Sunteți pe pagina 1din 5

Habit: History of the Concept

Charles Camic, Northwestern University, Evanston, IL, USA


2015 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

Abstract

This article examines aspects of the history of the concept of habit in Western social thought. As an expression, the concept of
habit has generally referred to a disposition to act as one has previously acted, whether in regard to simple behaviors, more
complex forms of conduct, or broader characterological tendencies (habitus). Among social thinkers who have used the
concept, habit has generally been applied to recurrent forms of moral, economic, political, and religious conduct insofar as
these occur more or less automatically, thus differing from reective forms of human action that entail the deliberative
selection of means and ends by normative standards. While the history of the concept of habit has been roughly coextensive
with the entirety of Western intellectual history, four phases are distinguished. The rst phase, running from antiquity to the
early 1800s, was marked by the frequent discussion of the role and signicance of habit by thinkers ranging from Aristotle to
the philosophers of the Enlightenment. The second phase, extending from the mid-nineteenth to the early twentieth century,
was characterized by two contending developments. One of these was the invocation of the concept of habit by a great many
European and American social theorists, including Emile Durkheim and Max Weber, and the use of the concept, in tandem
with models of reective action, to analyze human conduct in the social world. The second development in this period was the
effort on the part of natural scientists to restrict habit to more elementary human and subhuman behaviors. The third phase,
beginning roughly in the late 1910s, saw the successful appropriation of habit, narrowly conceived, by behaviorist psychol-
ogists and, in a strong countermovement, the abandonment of the concept by a majority of European and American social
thinkers, who for the next half century conceptualized all human conduct exclusively in reective terms. The fourth phase,
extending from the early 1980s to the present time, has witnessed steps by social theorists and empirical researchers to revive
and elaborate the concept of habit and to examine the relationship between habitual and reective forms of human action.

Found in ordinary languages the world over, habit and various automatically by the context cues that co-occurred with the
cognate expressions have functioned, for over two millennia, as relevant action in the previous situations (quoting Neal et al.,
concepts in diverse intellectual traditions in the social sciences, 2006: p. 198; see also Pollard, 2003: p. 411).
the humanities, and the natural sciences. As used in reference to When these repeated actions are differentiated from one
various recurrent and relatively automatic forms of human another in terms of their content, distinctions then arise
conduct in the social world, the discourse of habit is one of the between moral, cognitive, emotional, and motor habits. Of
great, albeit largely unacknowledged, cultural legacies of greater historical importance, however, has been another basis
Western civilization (Thomas, 1993: p. 8). Although the of differentiation. The actions whose repetition is designated as
history of the discourse has been roughly coextensive with habit may range from simple and circumscribed to complex
Western intellectual history itself, specic use of the concept, and generalized. Among the social thinkers who have used the
and explicit recognition of the aspects of human action to concept, habit has most frequently been applied to recurrent
which it refers, have waxed and waned during different periods patterns of action of moderate complexity and generality, i.e.,
in the development of the social sciences. to habits of economic, political, religious, and domestic
conduct; habits of obedience to rules and to rulers; habits of
sacrice, disinterestedness, and restraint; etc. At various
The Concept of Habit moments in the history of the concept, however, habit has
taken on meanings both narrower and broader: sometimes, it
In the course of its lengthy history, habit has led multiple has referred to simpler, or at least more elemental, behavioral
lives. Its origins lie in the unreective, indiscriminate, regularities, such as habits of talking, walking, eating, dressing,
quotidian use of habit in various popular discourses, which routine problem-solving, etc.; at other times, it has been
are littered with offhand references to habit (or to what is applied to the generalized and durable mode of action that
habitual, or done habitually) and which have historically a person may exhibit in one or more wider spheres of social life,
furnished a vocabulary that has been imported into more such as work, politics, and interpersonal relations (or in all of
raried discussions of philosophical and scientic subjects. these). When used in this more extended sense, the concept
Students of biological life and the physical world have often of habit has been largely synonymous with character or
used habit with reference to non-human animals, the habitus the latter is a term that traces back historically to the
dynamics of populations, the growth pattern of plants, and same linguistic roots as habit. The fact that habit has borne this
the tendencies of systems. (For these quotations, see Sparrow entire range of connotations serves as a precaution against
and Hutchison, 2013: p. 3.) Applied to human conduct, conating particular notions of habit with habit as such. The
habit has generally designated a tendency or disposition for assumption, prevalent in the middle decades of the twentieth
a person to act in ways that she or he has acted previously in century, that habit is a xed, mechanical reaction to discrete
similar contexts, insofar as that disposition is activated stimuli and thus devoid of subjective meaning is, for example,

International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, 2nd edition, Volume 10 http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/B978-0-08-097086-8.03084-1 475
476 Habit: History of the Concept

a view that has historically been associated mainly with habit habit as the force by which the good or bad actions of men
in the sense of simple behavioral regularities, not with more remain with them and become part of their characters
complex habitual forms of action. (quoting Hill, 1996: p. 210); while from Prussia Immanuel
At no point has the vocabulary of habit been an autono- Kant (17241804) held that all acquired habits are objec-
mous discourse. To a signicant degree, its usage has shifted tionable that virtue is moral strength in the pursuit of ones
over time because of the different ways in which habit has been duty, which should never be a matter of habit (Kant, [1798]
combined with, or distinguished from, other concepts. At one 1978: pp. 3234). David Hume, Thomas Reid, George Berke-
important period in its history, habit functioned as the ley, Etienne Condillac, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Johann Fichte,
antithesis of instinct, such that all noninstinctual behavior was Friedrich Schelling, and G.W.F. Hegel were among the many
regarded as habitual. Prior to and subsequent to this period, thinkers who took part in this wide-ranging discussion (on the
however, habit was ordinarily set over against purposive, thinkers named here and others, see Camic, 1986; Funke, 1958;
reective types of action characterized by the deliberate selec- Sparrow and Hutchison, 2013).
tion of means and ends according to various cognitive and
moral standards; in this case, habitual action served as the
An Age of Ferment
converse of those types of action foregrounded in reective
models of human conduct, such as those favored by many From the middle of the nineteenth century until the early
early- and mid-twentieth-century social scientists. At still other decades of the twentieth century, the language of habit was an
(albeit briefer) moments, however, habit has been taken not as even more prominent intellectual presence. This was true in
the opposite of, but as the precondition for, reexive action. European as well as in American philosophical, natural scien-
The same exibility of association has appeared with regard to tic, and social scientic thought, sociological thought in
moral conduct, which has sometimes been contrasted with particular.
habitual action, other times viewed as dependent upon it. In England, the concept of habit entered, with varying
Conceptual variability has been apparent as well at the degrees of explicitness, into the work of a diverse range of
collective level, where the common habits present throughout thinkers that included Jeremy Bentham, James and John Stuart
a social group have sometime been equated with custom, Mill, Herbert Spencer, Charles Darwin, Walter Bagehot, and
whereas other usages dene custom in terms of practices that Alfred Marshall; in France, into the writings of Jean-Baptiste
result from adherence to established social prescriptions and Lamarck, August Comte, Alexis de Tocqueville, Frederic LeP-
are, therefore, distinguishable from actions that have become lay, and Henri Bergson; and in Germany, into the work of
automatic owing to repetition or other habit-formation Friedrich Nietzsche, Ferdinand Tnnies, Georg Simmel, and
processes. (For a fuller treatment of the issues in this section, Edmund Husserl, among many others. In the United States, the
see Camic, 1986; Funke, 1958; Sparrow and Hutchison, 2013.) vocabulary of habit, which had long played signicant roles in
the teachings of popular social reformers, churchmen, and
educators, was mobilized in new ways by the founders of
Historical Development philosophical pragmatism, C.S. Peirce, William James, John
Dewey, and George Herbert Mead (see Shook and Margolis,
Antiquity to the Early 1800s
2009), by Darwinian natural scientists like Charles Whitman
The everyday discourse of habit was appropriated and rendered and Jacques Loeb, and by the rst generation of professional,
esoteric by Greek philosophers as they opened pathways for university-based social scientists. Among the latter were leading
later social thinkers. In the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle laid it economists such as Francis Walker, Laurence Laughlin, and
down that none of the moral virtues arise in us by nature, Thorstein Veblen, as well as all of the periods major sociolo-
that we are adapted by nature to receive them and are made gists, including Lester Ward, William Graham Sumner, Franklin
perfect by habit (Book 2, Chapter 1) (Aristotle, 1973; for Giddings, Albion Small, and W.I. Thomas.
discussion, see Lockwood, 2013). The same conceptual In this respect, the doctrines of contemporary American
vocabulary was incorporated into the philosophical and social sociologists accorded with those of the two towering European
teachings of Plato, Plotinus, Quintilian, Aquinas, William of sociological thinkers of the same era, Emile Durkheim
Ockham, Luther, Montaigne, Pascal, Locke, and Wolff, among (18581917) and Max Weber (18641920). Durkheims life-
a great number of other philosophers, theologians, and men of long position, for example, was that habits.are the real forces
letters; at the same time that generations of natural philoso- which govern us (Durkheim, [190506]1956: p. 152). For
phers applied the concept in studies of physical and biological him, as for the American pragmatists, human reection is
phenomena (Funke, 1958; Sparrow and Hutchison, 2013). a process that generally overloads or paralyzes action; only
In the Age of the Enlightenment, as part and parcel of the when habit is disrupted, and the individual or collective
emerging movement to create a science of man, the concept of being is . at a cross-roads situation [facing] a whole range of
habit received renewed attention from a range of social thinkers possible solutions, does reection emerge in order to restore
who shared the belief that habit is a widespread and potent equilibrium and allow habits of all kinds to reassert
phenomenon in social life, even as they characterized this themselves (Durkheim, [191314]1983: pp. 38, 7980). Given
phenomenon differently. In France, Claude Adrien Helvetius this understanding, Durkheim constructed a program for the
(171571) celebrated habit as the wellspring of public and moral regeneration of modern society that relied heavily on the
private morality and accepted it as a principle by which force of habit: on developing in children the habit of self
[humans everywhere] are actuated (Helvetius, [1758]1807: control and restraint and habits of group life; on cultivating
p. 57); in Scotland, Adam Ferguson (17231816) declared in occupational specialists an absolute regularity in habits
Habit: History of the Concept 477

and habits [of social interaction which], as they grow in to establish habits habits thus conceptualized in
strength, are transformed into rules of conduct; and on ourselves and others (quoting Park, [1915]1969; see also
instilling in societys leaders a habitus of moral being Camic, 1986).
(Durkheim, 190203[1961]: pp. 149, 249, 1893[1984]: pp.
187, 302, 190405[1977]: p. 29).
The Demise of Habit
Although engaged with very different intellectual questions,
Max Weber voiced similar views. Concerned with the analysis This important shift in usage was part of a broader social
of various forms of reective action, Weber nevertheless insis- organizational change that occurred as the subject of habit
ted on the importance of habit, holding that the further we go became the object of ownership battles among university-
back in history, the more we nd that conduct, and particularly based scholars situated in specialized and competing
social action, is determined in an ever more comprehensive academic disciplines. Indeed, as members of different
sphere exclusively by the disposition toward the purely disciplines engaged in turf wars to differentiate their
habitual; and that individuals are still markedly inuenced emerging academic elds from one another, habit assumed
by this force even today, when the great bulk of all everyday the role of a conceptual pawn, a role unknown to it in earlier
action [continues to occur in the form of an] almost automatic pre-professional writings where proprietary rights to the
reaction to habitual stimuli which guide behavior in a course concept were not yet in dispute.
which has been repeatedly followed (Weber, [1922]1978: pp. The watershed in this development was the behaviorist
320, 337, 25 (modied translation)). Understood in this way, movement, which engulfed American psychology in the early
the concept of habit gured into Webers treatment of and middle decades of the twentieth century. Launched by
economic, political, and religious traditionalism, into his John B. Watson (18781958) in an effort to invest the
writings on economic, political, legal, and communal action in discipline of psychology with the prestige that then inhered
the modern world, and even into his analysis of the process by in the application of concepts drawn from the natural
which ascetic Protestantism promoted the rational spirit of sciences, behaviorism claimed the realm of habit as its core
modern capitalism. Regarding the spirit of capitalism as topic of investigation, asserting that every mode of acting .
a particular habitus, Weber credited the early Calvinists with not belonging to mans hereditary equipment must be
creating, out of their religiously conditioned family traditions looked upon as a habit habit understood in physiological
and from the religiously inuenced life-style of the environ- terms as muscular and glandular changes which follow
ment, [a distinctive] habitus among individuals which upon a given stimulus. For Watson and his disciples, the
prepared them in specic ways to live up to the specic corollary of this argument was that a mechanistic habit-
demands of early modern capitalism (Weber, [1910]1968, psychology provided the way to guide society.toward the
[1910]1978: p. 1124). control of group and individual behavior (Watson, 1919:
As Weber, Durkheim, and their sociological contempo- pp. 270, 14, 23) from which corollary it followed that the
raries used the concept of habit to refer to forms of action of academic discipline required for the genuine scientic study
moderate as well as broader generality, however, natural of the social world was not [a social science like] sociology,
scientists of the period increasingly associated habit with but psychology, as it derives from biology, chemistry, and
recurrent human and subhuman activities of much simpler the other natural sciences (Allport, 1927: pp. 167168).
and more mechanical kinds. This, for instance, was the Because these sweeping ownership claims directly chal-
practice of Jean-Baptiste Lamarck (17441829), and Charles lenged the bases of their own academic disciplines, social
Darwin (180982) following the example, regularly spoke scientists (as well as humanists) from the period almost
of the owering habits of plants, the feeding habits of immediately recoiled from the language of habit, ceasing
insects, and the ying habits of pigeons (Darwin, [1859] their use of a concept that had been central to their analysis
1964: pp. 11, 183; [1872]1975: pp. 2931). This was also of human conduct since antiquity. Eager to stop the
the practice of many European physiologists and behaviorist campaign to eliminate, as a valid object of
psychologists as they turned attention to the study of the scientic investigation, the reective forms of action that had
neural foundations of simple animal and human reexes previously commanded recognition alongside habitual
to external stimuli, invoking habit to describe neural forms, sociologists of the era undertook an aggressive
pathways that were noninstinctual yet well established countercampaign to rescue purposive human conduct from
(see Fearing, 1930). This circumscribed usage gained wide assault. To accomplish this, they deliberately abandoned
currency among late-nineteenth and early-twentieth- their prior use of the discourse of habit, thereby abruptly
century American psychologists, who shared with William purging habitual phenomena from their conceptualization
James (18421910) the view that even the most complex of human conduct in the social world. This purge was
habits [are] nothing but concatenated discharges in the inaugurated by (a one-time proponent of the concept of
nerve-centres, due to the presence there of systems of habit) W.I. Thomas (18631947) and Florian Znaniecki
reex paths (James, [1890]1950: p. 108). Taking up this (18821958), whose work attacked the behavioristic
same formulation and substituting it for various broader school for its indistinct [application] of the term
sociological usages, early twentieth-century American habit to [all] uniformities of behavior and insisted that
social scientists came to dene the concept of habit in habit . be restricted to the biological eld, [since] it
terms of the physiology of the nervous system, involves no conscious, purposeful regulation of [conduct],
a formulation that led them to argue that education but merely . is unreective, [whereas] the uniformity
and social control are largely dependent upon our ability [characteristic of social life] is not a uniformity of organic
478 Habit: History of the Concept

habits but of consciously followed rules (Thomas and appreciation of the signicance of the phenomenon have
Znaniecki, [1918]1958: pp. 18491852). begun to reappear throughout the social sciences and the
Within a generation, this formulation became social humanities, notably in the work of contemporary philosophers
scientic dogma, eliminating all sociological talk of habit (Ostrow, 1990; Pollard, 2003; Shook and Margolis, 2009),
and replacing it with the language of attitude, which social psychologists (Charng et al., 1988; Neal et al., 2006;
Thomas and Znaniecki had simultaneously ushered onto Ouellette and Wood, 1998), and economists (Campbell and
center stage and which subsequently furnished American Cochrane, 1995; Carroll et al., 2000; Dynan, 2000; Fuhrer,
social scientists with a new vocabulary for describing recur- 2000; Kahneman, 2003; Li, 2005; Shachar, 2003).
rent tendencies in human conduct but without sacricing Moreover, just as they had previously spearheaded the
reective action models as the behaviorists had done (Camic, assault on the discourse of habit, so sociologists have been
1986; Fleming, 1967). Analogous movements away from the particularly active in the current resurrection of the discourse.
concept of habit occurred in European social thought, as To varying degrees, this about-face has been evident in the
Durkheim and Weber themselves subtracted the concept writings of sociological theorists of several different
from their work; and they occurred as well as in European persuasions, all of them of the view that habitual forms of
and American humanistic literatures (Fisher, 1973; Thomas, action warrant inclusion along with reective forms (Archer,
1993). 2012; Calhoun et al., 2012; Camic, 1986; Emirbayer and
Following this conceptual sea-change, the discourse of habit Mische, 1998; Giddens, 2009; Gronow, 2011; Joas, [1992]
lay dormant in the social sciences from the late 1910s to the 1996; Schatzki et al., 2001; Martin, 2011; Sewell, 2005;
early 1980s, a few isolated exceptions notwithstanding. Turner, 2010). Both explicitly and implicitly, this same view
Shortly after the start of the behaviorist revolution in has come to inform research in the specialty areas of
psychology, John Dewey (18591952) insistently harked economic sociology (Biggart and Beamish, 2003; White,
back to a broader conception of habit (1922), as Norbert 2004), the sociology of organizations (Adler, 2010), the
Elias, Martin Heidegger, Jean Piaget, and Maurice Merleau- sociology of science (Collins, 2012), the sociology of
Ponty would subsequently attempt to do in Europe morality (Hitlin and Vaisey, 2012), and the sociology of the
(Kestenbaum, 1977; Sparrow and Hutchison, 2013; and, for body (Shilling, 2008). In a further development, sociologist
Elias, [1939]1994; see also Berger and Luckmann, 1966). But Pierre Bourdieu (19302002) drawing on a previously
these philosophically oriented interventions failed to stem neglected strand in the work of Weber and Durkheim, has
the behaviorist tide or the social-scientic rejection of the resuscitated and elaborated the notion of habitus ([1980]
concept of habit that had emerged in reaction. Only among 1990), setting it in place as one of the foundation stones of
psychologists working in the behaviorist tradition, and his oeuvre. Among scholars inuenced by Bourdieus
among a few economists concerned with consumer behavior, writings, habitus has also crystallized as a major locus of
did habitual phenomena remain the focus of empirical theoretical inquiry and empirical investigation (Gorski, 2013;
research during the long mid-decades of the twentieth Hillier and Rooksby, 2005).
century (Deaton and Muelbaur, 1980; Smith, 1986). Although these numerous lines of recent work remain
Otherwise, social scientists simply dispensed with the generally disconnected from one another after the rst decade
concept, opting to conceive all human action as though it of the twenty-rst century, their simultaneous emergence and
were a reective process of selecting means to ends in accord likely future cross-pollination augur the return of the concept
with normative standards. of habit to a position of centrality in social-scientic theory
and research, and, accompanying this development, the
transformation of exclusively reective models of action into
Recent Developments analytical approaches concerned with the complex and
changing relationship between reective and habitual forms
The period from the 1980s to the 2010s has brought the onset of human conduct in the social world.
of another reversal, however. Behind this recent development
has been a change in the social-organizational conditions that
led to the demise of social-scientic interest in habit during See also: Attitude: History of Concept; Conceptual History:
the previous historical era. By the closing years of the twen- Begriffsgeschichte; Discipline Formation in the Social Sciences;
tieth century, the intellectual turf warfare among disciplines Enlightenment: Impact on the Social Sciences; Habitus: History
that had marked the early to middle decades of that century of a Concept; Scientic Disciplines, History of; Sociology,
was long ended, and its waning rendered increasingly anach- History of; Weberian Social Thought, History of.
ronistic the behaviorists proprietary claims on habit. The
obsolescence of these claims, and of the counterclaims that
they had called forth, freed up the concept of habit to reas- Bibliography
sume some of the broader connotations it once possessed and
to reenter, with scarcely any resistance, the social-scientic Adler, P.S., 2010. The Oxford Handbook of Sociology and Organization Studies:
analysis of human conduct. Classical Foundations. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.
To be sure, this revival of the language of habit has thus far Allport, F.H., 1927. The nature of institutions. Social Forces 6, 167179.
Archer, M.S., 2012. The Reexive Imperative in Late Modernity. Cambridge University
been spotty and gradual, and it has left untouched many areas Press, Cambridge, UK.
of the social sciences where the language might arguably be put Aristotle, 1973. In: McKeon, R. (Ed.), Introduction to Aristotle, second ed. University of
to use. Even so, references to concept of habit and a renewed Chicago Press, Chicago.
Habit: History of the Concept 479

Berger, P.L., Luckmann, T., 1966. The Social Construction of Reality. Doubleday, Hitlin, S., Vaisey, S. (Eds.), 2012. Handbook of the Sociology of Morality. Springer,
New York. New York.
Biggart, N.W., Beamish, T.D., 2003. The economic sociology of conventions: habit, James, W., [1890]1950. The Principles of Psychology. Dover, New York.
custom, practice, and routine in market order. Annual Review of Sociology 29, Joas, H., [1992] 1996. The Creativity of Action. University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
443464. Kahneman, D., 2003. A psychological perspective on economics. American Economic
Bourdieu, P., [1980]1990. The Logic of Practice. Stanford University Press, Review 93, 162168.
Stanford, CA. Kant, I., [1798]1978. Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View. Southern Illinois
Calhoun, C., Gerteis, J., Moody, J., Pfaff, S., Virk, I., 2012. Classical Sociological University Press, Carbondale, IL.
Theory. Wiley-Blackwell, New York. Kestenbaum, V., 1977. The Phenomenological Sense of John Dewey. Humanities
Camic, C., 1986. The matter of habit. American Journal of Sociology 91, Press, Atlantic Highlands, NJ.
10391087. Li, Y., 2005. The wealth-consumption ratio and the consumption-habit ratio. Journal of
Campbell, J.Y., Cochrane, J.H., 1995. By Force of Habit. National Bureau of Economic Business and Economic Statistics 23, 226241.
Research, Cambridge, MA. Lockwood, T.C., 2013. Habituation, habit, and character in Aristotles Nicomachean
Carroll, C., Overland, J., Neal, D.N., 2000. Saving and growth with habit formation. Ethics. In: Sparrow, T., Hutchison, A. (Eds.), A History of Habit: From Aristotle to
American Economic Review 90, 341355. Bourdieu. Lexington Books, Lanham, MD, pp. 1936.
Charng, H.-W., Piliavin, J., Callero, P.L., 1988. Role identity and reasoned action in Martin, J.L., 2011. The Explanation of Social Action. Oxford University Press,
the prediction of repeated behavior. Social Psychology Quarterly 51, 303317. New York.
Collins, H., 2012. Tacit and Explicit Knowledge. University of Chicago Press, Chicago. Neal, D.T., Wood, W., Quinn, J.M., 2006. Habits: a repeat performance. Current
Darwin, C., [1859]1964. On the Origin of Species. Harvard University Press, Directions in Psychological Science 15, 198202.
Cambridge, MA. Ostrow, J.M., 1990. Social Sensitivity. State University of New York Press, Albany, NY.
Darwin, C., [1872]1975. The Expression of Emotions in Man and Animals. University of Ouellette, J.A., Wood, W., 1998. Habit and intention in everyday life. Psychological
Chicago Press, Chicago. Bulletin 124, 5474.
Deaton, A., Muelbaur, J., 1980. Economics and Consumer Behavior. Cambridge Park, R.E., [1915]1969. Man not born human. In: Park, R.E, Burgess, E.W. (Eds.),
University Press, New York. Introduction to the Science of Sociology. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp.
Dewey, J., 1922. Human Nature and Conduct. Henry Holt, New York. 8284.
Durkheim, E., [1893]1984. The Division of Labor in Society. Free Press, New York. Pollard, B., 2003. Can virtuous actions be both habitual and rational? Ethical Theory
Durkheim, E., [190203]1961. Moral Education. Free Press, New York. and Moral Practice 6, 411425.
Durkheim, E., [190405]1977. The Evolution of Educational Thought. Routledge and Schatzki, T.R., Knorr Cetina, K., von Savigny, E., 2001. The Practice Turn in
Kegan Paul, London. Contemporary Theory. Routledge, London.
Durkheim, E., [190506]1956. Education and Society. Free Press, Glencoe, IL. Sewell Jr., W.H., 2005. Logics of History: Social Theory and Social Transformation.
Durkheim, E., [191314]1983. Pragmatism and Sociology. Cambridge University University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL.
Press, Cambridge, UK. Shachar, R., 2003. Party loyalty as habit formation. Journal of Applied Economics 18,
Dynan, K., 2000. Habit formation and consumer preferences. American Economic 251269.
Review 90, 319406. Shilling, C., 2008. Changing Bodies: Habit, Crisis and Creativity. Sage, London.
Elias, N., [1939]1994. The Civilizing Process (Edmund Jephcott, Trans.). Oxford: Shook, J.R., Margolis, J. (Eds.), 2009. A Companion to Pragmatism. Wiley-Blackwell,
Blackwell. Boston, MA.
Emirbayer, M., Mische, A., 1998. What is agency? American Journal of Sociology 103, Smith, L.D., 1986. Behaviorism and Logical Positivism. Stanford University Press,
9621023. Stanford, CA.
Fearing, F., 1930. Reex Action. Williams and Williams, Baltimore, MD. Sparrow, T., Hutchison, A. (Eds.), 2013. A History of Habit: From Aristotle to Bourdieu.
Fisher, P., 1973. The failure of habit. In: Engel, M. (Ed.), Uses of Literature. Harvard Lexington Books, Lanham, MD.
University Press, Cambridge, MA, pp. 318. Thomas, J.M., 1993. Figures of habit in William James. The New England Quarterly
Fleming, D., 1967. Attitude: history of a concept. Perspectives in American History 1, 66, 326.
287365. Thomas, W.I., Znaniecki F., [1918]1958. The Polish Peasant in Europe and America.
Fuhrer, J.C., 2000. Habit formation in consumption and its implication for monetary University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
policy models. American Economic Review 90, 367390. Turner, S., 2010. Explaining the Normative. Polity, Cambridge, UK.
Funke, G., 1958. Gewohnheit. Archive fur Begriffsgeschichte 3, 1606. Watson, J.B., 1919. Psychology from the Standpoint of a Behaviorist. Lippincott,
Giddens, A., 2009. Sociology. Polity Press, Cambridge, UK. Philadelphia.
Gorski, P.S. (Ed.), 2013. Bourdieu and Historical Anlaysis. Duke University Press, Weber, M., [1910]1968. Antikritisches zum Geist des Kapitalismus. In: Winckelmann,
Durham, North Carolina. J. (Ed.), Die Protestantische Ethik II. Siebenstern, Munich, pp. 149187.
Gronow, A., 2011. From Habits to Social Structures. Peter Lang, New York. Weber, M., [1910]1978. Anticritical last word on the spirit of capitalism. American
Helvetius, C.A., [1758]1807. De lEsprit. Jones, London. Journal of Sociology 83, 11051131.
Hill, L., 1996. Anticipations of nineteenth and twentieth century social thought in the Weber, M., [1922]1978. Economy and Society. University of California Press,
work of Adam Ferguson. Archives europennes de sociologie 37, 203228. Berkeley, CA.
Hillier, J., Rooksby, E. (Eds.), 2005. Habitus: A Sense of Place, second ed. Ashgate, White, H.C., 2004. Markets from Networks: Socioeconomic Models of Production.
Aldershot, UK. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.

S-ar putea să vă placă și