Sunteți pe pagina 1din 13

Public Choice 88: 1-13, 1996.

© 1996 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.

Towards a positive theory of political rhetoric:


Why do politicians lie?

MICHAEL L. D A V I S & M I C H A E L F E R R A N T I N O
Department o f Economics, Southern Methodist University, Dallas, T X 75275

Accepted 12 July 1994

Abstract. This paper presents a model in which politicians can increase the probability of election
by making exaggerated claims about the benefits of their own platform - referred to as positive
campaigning - and by exaggerating the undesirable characteristics of their rival - i.e., negative
campaigning. Such lies may be detected at some point in the future and thus result in a costly loss
in reputation. Thus the politician must tradeoff immediate benefits against potential future costs.
Of course this problem is similar to any commercial endeavor - a car maker, for example, is tempted
to claim that his car is better and the competition's is worse than it is. But it is shown that the lack
of transferable property rights to political office makes lying more likely in political markets. It
is also shown that there is a natural tendency for politicians to engage in more negative cam-
paigning.

1. Introduction

T h e 1858 Illinois s e n a t o r i a l c a m p a i g n witnessed w h a t m a n y r e g a r d as t h e m o s t


c o m p e l l i n g p o l i t i c a l e x c h a n g e in A m e r i c a n h i s t o r y , t h e d e b a t e s b e t w e e n
A b r a h a m L i n c o l n a n d S t e p h e n D o u g l a s . I n a series o f e n c o u n t e r s , as well as
in o t h e r c a m p a i g n i n g , D o u g l a s d o w n p l a y e d his views r e g a r d i n g t h e M i s s o u r i
C o m p r o m i s e , t h e D r e d S c o t t d e c i s i o n a n d t h e o t h e r t r a u m a s o f the 1850s, lead-
ing i n s t e a d w i t h the c h a r g e t h a t L i n c o l n was a secret a b o l i t i o n i s t w h o s e u l t i m a t e
o b j e c t i v e was r a c i a l e q u a l i t y . I n a speech, as q u o t e d in M c P h e r s o n (1987: 182),
D o u g l a s said:

L i n c o l n believes t h a t t h e A l m i g h t y m a d e the N e g r o e q u a l to t h e white m a n . . .


H e t h i n k s t h a t t h e N e g r o is his b r o t h e r . I d o n o t t h i n k the N e g r o is a n y k i n
o f m i n e at all... This g o v e r n m e n t . . , was m a d e b y white m e n , for the b e n e f i t
o f white m e n a n d their p o s t e r i t y , to b e e x e c u t e d a n d m a n a g e d b y white m e n .

A n d in a l a t e r speech ( M c P h e r s o n 1987: 185):


If you desire them (blacks) to come into the State and settle with the white
man, if you desire them to vote . . . . then support Mr. Lincoln and the Black
Republican party, who are in favor of the citizenship of the negro.

Douglas was lying. In fact, Lincoln's views on race relations were very much
in the 19th mainstream, he did not even favor abolition, let alone equality. To
quote again from McPherson (p. 186):

Lincoln spelled out his position with clarity: " I am not, nor ever have been
in favor of bringing about in any way the social and political equality of the
white and black races, (applause) - that I am not nor ever have been in
favor o f making voters or jurors of negroes, nor of qualifying them to hold
office, nor to intermarry with white people; and I will say in addition to this
that there is a physical difference between the races which I believe will for
ever forbid the two races living together on terms of social and political
equality."

Examined as a problem of rhetoric, Douglas' strategy is remarkable in two


regards. First, his prevarication was almost certainly inconsistent with his non-
political persona. Douglas, whatever his failings, seems hardly to have been the
cynical manipulator that these quotes suggest - it is difficult, for example, to
imagine him cheating Lincoln in a card game or a business dealing. Why, then, •
did he so effortlessly stoop to such dishonorable behavior during a political
campaign? Secondly, why, having chosen to lie, did he lie about Lincoln in-
stead of exaggerating some positive element of his own character or positions?
Lying creates both benefits and costs for liars. Thus, it seems reasonable to
examine the decision to lie through the lens of microeconomics. And indeed,
the economics o f lying can be thought of as a subset o f the economics o f infor-
mation. An incomplete list of the relevant literature would include the papers
by Akerlof (1970), Klein and Leffler (1981) and Crawford and Sobel (1982).
There is, of course, a substantial literature modelling political behavior as eco-
nomic behavior. In this piper, we attempt to link these two approaches in order
to better explain the kinds of behavior typified by the example of Lincoln and
Douglas. Tullock (1967: Ch. 9) also considers the economics o f lying. Because
the particulars of our model are very different, we obtain different (but not
contradictory) results. But both his model and ours share the same underlying
spirit.
In what follows, we attempt to explore how what we believe are important
distinctions between political markets and other markets affect the type of
claims made in each. We present two main results. First, that because of the
nature of property rights in political office, political rhetoric will be less honest
than other types of speech. Second, that because of the way political claims are
verified, there is a special tendency in political markets to exaggerate claims
about the deficiencies o f the competing side - in the jargon o f politics, negative
campaigning.
In the next section we present a brief verbal discussion that captures the
flavor of our work. Section 3 formally models the politicians decision about
whether to tell the truth. Section 4 considers how the model will be modified
if voters understand the incentives faced by the politicians. Conclusions and
further discussion are in Section 5.

2. Political markets, economic markets and lies

Lying, alas, is hardly unique to politics - children lie to parents, students to


teachers, and advertisers to consumers. In each of these relationships, though,
powerful forces exist to moderate untruths: parents can impound bicycles,
teachers will assign failing grades and jilted consumers can sue. But while these
explicit sanctions may, in some situations, make up an important part o f the
cost o f lying, nearly every liar must consider the value of lost reputation - dis-
honest children risk not only bicycles, but the future benefits that follow a par-
ent's trust.
The need to maintain reputation may be a particularly vital force for truth
in those instances where direct penalties to liars (e.g., lawsuits or forfeiture of
some bond) are costly or otherwise unavailable. Both political markets and
many economic markets have this characteristic. It is simply impractical to sue
a soup manufacturer who promises but does not deliver a palatable product.It
is similarly impractical to sue a politician who promises peace and prosperity
but creates war and depression. Often the best protection against a dishonest
vendor or deceitful politician is the threat to do business elsewhere.
The structure of property rights that characterizes the classic business firm
serves (not by accident, of course) to increase the importance of reputation to
the institution. In so far as property rights to the firm are transferable in an
efficient market, the value of future reputation is capitalized in the present
value of the firm. Thus, a firm that is tempted to tell a lie that may tarnish the
firm's reputation at some point in the future will be forced to weigh these costs
against the immediate benefits of the lie. This, of course, is not to say that firms
will tell the level of truth that maximizes wealth - if it is possible to deceive
consumers in the short run it may also be possible to deceive the capital markets
- but it is certainly true that the transferable property rights give owners of
firms an incentive to maintain a reputation for honest dealing.
A critical difference between many firms and politicians is that the latter do
not hold transferable property rights to their office.1 Thus, politicians as a
group have less incentive to be honest since they need only be concerned about
how lies will affect their reputation during their tenure in office. For instance,
a politician who plans to retire in one year would not be dissuaded from telling
a lie that could be discovered only two-years hence. 2
Political markets are also different from many other economic markets in
that the nature of the competition is essentially "winner-take-all." As we
demonstrate in the formal model that follows, this also creates powerful incen-
tives to lie that may not be found in other settings. Consider a politician run-
ning for office that, if lost, would end his career. If there was a serious danger
of defeat, there would be little reason not to lie, so long as the value to the poli-
tician of holding office with shattered reputation exceeded the alternative of
defeat.
Politicians advance their cause by making two kinds of claims: statements
about their advantages o f their positions, positive claims, and statements about
the disadvantages o f opponents, negative claims. This, of course, is true of ad-
vertising for many types products - the demand for a certain brand of soup
is bound to increase when another brand is found to be unwholesome.
The need to maintain reputation is an important deterrence to either type o f
lie only to the extent that a falsehood can be discovered. And herein, we think,
is another important difference between political and economic markets. In
many economic settings, positive and negative claims can be tested with about
equal ease, and so advertisers will not have a strong bias towards either type
of claim. However in political markets the outcome of the election is usually
critical in determining which claims will be tested. If negative claims succeed
in securing the desired outcome, they may never be tested. Thus, if they are
false, the politician making them suffers no loss o f reputation. On the other
hand, if positive campaigns are successful, the claims made are more likely to
be tested, and if false, cause the politician to suffer a loss of reputation. As we
explain more formally in the next section, this asymmetry creates a natural bias
towards negative campaigns.
To get a better feel for how this bias arises, consider the example o f a politi-
cian trying to decide whether to emphasize a negative theme - perhaps claim-
ing that the crime rate will rise if her opponent is elected - or some positive
theme - her own commitment to law and order. If the politician is elected on
the strength of her positive claims, she must know that her promises will be test-
ed against her performance. On the other hand, a successful campaign means
that negative claims can never be tested - the only way the electorate can ever
know whether the opponent would precipitate a crime wave would be to elect
him to office. Thus, if the positive or negative claims have the same impact on
the chances of election, the politician will be more tempted towards exaggerat-
ing the negative, since in so doing she increases the chances o f election and so
lowers the expected cost of lost reputation. There is an even stronger bias
towards negative campaigning when, if the election is lost reputation may be
unimportant. Indeed, if this is the case, then the politician ought to make the
most negative claims possible.
Political markets are probably not unique in creating asymmetric incentives
for negative claims. All that matters is that if the object of the claim behaves
in the desired way, the veracity of the claim is more difficult or verify. This may
arise due to inefficient information flows, foreclosure of options, or inefficient
information processing. For example, certain types of household maintenance
services are purchased infrequently. It may be costly to identify other cus-
tomers having experience with a particular seller, and obtaining a price quote
may involve a time-consuming house visit. If a potential seller informs a house-
holder that methods generally used by competitors for duct cleaning or con-
crete repair are inferior or will damage the house, such claims may be believed
and achieve a sale for the seller. This means, of course, that the quality of com-
petitors' services will remain untested. The perverse incentives are compound-
ed in that if the seller's positive claims about own performance prove to be un-
founded, the buyer may find that word-of-mouth and reports to local chamber
of commerce are inefficient methods of reducing the seller's reputation.
Another case of negative claims in commodity markets arises in advertising
to children. The purchase of goods consumed by children often involves com-
plicated interaction between parent and child. As a consequence, the child may
be unable to conduct experiments involving alternating purchases of competing
experience goods, even when the financial cost of such experiments are relative-
ly low. In addition, children are likely to be less skilled in revising their prior
beliefs than other consumers. These circumstances are likely to increase the
value to the advertiser of making exaggerated negative claims which, if be-
lieved, will forestall sampling of competing goods. For example, a recent TV
advertising campaign for a national chain of pizza restaurants-cum-game ar-
cades catering to children informs children that at other pizza restaurants they
will be exposed to bad food, intense boredom and opera singing. 3

3. The model

3.1. Notation and assumptions

We begin by assuming that a political issue must be decided in which there are
two clear sides. The politician knows the true nature of these outcomes and so
knows precisely the utility forthcoming to himself under each proposal as well
as the true value that constituents will receive from the success of each side.
Denote the politician's utility under the preferred policy as Up and the utility
under the less desirable policy as U n. Without loss of generality let u n = 0,
with UP > 0. Thus, for example, UP might represent the utility the politician
derives if he is elected as compared with defeat. If the issue is some legislative
proposal U p gives the value to the politician of seeing his position adopted as
opposed to some other.
The politician can influence the probability that the desired proposal will be
adopted by making claims as to the value (utility) that some constituent group
will receive under either side. This constituent group might simply be the voters
or, in the case of a legislative proposal, some special interest lobby that could,
if sufficiently motivated, influence the legislature. Let Vcp denote the value the
politician claims the constituent will receive under the proposal favored by the
politician and Vcn the value the politician claims constituents will receive un-
der the alternative. For example, Vcp might be the additional wealth the politi-
cian promises the voters if he is elected, and Vcn might be the decline the
voter's wealth that the politician claims will result from the election of his op-
ponent.
Assume that the probability of the favored policy being adopted depends
upon the difference in the values claimed under each. That is the probability
that the politician will receive Up is given by p=po+P(VCp-Vcn), with
P'(Vcp-v cn) > 0, where Po is simply the probability of the desired proposal
passing if the politician made no attempt to influence the outcome (i.e.,
P(O) = o).
We assume that during the campaign the constituents do not know the true
value that they will receive under each policy, which we denote Vtp and Vtn.
However, at some time in the future, after the matter is decided, they may ob-
tain better information as to the truth. We denote this realized, expost, value
as Vrp and VTM. Note that in our model as, we think, in the political world the
truth does not inevitably win out - i.e., Vtp need not equal Vtp.
We assume that lying is costly to the politician in that it reduces the value
of his reputation. To capture this, let the function r=R[(Vcp-vrp)2+
(vcn-vrn) 2] represent a measure, in units comparable to utility, of the politi-
cian's reputation. In the simplest case, Up might simply represent the income
the politician will receive under the favored outcome, and R would represent
the expected present value of all future income the politician would receive
from his position. As the difference between what the politician claimed and
what the constituent groups finally observes increases, it becomes more
difficult for the politician to influence future events in his favor and so r would
decline (i.e., we assume R'[.] < 0). As we develop more fully below, -R'(.) is
essentially the marginal cost of lying. Thus, we make the usual assumption that
marginal costs are non-decreasing (i.e., we assume R" (.) _<0).
Notice that in this formulation lying is symmetric in the sense that incorrect
claims as to advantages of the policy the politician wants adopted (or rather
claims that are latter perceived to be incorrect) have the same effect on reputa-
tion as incorrect claims about the issue the politician wants defeated. Notice
also that r may be stochastic, especially insofar as what the constituents realize
expost may be random. We consider this in more detail below. We recognize,
o f course, that this formulation o f reputation is at best a rough summary o f
what is surely a complex and mysterious process. However, since the purpose
of this paper is not to model the process by which constituents decide how
much faith to put in political rhetoric, this formulation is sufficient to make
the points we think relevant.
In our model, therefore, the politician has two decision variables: the posi-
tive claims to b e m a d e about the advantages o f desired policy, V cp, and nega-
tive claims about the alternative, V cn. The expected utility received from a pair
of claims is therefore

¢p(VCp, vcn) = [Po + p(Vcp-ven)]uP + 8R[(VcP-vrn)2 + (vcn-vrn)2] (1)

where 5 is simply a parameter to measure the relative importance of reputation


to current value. In the next two subsections we consider how the optimal levels
of the claims under various conditions.

3.2. Optimal lying when ex post verification is possible

We turn our attention next to the question of the optimal deception when all
falsehoods will eventually be discovered. Although this exercise is quite simple
and generates predictable results, it is useful in establishing a benchmark for
comparison with the case discussed in the next section in which some lies will
go undetected. If the constituency eventually discovers the truth about how it
will be affected by proposals, then it is true that V tp = V rp and V tn = V TM. Thus,
substituting into (1), we see that the optimal claims must satisfy

q)vcp = P ' (.)U p + 25R' [(VcP-Vtp) 2 + (vcn-vtn)2](VcP-Vtp) = 0 (2.1)

q)vca = -P' (.)U p + 26R' [(VcP-Vtp)2 + ( v c n - v t n ) 2 ] ( v c n - v tn) = 0 (2.2)

Simply manipulation of these first order conditions confirms the obvious: that
the politician will wish to exaggerate the desirable features of the proposition
that he favors (i.e., Vcp-v tp > 0) while exaggerating the undesirable features of
the negative (i.e., Vcn-vtn < 0). Perhaps more interestingly, we see that there is
no bias towards either positive or negative campaigning in the sense that the
magnitude of the positive lies are exactly matched in absolute value by the
negative lies. 4
3.3. Optimal lying when the truth is hidden

Suppose that constituents can only determine if a politician has told the truth
by comparing the claims that were made against what actually happened. Thus,
only those policies that get passed can actually be tested. Suppose further that
if the claim cannot be tested, the politician's reputation does not suffer. In
other words, if the favorable outcome occurs, then V tp = V tp, and V rn ----V on.
Similarly, if the unfavorable outcome comes to pass, then v r p = V cp and
V TM -----Vtn. This implies that the reputation is also stochastic and so the politi-
cians expected utility function is

q)(Vcp,vcn) = i~ {U p + 8R[VCp-vcn)2] } + (1-p)SR[(Vcn-vtn) 2 (3)

The optimal claims must satisfy

q)vCP(-) = p' (.) { U p + 8R[(Vcp-vtp) 2]-~R[(vcn-vtn) 2] }


(4.1)
+ [Po + P ( - ) ] f R ' [(VcP-Vtp)2](VcP-V tp) = 0

(DvCn(.) = -p'(.)[UP+SR[(Vcp-vtp)2]-6R[(Vcn-vtn)2]}
(4.2)
+ [1-Po-P(-)]~SR'[(vcn-vtn)2](vcn-vtn) = 0

If some lies can be hidden, then it will no longer be the case that the politician
will wish to balance negative and positive lies. It is straight-forward to demon-
strate through the usual techniques that an increase in Po causes a decrease in
the claim for the positive side and a decrease in the claims for the negative side.
Thus, as Po increases the positive claims move back towards the truth and the
negative claims move further away from truth.
Inspection of the first order conditions reveals why this is so. In expression
(4.1), the term [po+P(.)]~SR'[(Vcp-vtp)2](Vcp-vtp) represents the marginal
costs of increasing the positive lie. As Po goes up, these costs go up and as lies
become more expensive, fewer are told. In other words, to say that Po has
gone up is to say that the favorable outcome is more likely to come about.
Thus, the politician needs to be more careful about positive claims since these
are more likely to be tested.
In expression (4.2) the term [1-Po-P(-)]~R' [(vcn-vtn)2](vcn-v tn) is positive
and can be thought of as the marginal benefit o f reducing the negative lie. As
Po goes up, this marginal benefit declines. As the benefit to more honesty
regarding the opposition goes down, more lies are told about the opposition.
This result has an interesting corollary that supports our contention o f a bias
towards negative campaigning: in those contests evenly matched before cam-
paigning - i.e., those where Po = .5 - the politician will engage in more nega-
tive than positive rhetoric. To see this, suppose that after the campaign the
9

(vcn_vtn) 2
I

I ( Vcp-Vtp)2
i

.5 Po
Figure 1. Optimal lies as a function of pre-campaign odds of winning.

odds of victory are even - that is Po + p(Vcp-vcn) = .5. It is obvious from the
first order conditions that this implies that Vcp-v tp = -(vcn-vtn). It is, o f
course, also true that when the after campaign odds are even, the pre-campaign
odds must be less the .5. Thus, relying on the results that as Po goes up the
negative lies get bigger and the positive lies smaller, it follows that when Po =
.5 more negative campaigning occurs.
These results are summarized in Figure 1, which shows a graph of the op-
timal level of negative and positive lies - i.e., ( v c n - v t n ) 2 and ( V c p - v t p ) 2 - as
functions of the pre-campaign odds of victory. Here it is seen that the negative
lies increase with the pre-campaign odds and the positive lies decrease. It is also
seen that when the odds start off as even, there is already a bias towards nega-
tive claims.

3.4. Optical lies and the election oS..doom

In the models presented thus far, the politician is assumed to value reputation
even if the proposition fails. We made this assumption in order to demonstrate
that our hypothesis about negative campaigning holds under even highly un-
likely circumstances. In many cases this is obviously untrue. In particular,
reputation as an honest politician may not be o f much value in other occupa-
tions. Thus, if the proposition is whether the politician will be elected, a defeat
may render all reputation worthless. This is especially true when it is unlikely
that a defeated politician will ever be able to run again. As might be expected,
10

this makes lying more extreme and negative campaigning more likely.
Here again, we must consider separately the two cases where expost verifica-
tion is and is not possible. When constituents can verify claims at some point
in the future, the politician's objective function becomes

q)(Vcp'vcn) = [Po + p(vcp-vcn)] {Up + 6R[(Vcp-vrp) 2 + (vcn-vrn) 2] } (5)

The only difference between this and the objective function given by (1) is that
here the reputation function is deflated by the probability of success. This is
simply equivalent to lowering the costs of lying and so we expect that there
would be more lying. It is easily shown that in this case the lies are still sym-
metric.
A more interesting (or at least more extreme) result follows when we consider
what happens when constituents can not verify negative claims when the politi-
cian is successful. Here the politician's objective function is

q0(Vcp,vcn) = [po+P(VCp-vcn)]{UP+6R[(Vcp-vrp)2]} (6)

Since this is monotonically decreasing in V cn, the politician will make the
most extremely negative charges about the opposition possible. In other words,
if a victory means that negative claims have no impact on reputation, and if
defeat means that reputation is irrelevant, the politician should set the level of
negative campaigning so as to maximize the probability of victory.

4. Voters' processing of politicians' claims

What happens when voters expect politicians to lie and base their expectation
of the truth on a transformed version of the politician's claim, obtained
through some form of Bayesian revision of prior beliefs? In general, this will
reduce but not eliminate the politician's incentives to lie. In our model, the
politician is essentially a Stackleberg leader, making claims to voters whose
political support and evaluation of the politician's reputation is based on a rela-
tively crude reaction to lies which does not take into account the politician's
incentives. If we attribute more complex reactions to voters, this tends to
reduce but not eliminate the politician's ability to make misleading claims.
Consider first a relatively simple case in which voters react to politicians'
statements by revising their priors in a Bayesian fashion, but in which they do
not attribute overt strategic behavior to politicians. Specifically, voters assume
that there are congenitally " h o n e s t " politicians who telPthe truth with prob-
ability ~th and congenitally "dishonest" politicians which tell the truth with
probability ad,O < a d < a h < 1. The politicians report the value of a variable g
11

from which the voters derive utility and which will be subsequently confirmed.
Let the variable take only two values, a truthful value gt and a false value gf.
If politicians' utility is rising in the voter's perception of g, then gf>gt" In
addition, voters have a prior probability 13 that any given politician will be
honest. By straightforward application of Bayes' rule, after the politician
announces gt and the voters conform it, they revise their value of 13 to fit =
ahl3/(ahfi + ad(1-fi)), while if the politician announces gf and the voters later
confirm the values gt, they revise their value of 13to fif = ((1-~h)fi/((1-~h)fi -l-
(1-~td)(1-13)). If is straightforward to show that ~t > ~ > ~f" Thus, the voters'
repeated observation that an individual politician's claims are true or false lead
to an evolution of the politician's reputation, but a gradual one. If politicians
believe that voters reason in this way, it will thus reduce but not eliminate the
tendency to lie. 5
The most general case is one in which both voters react to politicians' claims
by revising their beliefs about politicians' honesty and in which politicians'
claims are made in a way which explicitly recognizes that voters do this.
Crawford and Sobel (1982) analyze a very general case of Bayesian Nash
equilibrium in which one better-informed player (a "sender") sends a possibly
noisy signal to another player (a "receiver '') who takes an action influencing
the welfare of both players. In our case, the politician is the sender and the
voter, the receiver. In general, in full Bayesian Nash equilibrium senders give
receivers noisy information which truthfully indicates a general range of the
sender's private information but not the precise value of the information.
When the sender and receiver have widely differing utility functions, the noise
is greater. This suggests a limited but still present potential for political obfus-
cation, as well as offering the prediction that politicians whose privately held
policy preferences differ strongly from those of the electorate are more likely
to lie.
It remains an open theoretical question whether voters' understanding of the
bias toward negative campaigning leads to an equilibrium which would
eliminate that bias entirely or merely reduce it. Given the general characteristics
of this class of models, we conjecture that a reduction rather than an elimina-
tion of bias is the likely theoretical result. Given that the negative bias is also
due in part to other failures in information markets and in information
processing as discussed in the introduction, it seems likely that persistence of
a bias toward negative campaigning is the most probable practical result, as it
could be sustained by, e.g., the existence of a significant minority of voters who
are somewhat inefficient in revising their priors.
12

5. Conclusions

It seems at times as if pleadings for a more virtuous government are only


slightly more common than surveys showing the public to rank the credibility
of politicians on roughly the same level as used car salesman and professional
wrestlers. This paper has been quit deliberately designed to do something
different - we are neither urging a more honest government (although that
might be something we would prefer) nor presenting empirical evidence of its
corruption. Rather, we argue that lying is a rational response to the peculiar
incentives faced by politicians. In particular, we have argued, first, that the
lack o f transferable property rights to political office makes it less costly for
the politician to lie. Second, we have claimed that if positive claims can be veri-
fied more easily than negative claims, there may be a natural bias in politics
towards negative campaigning.
Before finishing, we should make clear that we do not regard our claims as
conclusive - political rhetoric need not always be less honest or more negative
than commercial speech. Lying is, after all, wasteful and so there is potential
benefit to all interested parties in rules, habits or other institutions that lessen
deception. In particular, our model assumes naive voters who do not recognize
the asymmetries that we have identified. Clearly an interesting area of future
research is to modify our formulation to consider the consequences of more
sophisticated voters.
In this very simplified form, though, we think our analysis might help ex-
plain why things like ideology and " d e c e n c y " seem to be more important to
consumers in political markets than economic markets. 6 Consumers might not
really care whether the man who cooks their soup has a warm and loving fami-
ly, or is a mal-adjusted hermit. Indeed, they might not even care if he likes soup.
However, since the politician is not subject to the same market forces as the
soup manufacturer, voters might look for other signs of honesty. In particular,
they would like to know that the politician follows a personal ethic that values
truth (i.e., would feel guilty by lying), perhaps as evidenced by large and stable
family or membership in well-established church. Voters might also find com-
fort in a politician who follows a well-understood ideology, since this makes
it possible to test the veracity of the politician's claims against this ideology.
We will end by suggesting that many of the information assymetries dis-
cussed here in the context of political competition will exist in other settings
as well. In Section 2 we tried to point out that while we believe these problems
are more severe in political markets, they exist in economic markets as well.
But they will also be found in other settings as well. Consider, for example, two
employees competing for a promotion or two suitors competing for the same
persons affections. In both cases the rivals may have an incentive to exaggerate
their virtues and disparage their rivals. The ability of the potential employer
or lover to verify such claims will surely influence the types of lies.
13

Notes

1. Of course the property rights to many firms, especially small proprietorship and firms built
on the reputation of a particular individual, are not always easily transferred. See Dick and
Lott (1993) for a discussion.
2. In fact, this is only one example of how the lack of property rights to political office exacer-
bates the principal-agent relationship between politicians and constituents. For a review of
these arguments as well as some empirical analysis of the problem see Davis and Porter (1989)
or Lott and Davis (1992).
3. In extreme cases, the advertiser may adopt a very broad definition of substitute goods in order
to facilitate the negative comparison. In another recent TV campaign for instant oatmeal enti-
tled " W h a t ' s Hot, What's Not", children are informed that consuming the oatmeal will be
more pleasurable than either listening to music played on oversized banjos, folk dancing with
fat people in public squares, or riding a velocipede in formal dress.
4. To verify this result solve (2.1) for P'UP and substitute into 2.2 to obtain, upon cancelling
terms, (Vcp-vtp) = -(vcn-vtn).
5. Laffont and Tirole (1993: 630-634) consider the case of an official regulating public utilities
who is an agent of voting utility consumers and who is responsible for reporting the cost level
of the utility. If the utility makes cost-reducing investments, the voters would like the official
to report the cost reductions immediately so that price reductions can be implemented. The
firm, preferring to keep price high while lowering costs to obtain the benefits of regulatory lag,
may bribe the regulator to dishonestly report high cost to the consumers. In a framework simi-
lar to the one described above, Laffont and Tirole solve for the special case of a n = 1 while
adding appropriate additional structure and conclude that "career concerns may reduce the
government's incentive to collude (with regulated firms)".
6. Lott (1987), for example, has stressed the value of ideology in solving agency problems in polit-
ical markets.

References

Akerlof, G.A. (1970) The market for 'lemons': Quality uncertainty and the market mechanism.
Quarterly Journal o f Economics 84(August): 488-500.
Crawford, V.P. and Sobel, J. (1982) Strategic information transmission. Econometrica
50(November): 1431-1452.
Davis, M.L. and Porter, P.K. (1989) Measuring pure and apparent ideology in congressional
voting. Public Choice 60(2): 101-112.
Dick, A.R. and Lott, J.R. (1993) Reconciling voter behavior with term limits. Journal o f Public
Economics 50(October): 1-14.
Klein, B. and Leffler, K. (1981) The role of market forces in assuring contractual performance.
Journal o f Political Economy 89: 615-641.
Laffont, J.-J. and Tirole, J. (1993) A theory o f incentives in procurement and regulation. Cam-
bridge, MA: MIT Press
Lott, J.R. (1987) Political cheating. Public Choice 52(2): 169-187.
Lott, J.R. and Davis, M.L. (1992) A critical review and extension of the political shirking litera-
ture. Public Choice 74: 461-484.
McPherson, J. (1987) The battle cry o f freedom. New York; Oxford University Press.
Tullock, G. (1967) Toward a mathematics o f politics. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

S-ar putea să vă placă și