sets limits to itself, recognising that it cannot know these noumena through
any of the categories, and that it must therefore think them only under the title of an unknown
something.[26]
Furthermore, for Kant, the existence of a noumenal world limits reason to what he perceives to be its proper
bounds, making many questions of traditional metaphysics, such as the existence of God, the soul, and free will
unanswerable by reason. Kant derives this from his definition of knowledge as "the determination of given
representations to an object".[27] As there are no appearances of these entities in the phenomenal, Kant is able to
make the claim that they cannot be known to a mind that works upon "such knowledge that has to do only with
appearances".[28] These questions are ultimately the "proper object of faith, but not of reason".[29]

The dual-object and dual-aspect interpretations


Kantian scholars have long debated two contrasting interpretations of the thing-in-itself. One is the dual object
view, according to which the thing-in-itself is a distinct entity from the phenomena to which it gives rise. The other is
the dual aspect view, according to which the thing-in-itself and the thing-as-it-appears to us are two "sides" of the
same thing. This view is supported by the textual fact that, "Most occurrences of the phrase 'things-in-themselves'
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Noumenon

4/8

6/9/2015

Noumenon - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

are shorthand for the phrase, 'things considered in themselves' (Dinge an sich selbst betrachten)."[30] Although we
cannot see things apart from the way we do in fact see them, we can think them apart from our mode of sensibility
(perception); thus making the thing-in-itself a kind of noumenon or object of thought.

Criticisms of Kant's noumenon


Pre-Kantian critique
Though the term Noumenon did not come into common usage until Kant, the idea that undergirds it, that matter has
an absolute existence which causes it to emanate certain phenomena, had historically been subjected to criticism.
George Berkeley, who pre-dated Kant, asserted that matter, independent of an observant mind, was
metaphysically impossible. Qualities associated with matter, such as shape, color, smell, texture, weight,
temperature, and sound were all dependent on minds, which allowed only for relative perception, not absolute
perception. The complete absence of such minds (and more importantly an omnipotent mind) would render those
same qualities unobservable and even unimaginable. Berkeley called this philosophy immaterialism. Essentially there
could be no such thing as matter without a mind.

Schopenhauer's critique
Schopenhauer claimed that Kant used the word incorrectly. He explained in his "Critique of the Kantian
philosophy", which first appeared as an appendix to The World as Will and Representation:
But it was just this difference between abstract knowledge and knowledge of perception, entirely
overlooked by Kant, which the ancient philosophers denoted by noumena and phenomena. (See
Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism, Book I, Chapter 13, ' What is thought (noumena) is
opposed to what appears or is perceived (phenomena).' ) This contrast and utter disproportion
greatly occupied these philosophers in the philosophemes of the Eleatics, in Plato's doctrine of the
Ideas, in the dialectic of the Megarics, and later the scholastics in the dispute between nominalism and
realism, whose seed, so late in developing, was already contained in the opposite mental tendencies of
Plato and Aristotle. But Kant who, in an unwarrantable manner, entirely neglected the thing for the
expression of which those words phenomena and noumena had already been taken, now takes
possession of the words, as if they were still unclaimed, in order to denote by them his things-inthemselves and his phenomena.[31]
The Noumenon's original meaning of "that which is thought" is not compatible with the "thing-in-itself ", the latter
meaning things as they exist apart from being images in the mind of an observer.

See also
Anatta
Haecceity
Hypokeimenon
Schopenhauer's criticism of the Kantian philosophy
Transcendental idealism
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Noumenon

5/8

6/9/2015

Noumenon - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Unobservables
The Void (philosophy)
Noumenon and Phenomena - The summary of Sri Nisargadatta Maharaj's teachings (http://sri-nisargadattamaharaj.blogspot.in/2015/02/noumenon-and-phenomena-summary-of.html)

Notes
1. "1. intellectual conception of a thing as it is in itself, not as it is known through perception" "2.The of itself
unknown and unknowable rational object, or thing in itself, which is distinguished from the phenomenon through
which it is apprehended by the senses, and by which it is interpreted and understood; so used in the philosophy
of Kant and his followers." (http://www.websters-dictionary-online.org/definitions/Noumenon?cx=partner-pub0939450753529744%3Av0qd01-tdlq&cof=FORID%3A9&ie=UTF-8&q=Noumenon&sa=Search#922)
2. "Platonist frames of thought draw a dividing line between two realms. One realm, the inferior of the two, is the
material, physical world of (http://www.warren-wilson.edu/~dmycoff/plato.html) sense experience. It is the
"phenomenal" world, the world of objects, of the body, of immediate perception. The other, superior realm is the
world of the immaterial, the spiritual, the world of realities not accessible to the body's senses, the world known by
intellect or spiritual sense, the "noumenal" world."
3. Honderich, Ted, ed. (31 August 1995). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy (http://www.amazon.com/OxfordCompanion-Philosophy-Ted-Honderich/dp/0198661320/ref=sr_1_1?s=books&ie=UTF8&qid=1414514364&sr=11#reader_0198661320). Oxford University Press. p. 657. ISBN 0198661320. Retrieved 2014-10-28.
4. Hanna, Robert (2009). Completing the Picture of Kant's Metaphysics of Judgment
(http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-judgment/supplement2.html). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
5. The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Critique of
Pure Reason: Theme and Preliminaries", p. 308 ff.
6. The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on
"Transcendental Aesthetic", p. 310 ff.
7. The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Pure Concepts
of the Understanding", p. 311 ff.
8. See, e.g., The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on
"Critique of Pure Reason: Theme and Preliminaries", p. 308 ff.
9. See also, e.g., The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on
"Pure Concepts of the Understanding", p. 311 ff.
10. Critique of Pure Reason A256/B312, p. 27
11. Immanuel Kant (1781) Critique of Pure Reason, for example in A254/B310, p. 362 (Guyer and Wood), "The
concept of a noumenon, i.e., of a thing that is not to be thought of as an object of the senses but rather as a thing
in itself [...]"; But note that the terms are not used interchangeably throughout. The first reference to thing-in-itself
comes many pages (A30) before the first to noumenon (A250). For a secondary or tertiary source, see:
"Noumenon" (http://www.britannica.com/eb/article-9056357/noumenon) in Encyclopdia Britannica
12. "Noumenon: the name given to a thing when it is viewed as a transcendent object. The term 'negative noumenon'
refers only to the recognition of something which is not an object of sensible intuition, while 'positive noumenon'
refers to the (quite mistaken) attempt to know such a thing as an empirical object. These two terms are sometimes
used loosely as synonyms for 'transcendental object' and 'thing in itself', respectively. (Cf. phenomenon.)"
Glossary of Kant's Technical Terms (http://www.hkbu.edu.hk/~ppp/ksp1/KSPglos.html)
13. Thing in itself: an object considered transcendentally apart from all the conditions under which a subject can gain
knowledge of it. Hence the thing in itself is, by definition, unknowable. Sometimes used loosely as a synonym of
noumenon. (Cf. appearance.)" Glossary of Kant's Technical Terms
(http://www.hkbu.edu.hk/~ppp/ksp1/KSPglos.html). Palmquist defends his definitions of these terms in his article,
"Six Perspectives on the Object in Kant's Theory of Knowledge", Dialectica 40:2 (1986), pp.121151; revised and
reprinted as Chapter VI in Palmquist's book, Kant's System of Perspectives (Lanham: University Press of America,
1993).
14. Oizerman, T. I., "Kant's Doctrine of the "Things in Themselves" and Noumena", Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research, Vol. 41, No. 3, Mar., 1981, 333350; Karin de Boer, "Kant's Multi-Layered Conception of Things in
Themselves, Transcendental Objects, and Monads", Kant-Studien 105/2, 2014, 221-260.
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Noumenon
6/8

6/9/2015

Noumenon - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Themselves, Transcendental Objects, and Monads", Kant-Studien 105/2, 2014, 221-260.


15. "Other interpreters have introduced an almost unending stream of varying suggestions as to how these terms ought
to be used. A handful of examples will be sufficient to make this point clear, without any claim to represent an
exhaustive overview. Perhaps the most commonly accepted view is expressed by Paulsen, who equates 'thing in
itself' and 'noumenon', equates 'appearance' and 'phenomenon', distinguishes 'positive noumenon' and 'negative
noumenon', and treats 'negative noumenon' as equivalent to 'transcendental object' [pp. 4:148-50, 154-5, 192]. AlAzm and Wolff also seem satisfied to equate 'phenomenon' and 'appearance', though they both carefully distinguish
'thing in itself' from 'negative noumenon' and 'positive noumenon' [A4:520; W21:165, 3135; s.a. W9:162].
Gotterbarn similarly equates the former pair, as well as 'thing in itself' and 'positive noumenon', but distinguishes
between 'transcendental object', 'negative noumenon' and 'thing in itself' [G11: 201]. By contrast, Bird and George
both distinguish between 'appearance' and 'phenomenon', but not between 'thing in itself' and 'noumenon'
[B20:18,19, 537; G7:513-4n]; and Bird sometimes blurs the distinction between 'thing in itself' and 'transcendental
object' as well.[2] Gram equates 'thing in itself' not with 'noumenon', but with 'phenomenon' [G13:1,5-6]! Allison
cites different official meanings for each term, yet he tends to equate 'thing in itself' at times with 'negative
noumenon' and at times with 'transcendental object', usually ignoring the role of the 'positive noumenon' [A7:94;
A10:58,69]. And Buchdahl responds to the fact that the thing in itself seems to be connected with each of the other
object-terms by regarding it as 'Kant's umbrella term'.[3]" Stephen Palmquist on Kant's object terms
(http://www.hkbu.edu.hk/~ppp/ksp1/KSP6A.html)
16. Critique of Pure Reason Bxxvi-xxvii.
17. Critique of Pure Reason A256, B312, p. 273 (NKS)
18. "The Radical Unknowability of Kant's 'Thing in Itself'", Cogito 3:2 (March 1985), pp.101115; revised and
reprinted as Appendix V in Stephen Palmquist, Kant's System of Perspectives
(http://www.hkbu.edu.hk/~ppp/ksp1) (Lanham: University Press of America, 1993).
19. Mattey, G.J (http://hume.ucdavis.edu/mattey/phi175/phenomlec.html)
20. Critique of Pure Reason A250/B307, p. 267 (NKS)
21. Critique of Pure Reason A250/B30, p. 2677 (NKS)
22. "The noumena are forms or ideas, which exist in a realm beyond space and time." University of Leeds course
notes (http://www.philosophy.leeds.ac.uk/GMR/hmp/modules/ihmp0304/units/unit05/dcreason.html)
23. Critique of Pure Reason B309, p. 270 (NKS)
24. Allison, H. "Transcendental Realism, Empirical Realism, and Transcendental Idealism"
(http://journals.cambridge.org/action/displayAbstract;jsessionid=295CBB027ADE6D31BEA8AAABA8A8D8DC.jour
nals?&aid=8201604).
25. Critique of Pure Reason A253/B310
26. Critique of Pure Reason A256/B312, p. 273
27. Critique of Pure Reason B/137, p. 156
28. Critique of Pure Reason B/xx., p. 24
29. Rohmann, Chris. "Kant" A World of Ideas: A Dictionary of Important Theories, Concepts, Beliefs, and Thnkers.
Ballantine Books, 1999.
30. Mattey, GJ. Lecture Notes on the Critique of Pure Reason (http://hume.ucdavis.edu/mattey/kant/TIILEC.HTM)
31. The World as Will and Representation(vol. 1, Dover edition 1966, ISBN 0-486-21761-2 p. 476-477)

External links
The surd of metaphysics; an inquiry into the question: Are
Look up noumenon in
there things-in-themselves? (1903)
Wiktionary, the free
(http://archive.org/details/surdofmetaphysic00caru) Paul Carus,
dictionary.
18521919 Retrieved May 18, 2012
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy on Kant's metaphysics (http://www.science.uva.nl/~seop/entries/kantmetaphysics/).
Glossary of Kant's technical terms (http://www.hkbu.edu.hk/~ppp/ksp1/KSPglos.html) by Stephen
Palmquist
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Noumenon

7/8

6/9/2015

Noumenon - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Article from undergraduate journal Noesis


(http://www.chass.utoronto.ca/pcu/noesis/issue_v/noesis_v_2.html)
Lecture notes by G.J Mattey (http://www-philosophy.ucdavis.edu/mattey/kant/APPEAR.HTM)
Kant's System of Perspectives (http://www.hkbu.edu.hk/~ppp/ksp1) (Lanham: University Press of America,
1993) by Stephen Palmquist
Retrieved from "http://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Noumenon&oldid=661972295"
Categories: Epistemology Metaphysics Enlightenment philosophy Kantianism
This page was last modified on 12 May 2015, at 09:14.
Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License; additional terms may apply.
By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia is a registered trademark
of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.

http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Noumenon

8/8

S-ar putea să vă placă și