Sunteți pe pagina 1din 24

CONSCIOUSNESS AND DELUSIONS

Varun Pandey
B.A(H)Applied Psychology (2013-2016)
Amity University, Noida
In 200,000 years of history humans learned how to create a simulation of big bang
theory in a Large Hadron Collider the most massive machine ever built. We have
successfully learned the concept of how species reproduce to over come the problem
of existence. We have also travelled through space to find if we are alone in this
universe. We have built robots which are capable of self-learning (HONDA- ASIMO
is one fine example of such robots) but there has been a problem, which is the root of
all these problems, and that problem is the PROBLEM OF HAVING A
CONSCIOUSNESS.
Now why cant we be just another highly advanced version of the robots that
we build today and perform our tasks by INPUT and OUTPUT mechanism and only
talk about the numbers and logics? Why and how come that we possess a system
which is so highly advance that it creates the concept of ONE as a being and then
collects all those stimuli we obtain from the environment and process them as an
experience we often call Life.
In fact the whole concept of my typing this paper on my computer right now
sitting on my bed at 6:15 a.m. and me being able to recognize that while typing, my
roommates cellphone fired the alarm for morning wakeup call is something which
neurologists call the CONSCIOUSNESS.
Since a very long time philosophers have been arguing about mind and
consciousness. There have been many theories and the earliest of them is
consciousness being a part of some external intelligence, which makes us work and
experience life. But the word conscious originated in the late 16th century from a
Latin word CONSCIUS, which means knowing with others or in oneself. Which
tells us that since the inception of time there has been an urge to know what
ultimately makes us alive or what ultimately give us the experience of being alive.

In this paper we are going to discuss about the concept of consciousness based
on neurological and philosophical researches and ideas. Then well also investigate
about the other state of human mind, which we call as Delusional State.
WHAT IS CONSCIOUSNESS?
Consciousness is the quality or state of awareness, or, of being aware of an external
object or something within oneself. It has been defined as: sentience, awareness,
subjectivity, the ability to experience or to feel, wakefulness, having a sense of
selfhood, and the executive control system of the mind. Despite the difficulty in
definition, many philosophers believe that there is a broadly shared underlying
intuition about what consciousness is. As Max Velmans and Susan Schneider wrote in
The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness: "Anything that we are aware of at a
given moment forms part of our consciousness, making conscious experience at once
the most familiar and most mysterious aspect of our lives.
When I am in a conscious mental state, there is something it is like for me to be in
that state from the subjective or first person point of view. But how are we to
understand this? For instance, how is the conscious mental state related to the body?
Can consciousness be explained in terms of brain activity? What makes a mental state
be a conscious mental state? The problem of consciousness is arguably the most
central issue in current philosophy of mind and is also importantly related to major
traditional topics in metaphysics, such as the possibility of immortality and the belief
in free will.

The Metaphysics of Consciousness: Materialism vs. Dualism


Metaphysics is the branch of philosophy concerned with the ultimate nature of reality.
There are two broad traditional and competing metaphysical views concerning the
nature of the mind and conscious mental states: dualism and materialism. While there
are many versions of each, the former generally holds that the conscious mind or a
conscious mental state is non-physical in some sense. On the other hand, materialists
hold that the mind is the brain, or, more accurately, that conscious mental activity is

identical with neural activity. It is important to recognize that by non-physical,


dualists do not merely mean not visible to the naked eye. Many physical things fit
this description, such as the atoms, which make up the air in a typical room. For
something to be non-physical, it must literally be outside the realm of physics; that is,
not in space at all and undetectable in principle by the instruments of physics. It is
equally important to recognize that the category physical is broader than the
category material. Materialists are called such because there is the tendency to view
the brain, a material thing, as the most likely physical candidate to identify with the
mind. However, something might be physical but not material in this sense, such as an
electromagnetic or energy field. One might therefore instead be a physicalist in
some broader sense and still not a dualist. Thus, to say that the mind is non-physical is
to say something much stronger than that it is non-material. Dualists, then, tend to
believe that conscious mental states or minds are radically different from anything in
the physical world at all.

Dualism: General Support and Related Issues

There are a number of reasons

why some version of dualism has been held throughout the centuries. For one thing,
especially from the introspective or first person perspective, our conscious mental
states just do not seem like physical things or processes. That is, when we reflect on
our conscious perceptions, pains, and desires, they do not seem to be physical in any
sense. Consciousness seems to be a unique aspect of the world not to be understood in
any physical way. Although materialists will urge that this completely ignores the
more scientific third-person perspective on the nature of consciousness and mind, this
idea continues to have force for many today. Indeed, it is arguably the crucial
underlying intuition behind historically significant conceivability arguments against
materialism and for dualism. Such arguments typically reason from the premise that
one can conceive of ones conscious states existing without ones body or,
conversely, that one can imagine ones own physical duplicate without consciousness
at all.

Materialism: General Support


Some form of materialism is probably much more widely held today than in centuries
past. No doubt part of the reason for this has to do with the explosion in scientific
knowledge about the workings of the brain and its intimate connection with
consciousness, including the close connection between brain damage and various
states of consciousness. Brain death is now the main criterion for when someone dies.
Stimulation to specific areas of the brain results in modality specific conscious
experiences. Indeed, materialism often seems to be a working assumption in
neurophysiology. Imagine saying to a neuroscientist you are not really studying the
conscious mind itself when she is examining the workings of the brain during an
fMRI. The idea is that science is showing us that conscious mental states, such as
visual perceptions, are simply identical with certain neuro-chemical brain processes
much like the science of chemistry taught us that water just is H2O.

There are also theoretical factors on the side of materialism, such as adherence to the
so-called principle of simplicity which says that if two theories can equally explain
a given phenomenon, then we should accept the one, which posits fewer objects or
forces. In this case, even if dualism could equally explain consciousness (which
would of course be disputed by materialists), materialism is clearly the simpler theory
in so far as it does not posit any objects or processes over and above physical ones.
Materialists will wonder why there is a need to believe in the existence of such
mysterious non-physical entities. Moreover, in the aftermath of the Darwinian
revolution, it would seem that materialism is on even stronger ground provided that
one accepts basic evolutionary theory and the notion that most animals are conscious.
Given the similarities between the more primitive parts of the human brain and the
brains of other animals, it seems most natural to conclude that, through evolution,
increasing layers of brain areas correspond to increased mental abilities. For example,
having a well-developed prefrontal cortex allows humans to reason and plan in ways

not available to dogs and cats. It also seems fairly uncontroversial to hold that we
should be materialists about the minds of animals. If so, then it would be odd indeed
to hold that non-physical conscious states suddenly appear on the scene with humans.

There are still, however, a number of much discussed and important objections to
materialism, most of which question the notion that materialism can adequately
explain conscious experience.

Specific Theories of Consciousness


Most specific theories of consciousness tend to be reductionist in some sense. The
classic notion at work is that consciousness or individual conscious mental states can
be explained in terms of something else or in some other terms. This section will
focus on several prominent contemporary reductionist theories. We should, however,
distinguish between those who attempt such a reduction directly in physicalistic, such
as neurophysiological, terms and those who do so in mentalistic terms, such as by
using unconscious mental states or other cognitive notions.

1. Neural Theories
The more direct reductionist approach can be seen in various, more specific,
neural theories of consciousness. Perhaps best known is the theory offered by
Francis Crick and Christof Koch 1990 (see also Crick 1994, Koch 2004). The
basic idea is that mental states become conscious when large numbers of neurons
fire in synchrony and all have oscillations within the 35-75 hertz range (that is,
35-75 cycles per second). However, many philosophers and scientists have put
forth other candidates for what, specifically, to identify in the brain with
consciousness. This vast enterprise has come to be known as the search for the
neural correlates of consciousness or NCCs (see section 5b below for more).
The overall idea is to show how one or more specific kinds of neuro-chemical
activity can underlie and explain conscious mental activity (Metzinger 2000). Of

course, mere correlation is not enough for a fully adequate neural theory and
explaining just what counts as a NCC turns out to be more difficult than one might
think (Chalmers 2000). Even Crick and Koch have acknowledged that they, at
best, provide a necessary condition for consciousness, and that such firing patters
are not automatically sufficient for having conscious experience.

2. Representational Theories Of Consciousness


Many current theories attempt to reduce consciousness in mentalistic terms. One
broadly popular approach along these lines is to reduce consciousness to mental
representations of some kind. The notion of a representation is of course very
general and can be applied to photographs, signs, and various natural objects, such
as the rings inside a tree. Much of what goes on in the brain, however, might also
be understood in a representational way; for example, as mental events
representing outer objects partly because they are caused by such objects in, say,
cases of veridical visual perception. More specifically, philosophers will often call
such

representational

mental

states

intentional

states

which

have

representational content; that is, mental states which are about something or
directed at something as when one has a thought about the house or a perception
of the tree. Although intentional states are sometimes contrasted with phenomenal
states, such as pains and color experiences, it is clear that many conscious states
have both phenomenal and intentional properties, such as visual perceptions. It
should be noted that the relation between intentionality and consciousness is itself
a major ongoing area of dispute with some arguing that genuine intentionality
actually presupposes consciousness in some way (Searle 1992, Siewart 1998,
Horgan and Tienson 2002) while most representationalists insist that intentionality
is prior to consciousness (Gennaro 2012, chapter two).
The general view that we can explain conscious mental states in terms of
representational or intentional states is called representationalism. Although not
automatically reductionist in spirit, most versions of representationalism do
indeed attempt such a reduction. Most representationalists, then, believe that there
is room for a kind of second-step reduction to be filled in later by neuroscience.
The other related motivation for representational theories of consciousness is that

many believe that an account of representation or intentionality can more easily be


given in naturalistic terms, such as causal theories whereby mental states are
understood as representing outer objects in virtue of some reliable causal
connection. The idea, then, is that if consciousness can be explained in
representational terms and representation can be understood in purely physical
terms, then there is the promise of a reductionist and naturalistic theory of
consciousness. Most generally, however, we can say that a representationalist will
typically hold that the phenomenal properties of experience (that is, the qualia
or what it is like of experience or phenomenal character) can be explained in
terms of the experiences representational properties. Alternatively, conscious
mental states have no mental properties other than their representational
properties. Two conscious states with all the same representational properties will
not differ phenomenally. For example, when I look at the blue sky, what it is like
for me to have a conscious experience of the sky is simply identical with my
experiences representation of the blue sky.

3. First Order Representationalism


A First-order representational (FOR) theory of consciousness is a theory that
attempts to explain conscious experience primarily in terms of world-directed (or
first-order) intentional states. Probably the two most cited FOR theories of
consciousness are those of Fred Dretske (1995) and Michael Tye (1995, 2000),
though there are many others as well (e.g., Harman 1990, Kirk 1994, Byrne 2001,
Thau 2002, Droege 2003). Tyes theory is more fully worked out and so will be
the focus of this section. Like other FOR theorists, Tye holds that the
representational content of my conscious experience (that is, what my experience
is about or directed at) is identical with the phenomenal properties of experience.
Aside from reductionistic motivations, Tye and other FOR representationalists
often use the somewhat technical notion of the transparency of experience as
support for their view (Harman 1990). This is an argument based on the
phenomenological first-person observation, which goes back to Moore (1903),
that when one turns ones attention away from, say, the blue sky and onto ones
experience itself, one is still only aware of the blueness of the sky. The experience

itself is not blue; rather, one sees right through ones experience to its
representational properties, and there is nothing else to ones experience over and
above such properties.
Whatever the merits and exact nature of the argument from transparency (see
Kind 2003), it is clear, of course, that not all mental representations are conscious,
so the key question eventually becomes: What exactly distinguishes conscious
from unconscious mental states (or representations)? What makes a mental state a
conscious mental state? Here Tye defends what he calls PANIC theory. The
acronym PANIC stands for poised, abstract, non-conceptual, intentional
content. Without probing into every aspect of PANIC theory, Tye holds that at
least some of the representational content in question is non-conceptual (N),
which is to say that the subject can lack the concept for the properties represented
by the experience in question, such as an experience of a certain shade of red that
one has never seen before. Actually, the exact nature or even existence of nonconceptual content of experience is itself a highly debated and difficult issue in
philosophy of mind (Gunther 2003). Gennaro (2012), for example, defends
conceptualism and connects it in various ways to the higher-order thought theory
of consciousness (see section 4b.ii). Conscious states clearly must also have
intentional content (IC) for any representationalist. Tye also asserts that such
content is abstract (A) and not necessarily about particular concrete objects.
This condition is needed to handle cases of hallucinations, where there are no
concrete objects at all or cases where different objects look phenomenally alike.
Perhaps most important for mental states to be conscious, however, is that such
content must be poised (P), which is an importantly functional notion. The key
idea is that experiences and feelings...stand ready and available to make a direct
impact on beliefs and/or desires. For examplefeeling hungry has an
immediate cognitive effect, namely, the desire to eat.States with nonconceptual
content that are not so poised lack phenomenal character [because]they arise
too early, as it were, in the information processing (Tye 2000: 62).
One objection to Tyes theory is that it does not really address the hard problem of
phenomenal consciousness (see section 3b.i). This is partly because what really
seems to be doing most of the work on Tyes PANIC account is the very
functional sounding poised notion, which is perhaps closer to Blocks access
consciousness (see section 1) and is therefore not necessarily able to explain

phenomenal consciousness (see Kriegel 2002). In short, it is difficult to see just


how Tyes PANIC account might not equally apply to unconscious
representations and thus how it really explains phenomenal consciousness.
Other standard objections to Tyes theory as well as to other FOR accounts
include the concern that it does not cover all kinds of conscious states. Some
conscious states seem not to be about anything, such as pains, anxiety, or afterimages, and so would be non-representational conscious states. If so, then
conscious experience cannot generally be explained in terms of representational
properties (Block 1996). Tye responds that pains, itches, and the like do represent,
in the sense that they represent parts of the body. And after-images,
hallucinations, and the like either misrepresent (which is still a kind of
representation) or the conscious subject still takes them to have representational
properties from the first-person point of view. Indeed, Tye (2000) admirably goes
to great lengths and argues convincingly in response to a whole host of alleged
counter-examples to representationalism. Historically among them are various
hypothetical cases of inverted qualia (see Shoemaker 1982), the mere possibility
of which is sometimes taken as devastating to representationalism. These are
cases where behaviorally indistinguishable individuals have inverted color
perceptions of objects, such as person A visually experiences a lemon the way that
person B experience a ripe tomato with respect to their color, and so on for all
yellow and red objects. Isnt it possible that there are two individuals whose color
experiences are inverted with respect to the objects of perception? (For more on
the importance of color in philosophy, see Hardin 1986.)
A somewhat different twist on the inverted spectrum is famously put forth in
Blocks (1990) Inverted Earth case. On Inverted Earth every object has the
complementary color to the one it has here, but we are asked to imagine that a
person is equipped with color-inverting lenses and then sent to Inverted Earth
completely ignorant of those facts. Since the color inversions cancel out, the
phenomenal experiences remain the same, yet there certainly seem to be different
representational properties of objects involved. The strategy on the part of critics,
in short, is to think of counter-examples (either actual or hypothetical) whereby
there is a difference between the phenomenal properties in experience and the
relevant representational properties in the world. Such objections can, perhaps, be
answered by Tye and others in various ways, but significant debate continues

(Macpherson 2005). Intuitions also dramatically differ as to the very plausibility


and value of such thought experiments. (For more, see Seager 1999, chapters 6
and 7. See also Chalmers 2004 for an excellent discussion of the dizzying array of
possible representationalist positions.)

4. High Order Representationalism


As we have seen, one question that should be answered by any theory of
consciousness is: What makes a mental state a conscious mental state? There is a
long tradition that has attempted to understand consciousness in terms of some
kind of higher-order awareness. For example, John Locke (1689/1975) once said,
consciousness is the perception of what passes in a mans own mind. This
intuition has been revived by a number of philosophers (Rosenthal, 1986, 1993b,
1997, 2000, 2004, 2005; Gennaro 1996a, 2012; Armstrong, 1968, 1981; Lycan,
1996, 2001). In general, the idea is that what makes a mental state conscious is
that it is the object of some kind of higher-order representation (HOR). A mental
state M becomes conscious when there is a HOR of M. A HOR is a metapsychological state, i.e., a mental state directed at another mental state. So, for
example, my desire to write a good encyclopedia entry becomes conscious when
I am (non-inferentially) aware of the desire. Intuitively, it seems that conscious
states, as opposed to unconscious ones, are mental states that I am aware of in
some sense. This is sometimes referred to as the Transitivity Principle. Any
theory which attempts to explain consciousness in terms of higher-order states is
known as higher. It is best initially to use the more neutral term representation
because there are a number of different kinds of higher-order theory, depending
upon how one characterizes the HOR in question. HO theories, thus, attempt to
explain consciousness in mentalistic terms, that is, by reference to such notions as
thoughts and awareness. Conscious mental states arise when two
unconscious mental states are related in a certain specific way; namely, that one
of them (the HOR) is directed at the other (M). HO theorists are united in the
belief that their approach can better explain consciousness than any purely FOR
theory, which has significant difficulty in explaining the difference between
unconscious and conscious mental states.

There are various kinds of HO theory with the most common division between
higher-order thought (HOT) theories and higher-order perception (HOP) theories.
HOT theorists, such as David M. Rosenthal, think it is better to understand the
HOR as a thought of some kind. HOTs are treated as cognitive states involving
some kind of conceptual component. HOP theorists urge that the HOR is a
perceptual or experiential state of some kind (Lycan 1996), which does not
require the kind of conceptual content, invoked by HOT theorists. Partly due to
Kant (1781/1965), HOP theory is sometimes referred to as inner sense theory
as a way of emphasizing its sensory or perceptual aspect. Although HOT and
HOP theorists agree on the need for a HOR theory of consciousness, they do
sometimes argue for the superiority of their respective positions (such as in
Rosenthal 2004, Lycan 2004, and Gennaro 2012). Some philosophers, however,
have argued that the difference between these theories is perhaps not as important
or as clear as some think it is (Gzeldere 1995, Gennaro 1996a, Van Gulick
2000).
A common initial objection to HOR theories is that they are circular and lead to
an infinite regress. It might seem that the HOT theory results in circularity by
defining consciousness in terms of HOTs. It also might seem that an infinite
regress results because a conscious mental state must be accompanied by a HOT,
which, in turn, must be accompanied by another HOT ad infinitum. However, the
standard reply is that when a conscious mental state is a first-order world-directed
state the higher-order thought (HOT) is not itself conscious; otherwise, circularity
and an infinite regress would follow. When the HOT is itself conscious, there is a
yet higher-order (or third-order) thought directed at the second-order state. In this
case, we have introspection, which involves a conscious HOT directed at an inner
mental state. When one introspects, one's attention is directed back into one's
mind. For example, what makes my desire to write a good entry a conscious firstorder desire is that there is a (non-conscious) HOT directed at the desire. In this
case, my conscious focus is directed at the entry and my computer screen, so I am
not consciously aware of having the HOT from the first-person point of view.
When I introspect that desire, however, I then have a conscious HOT
(accompanied by a yet higher, third-order, HOT) directed at the desire itself (see
Rosenthal 1986).
Peter Carruthers (2000) has proposed another possibility within HO theory;

namely, that it is better for various reasons to think of the HOTs as dispositional
states instead of the standard view that the HOTs are actual, though he also
understands his dispositional HOT theory to be a form of HOP theory
(Carruthers 2004). The basic idea is that the conscious status of an experience is
due to its availability to higher-order thought. So conscious experience occurs
when perceptual contents are fed into a special short-term buffer memory store,
whose function is to make those contents available to cause HOTs about
themselves. (Carruthers 2000: 228). Some first-order perceptual contents are
available to a higher-order theory of mind mechanism, which transforms those
representational contents into conscious contents. Thus, no actual HOT occurs.
Instead, according to Carruthers, some perceptual states acquire a dual intentional
content; for example, a conscious experience of red not only has a first-order
content of red, but also has the higher-order content seems red or experience
of red. Carruthers also makes interesting use of so-called consumer semantics
in order to fill out his theory of phenomenal consciousness. The content of a
mental state depends, in part, on the powers of the organisms, which consume
that state, e.g., the kinds of inferences, which the organism can make when it is in
that state. Daniel Dennett (1991) is sometimes credited with an earlier version of
a dispositional account (see Carruthers 2000, chapter ten). Carruthers
dispositional theory is often criticized by those who, among other things, do not
see how the mere disposition toward a mental state can render it conscious
(Rosenthal 2004; see also Gennaro 2004, 2012; for more, see Consciousness,
Higher Order Theories of.)
It is worth briefly noting a few typical objections to HO theories (many of which
can be found in Byrne 1997): First, and perhaps most common, is that various
animals (and even infants) are not likely to have to the conceptual sophistication
required for HOTs, and so that would render animal (and infant) consciousness
very unlikely (Dretske 1995, Seager 2004). Are cats and dogs capable of having
complex higher-order thoughts such as I am in mental state M? Although most
who bring forth this objection are not HO theorists, Peter Carruthers (1989) is
one HO theorist who actually embraces the conclusion that (most) animals do not
have phenomenal consciousness. Gennaro (1993, 1996) has replied to Carruthers
on this point; for example, it is argued that the HOTs need not be as sophisticated
as it might initially appear and there is ample comparative neurophysiological

evidence supporting the conclusion that animals have conscious mental states.
Most HO theorists do not wish to accept the absence of animal or infant
consciousness as a consequence of holding the theory. The debate continues,
however, in Carruthers (2000, 2005, 2008) and Gennaro (2004, 2009, 2012,
chapters seven and eight).
A second objection has been referred to as the problem of the rock (Stubenberg
1998) and the generality problem (Van Gulick 2000, 2004), but it is originally
due to Alvin Goldman (Goldman 1993). When I have a thought about a rock, it is
certainly not true that the rock becomes conscious. So why should I suppose that
a mental state becomes conscious when I think about it? This is puzzling to many
and the objection forces HO theorists to explain just how adding the HO state
changes an unconscious state into a conscious. There have been, however, a
number of responses to this kind of objection (Rosenthal 1997, Lycan, 1996, Van
Gulick 2000, 2004, Gennaro 2005, 2012, chapter four). A common theme is that
there is a principled difference in the objects of the HO states in question. Rocks
and the like are not mental states in the first place, and so HO theorists are first
and foremost trying to explain how a mental state becomes conscious. The
objects of the HO states must be in the head.
Third, the above leads somewhat naturally to an objection related to Chalmers
hard problem (section 3b.i). It might be asked just how exactly any HO theory
really explains the subjective or phenomenal aspect of conscious experience.
How or why does a mental state come to have a first-person qualitative what it is
like aspect by virtue of the presence of a HOR directed at it? It is probably fair
to say that HO theorists have been slow to address this problem, though a number
of overlapping responses have emerged (see also Gennaro 2005, 2012, chapter
four, for more extensive treatment). Some argue that this objection misconstrues
the main and more modest purpose of (at least, their) HO theories. The claim is
that HO theories are theories of consciousness only in the sense that they are
attempting to explain what differentiates conscious from unconscious states, i.e.,
in terms of a higher-order awareness of some kind. A full account of qualitative
properties or sensory qualities (which can themselves be non-conscious) can
be found elsewhere in their work, but is independent of their theory of
consciousness (Rosenthal 1991, Lycan 1996, 2001). Thus, a full explanation of
phenomenal consciousness does require more than a HO theory, but that is no

objection to HO theories as such. Another response is that proponents of the hard


problem unjustly raise the bar as to what would count as a viable explanation of
consciousness so that any such reductivist attempt would inevitably fall short
(Carruthers 2000, Gennaro 2012). Part of the problem, then, is a lack of clarity
about what would even count as an explanation of consciousness (Van Gulick
1995; see also section 3b). Once this is clarified, however, the hard problem can
indeed be solved. Moreover, anyone familiar with the literature knows that there
are significant terminological difficulties in the use of various crucial terms
which sometimes inhibits genuine progress (but see Byrne 2004 for some helpful
clarification).
A fourth important objection to HO approaches is the question of how such
theories can explain cases where the HO state might misrepresent the lower-order
(LO) mental state (Byrne 1997, Neander 1998, Levine 2001, Block 2011). After
all, if we have a representational relation between two states, it seems possible for
misrepresentation or malfunction to occur. If it does, then what explanation can
be offered by the HO theorist? If my LO state registers a red percept and my HO
state registers a thought about something green due, say, to some neural
misfiring, then what happens? It seems that problems loom for any answer given
by a HO theorist and the cause of the problem has to do with the very nature of
the HO theorists belief that there is a representational relation between the LO
and HO states. For example, if the HO theorist takes the option that the resulting
conscious experience is reddish, and then it seems that the HO state plays no role
in determining the qualitative character of the experience. On the other hand, if
the

resulting

experience

is

greenish,

then

the

LO

state

seems

irrelevant. Rosenthal and Weisberg hold that the HO state determines the
qualitative properties even in cases when there is no LO state at all (Rosenthal
2005, 2011, Weisberg 2008, 2011a, 2011b). Gennaro (2012) argues that no
conscious experience results in such cases and wonders, for example, how a sole
(unconscious) HOT can result in a conscious state at all. He argues that there
must be a match, complete or partial, between the LO and HO state in order for a
conscious state to exist in the first place. This important objection forces HO
theorists to be clearer about just how to view the relationship between the LO and
HO states. Debate is ongoing and significant both on varieties of HO theory and
in terms of the above objections (see Gennaro 2004a). There is also

interdisciplinary interest in how various HO theories might be realized in the


brain (Gennaro 2012, chapter nine).

5. Other Cognitive Theories


Aside from the explicitly representational approaches discussed above, there are
also related attempts to explain consciousness in other cognitive terms. The two
most prominent such theories are worth describing here:
Daniel Dennett (1991, 2005) has put forth what he calls the Multiple Drafts
Model (MDM) of consciousness. Although similar in some ways to
representationalism, Dennett is most concerned that materialists avoid falling
prey to what he calls the myth of the Cartesian theater, the notion that there is
some privileged place in the brain where everything comes together to produce
conscious experience. Instead, the MDM holds that all kinds of mental activity
occur in the brain by parallel processes of interpretation, all of which are under
frequent revision. The MDM rejects the idea of some self as an inner observer;
rather, the self is the product or construction of a narrative, which emerges over
time. Dennett is also well known for rejecting the very assumption that there is a
clear line to be drawn between conscious and unconscious mental states in terms
of the problematic notion of qualia. He influentially rejects strong emphasis on
any phenomenological or first-person approach to investigating consciousness,
advocating instead what he calls heterophenomenology according to which we
should follow a more neutral path leading from objective physical science and
its insistence on the third person point of view, to a method of phenomenological
description that can (in principle) do justice to the most private and ineffable
subjective experiences. (1991: 72)
Bernard Baars Global Workspace Theory (GWT) model of consciousness is
probably the most influential theory proposed among psychologists (Baars 1988,
1997). The basic idea and metaphor is that we should think of the entire cognitive
system as built on a blackboard architecture which is a kind of global
workspace. According to GWT, unconscious processes and mental states
compete for the spotlight of attention, from which information is broadcast
globally throughout the system. Consciousness consists in such global

broadcasting and is therefore also, according to Baars, an important functional


and biological adaptation. We might say that consciousness is thus created by a
kind of global access to select bits of information in the brain and nervous
system. Despite Baars frequent use of theater and spotlight metaphors, he
argues that his view does not entail the presence of the material Cartesian theater
that Dennett is so concerned to avoid. It is, in any case, an empirical matter just
how the brain performs the functions he describes, such as detecting mechanisms
of attention.
Objections to these cognitive theories include the charge that they do not really
address the hard problem of consciousness (as described in section 3b.i), but only
the easy problems. Dennett is also often accused of explaining away
consciousness rather than really explaining it. It is also interesting to think about
Baars GWT in light of the Blocks distinction between access and phenomenal
consciousness (see section 1). Does Baars theory only address access
consciousness instead of the more difficult to explain phenomenal consciousness?
(Two other psychological cognitive theories worth noting are the ones proposed
by George Mandler 1975 and Tim Shallice 1988.)

6. Quantum Approaches
Finally, there are those who look deep beneath the neural level to the field of
quantum mechanics, basically the study of sub-atomic particles, to find the key to
unlocking the mysteries of consciousness. The bizarre world of quantum physics
is quite different from the deterministic world of classical physics, and a major
area of research in its own right. Such authors place the locus of consciousness at
a very fundamental physical level. This somewhat radical, though exciting, option
is explored most notably by physicist Roger Penrose (1989, 1994) and
anesthesiologist Stuart Hameroff (1998). The basic idea is that consciousness
arises through quantum effects, which occur in subcellular neural structures
known as microtubules, which are structural proteins in cell walls. There are also
other quantum approaches, which aim to explain the coherence of consciousness
(Marshall and Zohar 1990) or use the holistic nature of quantum mechanics to
explain consciousness (Silberstein 1998, 2001). It is difficult to assess these

somewhat exotic approaches at present. Given the puzzling and often very
counterintuitive nature of quantum physics, it is unclear whether such approaches
will prove genuinely scientifically valuable methods in explaining consciousness.
One concern is simply that these authors are trying to explain one puzzling
phenomenon (consciousness) in terms of another mysterious natural phenomenon
(quantum effects). Thus, the thinking seems to go, perhaps the two are essentially
related somehow and other physicalistic accounts are looking in the wrong place,
such as at the neuro-chemical level. Although many attempts to explain
consciousness often rely of conjecture or speculation, quantum approaches may
indeed lead the field along these lines. Of course, this doesnt mean that some
such theory isnt correct. One exciting aspect of this approach is the resulting
interdisciplinary interest it has generated among physicists and other scientists in
the problem of consciousness.

PANPSYCHISM:

UNIVERSAL

APPROACH

TO

CONSCIOUSNESS
A few philosophers believed that consciousness is something which cannot be
quantified by simply correlating it to something else which is already present with us
as the tools for fundamental approach towards classifying the universe as we know of
today.
Rather they surmise that each and everything in this universe may have some degree
of consciousness. This view is sometimes called panpsychism: pan for all, psych for
mind, every system is conscious, not just humans, dogs, mice, flies, but even Rob
Knight's microbes, elementary particles. Even a photon has some degree of
consciousness. The idea is not that photons are intelligent or thinking. It's not that a
photon is wracked with angst because it's thinking, "Aww, I'm always buzzing around
near the speed of light. I never get to slow down and smell the roses." No, not like
that. But the thought is maybe photons might have some element of raw, subjective
feeling, some primitive precursor to consciousness.
A really exciting thing is in recent years a neuroscientist, Giulio Tononi, has taken
this kind of theory and developed it rigorously with a mathematical theory. He has a

mathematical measure of information integration, which he calls phi, measuring the


amount of information integrated in a system. And he supposes that phi goes along
with consciousness. So in a human brain, incredibly large amount of information
integration, high degree of phi, a whole lot of consciousness. In a mouse, medium
degree of information integration, still pretty significant, pretty serious amount of
consciousness. But as you go down to worms, microbes, particles, the amount of phi
falls off. The amount of information integration falls off, but it's still non-zero. On
Tononi's theory, there's still going to be a non-zero degree of consciousness. In effect,
he's proposing a fundamental law of consciousness: high phi, high consciousness.

Altered States Of Consciousness


It is a condition of the conscious level in which there are significant changes from
the normal waking state in cognitive and behavioral functioning. These changes
include, but are not limited to, the following:
The mental processing of information are shallow and uncritical;
Self-perceptions and perceptions of the environment are distorted;
Self-control and normal inhibitions diminish, and may even disappear.
Its important to remember that the characteristics of an altered state of consciousness
include only what is going on at the conscious level: the characteristics of the
preconscious and unconscious levels are not included when describing an altered
state.
Sleep is an altered state of consciousness that we generally experience every day. We
can describe the characteristics of sleep in terms of the three sets of changes defining
an altered state:
1. We are unable to engage in complex thinking (i.e., we process information poorly).
2. We are not self-aware (we dont perceive ourselves as physical bodies lying in a
bed) nor do we perceive the world around us accurately.
3. We are unable to exhibit self-control (i.e., we cant regulate our behaviors,
emotions, and cognitions), especially with respect to social rules.
Thus, during sleep, the characteristics of the conscious level of awareness have
undergone significant changes from the normal waking state.

In defining what is meant by levels of awareness and by an altered state of


consciousness, we begin to see how important and how difficult it is to define
psychological concepts clearly. The way in which a concept is defined is important
because the definition determines how we think about the concept as well as the
actions we take with respect to it. For example, the way in which medical doctors
define the concept of death will influence at which point they stop trying to
resuscitate a person (e.g., Miller, 2009).
An important difficulty for defining psychological concepts for the purposes of
scientific research is that many of the terms are also used in everyday life. This can
cause confusion among laypeople because researchers often use a term, such as
intelligence, in a way that differs from its use in everyday life. For example, there are
at least two meanings of the concept of unconscious in everyday life:
(1) When we say that Stephanie has repressed memories in her unconscious, we
mean that she is unaware of memories that exist somewhere within her mind. In
this case, the term unconscious refers to a level of awareness containing mental
content that is either very difficult or impossible to attend to.
(2) When we say that Stephanie is unconscious, we mean that she shows no
awareness of the external world around her, such as when she has been given a
general anesthetic during major surgery. In this case, the term unconscious refers
to an altered state of consciousness: the person is aware mostly of internal mental
events and unaware of the external world.
A few altered states of consciousness:
1. DELUSIONS
2. HYPNOSIS
3. SLEEP
4. CONTEMPLATION OF ART (MUSIC, DANCE, PAINTING and DRAMA)
What can cause altered states of consciousness?
1. MEDITATION
2. DREAMS
3. HYPNOSIS
4. SEX
5. PSYCHEDELIC DRUGS
6. BRAIN STIMULATION AND BIOFEEDBACK

DELUSIONS
A delusion is a belief held with strong conviction despite superior evidence to the
contrary. As a pathology, it is distinct from a belief based on false or incomplete
information, confabulation, dogma, illusion, or other effects of perception.
Delusions typically occur in the context of neurological or mental illness, although
they are not tied to any particular disease and have been found to occur in the context
of many pathological states (both physical and mental). However, they are of
particular diagnostic importance in psychotic disorders including schizophrenia,
paraphrenia, manic episodes of bipolar disorder, and psychotic depression.
The psychiatrist and philosopher Karl Jaspers was the first to define the three main
criteria for a belief to be considered delusional in his 1913 book General
Psychopathology. These criteria are:
Certainty (held with absolute conviction)
Incorrigibility (not changeable by compelling counterargument or proof to the
contrary)
Impossibility or falsity of content (implausible, bizarre or patently untrue
Furthermore, when a false belief involves a value judgment, it is only considered as a
delusion if it is so extreme that it cannot be, or never can be proven true. For example:
a man claiming that he flew into the sun and flew back home. This would be
considered a delusion, unless he was speaking figuratively.
Delusions are categorized into four different groups:
Bizarre delusion: A delusion that is very strange and completely implausible; an
example of a bizarre delusion would be that aliens have removed the reporting
person's brain.
Non-bizarre delusion: A delusion that, though false, is at least possible, e.g., the
affected person mistakenly believes that he is under constant police
surveillance.
Mood-congruent delusion: Any delusion with content consistent with either a
depressive or manic state, e.g., a depressed person believes that news anchors
on television highly disapprove of him, or a person in a manic state might
believe she is a powerful deity.
Mood-neutral delusion: A delusion that does not relate to the sufferer's emotional

state; for example, a belief that an extra limb is growing out of the back of
one's head is neutral to either depression or mania.

THEMES OF DELUSIONS
Delusion of control: This is a false belief that another person, group of people, or
external force controls one's general thoughts, feelings, impulses, or behavior.
Cotard delusion: This is a false belief that one does not exist or has died.
Delusional jealousy: A person with this delusion falsely believes that a spouse or
lover is having an affair, with no proof to back up their claim.
Delusion of guilt or sin (or delusion of self-accusation): This is an ungrounded
feeling of remorse or guilt of delusional intensity.
Delusion of mind being read: The false belief that other people can know one's
thoughts.
Delusion of thought insertion: The belief that another thinks through the mind of
the person.
Delusion of reference: The person falsely believes that insignificant remarks,
events, or objects in one's environment have personal meaning or significance.
Erotomania A delusion in which someone falsely believes another person is in
love with him or her.
Grandiose religious delusion: The belief that the affected person is a god, or
chosen to act as a god.
Somatic delusion: A delusion whose content pertains to bodily functioning, bodily
sensations, or physical appearance. Usually the false belief is that the body is
somehow diseased, abnormal, or changed. A specific example of this delusion
is delusional parasitosis: a delusion in which one feels infested with insects,
bacteria, mites, spiders, lice, fleas, worms, or other organisms. Affected
individuals may also report being repeatedly bitten. In some cases,
entomologists are asked to investigate cases of mysterious bites. Sometimes
physical manifestations may occur including skin lesions.
Delusion of poverty: The person strongly believes that he is financially
incapacitated. Although this type of delusion is less common now, it was
particularly widespread in the days before state support.

To define delusional thinking in a specific patient, it is important to consult a local


psychiatrist who can make a thorough examination before diagnosing the problem.
Explaining the causes of delusions continues to be challenging and several theories
have been developed. One is the genetic or biological theory, which states that close
relatives of people with delusional disorder are at increased risk of delusional traits.
Another theory is the dysfunctional cognitive processing, which states that delusions
may arise from distorted ways people have of explaining life to themselves. A third
theory is called motivated or defensive delusions. This one states that some of those
persons who are predisposed might suffer the onset of delusional disorder in those
moments when coping with life and maintaining high self-esteem becomes a
significant challenge. In this case, the person views others as the cause of their
personal difficulties in order to preserve a positive self-view.
This condition is more common among people who have poor hearing or sight. Also,
ongoing stressors have been associated with a higher possibility of developing
delusions. Examples of such stressors are immigration or low socio-economic status.
Researcher, Orrin Devinsky, MD, from the NYU Langone Medical Center, performed
a study that revealed a consistent pattern of injury to the frontal lobe and right
hemisphere of the human brain in patients with certain delusions and brain disorders.
Devinsky explains that the cognitive deficits caused by those injuries to the right
hemisphere, results in the over compensation by the left hemisphere of the brain for
the injury, which causes delusions.
A study carried out at The Warwick Medical School at the University of Warwick,
indicated that children who suffered bullying are more likely to develop psychotic
symptoms in early adolescence. The background facts demonstrated that
hallucinations and delusions are common in childhood as well as in adulthood and
that children who experience such symptoms are more prone to develop psychosis
later in life. Furthermore, the study demonstrated that two for children who suffered
bullying at age eight or ten multiplied the risk of psychotic symptoms, including
delusions. The authors remark that bullying can cause chronic stress that may have an
effect on a genetic predisposition to schizophrenia and result in setting off the
symptoms.

The following can indicate a delusion:


The patient expresses an idea or belief with unusual persistence or force.
That idea appears to have an undue influence on the patient's life, and the way of
life is often altered to an inexplicable extent.
Despite his/her profound conviction, there is often a quality of secretiveness or
suspicion when the patient is questioned about it.
The individual tends to be humorless and oversensitive, especially about the belief.
There is a quality of centrality: no matter how unlikely it is that these strange things
are happening to him, the patient accepts them relatively unquestioningly.
An attempt to contradict the belief is likely to arouse an inappropriately strong
emotional reaction, often with irritability and hostility.
The belief is, at the least, unlikely, and out of keeping with the patient's social,
cultural and religious background.
The patient is emotionally over-invested in the idea and it overwhelms other
elements of their psyche.
The delusion, if acted out, often leads to behaviors which are abnormal and/or out
of character, although perhaps understandable in the light of the delusional
beliefs.
Individuals who know the patient observe that the belief and behavior are
uncharacteristic and alien.
The following features are found:
It is a primary disorder.
It is a stable disorder characterized by the presence of delusions to which the patient
clings with extraordinary tenacity.
The illness is chronic and frequently lifelong.
The delusions are logically constructed and internally consistent.
The delusions do not interfere with general logical reasoning (although within the
delusional system the logic is perverted) and there is usually no general
disturbance of behavior. If disturbed behavior does occur, it is directly related
to the delusional beliefs.
The individual experiences a heightened sense of self-reference. Events, which, to
others, are non-significant, are of enormous significance to him or her, and the
atmosphere surrounding the delusions is highly charged.

S-ar putea să vă placă și