Sunteți pe pagina 1din 8

Journal of Advanced Nursing, 1998, 27, 12421249

The qualitative-quantitative debate: moving from


positivism and confrontation to post-positivism
and reconciliation
Alexander M. Clark BA(Hons) RN
Doctoral Research Student, Department of Nursing and Community Health, Glasgow
Caledonian University, City Campus, Cowcaddens Road, Glasgow G4 0BA, Scotland

Accepted for publication 8 June 1997

CLARK A.M. (1998) Journal of Advanced Nursing 27, 12421249


The qualitative-quantitative debate: moving from positivism and confrontation
to post-positivism and reconciliation
Critiques of logical positivism form the foundation for a significant number of
nursing research papers, with the philosophy being inappropriately deemed
synonymous with empirical method. Frequently, proposing an alternative
method to those identified with the quantitative paradigm, these critiques are
based on a poor foundation. This paper highlights an alternative philosophy to
positivism which can also underpin empirical inquiry, that of post-positivism.
Post-positivism is contrasted with positivism, which is presented as an
outmoded and rejected philosophy which should cease to significantly shape
inquiry. Though some acknowledgement of post-positivism has occurred in the
nursing literature, this has yet to permeate into mainstream nursing research.
Many still base their arguments on a positivistic view of science. Through
achievement of a better understanding of post-positivism and greater focus on
explicating the philosophical assumptions underpinning all research methods,
the distinctions that have long been perceived to exist between qualitative and
quantitative methodologies can be confined to the past. Rather methods will be
selected solely on the nature of research questions.

Keywords: research, paradigms, philosophy, methodology, science

deemed here to be the philosophical. In line with defi-


TRENDS IN NURSING RESEARCH:
nitions of the discipline of philosophy, the philosophical
PHILOSOPHIES, PARADIGMS AND
level of a research method focuses on its assumptions relat-
METHODS
ing to the most general features of the world, encompassing
To argue any proposed position effectively, it is imperative aspects such as the mind, matter, reason and proofs for
that accuracy, clarity and congruence are present regarding knowledge (Blackburn 1994). As will be outlined, different
terms used. Though some concepts are discussed and used research methods may share or greatly differ in their
extensively to frame arguments (the concept of paradigms philosophical conceptualizations of truth.
being a prime example) this need not warrant that the Consequently, when using a specific research method,
author whole heartedly condones their use. consciously or otherwise, assumptions about philosophi-
cal aspects are made. For example, if undertaking a
Heideggerian phenomenological study, the philosophy
Philosophical level of research methods
which underpins this research method dictates that certain
Research methods can be described, examined and catego- perspectives are adopted regarding what it is to be a
rized at different levels. The most fundamental level is person. Reality is deemed to be interpretive with inquiry

1242 1998 Blackwell Science Ltd


The qualitative-quantitative debate

centred around Being. Using the concept of Being-in-the- et al. 1986, Cull Wilby & Pepin 1987, Cushing 1994, Carr
world, Heidegger emphasizes that all human existence is 1994). Historically, nursing authors tend instead to use the
shaped by and cannot be disassociated from past experi- concept to categorise research methods into one of two
ences, culture, history and even future intentions (Walters paradigms, the qualitative or the quantitative (Ford-Gilboe
1994, Koch 1995). et al. 1995, Carr 1994, Cushing 1994, Rolfe 1994, Dzurec
Such a stance has extensive implications regarding truth & Abraham 1993, Gortner & Schultz 1988, Moccia 1988,
alone. Because it is acknowledged that humans cannot be Leininger 1985).
separated from their own Being, the possibility of
researcher objectively in inquiry is not supported. This
Questioning the qualitative-quantitative distinction
stance acknowledges the researchers influence in shaping
all stages of their inquiry, with no party, such as an expert Though some distinction between methods is well placed,
analyst or even a participant, being able to verify research- as will be shown, it is being acknowledged that philo-
ers interpretive findings as being objectively true to the sophically the qualitative and quantitative paradigms are
original experience (Sandelowski 1993). Participants not as diverse or mutually incompatible as is often con-
narratives are so prone to revision and reinterpretation veyed. Staunch identification of methods with particular
over time by the participant themselves, that no bench- paradigms may not be as accurate, or even as useful, an
mark can exist from which to evaluate the truthfulness endeavour as past trends would indicate. This tendency
of interpretations (Boykin & Schoenhofer 1991). may lead to over-simplification of methods in relation to
The concept of objective truth is not appropriate to this paradigms, or worse, confusion over the philosophies and
research method, because it goes against the revisionist assumptions that underpin particular methods.
nature of experience. This absolute rejection of objec- Though empiricism has been recognized as a philosophy
tivity of truth in relation to inquiry is in contrast to that in itself (Blackburn 1994), it is supported here that it is best
ascribed to by other methods, such as experimentalists. understood as a quantitative paradigm that can be shaped
by more than one philosophy. The remainder of this paper
highlights disagreement which exists regarding the philos-
Paradigm level of research methods
ophy deemed to underpin empiricism. These disputes
The philosophical aspects underpinning methods facili- appear to originate from regarding all empirical methods as
tate the categorization of research methods into paradigms. being shaped by a single philosophy, that of positivism.
The concept of paradigm was proposed initially by After positivism is outlined, and its presence and influ-
Thomas Kuhn in 1962 (Kuhn 1970). The concept is appro- ence in nursing literature examined, it is proposed that
priately applied when a high level of professional consen- post-positivistic philosophy has replaced positivism as
sus is recognized to exist within particular communities that which underpins most researchers empirical method.
of scientists, regarding aspects of philosophical beliefs, Examination of post-positivistic philosophy and its influ-
theories, standards for research and exemplary findings ence in nursing literature is undertaken, with reasons for
(Kuhn 1970, Poythress 1988). That the formation of para- its lack of acknowledgement speculated on. These reasons
digms is related to philosophical assumptions is emphas- are then formulated into guidance for researchers using
ized by Kuhn (1970 pp. 45) in his comment that: any method(s). Overall, it is noted that the strict categoriz-
ing of methods into paradigms, can cause simplification
Effective research scarcely begins before a scientific community
and inaccuracy, as such this is a practice which should be
thinks it has acquired firm answers to questions like the following:
questioned.
What are the fundamental entities of which the universe is com-
posed? How do these interact with each other and with the senses?
What questions may be legitimately asked about such entities and THE NATURE OF POSITIVISM:
what techniques employed in seeking solutions? DETACHMENT AND CERTAINTY
Here Kuhn highlights that in the carrying out of research The historical evolution and nature of the philosophy of
endeavour, philosophical positions are adopted about the logical positivism are comprehensively documented by
nature of matter, what can be known, and how can this Guba & Lincoln (1994), Holton (1993) and Feigl (1969) who
knowledge be attained. Within paradigms, in addition to highlight how the philosophy was expressed in research
philosophical aspects, it is likely that consensus will also method. Truth in positivist inquiry is achieved through
exist (where applicable to methods) regarding funda- the verification and replication of observable findings con-
mental equations, their associated theories and the basic cerning directly perceivable entities or processes (Wolfer
concepts forming these theories (Kegley 1995). 1993, Poole & Jones 1996). The perspective assumes the
The concept of paradigm is more frequently presented existence of an objective reality, i.e. one that is indepen-
by nursing authors in isolation from other aspects of dent of the knower (Holton 1993) which can be accurately
Kuhns cyclical theory of scientific development (Allen perceived through the human senses.

1998 Blackwell Science Ltd, Journal of Advanced Nursing, 27, 12421249 1243
A.M. Clark

Jones 1996). This cumulative, universal, and law-centred


Correspondence theory of truth
view of science has been challenged by scientific theorists
Relatedly, positivism adopts a correspondence view of (Popper 1959, Kuhn 1970, Ziman 1991, Dolby 1996) and
truth, with true statements taken to correspond with the philosophers, notably David Hume (Hume 1975), known
knowable facts of reality. Truth is therefore dependent not collectively as inductive skeptics (Landesman 1997).
on belief but the correspondence of belief to facts present These challenges focused on the limitations which had to
in external reality. Fundamental to the stance is a rejection be attached to universally generalizing from a limited
of metaphysical speculations such as those concerning number of cases, highlighting particularly the situational
apriori and transcendental knowledge (Feigl 1969). and perceptual factors influencing scientists work.
Phenomena such as meanings and experiences are there- Kuhn (1970), taking a more historical perspective, high-
fore outwith the scope of positivism (Greene 1979, lights previous scientific explanations taken to be indubit-
Dzurec 1989). ably true. Analysing some subsequently shown to be false
Progress in scientific development, as outlined by Kuhn (Aristotelian dynamics, phlogistic chemistry and caloric
(1970), pointed to the inevitability of accepting the influ- thermodynamics), Kuhn proposes that those who study
ence of unobservable entities such as molecules, atoms these views of nature will conclude that the methods used
and electrons. This caused the positivists to revise their were no less scientific or idiosyncratic than those used in
original denial of unobservables to a modified form of current times. If these discredited theories are to be
instrumentalism. This stance deemed unobservable con- called myths:
cepts to be useful for calculation and understanding
... then myths can be produced by the same sorts of methods and
related to the control and prediction of observable phen-
held for the same sorts of reasons that now lead to scientific
omena. However, irrespective of their pragmatic use, unob-
knowledge. If on the other hand they are called science, then
servables were still denied any form of real existence.
science has included bodies of belief quite incompatible with the
This antirealist stance regarding theoretical entities,
ones we hold today.
drew a fundamental distinction between observable and
Kuhn (1970 p. 2)
theoretical aspects. Though useful for control and predic-
tion, that which could not be seen could not make claims Kuhn thus illustrates the historical transitoriness that
to existence. Consequently, though theories involving supposedly universally true findings can possess. We are
unobservable phenomena could be used to generate pre- never in a position to prove the universality of findings,
dictions relating to reality, they could not explain occur- as Kuhn highlights, history would warn against making
rences because they were not held to exist (Gortner & such a claim.
Schultz 1988, Blackburn 1994, Poole & Jones 1996). Under
this view, theories had limited explanatory power.
Positivism and nursing inquiry
An additional facet of positivist inquiry which has gen-
erated much criticism is its adherence to an atheoretical, It is well recognized that in its endeavours to become estab-
abiased view of the researchers involvement in the lished in the first half of the 20th century, nursing research
research process. Positivist philosophers acknowledged was dominated by the medical model and its associated
and valued rationality and intellectualism but these were positivist philosophy (Cull-Wilby & Pepin 1987, Nagle &
tempered with great focus on objectivity, globalism, Mitchell 1991, Doering 1992, Cushing 1994). A consider-
anti-individualism, un-self-conscious and non-self- able amount of agreement is apparent amongst the many
reflectiveness in inquiry (Holton 1993). Dualism (or different descriptions of the positivist view. This research
Cartesianism) and the associated capability of separating was quantitative and operated with what was known as
biases of the mind from the world (and thus the researcher the positivistic received view (Carter 1985, Guba 1990,
from all stages of the research process) were therefore sup- Doering 1992, Guba & Lincoln 1994).
ported (Guba 1990, Holton 1993). Only if individuals When made explicit, as demonstrated by Poole & Jones
could achieve this total detachment could inquiry be bias (1996), the philosophical assumptions of positivism can
free and truly objective. Consequently, researchers were be readily questioned by historical counterexample (Kuhn
deemed to be neutral observers who indubitably report- 1970, Guba 1990) and through the application of reason.
ed their observations free from any cultural, social or Though positivism has been noted to influence a number
experiential based biases (Phillips 1990). of early nursing theorists work, notably Orem and Roy
(Nagle & Mitchell 1991), as will be outlined, positivistic
Laws conceptions of truth and inquiry have philosophically
In creating and building knowledge, positivist inquiry been widely dismissed as incompatible with nursing
focused on discovering infallible and universal laws research.
through the cumulative piecing together of bits of knowl- Barnum (1994) and Rolfe (1994) report the tendency in
edge (Bronowski 1956, Dzurec 1989, Holton 1993, Poole & nursing literature of dichotomizing research endeavours

1244 1998 Blackwell Science Ltd, Journal of Advanced Nursing, 27, 12421249
The qualitative-quantitative debate

into either quantitative or qualitative paradigms, as mutu- (Kuhn 1970) and Charles Hanson (Hanson 1958).
ally exclusive polar opposites, encompassing a differing Fundamentally, a different conceptualization of truth was
view of reality and truth. With significant consistency, proposed by the post-positivists. Like positivism, meta-
nursing literature states that empirical inquiry is aligned physical considerations were still deemed to be outwith
solely with a positivist philosophy (Ray 1985, Leininger the sphere of science (Bronowski 1956). However, in con-
1985, Allen et al. 1986, Cull-Wilby & Pepin 1987, Moccia trast, a realist perspective of science was advocated, with
1988, Dzurec 1989, Nagle & Mitchell 1991, Doering 1992, unobservables deemed to have existence and the capability
Carr 1994, Darbyshire 1994, Streubert 1995, Playle 1995, of explaining the functioning of observable phenomena
Hicks & Hennessy 1997). (Bronowski 1956, Schumacher & Gortner 1992).
Such labelling is frequently used to provide contrast to Theoretical explanations therefore had greater predictive
an authors subsequent proposal of an alternative philos- value. Like the positivists, science was still deemed to
ophy or method (Schumacher & Gortner 1992) as demon- require precision, logical reasoning and attention to evi-
strated by Bailey (1997), Horsfall (1995), Darbyshire dence but was not confined to that which could be directly
(1994), Rolfe (1994), Mason (1993), Dzurec & Abraham perceived. Evidence could be in inferable forms such as
(1993), Moccia (1988), Allen et al. (1986) and Tinkle & the self-reports inherent in interviews or questionnaires
Beaton (1983) bar many. These authors critiques of positiv- (Bronowski 1956). As such, distinction drawn between
ism highlight the plain inadequacies to nursing of an empirical methods and the qualitative paradigm, as under-
approach which denies the importance of subjective, taken by Tesch (1990), cannot be based on the nature of
social, spiritual and interpretative aspects of the person, data (i.e. non-numerical or numerical).
their relationships and psychosomatics. Positivism Post-positive research need not exclude either qualitat-
employs an overly reductionist view of the person in its ive (i.e. non-numerical) data or truths found outside
quest for universal mechanistic rules which are culturally quantitative method; acceptance of this is crucial to
independent. This view of human existence is incongruent rejecting the strict dichotomy often drawn between the
with that focused on by nursing. qualitative and quantitative paradigms. This notion was
Crucially, though these criticisms are in themselves central to the work of scientist Jacob Bronowski
valid, they need not apply to all empiricist work because (Bronowski 1956, p. 31) who spoke of art and science as
such work need not evolve only around a positivist philos- having the same overall aim of highlighting unity in
ophy. As Norbeck (1987) and Barnum (1994) allude to, diversity:
there exists no intrinsic link between logical positivism
The scientist or the artist takes two facts or experiences which
and empiricism. To make such a connection is to assume
are separate; he finds in them a likeness which had not been seen
that empiricism can only operate with the philosophical
before; and he creates a unity by showing the likeness.
assumptions of positivism. Rather, empiricism can also
operate under a post-positivistic philosophy, which his- Though Bronowski further argues that scientific and
torically superseded positivism, evolving in response to artistic exploration must remain distinctive, nevertheless
its increasingly obvious limitations. it remains that the truths inherent within each, though
essentially different in nature, are valid. Taking a modified
position to Bronowski (1956), Sandelowski (1993) and
BEYOND THE LIMITATIONS OF
Gadamer (1989) note that many parallels exist between
POSITIVISM TO POST-POSITIVISM
truths based in artistic experience and those discovered in
The philosophy of post-positivism is increasingly being many traditionally qualitative based hermeneutic enquir-
noted as that which underpins contemporary empirical ies. Post-positivism does not reject the truths present in
research activity (Phillips 1990, Schumacher & Gortner methodologies focusing on the experiences or meanings of
1992, Dzurec & Abraham 1993, Ford-Gilboe et al. 1995). individuals, as encompassed by the phenomenological,
This has severe implications for those mentioned who grounded theory and other interpretive methodologies.
equate all empirical methods with a positivistic philos-
ophy. Given that empirical methods may not be under-
Role of the researcher
pinned with positivistic views, the fundamental
justifications authors so frequently provide for their Importantly, under post-positivistic philosophy, the
alternative perspectives can be noted to be weak. As dem- researcher and his or her perceptions were not seen as
onstrated by Poole & Jones (1996), even those practising being wholly detached from inquiry. Science was certainly
and advocating empirical methods, are heavily critical of not seen as personal opinion or private experience, but
positivistic philosophy. personal processes and involvement were acknowledged
The main influences in promoting post-positivist philo- as being characteristic of human inquiry. A distinction was
sophies were the works of Karl Popper (Popper 1959), therefore drawn between retinal images and similar raw
Jacob Bronowski (Bronowski 1950, 1956), Thomas Kuhn data of sensory experience and the cognitive processes of

1998 Blackwell Science Ltd, Journal of Advanced Nursing, 27, 12421249 1245
A.M. Clark

perception and their experiential, cultural and knowledge most likely to know the probability of a finding gaining
related biases (Hanson 1958, Norbeck 1987, Schumacher closer approximation to truth. As is demonstrated by
& Gortner 1992, Dzurec & Abraham 1993, Poole & Jones prominent scientific theorists (Kuhn 1970, Ziman 1991,
1996). The strict adherence to dualism inherent in the pos- Dolby 1996) entire movements of science could, in time,
itivist approach cannot apply in post-positivist philos- be shown to be far less close to truth than their proponents
ophy. It is acknowledged that the researching human, with originally believed.
or without instruments, must shape the research process.
Necessity existed not only in recognizing the inter-
Implications of post-positivistic philosophy for
pretive element of all human undertaken research inquiry,
nursing research
but also the theory ladeness of scientific instruments. Use
of scientific instruments, such as electron microscopes and As highlighted, criticisms of empiricism are still based on
telescopes, involve not only the idiosyncrasies of human a positivistic view of empirical method with little
perception but have also beneath their own workings many acknowledgement of even the possibility of post-
sets of previously developed theories pertaining to physics positivistic philosophies shaping nursing research.
and chemistry. All of these theories are also prone to Explanation regarding many authors lack of acknowledge-
uncertainty and the possibility of further change ment of the post-positivism may point to either a resistance
(Schumacher & Gortner 1992). to its tenets or an unawareness of its existence in relation
The contextually bound nature of research findings, con- to positivism.
sequential in the acknowledgement of researcher and The former explanation, given the extreme and readily
theoretical biases, warrants that knowledge deemed to be refutable nature of positivism, as demonstrated by Poole
truthful under post-positivistic inquiry is not universally & Jones (1996) and Guba (1990), may be a tempting one
generalizable to all cases and all situations. Rather, find- for researchers to indulge in, especially those proposing a
ings are viewed as contextually related and could be radically alternative view. But to argue against a perspec-
inductively applied with reference to probability of the tive which ... few, if any philosophers these days sub-
similar case holding elsewhere. This stance is in contrast scribe to... (Phillips 1990 p. 39) is unlikely to add great
to the positivists who advocated immutable law. As weight to the strength of the proposed alternative, given
Schumacher & Gortner (1992 p. 6) advocate, even in the positivism is so vulnerable to straightforward criticism. As
physics, true laws are most infrequent with relationships Silverman (1993 p. 21) adds:
being proposed on an all things being equal basis. As
with all research, this seldom occurs in the natural In the 1970s, it was common to criticise what was called positiv-
environment. ism... it became increasingly clear that positivists were made of
Relatedly, post-positivistic inquiry had a less ambitious straw since very few researchers could be found who equated the
aim attached to inquiry than the positivists, that of gaining social and natural worlds or believed that research was properly
a greater approximation of truth. This stance also encom- theory-free.
passed an acknowledgement of the inevitability of
researcher biases and the complications of claims to uni- The latter explanation related to awareness, however,
versal knowledge (Bronowski 1956, Schumacher & Gortner would seem more plausible given that in the main, nursing
1992, Poole & Jones 1996). research studies in both traditional qualitative and quanti-
tative camps have been consistently noted to seldom
articulate or debate their philosophical underpinnings
Coherence view of truth
(Bowers 1992, Wolfer 1993, Walters 1994, Ray 1994, Playle
Unlike the positivists who claimed to be able to accurately 1995, Horsfall 1995, Kikuchi et al. 1996). This tendency
know reality and discover universal truths under the corre- has also been noted in wider scientific research (Dolby
spondence model, recognizing the futility of gaining 1996, Harman 1996). Superficially, it may therefore appear
definitive knowledge of reality (i.e. that which is certain) that those utilizing empirical methods ascribe to a positiv-
leads post-positivists away from a positivist conception of istic philosophy. Alternatively, post-positivistic assump-
truth. That some guide to what could be trusted as true tions underpinning methods and their significance and
was required amongst this uncertainty, can explain the implications for findings may remain implicit. Either way,
adoption of a coherence view of truth in which claims to identifying empirical studies with positivist or post-
knowledge were judged in the context of rational, positivist philosophies could then not be readily
informed communal judgements (Bronowski 1956, undertaken.
Norbeck 1987, Gortner & Schultz 1988, Ziman 1991, Regarding the level of understanding reflected in the
Schumacher & Gortner 1992, Dolby 1996). nursing literature about science, Paley comments that con-
Little indication could exist that was more trustworthy temporary views of science are absent in current nursing
than the informed, albeit subjective, evaluations of those theory, describing this as stunning, he adds that:

1246 1998 Blackwell Science Ltd, Journal of Advanced Nursing, 27, 12421249
The qualitative-quantitative debate

With few exceptions, the debate seems to be stuck in a mid- solely on the weaknesses of positivist philosophy. Though
century time-warp. published over a significant time, the view of empiricism
(Paley 1996 p. 670) (and research methods as a whole) expressed by these
authors remains to be explicitly acknowledged, encom-
Given the wealth of connections drawn between the out- passed, or even implicitly indicated in significant amounts
dated philosophy of positivism and empiricism, and the of nursing research. This is the case for those contributing
lack of acknowledgement of post-positivism, Paleys pos- to both the recognized qualitative or quantitative
ition is hard to deny. That this accusation holds may be literature.
due to the general lack of attention described above, Despite the openness of post-positivism to other means
regarding philosophical aspects of research methods. of inquiry, it may be argued that post-positivism retains
some of the weaknesses of positivism that made it inappro-
priate for nursing inquiry. The approach still focuses on
Increasing the philosophical focus
rendering complex aspects of human beings researchable,
This general lack of attention toward the explication of seeking causation, prediction and explanation in the pat-
philosophical foundations has significant implications for terns and regularities of life (Bronowski 1956, Guba 1990).
all research methods. With philosophical assumptions However, as is frequently agreed upon (Moody 1990,
remaining implicit, qualitative and quantitative research Wolfer 1993, Dreher 1994, Powers & Knapp 1995, Morse &
endeavours are prone to be presented in an overly simpli- Field 1996, Polit & Hungler 1997), research questions
fied and demarcated form. Consequently being treated as should be answered with appropriate research methods.
homogenous groups, free from diversity and in opposition Particular methods cannot answer every type of problem
to each other. This trend was also noted by Atkinson pertaining to physical, spiritual, psychological and experi-
(1995). ential realms (Wolfer 1993, Rolfe 1994, Ford-Gilboe et al.
When examined in detail, the qualitative paradigm alone 1995).
encompasses a diversity of methods that can vary in philo- Methods belonging to the traditional qualitative para-
sophical assumptions about reality, aims and valid data digm therefore retain great use in answering many vital
collection methods and sources (Sandelowski 1986, questions which quantitative methods cannot. It remains
Thorne 1991, Atkinson 1995). That the philosophical vital that method selection is based not on a limited view
issues beneath these aspects are often ignored, of science, but on an accurate understanding of all forms
accompanied by the tendency for listing methods under of inquiry, with justifications being based on contemporary
paradigms, contributes to the distinction perceived to be understandings about how best to answer research
between qualitative and quantitative paradigms. questions.
Whereas the failings of positivism may form justification
for alternative methods, these need not be those tradition-
CONCLUSION
ally equated with the qualitative paradigm. Post-
positivism was itself a reaction to the limitations of posi- Authors frequently use the inadequacies of positivism as
tivism. Those solely associating positivism with empiri- a foundation for their alternative views. It is vital that
cism, negating the existence of post-positivism, would authors have an accurate understanding of the positivist
have empiricists reject the value of these methodologies. perspective. To equate positivism with all empirical
The triangulation of qualitative and quantitative methods method is erroneous, confusing a general philosophy with
in the same research studies indicates a tacit acceptance a particular method. Though empirical methods can be
of post-positivistic philosophy, with such researchers shaped by positivistic philosophy, it is increasingly being
recognizing the diversity of truths reachable through dif- recognized that empirical work can alternatively be based
ferent forms of inquiry, but valuing each for the contri- on a post-positivistic philosophy which avoids many of
bution they can make to knowledge development and the inadequacies correctly associated with the positivist
nursing practice. school.
Authors proposing alternatives to empirical inquiry
must acknowledge the advances post-positivism has
ACKNOWLEDGING POST-POSITIVISM IN
brought to empirical method and base their counter argu-
NURSING RESEARCH
ments on an appropriate and contemporary understanding
Acknowledgement of post-positivism has formed the of inquiry. Health researchers should become familiar with
rationale for a number of papers (Watson 1981, Norbeck the assumptions underpinning post-positivism, basing
1987, Schumacher & Gortner 1992, Dzurec & Abraham their justifications for both quantitative and qualitative
1993, Weiss 1995, Poole & Jones 1996). These have articu- research methods around this knowledge.
lated both the need to retain and value all methods and Admittedly, many authors on both sides of the qualitat-
warned against dismissing the empirical approach based ive-quantitative debate have compounded inappropriate

1998 Blackwell Science Ltd, Journal of Advanced Nursing, 27, 12421249 1247
A.M. Clark

conceptualizations by failing to effectively highlight the Carr L.T. (1994) The strengths and weaknesses of quantitative and
philosophical assumptions beneath their methods. qualitative research: what method for nursing? Journal of
Quantitative researchers must recognize that the reassur- Advanced Nursing 20, 716721.
ance of common sense and scientific convention does not Carter M. (1985) The philosophical dimensions of qualitative
nursing science research. In Qualitative Research Methods in
warrant that their methods are atheoretical and without
Nursing (Leininger M. ed.), Grune and Stratton, Orlando,
philosophical assumptions or implications. Should philo-
pp. 2732.
sophical assumptions and their associated implications be Cull-Wilby B.L. & Pepin J.I. (1987) Towards a coexistence of para-
highlighted in the reporting of findings, it may be more digms in nursing knowledge development. Journal of Advanced
clear to what degree current research in nursing and medi- Nursing 12, 515521.
cine continues to operate with positivist views. Where Cushing A. (1994) Historical and epistemological perspectives on
research is noted or strongly inferred to operate with a research and nursing. Journal of Advanced Nursing 20,
positivist philosophy, this should be identified as a weak- 406411.
ness. Rather, empirical researchers should encompass con- Darbyshire P. (1994) Skilled expert practice: is it all in the mind?
temporary understanding of science in their methods, A response to Englishs critique of Benners novice to expert
shaping their design, findings and generalizing model. Journal of Advanced Nursing 19, 755761.
Doering L. (1992) Power and knowledge in nursing: a feminist
accordingly.
poststructualist view. Advances in Nursing Science 14(4),
Operating under a post-positivist philosophy, the
2433.
empirical methods of quantitative research and those of Dolby R.G.A. (1996) Uncertain Knowledge. Cambridge University
the qualitative approaches are not as diametrically Press, London.
opposed as is frequently conveyed. Truths in these per- Dreher M. (1994) Qualitative research methods from the
spectives must be reciprocally recognized; to fail to do so reviewers perspective. In Critical Issues in Qualitative
would be to deny both that progress has been made Research Methods (Morse J.M. ed.), Sage, London, pp. 281297.
through empirical endeavour since the 17th century or that Dzurec L.C. (1989) The necessity for and evolution of multiple
art, human experiences, and human meanings are devoid paradigms for nursing research: a poststructualist perspective.
from any forms of truth. Advances in Nursing Science 11(4), 6977.
Dzurec L. & Abraham I. (1993) The nature of inquiry: linking
quantitative and qualitative research. Advances in Nursing
Acknowledgements Science 16(1), 7379.
Feigl H. (1969) The origin and spirit of logical positivism. In The
My thanks go to Dr Valerie Fleming, Dr Debbie Tolson, Legacy of Logical Positivism (Achinstein P. & Baker S.F. eds),
Susan Kerr and Anna ONeill, all at the Department of John Hopkins Press, Baltimore, pp. 324.
Nursing and Community Health, Glasgow Caledonian Ford-Gilboe M., Campbell J. & Berman H. (1995) Stories and num-
University, for their comments regarding this paper. bers: coexistence without compromise. Advances in Nursing
Science 18(1), 1426.
Gadamer H. (1989) Truth and Method 2nd edn rev. Sheed and
Ward, London.
References
Gortner S.R. & Schultz P.R. (1988) Approaches to nursing science
Allen D., Benner P. & Diekelmann N.L. (1986) Three paradigms methods. Image: Journal of Nursing Scholarship 20(1), 2224.
for nursing research: methodological implications. In Nursing Greene J. (1979) Science, nursing and nursing science: a concep-
Research Methodology: Issues and Implementation (Chinn P.L. tual analysis. Advances in Nursing Science 2(1), 5764.
ed.), Rockville, Aspen, pp. 2338. Guba E. (1990). The alternative paradigm dialogue. In The
Atkinson P. (1995) Some perils of paradigms. Qualitative Health Paradigm Dialog (Guba E. ed.), Sage, London, pp. 1730.
Research 5(1), 117124. Guba E.G. & Lincoln Y.S. (1994) Competing paradigms in qualitat-
Bailey P. (1997) Finding your way around qualitative methods in ive research. In Handbook of Qualitative Research (Denzin N.K.
nursing research. Journal of Advanced Nursing 25, 1822. & Lincoln Y.S. eds), Sage, London, pp. 105117.
Barnum B.J.S. (1994) Nursing Theory: Analysis, Application, Hanson N. (1958) Patterns of Discovery, Cambridge University
Evaluation. J.B. Lippincott, Philadelphia. Press, Cambridge.
Blackburn S. (1994) Dictionary of Philosophy. Oxford University Harman W.W. (1996) The shortcomings of Western Science.
Press, Oxford. Qualitative Inquiry 2(1), 3038.
Bowers L. (1992) Ethnomethodology: an approach to nursing Hicks C. & Hennessy D. (1997) Mixed messages in nursing
research. International Journal of Nursing Studies 29(1), 5967. research: their contribution to the persisting hiatus between evi-
Boykin A. & Schoenhofer S.O. (1991) Story as link between nurs- dence and practice. Journal of Advanced Nursing 25, 596601.
ing, practice, ontology, epistemology. Image: Journal of Nursing Holton G. (1993) Science and Anti-Science. Harvard University
Scholarship 23(4), 245248. Press, London.
Bronowski J. (1950) The Common Sense of Science. Pelican, Horsfall J. (1995) Madness in our methods: nursing research,
London. scientific epistemology. Nursing Inquiry 2, 29.
Bronowski J. (1956) Science and Human Values. Penguin, Hume D. (1975) Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding
London. Oxford, Clarendon.

1248 1998 Blackwell Science Ltd, Journal of Advanced Nursing, 27, 12421249
The qualitative-quantitative debate

Kegley J. (1995) Science as tradition and tradition shattering. In Powers B.A. & Knapp T.R. (1995) A Dictionary of Nursing Theory
In Search of Nursing Science, (Omery A., Kasper C. & Page G. and Research 2nd edn. Sage, London.
eds), Sage, London, pp. 4357. Poythress V.S. (1988) Science and Hermeneutics. Apollos,
Kikuchi J.F., Simmons H. & Romyn D. (1996) Prologue: Speaking Leicester.
of Truth. In Truth in Nursing Inquiry (Kikuchi J.F., Simmons H. Ray M. (1985) A philosophical method to study nursing phen-
& Romyn D. eds), Sage, Newbury Park, California, pp. viiixii. omena. In Qualitative Research Methods in Nursing,
Koch T. (1995) Interpretive approaches in nursing research: the (Leininger M. ed.), Grunne and Stratton, Orlando, pp. 8192.
influence of Husserl and Heidegger. Journal of Advanced Ray M. (1994) The richness of phenomenology: philosophic, the-
Nursing 21, 827836. oretic and methodologic concerns. In Critical Issues in
Kuhn T. (1970) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions 2nd edn. Qualitative Research (Morse J. ed.), Sage, London, pp. 117133.
University of Chicago Press, Chicago. Rolfe G. (1994) Towards a new model of nursing research. Journal
Landesman C. (1997) An Introduction to Epistemology. Blackwell of Advanced Nursing 19, 969975.
Science, Oxford. Sandelowski M. (1986) The problem of rigor in qualitative
Leininger M. (1985) Nature, rationale and importance of qualitat- research. Advances in Nursing Science 8(3), 2737.
ive research methods in nursing. In Qualitative Research Sandelowski M. (1993) Rigor or rigor mortis: the problem of rigor
Methods in Nursing (Leininger M. ed.), Grunne and Straton, in qualitative research revisited. Advances in Nursing Science,
Orlando, pp. 126. 16(2), 18.
Mason S. (1993) Employing quantitative and qualitative methods Schumacher K.L. & Gortner S.R. (1992) (Mis)conceptions and
in one study. British Journal of Nursing 2(17), 869872. reconceptions about traditional science. Advances in Nursing
Moccia P. (1988) A critique of compromise: beyond the methods Science 14(4), 111.
debate. Advances in Nursing Science 10(4), 19. Silverman D. (1993) Interpreting Qualitative Data: Methods for
Moody L. (1990) Preface. In Advancing Nursing Science Through Analysing Talk, Text and Interaction. Sage, London.
Research, (Moody L. ed.), Sage, London, pp. 911. Streubert H.J. (1995) Philosophical dimensions of qualitative
Morse J.M. & Field P.A. (1996) Nursing Research: The Application research. In Qualitative Research in Nursing: Advancing the
of Qualitative Approaches 2nd edn. Chapman and Hall, Humanistic Imperative (Streubert H.J. & Carpenter D.R. eds),
London. J.P. Lippincott, Philadelphia, pp. 115.
Nagle L.M. & Mitchell G.J. (1991) Theoretic diversity: evolving Tesch R. (1990) Qualitative Research: Analysis types and software
paradigmatic issues in research and practice. Advances in tools. Falmer Press, London.
Nursing Science 14(1), 1725. Thorne S.E. (1991) Methodological orthodoxy in qualitative nurs-
Norbeck J.S. (1987) In defence of empiricism. Image: Journal of ing research: analyses of the issues. Qualitative Health Research
Nursing Scholarship 19(1), 2830. 1(2), 178199.
Paley J. (1996) Intuition and expertise: comments on the Benner Tinkle M. & Beaton J. (1983) Toward a new view of science: impli-
debate. Journal of Advanced Nursing 23, 665671. cations in nursing research. Advances in Nursing Science 2,
Phillips D. (1990) Postpositivistic science myths and realities. In 12.
The Paradigm Dialog, (Guba E. ed.), Sage, London, pp. 3145. Walters A. (1994) Phenomenology as a way of understanding in
Playle J. (1995) Humanism and positivism in nursing: con- nursing. Contemporary Nursing 3, 134141.
tradictions and conflicts. Journal of Advanced Nursing 22, Watson J. (1981) Nursings scientific quest. American Journal of
979984. Nursing 29(7), 413416.
Polit D. & Hungler B. (1997) Essentials of Nursing Research: Weiss S. (1995) Contemporary empiricism. In In Search of Nursing
Methods, Appraisal and Utilization 4th edn. J.B. Lippincott, Science (Omery A., Kasper C. & Page G. eds), Sage, London,
Philadelphia. pp. 1326.
Poole K. & Jones A. (1996) A re-examination of the experimental Wolfer J. (1993) Aspects of reality and ways of knowing in nurs-
design for nursing research. Journal of Advanced Nursing 24, ing: in search of an integrating paradigm. Image: Journal of
108114. Nursing Scholarship 25(2), 141146.
Popper K. (1959) The Logic of Scientific Discovery. Hutchinson, Ziman J. (1991) Reliable Knowledge. Cambridge University
London. Press, London.

1998 Blackwell Science Ltd, Journal of Advanced Nursing, 27, 12421249 1249

S-ar putea să vă placă și