Sunteți pe pagina 1din 68

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9, 217-284

Printed in the United States of America

Precis of The Foundations of


Psychoanalysis: A Philosophical
Critique
Adolf Grunbaum
Departments of Philosophy, Psychiatry, and History and Philosophy of
Science, University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh, Pa. 15260

Abstract: This book critically examines Freud's own detailed arguments for his major explanatory and therapeutic principles, the
current neorevisionist versions of psychoanalysis, and the hermeneuticists' reconstruction of Freud's theory and therapy as an
alternative to what they claim was a "scientistic" misconstrual of the psychoanalytic enterprise. The clinical case for Freud's
cornerstone theory of repression - the claim that psychic conflict plays a causal role in producing neuroses, dreams, and bungled
actions - turns out to be ill-founded for two main reasons: (a) Even if clinical data were valid, the method of free association has failed
to support the psychoanalytic theory of unconscious motivation; (b) Clinical data tend in any case to be artifacts of the analyst's self-
fulfilling expectations, thus losing much of their evidential value. The hypothesis that psychoanalytic treatment is in reality a placebo
poses a serious challenge to the assumption that insight is a key causal factor when therapy is successful. This challenge has yet to be
met by psychoanalysts. Similar conclusions undermine the neorevisionist versions of psychoanalysis. The most influential
hermeneuticists, on the other hand, are shown to have imposed an alien philosophy on psychoanalysis, partly through their reliance
on gross misconceptions of the natural sciences. Karl Popper's criticism of the Freudian corpus as empirically untestable has
misjudged its evidential weaknesses, which are more subtle. If there exists empirical evidence for the principal psychoanalytic
doctrines, it cannot be obtained without well-designed extraclinical studies of a kind that have for the most part yet to be attempted.

Keywords: dream interpretation; explanation; Freud; hermeneutics; neurosis; philosophy of science; placebo; psychoanalysis;
psychopathology; repression

The Foundations of Psychoanalysis: A Philosophical Cri- weaknesses of Freud's clinical theory for a philosophical
tique (Grunbaum 1984; henceforth Foundations) offers a "counterattack" against those who criticize it as poor
philosophical assessment of the theoretical, epis- science. Quite recently Ricoeur (1981, p. 259) endorsed
temological, and heuristic grounds of Freud's monu- anew Habermas's complaint that Freud had fallen prey to
mental clinical theory.1 The appraisal concentrates on the a portentous "scientistic self-misunderstanding."
central arguments offered by the founding father, be-
cause his own reasoning, though deeply flawed, is consid-
erably more challenging than most of the defenses by his Habermas. According to Habermas, Freud incurred a
later exponents.2 The latter - orthodox and revisionist - "scientistic self-misunderstanding" when he attributed
are also subjected to critical scrutiny, with special atten- natural science status to his own clinical theory. As seen
tion to one such post-Freudian development, the so- by Habermas (1971, pp. 246-52), and also by George
called hermeneutic reconstruction of psychoanalysis. Klein (1976, pp. 42-49), this error arose from over-
generalizing a projected reduction of the clinical theory to
a neurobiologically inspired (i.e. scientific) "energy"
Introduction: Critique of the hermeneutic model of the mind. In my case against Habermas, the
conception of psychoanalytic theory and therapy following five considerations are developed in detail:
1. Habermas (and Klein) misrepresent the mature
During the past 15 years, the philosophers Paul Ricoeur Freud's notion of what is scientific as requiring reduction
(1970; 1974; 1981) and Jurgen Habermas (1970; 1971; to the laws of the physical sciences, thereby making the
1973), as well as the psychoanalysts George Klein (1976) scientific status of the clinical theory parasitic on Freud's
and Roy Schafer (1976), have put forward the so-called energy model. Such a reading is contradicted by explicit
hermeneutic reconstructions of the Freudian corpus in and definitive texts (S.E. 1925, 20:32-33; 1914, 14:77),
order to supplant Freud's own view of the psychoanalytic showing that during all but the first few years of his
enterprise as a natural science (S.E. 1933, 22:159; 1940, psychoanalytic career, Freud's view of what is scientific
23:158, 282). Such influential latter-day analysts as was based on methodological features, not on reducibility
Charles Brenner (1982, pp. 1-5) also espoused Freud's to physical laws.
scientific view. 2. According to Habermas, the dynamics of psycho-
Thus Ricoeur (1970, p. 358) tried to use the scientific analytic therapy exhibit a sort of causation not present in

J986 Cambridge University Press OUO-525X/86I020217-68I$06.00 217


Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
the causality of nature: The patient's psychoanalytic "self- Having run afoul of this commonplace, Ricoeur goes on
reflection" supposedly "dissolves," "overcomes," or to restrict the application of psychoanalytic theory to the
"subdues" the connection linking the neurosis to its cause patient's speech from the couch: Its subject matter, he
(Habermas 1971, pp. 256-57, 271; 1970, pp. 302, 304). tells us (1970, p. 275), is "analytic experience [in the
This is simply an error. There is no such causal dissolution dyadic clinical doctor-patient setting], insofar as the
according to psychoanalytic theory any more than there is latter operates in the field of speech." Again, the object of
in physical theory. psychoanalytic knowledge is "only that part of [analytic]
3. Important laws in electromagnetic theory and other experience which is capable of being said" (1981, p. 248).
branches of physics contradict Habermas's claim that law- From this, Ricoeur draws the following conclusions: (t)
based explanations in the natural sciences always rely on Unlike the behavioral "facts" of scientific psychology,
"context-free" or nonhistorical laws of nature. On the "facts in psychoanalysis are in no way facts of observable
basis of this ill-founded claim, Habermas asserts that behaviour" (1981, p. 248), and (it) the empirical scrutiny
there is a fundamental contrast between law-based expla- characteristic of the observational sciences cannot in-
nations in the natural sciences and those using psycho- trude on the hermeneutic construal of Freudian theory.
analytic generalizations, which are applied to individual The "facts" dealt with in psychoanalysis, we are told, "are
life histories in a personalized narrative (Habermas 1971, not verifiable by multiple independent observers" (1974,
pp. 272-73). p. 186). As partial grounds for (t), Ricoeur depicts Skin-
4. Habermas's thesis that the analyzed patient has a nerian behaviorism as the prototype for scientific psy-
cognitive monopoly on the proof or disproof of psycho- chology. Yet his use of behaviorism as the paradigm is
analytic hypotheses completely begs the question. Many incorrect and misleading, if only because cognitive psy-
Freudian assumptions are testable without any recourse chology, for example, takes mental states into considera-
at all to the subjective judgments of patients in the tion, no less than psychoanalysis does. [See also BBS
treatment setting. Yet Habermas insists that there is a special issue on the work of B. F. Skinner: BBS 7(4) 1984. ]
critical difference between the analytic patient's priv- Thus it emerges that Ricoeur's claims (i) and (it) are ill-
ileged knowledge and that of the objective observer in the founded, even if one does not challenge his restricting of
natural sciences. psychoanalytic theory to the dyadic "work of speech with
5. Habermas's 1971 book failed to take into account the patient" in the treatment setting. It is extensively
Pierre Duhem's insightful discussion of refutation in argued in Foundations, however, that this restriction is
physics, written half a century earlier. Thus uninformed, itself unwarranted. For example, it is unsound to infer
Habermas relied on an incorrect notion of how physical that dreamers' verbalized recollections of their dreams,
hypotheses are refuted, and posited a false contrast with rather than the dreams themselves, are the domain of
the logic of falsifying psychoanalytic interpretations. relevance for any theory of dreams, merely because these
Freud's "scientistic self-misunderstanding" (Haber- utterances are presumed to be the only available data for
mas 1971, Chapter 10) is claimed to be demonstrated by such a theory. Of course, Freud himself never made this
just the theses that Foundations shows to be untenable. inference, although he accepted its premise.
Habermas claims that this misunderstanding has had far- Ricoeur attempts in vain to strengthen his case on the
reaching consequences, if only because it prevented our basis of Freud's modification of the original seduction
recognizing that psychoanalysis was actually a depth- theory of hysteria. Freud had initially claimed that actual
hermeneutic mode of inquiry, the only tangible example childhood seductions were the causes of this neurosis, but
of a science incorporating methodical self-reflection, and later he was driven to substitute imagined seductions: "In
potentially a prototype for the other sciences of man.
the world of the neuroses it is psychical [as contrasted
with material] reality which is the decisive kind" (S.E.
Ricoeur. In his "hermeneutic" account, Ricoeur ignores 1917, 16:369; italics in original). But ascribing this causal
the fact that observations in physics are already theory- role to psychic reality does not help Ricoeur's her-
laden and are then further interpreted theoretically, a meneutic thesis. Even for imaginary seductions, there
point emphasized by Freud (S.E. 1915, 14:117). Ricoeur remains the burden of showing that they have patholog-
thereby creates a false contrast between the psycho- ical effects. Nowhere does Ricoeur provide even a hint of
analyst and the natural scientist in the garb of the behav- evidence that children who fantasize seduction develop
iorist: "Strictly speaking, there are no 'facts' in psycho- hysteria because of these fantasies. Gathering the requi-
analysis, for the analyst does not observe, he interprets" site evidence would require precisely the scientific meth-
(Ricoeur 1970, p. 365). In truth, well before the ap- ods rejected by the hermeneuticist.
pearance of Ricoeur's (1970) book, Popper (1959), Sellars Thus, just as the free association method cannot show
(1961), and Hanson (1958) - not to mention Kant with his that actual childhood seductions have caused hysteria, it
"percepts without concepts are blind" - had already is unable to show that imagined ones have done so.
discredited the crude observation-theory dichotomy that Indeed, Freud's substitution of fantasies for real seduc-
Ricoeur (1981, pp. 247-48) uncritically assumes for the tions only makes it harder to provide evidence of causa-
natural sciences. Thus, to the serious detriment of his tion. By the same token, the very quest for the veiled
case for hermeneutics, he is unaware that insofar as the "meaning" that psychoanalytic explanation is expected to
interpretative activity of any observer already implies disclose cannot succeed without relying on methods of
that there can be no "pure" data - i.e. "facts" to be causal inquiry and validation that hermeneuticists de-
explained - theory in the natural sciences is on the same clare inappropriate outside the natural sciences. A hydro-
epistemic footing as the clinical hypotheses generated by phobic's fear of drinking is connected in thematic content
analysts. to a repressed feeling of disgust for seeing a dog lapping

218 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
water from a person's glass. But no matter how strong following two sets of relations: (i) the way an effect
such a thematic affinity between a supposedly repressed manifests its cause and can hence serve as evidence for its
thought and a neurotic symptom, this "meaning connec- operation and (it) the way a linguistic symbol represents
tion" is not enough to show that the repressed thought is its referent semantically or designates its attributes. Fur-
the "hidden intentionality" behind the behavior. Thema- thermore, to be a vicarious outlet for an ungratified,
tic affinity itself is not sufficient for causation. Even hidden desire is plainly quite different from being any
analysts who do not consider themselves hermeneuticists kind of linguistic representation. In conflating the psy-
are susceptible to what might be dubbed "the thematic choanalytic and semantic uses of the term "symbol,"
affinity fallacy." Ricoeur has wrongly assimilated inferrability and
It would even be wrong to suppose that there is vicariousness, on the one hand, to semantic reference, on
typically thematic affinity between the ideational or affec- the other. His "semantics of desire" are themselves the
tive content of a repressed desire and the symptoms that result of a semantic error.
provide an outlet for it. As Breuer and Freud emphasized
at the outset (S.E. 1893, 2:5), "the typical hysterical Reasons versus causes. The thesis that, in psycho-
symptoms" or outcroppings of repressed ideation do not analysis, explanatory motives are reasons but not causes is
have any apparent thematic connection at all to their shown to be untenable on the following grounds:
presumed causes. And, as Freud stressed later, the 1. The thesis rests on a misconception of the relation of
products ("derivatives") of the dynamic unconscious that causal relevance between an antecedent X and an out-
are thrust back into consciousness usually have a rela- come Y; it overlooks that X may be physical, mental, or
tively distant topical connection to the repressed motif in psychophysical, so long as it makes a difference to the
which they presumably originated (S.E. 1915, 14:149- occurrence of Y, and affects the incidence of Y. But in
51, 190-91). psychoanalysis, explanatory unconscious motives are
The upshot of these observations is that, pace Ricoeur, held to have just that kind of relevance to the phenomena
neither the supposed causal role of seduction fantasies they explain. Thus, the hypothesized unconscious
nor the explanatory role of "meaning" exempts psycho- motives X can be (partial) causes of human conduct Y,
analysis from the modes of explanation and validation of whether or not psychoanalytic explanations conform to
natural science. the so-called practical syllogism (see below).
In a further futile effort to hermeneuticize psycho- 2. Explanations in terms of reasons normally do con-
analysis, Ricoeur offers a "semiotic" construal of the form to the practical syllogism: An agent carries out an
various outcroppings of repressed ideation as linguistic action A, because he desires to achieve a goal G, and also
communications, with the clinical theory providing a believes that doing A will achieve G. Thus the desire-
"semantics of desire." In psychoanalytic theory, both full- cum-belief set supplies "the reason" for doing A. And, in
fledged neurotic symptoms and minineurotic ones (e.g. virtue of (1), an explanatory reason for an action is causally
manifest dream contents, Freudian slips, jokes) are seen relevant to its performance. Hence such reasons are
as compromise-formations, products of the defensive causes.
conflict between the repressed ideas and the repressing 3. Though explanatory reasons do qualify as (partial)
ones (S.E. 1896, 3:170; 1917, 16:358-59). As such, symp- causes, it is shown that unconscious motives do not
toms have also traditionally been viewed as "symbols" of constitute such "reasons," because classical psycho-
what is repressed. But they are "symbols" in the nonse- analytic explanations typically do not even conform to the
mantic sense of being substitutive formations affording practical syllogism. It turns out that the explanatory
replacement satisfactions or outlets, not linguistic repre- motives do not include an unconscious belief that the
sentations of their hypothesized unconscious causes. explained behavior is a means of realizing the repressed
Vicarious wish-fulfillment in dreams, for example, hardly aim. Therefore, such behavior fails to be a species of
amounts to the semantic function of linguistic commu- intended action, although the impulse that instigates it
nication. As one might accordingly expect, Freud himself can be said to be a repressed aim or "intention."
tells us that "a dream does not want to say anything to Thus, when Freud maintained that both unconscious
anyone. It is not a vehicle for communication" (S.E. 1916, and conscious motives qualify as causes (S.E. 1909,
15:231). Ironically, Ricoeur (1970, p. 5) bases his seman- 10:199; 1910, 11:38), he certainly was not erroneously
tic construal on dreams. supposing that all causes had to be physical. Yet Klein
To take another example, when paranoiacs give verbal (1976, p. 56, also 12, 21) has claimed that bona fide
or nonverbal expression (e.g. by suspicious glances) to psychoanalytic explanations provide "reasons rather than
their delusions of persecution, this distrustful behavior is causes" for human conduct. In the same vein, Roy
taken as good psychoanalytic evidence of repressed ho- Schafer (1976, pp. 204-5) writes that the unconscious
mosexual longings. Even assuming that this interpreta- "reasons" fail to qualify as causes. Apparently, the expo-
tion is correct, however, the behavior still does not nents of the reasons versus causes thesis are, in effect,
constitute communicative acts that refer semantically to contradicting Freud's views rather than explicating them.
the unconscious sexual feelings. More generally, even . Overall, it is difficult to avoid the conclusion that the
when symptoms and other derivatives are actually ver- "humanistic" implementation of the Freudian enterprise
balized, and even if they are thematically connected to by a hermeneutic reconstruction is just an investigative
their unconscious causes, they do not linguistically desig- cul-de-sac and a negativistic ideological battle cry, hardly
nate the repressions that engender them (although they a promising prototype for the human sciences generally.
manifest them)! In view of the weakness of the arguments offered to
In sum, it is incorrect to assimilate to one another the hermeneuticize Freud, it is difficult to avoid making

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 219


Grtinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
conjectures about underlying ideology. Proponents seem nontestability that clinical data in particular cannot serve
to want (a) to free the study of human ideation from the as a basis for genuine empirical tests.
evidential burdens of the standard empirical sciences and [At the time that the writing of Foundations was com-
(b) to draw an ontological boundary line between mental pleted, Popper's 1983 book, Realism and the Aim of
and other natural processes so as to strengthen the case Science, was not yet available in print. I could not take
for (a). Their motivation is likely to be religious, political, this later discussion of psychoanalysis into account, but I
or the understandable desire to safeguard a lifetime will have the opportunity to do this in the section of my
professional investment in the practice of psychoanalytic Response that is devoted to Popper's accompanying
treatment. What other stakes could the proponents of commentary.]
hermeneutic reconstructions have? When Popper claims that his falsifiabiliry criterion
Freud's actual criteria for theory validation were essen- excludes psychoanalysis from the pantheon of the bona
tially those of hypothetico-deductive inductivism (S.E. fide empirical sciences, his principal concern is not with
1914, 14:77; 1915, 14:117; 1925, 20:32). He regarded Freudian theory as such, important though psycho-
adherence to these as the hallmark of the scientific status analysis is. In Popper's earlier works (1962, pp. 156-57,
he claimed for his theory. I undertook to appraise Freud's 255-58) we find psychoanalysis playing a role not so much
arguments for his clinical theory of personality and thera- as itself the prime target of his charge of nonfalsifiability,
py by those very standards. Hence the verdict I reached but rather as a centerpiece for his critique of inductivism
on that basis was not based on imposing some extraneous as a method of scientific theory-validation or a criterion of
methodological purism. Nor does my application of demarcation between science and nonscience. For, as I
Freud's avowed norm of scientific rationality to psycho- read Popper (pp. 33-38), inductivism does accept the
analysis imply that I consider it the criterion of demarca- claims of abundant empirical confirmation made by ad-
tion between science and nonscience. In short, I grant herents of Freud's theory, as well as by proponents of
Freud his own canons of scientific status in addressing the Adler's revisionist version of psychoanalysis and by con-
following key question: Did his clinical2 arguments vindi- temporary Marxists.
cate the knowledge claims he made for his evolving Indeed, Popper (pp. 35-37) seems to have become
theory in labeling it "scientific"? convinced of the unfalsifiability of psychoanalysis partly
My answer has two parts. First, the reasoning on which because he thought it was always confirmed inductively,
Freud rested the major hypotheses of his clinical edifice come what may. Thus, by 1919 he had persuaded himself
was fundamentally flawed, even if the validity of his both that inductivism does not have the methodological
clinical evidence were not in question. Second, as it resources to challenge the scientific status of psycho-
happens, far from deserving to be taken at face value, the analysis and that Freud's theory - as well as Adlerian
clinical data are themselves suspect; more often than not, revisionism and Marxism - was in fact empirically irre-
they may be the patient's responses to the suggestions futable. On this basis, Popper argued that the inductivist
and expectations of the analyst. method of confirmation and its criterion of demarcation
are unacceptably permissive.
Hence, the real philosophical villain of Popper's story
The clinical method of psychoanalytic
was inductivism rather than psychoanalysis or Marxism as
investigation: Pathfinder or pitfall? (Part I)
such, although he deplored the latter in their own right.
Is Freud's theory empirically testable? (Chapter 1) Having found to his dismay in 1919 that inductivism still
held sway as a criterion of demarcation, Popper used
Freud himself always claimed that the treatment setting psychoanalysis - Freudian and Adlerian - as the pi&ce de
is the arena par excellence for psychoanalytic research, resistance in his case against it. He therefore concluded:
experimental tests being essentially superfluous, if not "Thus there clearly was a need for a different criterion of
inappropriate. By contrast, Eysenck (1963) asserted that demarcation" (1962, p. 256). In short, psychoanalysis has
Freudian theory is experimentally testable but denies been and (at least as of 1974) remains Popper's prime
that well-designed clinical tests are feasible. Others, such illustration of the superiority of his falsifiability criterion.
as Glymour (1980), have contended that there are after all But if he were right that Freud's theory is untestable
viable strategies for supporting or refuting psychoanalytic altogether, then it would clearly be pointless to inquire
hypotheses on the couch. Glymour allowed for both whether this theory has been or can be tested clinically.
clinical and experimental tests. Thus, all of these writers Popper's challenge must accordingly be dealt with from
do agree that at least some parts of the Freudian corpus the outset. It turns out to be ironic that Popper should
are in fact testable by empirical findings of some sort. have chosen psychoanalytic theory as a prime illustration
Just this shared assumption of actual testability has of his thesis that inductive confirmations can easily be
repeatedly been denied by Popper, who has even re- found for nearly every theory if we look for them: It is
jected the logical possibility of testing psychoanalysis precisely Freud's theory that furnishes compelling evi-
empirically. As recently as when he replied to his critics dence against this caricature of the inductivist tradition
in 1974 (pp. 984-85), Popper reiterated his earlier claim (Foundations, p. 280).
that Freud's theory, as well as Adler's, is "simply non- Popper is concerned to contrast the scientific status of
testable, irrefutable. There was no conceivable human modern physics with the nonscientific or pseudoscientific
behaviour which would contradict them" (Popper 1962, character of psychoanalysis. He does so by claiming that
p. 37). Indeed, Popper emphasizes that "psychoanalysis the former is empirically falsifiable whereas the latter is
was immune [to falsification by any logically possible not. But before he can say that potential negative findings
empirical findings] to start with, and remained so" (1974, can refute physical theories, Popper must make use of
p. 986). It is then a mere corollary of this thesis of two important qualifications.

220 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
1. All reports of observations codifying contrary evi- Did Freud vindicate his method of clinical
dence in physics are fallible, if only because they them- investigation? (Chapter 2)
selves are already theory-laden; hence "falsifications" are
revokable. Despite Freud's basic reliance on clinical testing, he did
2. "Disregarding the possibility of immunizing strat- acknowledge the challenge that data from the couch may
agems" (Popper 1974, 11:1004), potential falsifying data be unreliable, because they are influenced by patients'
do exist in physics. But because of this ever-present conformity to the doctor's self-fulfilling expectations. For
logical possibility of resorting to immunization, it would, example, the patient may obligingly produce a
in my view, have been preferable if Popper had used the pseudomemory that would lend spurious confirmation to
term "disconfirmability," rather than "falsifiability" or the therapist's reconstruction of his patient's childhood.
"refutability." In discussing his views, I will use his In this way, the doctor can regiment the "memories"
locutions, however. recovered by free association. Even friendly critics such
It is important to note that, immediately after predicat- as Wilhelm Fliess have charged that analysts induce their
ing the falsifiability of Newtonian physics upon "dis- docile patients by suggestion to furnish the very re-
regarding" feasible immunizing strategies, Popper de- sponses needed to validate the psychoanalytic theory of
clares in the next sentence: "And this is the heart of the personality (Freud 1954, pp. 334-37). Freud himself
matter, for my criticism of Freud's theory was that it deemed it necessary to counter decisively this serious
simply does not have potential falsifiers" (1974, p. 1004). charge of spurious clinical confirmation. For if the pa-
But what is sauce for the goose is, I submit, sauce for the tient's responses are merely a result of brainwashing,
gander. Accordingly, it is to be understood that when I then Freudian analysis might have beneficial emotional
claim that Freud's clinical theory does have potential effects not because it allows the patient to acquire genu-
falsifiers, I do so subject to the same two qualifications on ine self-knowledge, but because of suggestion operating
which Popper relied in the case of physics. as a placebo under the guise of nondirective therapy. [See
Chapter 1 sets forth seven sets of grounds to refute also Rosenthal & Rubin: "Interpersonal Expectancy Ef-
Popper's charge that psychoanalytic theory is not falsifia- fects" BBS 1(3) 1978.]
ble. This charge, I must emphasize, is logically indepen- Freud had actually provided fuel for such criticism. In
dent of the sociological objection that Freudians are not order to overcome patients' fierce resistances to analysts'
responsive to criticism of their hypotheses. After all, a interpretations of their unconscious conflicts, he ex-
theory may well be invalidated by known evidence, even plained, analysts cannot rely on the patients' intellectual
as its true believers refuse to acknowledge this refutation. insight but must decisively enlist their need for their
That the recalcitrance of Freudians in the face of falsifying doctor's approval as a parental surrogate, the so-called
evidence, however scandalous, is not at all tantamount to positive "transference" feelings (S.E. 1917, 16:445; 1919,
the irrefutability of their theory should be especially 17:159). In fact, Freud himself points out that precisely
evident from some of Popper's other doctrines. As he tells this affectionate help-seeking subservience on the part of
us, theories, on the one hand, and the intellectual con- the patient "clothes the doctor with authority and is
duct of their protagonists, on the other, "belong to two transformed into belief in his communications and expla-
entirely different 'worlds'" (1974, 1:144, italics in origi- nations" (S.E. 1917, 16:445). Thus, at the end of his 1917
nal). Yet because Popper sometimes discusses them in lecture "Transference," and much more fully in the
the same breath, my response to his views on psycho- crucial following one, "Analytic Therapy," Freud square-
analysis takes both into account. ly addressed the serious possibility that suggestion is the
Foundations offers the following items in connection decisive agent in his therapy and at the same time, the
with the supposed unfalsifiability of Freudian theory: (1) fatal flaw of the psychoanalytic method of investigation.
Examples of Freudian causal hypotheses that are demon- As he put it there:
strably falsifiable and of predictions derivable from them You asked me why we do not make use of direct
that qualify as "risky" by Popper's standards; (2) Popper's suggestion in psychoanalytic therapy, when we admit
failure to furnish an actual proof of empirical irre- that our influence rests essentially on transference
futability, with reliance instead on a contrived illustration [which amounts to the utilization of the patient's per-
of psychoanalytic explanation involving two men and a sonal relationship to the analyst] - .that is, on sug-
drowning child (1962, p. 35; 1974, 11:985); (3) Freud's gestion; and you added a doubt whether, in view of this
own successive modifications of his evolving clinical theo- predominance of suggestion, we are still able to claim
ry (Fancher 1973; Sulloway 1979), conceptual changes that our psychological discoveries are objective [rather
that were neither immunizing maneuvers nor capricious, than self-fulfilling products of unintentional sug-
but rather reactions to seemingly adverse findings; (4) gestion]. I promised I would give you a detailed reply
Freud's explicit statement about the sort of evidence he (S.E. 1917, 16:448)
would acknowledge as a refuting instance for his hypoth- From the careful answer Freud goes on to give, I have
esized etiology of anxiety neurosis, as well as other teased out a central postulate on which he relies when it
documentation of sophisticated methodological tactics becomes one of the two premises of what I have dubbed
not vulnerable to Popper's wholesale criticism, even his "tally argument." As I read this bold premise, it is a
when Freud delayed for nearly a decade public acknowl- conjunction of the following two causally necessary
edgment of the 1897 collapse of his seduction theory of conditions:
hysteria; (5) Popper's total neglect of Freud's 1937 "Con-
structions in Analysis" paper, which is addressed to the 1. Only the psychoanalytic method of interpretation
issue of evading clinical falsifications on the principle and treatment can yield or mediate for the patient correct
"heads I win, tails you lose. " insight into the unconscious causes of his neurosis.
2. The patient's correct insight into the confiictual

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 221


Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
cause of his condition and into the unconscious dynamics 2. The clinical data furnished by successfully treated
of his character is in turn causally necessary for the neurotics do not result from self-fulfilling predictions.
durable cure of his neurosis. The patient's assent to his analyst's interpretations is
I refer to the conjunction of these two Freudian claims reliable and his own introspections can be believed, once
as his "Necessary Condition Thesis" or, for brevity, his repressions no longer distort his outlook.
"NCT." In view of its importance, I have also dubbed it 3. Only psychoanalytic treatment can produce genuine
"Freud's Master Proposition" (Griinbaum 1983, p. 17). It cures of neuroses (S.E. 1917, 16:458), hence it can take
is to be understood that Freud asserts it with respect to credit for the recoveries of its patients without statistical
the "psychoneuroses," as distinct from the so-called actu- comparisons with the results from untreated control
al neuroses. A "psychoneurosis" is a mental disorder groups or from controls treated by rival modalities (cf.
caused by repressed infantile experiences, whereas the S.E. 1917, 16:461-62).
etiologic factors in an "actual" neurosis are external ones Moreover, analytic therapy's successes are not placebo
in an adult's current life situation. effects, for if NCT is to be believed, the working through
Freud states his NCT more cryptically and immediate- of the patient's unconscious conflicts is the decisive
ly draws the corollary conclusion that the clinical data therapeutic factor (although the analyst's role as a parent-
from successfully analyzed patients are reliable after all: surrogate serves as an icebreaker). Freud did recognize
After all, his conflicts will only be successfully solved that the patient's so-called transference attachment to his
and his resistances overcome if the anticipatory ideas doctor plays a catalytic role in the earlier stages of treat-
[i,e. psychoanalytic interpretations] he is given tally ment (S,E, 1926, 20:190), Yet he evidently singled out
with what is real in him. Whatever in the doctor's the patient's correct causal insight as the one quintessen-
conjectures is inaccurate drops out in the course of the tial ingredient "which distinguishes [the therapeutic dy-
analysis [footnote omitted]; it has to be withdrawn and namics of] analytic treatment from any kind of treatment
replaced by something more correct. (S.E. 1917, by suggestion" (S.E. 1914, 12:155-56; cf. also 1917,
16:452) 16:450-52).
More explicitly, if NCT is to be believed, the disclosure of As long as Freud believed in the validity of his NCT and
the patient's hidden conflicts is indispensable to his cure the genuineness of his cures, he could have confidence in
and will occur only if incorrect analytic interpretations - the three theses just formulated. The NCT, however, still
spuriously confirmed by the patient's contaminated re- requires successful treatment outcomes in order to be
sponses - have been discarded in favor of correct ones. interpreted as a justification for making causal inferences
Such interpretations will then presumably have derived on the basis of free associations. Thus, in Freud's tally
from clinical data not distorted by the patient's com- argument, therapeutic success was needed to justify even
pliance with his doctor's subtly communicated expecta- those hypotheses that, by themselves, pertain neither to
tions. Though the data are initially contaminated by the dynamics (causal factors) nor to the outcome of psy-
suggestion, they can be selectively sorted as they accu- choanalytic treatment.
mulate so as to discard the unreliable ones. Given that the empirical tenability of the NCT premise
In short, Freud postulated his NCT, asserted that his is the pivot on which the tally argument turns, what clues
therapy achieves genuine cures, and then went on to use does Freud give us as to the evidence that prompted him
these two risky claims to vouch for the trustworthiness to hold this premise until at least 1917? Apparently, he
(i.e. the reliability and validity) of clinical data from felt driven to postulate it to account for the observed
neurotic patients whose analyses had presumably been patterns of failure and success in treatment. Before a
successful. In view of his use of the phrase "tally with decade had elapsed, however, even Freud's own evi-
what is real," I have introduced the label "tally argu- dence conflicted with the claim that the cure of a neurosis
ment" for the argument whose two premises I have just depends on the patient's correct insight into its causes.
stated and whose conclusions I am developing. This Thus, by 1926, he conceded that his type of treatment was
designation has since been adopted by other writers. not indispensable and merely expedited recoveries that
Indeed, if one grants Freud the truth of his NCT, and were in the offing anyway (S.E. 1926, 20:154). The
the finding that there are successfully analyzed ("cured") possibility of such spontaneous remission contradicts
patients, then a whole series of major conclusions can be NCT, which can then no longer be used to justify count-
drawn. Each of these consequences, if true, contributes ing even spectacular therapeutic successes as support for
to answering the objection that suggestion contaminates causal inferences.
clinical data and is the real cause of any therapeutic Then in 1937 Freud went on to report that a satisfactory
success. psychoanalysis will not even prevent the recurrence of
These conclusions of the tally argument include: the problem for which the patient was treated, let alone
1. If a patient has been cured, the causal interpreta- immunize him against the outbreak of a different one
tions his doctor gave him (at least in the later stages of the (S.E. 1937, 23:216-53). Thus, far from holding out hope
analysis) must have been correct or close to the mark. for cures, Freud essentially confined the prospects of
Hence the collective success of psychoanalytic treatment psychoanalysis to palliation. Evidently, far from continu-
is evidence for the truth of the Freudian theory of ing to claim that there was empirical support for the two
personality, including the specific causes to which it premises of his tally argument in his later years, Freud
attributes the psychoneuroses, and even its general hy- himself gradually renounced or significantly weakened
potheses about psychosexual development. Further- both of them.
more, Freudian analysis of the unconscious by means of As if this were not enough, in recent decades, in
free association is validated as an investigative method by comparative studies of treatment outcome from rival
its therapeutic success. therapies, psychoanalytically oriented psychotherapy has

222 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Griinbauiri: Foundations of psychoanalysis
not been found to be superior to any of the other therapies he wrote that evidence of therapeutic gain was from the
that exceed the spontaneous remission rate for untreated start intrinsic to the clinical validation of the psycho-
controls. Adequate comparative studies for long-term analytic theory of the unconscious: "In psycho-analysis
psychoanalysis still remain to be carried out, but it is not a there has existed from the very first an inseparable bond
promising sign that recent comparative investigations of between cure and research" (S.E. 1926, 20:256). Indeed,
psychotherapy do not find professional psychotherapy we shall now see that, in the cathartic method, the
superior to treatments designed to be placebos (Prioleau, dependence of the causal inferences on treatment out-
Murdock & Brody 1983). These results cast some further come was crucial: It was therapeutic success that enabled
doubt on NCT, which implies that only analytic therapy Breuer and Freud to conclude that repressed traumatic
can cause genuine cures of neuroses. experience was necessary to cause hysteria.
Yet if analytic treatment is not superior to its rivals in Thus, psychoanalytic causal hypotheses that do not
the pertinent diagnostic categories, it becomes quite themselves pertain either to the dynamics or the outcome
reasonable - though not compelling - to interpret its of analytic therapy (e.g. the trauma theory of hysteria)
therapeutic achievements as placebo effects. If so, any have nonetheless been parasitic on therapeutic results,
success of psychoanalysis is not produced by the patient's since Freud used such results partly to validate making
acquiring self-knowledge after all. In this vein, Jerome inferences from clinical data at all, and partly to guide and
Frank (1973) has contended that both analysts and their support the specific inferences themselves.
rivals heal neurotics by being supportive, not by uncover-
ing their repressions. Indeed, Frank's hypothesis even
allows rival therapies to have differential efficacy through Appraisal of Freud's arguments for the repression
different degrees of placebo effect. To be sure, it is still etiology of the psychoneuroses (Chapter 3)
arguable that improvements after psychoanalytic treat- The causal and explanatory significance of unconscious
ment are not placebo effects. But because, as some noted processes in psychoanalytic theory rests on two funda-
analysts have conceded, "all-pervading" improvements mental inductive inferences. These were made by Freud
or even cures can be produced by rival treatments such as in collaboration with his senior mentor Josef Breuer. As
behavior therapy, and also by extraclinical life events we are told in their joint "Preliminary Communication"
(Malan 1976, pp. 172-73, 269, 147), Freud's NCT has of 1893 (S.E. 1893, 2:6-7), they began with an observa-
become untenable. tion made after having treated hysterical patients cathar-
The collapse of the NCT completely undercuts the tically with hypnosis. In the course of the treatment it had
pivotal therapeutic argument given by the mature Freud turned out that, for each symptom, the victim had re-
for the evidential value of the clinical data generated by pressed the memory of a trauma that had closely pre-
the psychoanalytic method. As Chapter 10 shows, with- ceded its onset and was somehow thematically connected
out the tally argument, Freud's appeal to cross-cor- to it (see "thematic affinity fallacy" in earlier section on
roboration by converging clinical findings fails, because Ricoeur). For example, Breuer's pioneering patient Anna
each corroborating piece is secured by the free-associa- O., who had a phobia for drinking liquids, had repressed
tion method whose validity is in question. Moreover, no the sight of a dog drinking water from a friend's glass,
empirically viable substitute for the NCT capable of which had disgusted her. Besides repressing this trau-
supporting Freud's conclusions seems to be in sight. matic memory, the patient had also suppressed the affect
Without a substitute for the NCT there appears to be no induced by the trauma. In the case of each symptom, our
way to free clinical data from the possibility of contamina- two therapists tried to lift the repression of the trauma
tion by suggestion. Yet after Freud gave up the NCT, he and to release the pent-up affect. When their technique
seems to have forgotten that this left the evidential value succeeded in both respects, they observed, a dramatic
of clinical data in serious doubt, and he continued to rest (and apparently permanent) disappearance of the
his case on clinical findings (S.E. 1926, 20:254; 1917, symptom.
16:255). Impressed by this outcome, Breuer and Freud formu-
The emphasis in Part I was on Freud's unsuccessful lated their first major causal hypothesis: The improve-
effort to neutralize doubts about the evidential value of ments observed after treatment were caused by the
clinical data. Part II shows that even if clinical evidence cathartic lifting of the repressions. But before the found-
could be taken at face value, Freud's principal clinical ers of psychoanalysis attributed the improvement to the
arguments for his entire cornerstone theory of repression lifting of the repression, they had considered the rival
still turn out to be fundamentally flawed. hypothesis that it was actually caused by the patient's
expectations of relief from his symptom rather than by his
achieving insight into his repression. In this perspective,
The cornerstone of the psychoanalytic edifice: Is the search for insight is only a treatment ritual serving to
the Freudian theory of repression well founded? strengthen the patient's therapeutic expectations. Breuer
(Part II) and Freud believed they could rule out this rival hypoth-
esis, which I call "the hypothesis of placebo effect"
In Part I, the focus was on Freud's appeal to therapeutic (Grunbaum 1981; 1986).
success as his evidence for claiming that his clinical Breuer and Freud pointed out that symptoms had been
method did not lead merely to self-fulfilling predictions. removed, one at a time, such that any one symptom
Freud relied on therapeutic success, however, not only to disappeared only after the lifting of a particular repression
validate (via the NCT) the data obtained by free associa- (S.E. 1893, 2:7). I suggest, however, that even such
tion, but also as a basis for inferring the causal hypotheses separate symptom removals need not be caused by the
of his theory of psychopathology in the first place. In 1926 lifting of repressions; instead, they may be placebo effects

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 223


Grunbaurn: Foundations of psychoanalysis
after all, generated by the patient's awareness that the repressions of adult traumas was therapeutically effec-
therapist was trying to uncover an episode thematically tive. Freud began to be haunted by the triumph of the
connected to the symptom. Thus, it was presumably placebo hypothesis over his (and Breuer's) therapeutic
communicated to the patient that his doctor believed that hypothesis. As he recognized, the vicissitudes of his
recalling the episode might help to eliminate the symp- personal relations to the patient were highly correlated
tom. Breuer and Freud do not tell us why the likelihood with the pattern of symptom relapses and intermittent
of a placebo effect is lower when several symptoms are remissions. In his own view, this correlation "proved that
wiped out than when only one symptom is involved. As the personal emotional relation between doctor and pa-
evidence against the placebo hypothesis it would have tient was after all stronger than the whole cathartic
been essential to compare treatment outcome with the process" (S.E. 1925, 20:27). But without the therapeutic
results from a suitable control group whose repressions support for the causal role of repression, the very cor-
were not lifted. If that control group fared equally well nerstone of psychoanalysis was completely undermined.
therapeutically, treatment gains from psychoanalysis Hence at that point, the new clinical psychoanalytic
would then presumably be placebo effects, because they structure tumbled down and lay in shambles. So also did
would not have been caused specifically by psycho- free association as a method of establishing causation.
analytic insight. Hence there existed no adequate evi- Nonetheless, Freud was undaunted. He took courage,
dence that lifting repressions caused symptoms to because he thought that, in a new sexual version, the
disappear. etiologic repression hypothesis could be rehabilitated on
Yet Breuer and Freud did believe at the time that their secure therapeutic foundations after all. The elimination
therapeutic results had ruled out the placebo hypothesis of adult repressions had been a therapeutic failure. He
and they accordingly attributed the gains made by their conjectured, however, that uncovering much earlier
hysterics to the resurrection of buried painful memories. childhood repressions with sexual content might elimi-
They also thought that this hypothesized process of pro- nate hysteria, and he hypothesized that the patient's free
ducing therapeutic success was evidence that an original associations would indicate an early sexual repression as
act of repression was necessary to cause the neurosis, and the cause of hysteria (S.E. 1896, 3:194-99). As he reports,
continuing repression was necessary to maintain it. It the very early repressions that then emerged had sexual
then followed that the removal of the repression would themes.
eliminate the neurosis. Freud now rejected the placebo hypothesis by invok-
Notice that the improvement itself was not what justi- ing NCT, as we saw. But, as the summary of Chapter 2
fied inferring that repression had caused the symptom: It made clear, his attempt to provide therapeutic support
was the causal attribution of the improvement to the for the new childhood sexual hypothesis in 1917 fared no
lifting of the repression. Thus, without relying on what better empirically than his and Breuer's original appeal to
they assumed to be the causal dynamics that produced cathartic success in the mid-l890s. (Freud had disavowed
their therapeutic results, Breuer and Freud could never Breuer's nonsexual etiologic hypotheses as clinically du-
have interpreted these clinical data as evidence that bious in 1896.) Nor has there been any other therapeutic
repression was a cause of hysteria. Yet even if the validation. [See my response to Cioffi's accompanying
therapeutic gains had been caused by lifting repressions, commentary for further details.]
there would only be grounds for attributing the mainte- Let me caution against a possible serious misunder-
nance of the symptoms to those repressions, not their standing, however. Like Freud, the vast majority of his
initial formation. Moreover, this conclusion still requires followers continue to maintain that free associations are
the qualification that either the cognitive repression or crucial for the validation of both their etiologic hypoth-
the affective suppression of a trauma is the required cause eses about the causes of neuroses and the psychoanalytic
(Foundations, pp. 180-81). theory of dreams and slips. These advocates cannot dis-
Freud soon replaced Breuer's hypnotic technique by pense with a therapeutic foundation. For my own part,
free association, believing that the new method retrieved however, I find it unwarranted to use free association to
repressed traumatic experiences, and concluding that validate causal inferences. I therefore see no reason to
free associations not only recover repressed memories, assign any privileged role to therapeutic results among
but can establish that the repression of the latter caused possible tests of psychoanalytic hypotheses. For example,
the neurosis in question. In this way, Freud elevated free Freud's 1915 theory of paranoia could be tested epidemi-
association to the status of a specific causal litmus test: ologically without any recourse to therapeutic data [see
There was no other justification. In other words, the my response on issues of falsifiability.]
hypothesis that therapeutic success is caused by the Freud did not limit his reliance on free association to
removal of repressions is to this day the sole justification research on the causes of neurotic symptoms. When he
for assuming that free associations show repressions to be found that his patients reported their dreams while free
causes; hence there is nothing left when Freudians dis- associating to their neurotic symptoms, he concluded that
claim the therapeutic efficacy of their treatment. "manifest" dream contents are produced very much the
Soon after Freud began to practice without Breuer, it way neurotic symptoms are (S.E. 1900, 4:101). He saw
became evident that they had been too hasty in rejecting such symptoms as vicarious gratifications and outlets, or
the rival hypothesis of placebo effect. The remissions "compromises between the demands of a repressed im-
achieved by further patients Freud himself treated ca- pulse and the resistance of a censoring force in the ego"
thartically did not turn out to be durable. The pattern of (S.E. 1925, 20:45). Thus, he made the extrapolation that
relapses, additional treatment, temporary remissions, repression is causally necessary for both neurotic symp-
and further relapses made it doubtful that removing the toms and dream production. He accordingly enlarged the

224 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Grtinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
scope of the free-association method from research on the down to 'chance' (S.E. 1901, 6:239). A further necessary
causes of neurosis (aimed at therapy) to research on the condition is that the slip be caused by a repression in the
unconscious causes of dreaming (S.E. 1900, 4:101, 5:528). sense of being a compromise, resulting from the conflict
The extrapolation was also extended, mutatis mutan- between a repressed motive and a conscious intention.
dis, to slips and bungled actions. Here too Freud used Typically, the repressed motive is one of so-called "un-
free association not merely heuristically, as a means of pleasure" (Strachey's translation of Unlust) such as pain,
generating causal explanations of slips, but also as a basis distress, aversion, or moral censorship. Thus, Freud's
for validating the explanatory hypotheses. For example, theory explains slips "in which the parapraxis produces
he conceived of a slip of the tongue as a compromise nothing that has any sense of its own'Tor either the
between a repressed motive that crops up in the form of a subject who commits the slip or for others (S.E. 1916,
disturbance, on the one hand, and the conscious inten- 15:41). Plainly, slips resulting from conscious or "pre-
tion to make a certain utterance, on the other. conscious" motives are not Freudian, though Freud does
The theoretical extrapolation to dreams and slips of give examples of them for the purpose of comparison
course inherited the problem of the original theory of (S.E. 1916, 15:40-55).
neurotic symptoms, namely, the collapse of the The mere statement of what is meant by the term
therapeutic support. But even if that support had actually "Freudian slip" does not entail that there do exist slips
turned out to be empirically viable, the extrapolations with the requisite property of being caused by a re-
would have been unjustified because they lacked any pressed motive and being laden with some negative
therapeutic base or other supporting evidence of their affect. The burden of the psychoanalytic theory of para-
own. Freud provided no evidence that the permanent praxes is to furnish evidence that there actually are such
lifting of a repression to which he had attributed a slip slips. My main aim in the chapter is to examine whether
would be "therapeutic" in the sense of enabling the Freud's arguments were able to show this.
person to correct the slip or to avoid repeating it. Thus the A certain memory lapse in the recitation of a Latin
two extrapolations had no independent support. quotation is cited in the psychoanalytic literature as a
Chapter 3 concludes with an important caveat. Plainly, typical example of a Freudian slip. A young man forgot
the very occurrence of repression - in the psychoanalytic the Latin word aliquis ("someone") in his recitation of a
sense of banishing a thought from consciousness or deny- line from Virgil's Aeneid. The full line reads: "Exoriare
ing it entry (S.E. 1915, 14:147) - is a necessary condition aliquis nostris ex ossibus ultor" ("Would that someone
for the causal role that Freud attributed to it. If repression arise from our bones as an avenger"). The young man, an
does not even exist, it can hardly cause other phenomena. Austrian Jew - hereafter "AJ" - used the passage to
Yet it must not be overlooked that the mere existence of convey his resentment of religious discrimination against
repression as a psychological phenomenon (which was him. Freud supplied the missing word. Then AJ's associa-
conjectured before Freud by Herbart and Schopenhauer) tions issuing from this word - interspersed with some of
is not sufficient to demonstrate that it causes neurotic Freud's interjections - revealed, in due course, that he
symptoms, dreams, or slips. had harbored a repressed fear. He suspected that an
Paul Kline (1981, pp. 196, 208, 436), Seymour Fisher Italian girlfriend had become pregnant by him. Freud
(1982, p. 680), as well as others (Erdelyi & Goldberg then informed him that this repressed anxiety had "unde-
1979), gloss over the large gap between merely showing niably" produced his aliquis lapse, whereas the subject
that repression exists and providing evidence that it has was doubtful that his worry - though genuine - had had
the causal role that Freud attributed to it. These investi- any causal bearing on his forgetting. Freud was convinced
gators use the phrase "theory of repression" in a highly that AJ's repressed wish not to have any progeny from his
ambiguous way. It can denote either the hypothesis of sexual liaison had interfered with his Latin rendition of
bare existence or the far stronger assertion of a multiple his desire to have descendants who would avenge the
causal role. [My responses to Kline's and Erdelyi's com- adversity suffered by the Jews.
mentaries will develop this point.] In a detailed examination of the aliquis slip, I argue that
far from furnishing evidence for the existence of bona fide
Freudian slips, it serves to exhibit the weakness of the
Examination of the psychoanalytic theory of slips - of empirical basis of the psychoanalytic repression model of
memory, the tongue, ear, and pen (Chapter 4) parapraxes. The grounds for this unfavorable conclusion
Freud referred to slips generically in German as include the following: There is no justification for drawing
Fehlleistungen, which means "misbegotten perfor- a causal connection between the fear of pregnancy and
mances" or "bungled actions." His translator James the memory lapse merely on the basis of the thematic
Strachey coined the neologism "parapraxes" to render connection between the content of the repressed wish
the German term. The category "slips" does not include and the desire expressed by the Latin phrase. As argued
every failure of memory, speech, or action, however. It is earlier, thematic affinity alone is not evidence for a causal
restricted to errors one does not make normally or connection; there is need for further evidence that a
habitually. thematically connected repression actually caused the
memory lapse. Moreover, in typical parapraxes, the the-
There are two necessary conditions that must be fulfill-
matic affinity is considerably more tenuous than in the
ed by any slip if it is also to qualify as a Freudian slip in the aliquis example. In fact, it is always possible tofindsome
technical, rather than the colloquial, sense. As Freud thematic thread, however farfetched, connecting any
tells us: "If we perceive the parapraxis at all, we must not given lapse to some repression or other. Thus, even if
be aware in ourselves of any motive for it. We must rather strong thematic affinity alone did implicate a repressed
be tempted to explain it by 'inattentiveness,' or to put it

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 225


Grunbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
cause, it would not be present in typical parapraxes. The (S.E. 1900, 4:chap. 2). It was his attempt to interpret the
aliquis example is not representative. Irma dream which begat a "eureka" experience yielding
Doubts about whether a given repression is really the the "secret" of all dream formation (Freud 1954, p. 322):
cause of a slip cannot be countered by pointing, as Freud The dream "content was the fulfillment of a wish and its
did (S.E. 1916, 15:50), to the introspective confirmation motive was a wish" (S.E. 1900, 4:119; italics omitted).
of the subject who made the slip. Even if the person who In his 1895 "Project," Freud proposed a neurological
"slipped" were not under the suggestive, intimidating rationale for the "secret." That neurobiological account,
influence of the analyst, how could he possibly know any and its clinical notion of wish fulfillment, have been
better than the rest of us that the unconscious fear in challenged by Hobson and McCarley in two influential
question had actually caused his slip? The case against papers (Hobson & McCarley 1977; McCarley & Hobson
Freud's appeal to introspective confirmation is well sup- 1977). As they point out, during the past 80 years various
ported. There is substantial experimental evidence from findings have undermined the concepts of neuronal func-
cognitive psychology that subjects do not have knowledge tion and of the energy economy of the brain out of which
of the causes of their own behavior (Nisbett & Ross 1980). Freud's account was built. They conclude that recent
The important conclusion is this: If any slips are actu- neurophysiological findings have largely supplanted
ally caused by repressions, Freud gives us no good reason Freud's psychological theory of dreaming as wish-fulfill-
to think that his clinical methods could identify and ment by providing a better explanation of dream produc-
empirically confirm their causes as such, no matter how tion. Yet, they do not claim to have refuted the purely
interesting the elicited "free" associations might other- psychological aspect of the theory.
wise be. This conclusion seems unavoidable, even if one Chapter 5 critically analyzes Freud's psychological
were to grant that the analyst does not influence the theory of dreams with reference to his treatment of the
subject's "free" associations to the content of a slip. (The Irma dream. His argument was that, in the case of Irma,
experimental psychologist Motley [1980] claims to have free association yields wish motives that, from the view-
found experimental support for the psychoanalytic theory point of commonsense psychology, have clearly given rise
of speech errors. I argue that his ingenious experiments, to that particular dream. Freud is then prepared to base
valuable though they are, do not provide evidence for or his general theory of dreams as wish fulfillments on the
against the Freudian theory of slips of the tongue.) results from the method that he claims to have validated
Thus far it has been granted, for argument's sake, that by his analysis of Irma (S.E. 1900, 4:121). I argue,
the analyst does not influence the patient's free associa- however, that Irma fails to validate Freud's method of
tions, but in the remainder of this chapter, several sorts of dream interpretation or to support the hypothesis that
questions are raised: Does free association indeed bring repressed infantile wishes cause dreams.
out repressed wishes, or anger, guilt, fear, and so on, Though touted as "the dream specimen of psycho-
without contamination by other influences? If uncon- analysis" (Erikson 1954), Irma no more qualifies as a
scious thoughts surface, by what criteria does the analyst paradigm for Freud's theory of dreams than the aliquis
decide when, during the investigation of parapraxes and slip does for his theory of parapraxes. First, in this dream
dreams, to call a halt to the flow of associations? Presum- analysis, free association does not play the role it is
ably if the intelligent and imaginative patient is permitted claimed to play in revealing repressions. Moreover, Irma
to free associate in this way long enough, his unfettered does not illustrate the causal role of a repressed wish
ruminations will in due course yield almost any kind of (infantile or otherwise). At best, the Irma dream is a
thematic content of which he had (at least recently) not pedagogical preparation for psychoanalytic dream theo-
been conscious: thoughts about death, God, and indeed ry, rather than a representative specimen. At worst, it is a
cabbages and kings. But, if so, how does the analyst avoid piece of salesmanship, offering a snare and a delusion to
a selection bias in the face of the thematic variety of the the unwary. Erikson's (1954) attempt to give Irma the
associations, particularly since imposing some limit on infantile motivational underpinning required by
duration is unavoidable? orthodox doctrine does nothing to alter this verdict.
One of the answers is drawn from writings of the analyst The chapter's main findings are that Freud's theory of
Judd Marmor (1970), who summarizes experimental dreams is at best ill-founded and that there are even two
studies indicating how compliant patients are, even un- independent clinical arguments implying that it is false.
der free association, and how they thereby render clinical
hypotheses self-fulfilling.
Appraisal of Freud's further arguments for the
The chapter concludes with a discussion of how some
emergence of unadulterated repressions under
analysts coax their patients to fulfill prior theoretical
expectations (e.g. penis envy in women), whereas other "free" association (Chapter 6)
analysts deplore this practice without providing a recipe The doubts that have been raised so far concerning the
for successfully avoiding it. psychoanalytic accounts of slips and dreams include the
failure of free association to ensure that repressed idea-
tion emerges without contamination by suggestion. Al-
Repressed Infantile wishes as instigators of all dreams:
ways mindful of this problem, Freud kept offering further
Critical scrutiny of the compromise model of
reasons for his belief that free association "guarantees to a
manifest dream content (Chapter 5)
great extent that . . . nothing will be introduced into it
In 1895, Freud had a dream - the "Irma Injection by the expectations of the analyst" (S.E. 1925, 20:41). In
Dream" (S.E. 1950, 1:340-42) - which was destined to this vein, he assures us of the analyst's ability to dis-
become the "Specimen Dream" of his clinical theory tinguish the patient's bona fide memories from imagined

226 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Grtinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
ones: "Any danger of falsifying the products of the pa- therapeutic achievements. Hence one could by now ask
tient's memory by suggestion can be avoided by prudent impatiently: Why could Freud not dispense with
handling of the technique; but in general the arousing of therapeutic arguments altogether and rely instead on
resistances is a guarantee against the misleading effects of other sorts of clinical evidence (see footnote 2) to provide
suggestive influence" (S.E. 1923, 18:25). This is the myth support for his theory of psychopathology? Chapter 8
that analytic interpretations are nondirective and that develops the reply that such attempts have been just as
analysts are mere catalysts for the emergence of uncon- unsuccessful as therapeutic validation by considering
taminated repressions. Clark Glymour's recent account (1980) of testability on
There is empirical evidence against the view that the couch. Here I will summarize only one of several
psychoanalytic treatment is a valid means of gaining reasons given in Foundations for this conclusion.
access to memories. Loftus (1980) has shown that (1) Freud conjectured that the development of a neurosis
human memory is to a remarkable extent malleable (as N depends not only on an individual's exposure to patho-
illustrated by a pseudomemory from Jean Piaget's early genic experiences P, but also on his hereditary vul-
life); (2) there is considerable interpolation, reconstruc- nerability: P is necessary but not sufficient to cause JV.
tion, and distortion of memories by theoretical beliefs or One can hence retrodict that anyone afflicted with N has
expectations; and (3) under the influence of leading ques- suffered P. It has been suggested that in Freud's Rat Man
tions, there is a strong tendency to fill memory gaps with case, for example, clinical evidence would have sup-
confabulated material. ported this causal necessity hypothesis by confirming the
Nonveridical memories seem to be most likely with occurrence of the retrodicted childhood experience P
just those responses that are supposed to lay bare repres- (Glymour 1980, p. 272).
sions and disguised defenses after resistances have been Suppose for argument's sake that in his analysis the Rat
overcome. Yet Freud particularly emphasized such data Man had reported remembering the traumatic sexual
in the validation of his theory of repression. To say that event retrodicted by Freud. Assume further that one can
the contamination of clinical data cannot be eliminated trust so early a memory under the suggestive conditions
without recourse to extraclinicalfindingsis not, of course, of an analysis. It is then evident that confirming the prior
to say that every analytic interpretation to which a patient occurrence of the trauma does not show that it was a cause
agrees under the influence of the analyst is false. Howev- of the Rat Man's obsessions. Surely the mere fact that an
er, in the analytic setting one cannot identify which event is traumatic does not indicate a causal role in a
clinical data are valid. neurosis. The human condition would be much worse
than it already is if every psychic blow gave rise to a
neurosis. Yet prominent psychoanalysts have reasoned
Remarks on post-Freudian defenses of the fundamental that the causal relevance of P to N is supported by the
tenets of psychoanalysis (Chapter 7) mere fact that those who are beset by N and suffered P fit
Is the present critique of the basic pillars of psycho- Freud's retrodiction (Waelder 1962, pp. 625-26). Such
analysis anachronistic? Does it not focus on Freud's an inference is no better than post hoc ergo propter hoc.
reasoning while disregarding the specific modifications Two results emerge: (i) The analytic setting appears
and elaborations by those post-Freudians whose doc- unable to yield evidence to support the inference that the
trines are recognizably psychoanalytic (in content rather retrodicted P was a cause of N, and (it) its retrospective
than only in name)? The answer is that the unfavorable methods cannot even verify that P occurred. To my
conclusions of Parts I and II are just as applicable to the knowledge, apart from the sorts of arguments I have
currently fashionable revisionist versions of psycho- examined, there is no other clinical support (either
analysis that go under the names of Kohutian "self- therapeutic or nontherapeutic) for Freud's theory of sexu-
psychology" and of "object relations theory." Insofar as al repression as the cause of the neuroses. I conclude that
these post-Freudian theories are indeed psychoanalytic, the sexual version of Freud's theory of psychopathology
they do subscribe to some version of the theory of has no more clinical support than Breuer's nonsexual
repression. They also rely on free association to find the version.
unconscious causes of behavior, using the lifting of re-
pressions as one means of therapy (Eagle 1983a).
How, for example, can Kohut claim stronger clinical Epilogue (Part III)
validation for his pre-Oedipal variety of unconscious The method of free association and the future appraisal
cause than Freud can for the sexual ones? Eagle (1983a;
of psychoanalysis (Chapter 9)
1984a) has argued that the causal and therapeutic claims
of self-psychology and of object relations theory rest on In this Chapter I welcome the analyst Eissler's (1969)
even more dubious bases than do Freud's corresponding refreshing anticipation of the conclusion that the future
hypotheses. Hence the neorevisionist work does not validation or discontinuation of Freudian theory will
answer the objections I have raised against orthodox come largely from extraclinical findings. However, de-
psychoanalysis. spite his suggestion that we expand the investigative
horizons of Freud's theory well beyond the clinical set-
ting, the lesson that Eissler derives from the limitations of
Can the repression etiology of psychoneurosis be clinical findings does not go nearly far enough. Accepting
tested retrospectively? (Chapter 8) the validity of Freud's method of free association, he
As noted in prior chapters, Freud's clinical support for his glosses over the serious problems of clinical testing set
causal inferences has ultimately been predicated on forth in Chapters 2-8.

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 227


Commentaryi'Grunbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
Critique of Freud's final defense of the probative value mundFreud, trans, by J. Strachey etal. London: Hogarth Press,
of data from the couch: The pseudo-convergence of 1953-1974, 24 volumes. Each reference will use the abbrevia-
clinical findings (Chapter 10) tion "S.E.," followed by the year of first appearance, volume
number, and page(s).
As noted at the end of the summary of Chapter 1 (apropos 2. Note that clinical arguments rest on data that are "clinical"
of Popper), in a very late paper (S.E. 1937, 23:257-69), only in the following technical sense (in which the term will be
Freud claims that psychoanalytic interpretations do not used throughout this Precis and my Response): Clinical data are
rely on "heads I win, tails you lose" to evade falsification data obtained from the psychoanalytic treatment-setting
nolens volens. He argues that the analyst's response to the through the analysts observations of what the patient says and
patient's assent and dissent does not invariably twist the does. The results of research done outside psychoanalytic ses-
patient's remarks into a confirmation (p. 262). sions - such as those of epidemiologic or experimental studies -
are called extraclinical data.
Freud appealed to converging evidence, contending
that other clinical data can cross-validate a patient's ac-
ceptance or rejection of his analyst's interpretations. All
clinical evidence, however, whether corroborative or
not, is suspect, because it all depends on the method of
free association with its potential suggestive effects. Open Peer Commentary
Three major conclusions emerge from the appraisals I
have given in Foundations: Commentaries submitted by the qualified professional readership of
1. Insofar as the evidence for the psychoanalytic corpus this journal will be considered for publication in a later issue as
depends on data from the treatment setting, this support Continuing Commentary on this article. Integrative overviews and
is remarkably weak. syntheses are especially encouraged.
2. In view of the methodological shortcomings of
clinical psychoanalytic inquiry, a proper test of Freud's
central hypotheses calls for well-designed extraclinical
studies, either epidemiologic or experimental (Eysenck With a friend like Professor Grunbaum does
& Wilson 1973; Kline 1981; Masling 1983). For the most psychoanalysis need any enemies?
part, such studies have yet to be performed. Arthur Caplan
3. Despite the poverty of the clinical support, it could Hastings Center, Hastings-on-Hudson, N.Y. 10706
still conceivably turn out that Freud's brilliant theoretical
imagination was actually serendipitously right in some Few disciplines in biomedicine or the natural sciences have had
respects. But whereas psychoanalysis may thus be said to to endure the kind of abuse and admiration heaped upon
be scientifically alive, it is currently hardly well, at least psychoanalysis. It is the kind of theory (or theories), and its
proponents the kind of theoreticians, that philosophers of sci-
insofar as its clinical foundations are concerned. Nor are ence yearn to confront. Its proponents and critics do not even
the experimental findings I mention in Chapter 3 (pp. agree on what psychoanalysis is - a clinical therapy, a theory of
188-89), Chapter 4 (pp. 202-5), Chapter 5 (pp. 217-19), mental functioning, or both. In fact, the staunchest advocates of
and Chapter 9 (p. 270) favorable. psychoanalysis are so insecure about the theoretical soundness
and scientific status of the discipline that they attend closely to
the comments of philosophers of science as to the soundness of
Coda on exegetical myth-making in Karl Popper's
the whole enterprise. This willingness to heed philosophy in
indictment of the clinical validation of itself makes psychoanalysis almost unique among all of the
psychoanalysis (Chapter 11) disciplines that wish to lay claim to the mantle of science,
The inductivist methodology I used to assess Freud's although cynics might complain that by the time a discipline is
causal hypotheses is the modern version of the centuries- paying close attention to philosophers of science it is on its last
legs anyway.
old tradition going back to F. Bacon and J. S. Mill. On this
Nonetheless, students of psychoanalysis or those interested
basis, Chapters 1-10 reached a rather negative conclu- in the discipline would seem to me to be well served by paying
sion about the clinical evidence for the theory of repres- close attention to the methodological analysis offered by Pro-
sion, and even about clinical testability in general. As is fessor Grunbaum. Although his prose often makes for difficult
now clear, the clinical validation of psychoanalysis would reading, perhaps reflecting too many long hours spent working
be no more acceptable to a traditional inductivist (like through the obtuse grammar of most psychoanalytic writings,
Bacon or Mill) than to Popper (1962, p. 38, fn. 3). Hence, Grunbaum in The Foundations of Psychoanalysis has provided
the specifically clinical support claimed by many Freudi- an important and lucid analysis of the methodological commit-
ans, but rejected by inductivism, can no longer be used as ments of the Freudian roots of psychoanalysis.
a basis for Popper's charge that an inductivist criterion of Grunbaum shows that those such as Habermas (1973),
demarcation between science and nonscience is too per- Ricoeur (1970), and Klein (1976) who have been concerned to
defend psychoanalysis against its many fervent critics by de-
missive. Since psychoanalysis is in fact falsifiable, Popper bunking the "scientistic" elements of Freud's work have
cannot use Freud's theory to strengthen the case for his achieved, at best, a Pyrrhic victory. Those of a hermeneutical
criterion of demarcation. Finally, his astonishing omis- frame of mind argue for the abandonment of the attempt to
sion of Freud's reference to the tally argument from a key assess psychoanalytic theory and technique (at least in their
passage in his critique makes Popper's account of Freud Freudian guise) with respect to its success in providing lawlike,
rather unfair and misleading. causally based principles and laws of human behavior in favor of
some form of narrative interpretation of the allegedly unique,
NOTES context-specific, historically bound, and reason-based rumina-
1. All citations of Freud's writings in English will be from the tions of patients on an epistemically privileged couch. It is quite
Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works ofSig- clear that this simply .misses the point of Freud's theoretical

228 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Commentary/Grunbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis

enterprise. Whereas it may be possible to construct a her- really the case that there is no difference in the degree of
meneutical psychoanalysis, a prospect Grunbaum does not permanence of symptom alleviation among those who have
acknowledge, it seems to me that Griinbaum's arguments irre- been treated with some form of Freudian technique and those
futably prove that, whatever such a psychoanalysis might be, it who have not? Is there really a sound enough data base available
would not, in any interesting sense, be Freudian. concerning the ubiquitousness of spontaneous remissions or the
Similarly, Grunbaum seems to me to be equally on target in permanence of symptom alleviation in those who have not been
his scathing dismissal of psychoanalysis's most notorious bete subjected to analysis to know that this element of what Grun-
noire, Karl Popper (1962, q.v.), contending instead that it is baum refers to as "the necessary condition thesis" must be
simply wrong to claim that psychoanalysis makes no testable, abandoned? The inadequate status of epidemiological data con-
falsifiable claims either with respect to therapeutic efficacy or to cerning therapeutic efficacy in most areas of medicine should
the ontological hardware of the unconscious. If falsification is give the defenders of the Freudian enterprise pause before they
the only criterion standing between psychoanalysis and entry yield to Griinbaum's critique of this element of the tally
into the august company of the sciences, then entry is assured, argument.
for there are plenty of instances of falsified hypotheses to be Second, is the analysis of transference a hopeless method for
found littering the Freudian and neo-Freudian corpus. disentangling by-products of suggestion or mere placebo effects
But Griinbaum's most important contribution to the debate from what is valid insight on the part of a patient into the nature
about the scientific status of psychoanalysis is his recognition of of the sources of his afflictions? So little is known about the
the essential role that therapeutic efficacy played for Freud in effects of suggestion or the power and nature of the placebo
the empirical confirmation of psychoanalytic theory and tech- effect that devout Freudians might be poorly served by follow-
nique. Nearly all of the existing contemporary discussion of ing Griinbaum's suggestion that this technique has not stood the
psychoanalysis (e.g. Fisher & Greenberg 1977; Lieberson 1985) test of empirically based research.
is concerned to show either that Freud was terribly obtuse in Last, are there no means for retrospectively analyzing what
failing to recognize the irremediably flawed nature of clinical takes place in the clinical encounter so as to show that at the end
evidence from the couch in testing psychoanalytic hypotheses or of what is viewed as a successful analysis a patient's introspective
that he simply failed to realize how amenable psychoanalytic self-observations can be given probative force by an analyst who
technique would be to confirmation and discontinuation once is persuaded that they "tally" with his own causal hypotheses?
such indices as subliminal perception, galvanic skin responses, To some extent only the obstinacy of analysts themselves, who
and the epidemiological prevalence of lesbianism became refuse to try and obtain consent for research purposes to the
available. taping of psychoanalytic sessions, makes this claim such an easy
Grunbaum shows that neither claim is sound vis-a-vis Freud's mark for Griinbaum's darts.
work. Freud was acutely aware of the danger that clinical data The rage today among those analysts interested in saving
derived from therapeutic encounters with patients would be psychoanalysis from its harshest philosophical critics is to move
dismissed either as the by-product of theoretically inspired outside the clinical encounter to try and find data that would
suggestion or as just so much placebo effect. Surely Grunbaum vindicate their theory. They are surely welcome to do so, but if
is right in this since how could Freud, whose earliest they do, what they ultimately discredit or vindicate will in all
therapeutic efforts were so closely tied to the technique of likelihood have little to do with Freudian psychoanalysis.
hypnosis, not be extraordinarily sensitive to the powers of Grunbaum has done psychoanalysis a far greater service by
suggestion or the placebo effect? pointing out the exact nature of the methodological commit-
Griinbaum's reconstruction of the "tally argument" as ments the founder of the discipline has left to his followers.
Freud's attempt to circumvent the challenge posed by sug- Those who wish to follow in Freud's "pedal invasions" are,
gestibility is a seminal contribution to the understanding of both thanks to Grunbaum, in a position to better understand where
the history of Freud's work and the central role that therapeutic they must go. One could hardly ask a friend to be more helpful
efficacy must play in any assessment of Freudian theories of than that.
psychoanalysis. The only way in which the centrality of the
analysis of transference in Freudian theory can be made credi-
ble is by viewing this aspect of the therapy in the context of
Freud's concern with developing a technique that would escape
the dangers of suggestibility while at the same time preserving The scaffolding of psychoanalysis
the value of clinical data and, ultimately, the significance of
therapeutic efficacy. Peter Caws
George Washington University, Washington, D.C. 20052
If Grunbaum is right, as I believe he is, to point to the tally
argument as the methodological linchpin of Freudian psycho- What does "foundations" mean in Griinbaum's title? His book is
analysis, then it is easy to see why those who would turn to about the claims of psychoanalysis to scientific status, and it rests
extraclinical methods for verifying psychoanalysis have moved on an implicit assumption that sciences have'foundations on
outside the realm of the Freudian research strategy or program. which theoretical edifices are built. Now, in the singular, the
Perhaps, as many have argued, it is possible to verify elements term has a nice ambiguity that is nevertheless illuminating: The
of Freudian theory by means of prospective trials or cleverly foundation of psychoanalysis as we have inherited it was due to
designed, controlled experiments. But the hypotheses that are Freud, and even Grunbaum has no wish to challenge that. But
verified in this way will bear little relation to the theoretical the foundations (in the second sense of the term) laid down at the
structure that Freud and his early followers believed they had time of the foundation (in its first sense) may have been flawed,
constructed to explain the therapeutic efficacy of psychoanalytic and in that case it would be reasonable to look for weaknesses in
techniques. the resulting edifice.
I would argue that the most interesting questions raised by However, we have to be sure that the edifice was actually
Griinbaum's analysis do not concern what psychoanalysis is or built, and I am not sure, in the case of psychoanalysis, that it
should become once its Freudian foundations are removed. ever was. Perhaps all that could be built was the scaffolding. And
Rather, I should think that those committed to the Freudian the scaffolding might not, and indeed probably would not, rest
research strategy would want to reexamine Griinbaum's attack on the foundation at all. I do not wish to strain this metaphor,
on the validity of the tally argument to see whether anything can but it explains my title and its implications are obvious enough.
still be salvaged from this methodology. A lot of what Grunbaum criticizes, even in Freud's own work,
Three lines of inquiry appear most promising. First, is it has very little to do with what Freud originally wanted the

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 229


Commentary/Grunbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
foundations of psychoanalysis to be. In the Project for a Scien- task of analysis is the establishment of causal connections that
tific Psychology his ambition was to have a causal account resting hold within the complex structure of that patient's cognitive and
on neurophysiological evidence, even though such evidence emotional life.
was strictly unobtainable at the time. What he actually did Of course the experienced and sensitive analyst will be
manage to build was not on this foundation (and of course he helped by other cases, or case studies, or even general the-
knew this perfectly well). It is true that he claimed scientific oretical considerations, in the formulation of hypotheses about
status for it anyway - or at any rate he claimed that it had the case in question. But the reason psychoanalysis is not the
scientific interest and should be regarded as a part of the science science Freud hoped for, and the reason it collapses so readily
of psychology. But it has to be admitted that psychoanalysis as a before Grunbaum's onslaught, is, I believe, that the science
fiill-fledged natural science has remained promissory. itself, and not just some new boundary conditions, has to be
Part of Griinbaum's intention is to expose theoretical and built afresh in every new clinical encounter. We can't be sure it
methodological inadequacies, and in this he is devastatingly will even look Freudian, even though the process might begin
successful. However, there is something about his enterprise (and very likely with profit) from Freudian assumptions. All that
that makes one wonder whether perhaps it was too easy. His is publicly available for this building is the scaffolding. If, when
book is one of the most combative I have ever read, although it it is torn down, the edifice - in this case the self-understanding
must be said that it is jovially combative - Grunbaum enjoys his of the patient - remains standing, its weaknesses will after all
victories and signals them with triumphant exclamation points. perhaps not have mattered that much.
But from the very beginning, when he rolls in to crush Haber-
mas with a sort of argumentative tank, one has a sense of
mismatch between the weapons and their target. The latter's
work is soflimsythat it just tumbles down. But this may perhaps
be because in its clinical (rather than its metapsychological) form
psychoanalysis wasn't built on any foundation. Did Freud rely on the tally argument to meet
Grunbaum nevertheless provides one by reverse extrapola-
tion. It consists of an argument and a hypothesis: The tally the argument from suggestibility?
argument and the hypothesis of the etiological centrality of
repression. Needless to say he demolishes both to his own F. Cioffi
satisfaction and, I may add (with one caveat), to mine: I have Department of Philosophy, University of Essex, Colchester C04 3SQ,
England
very few arguments, in fact, with the particular destructive
conclusions that Grunbaum reaches. The caveat has to do with Grunbaum's ambitious and illuminating book is marred by a
the interpretation of an expression in the premise of the tally profound misconception as to the role that appeal to therapeutic
argument. Freud says that the ideas given to the patient must efficacy played in Freud's defense of the legitimacy of his
"tally with what is real in him" (my emphasis), but Grunbaum interpretative practice and therefore of the claims it was invoked
sometimes seems to make this mean what was true about him, to support. According to Grunbaum, "Freud had placed car-
which of course is a very different matter. It may be irrelevant dinal reliance on the Tally Argument [i.e. that interpretations
whether the patient's past external history confirms what he and reconstructions are only therapeutically effective when they
claims about his childhood if in fact there is a present internal are true] to counter the indictment that clinical data are inauth-
structure of fears and repressed memories (which need not be entic as a result of suggestibility" (p. 166).
veridical) that needs to be dismantled. Insofar as Freud placed "cardinal reliance" on anything, it
What is at issue is the patient's predicament, and that is why was on what Grunbaum refers to as the "consilience" between
Habermas insists, to Grunbaum's scornful indignation, on the his inferences and the clinical and extraclinical data. He be-
privileged status of the patient's own judgment. Grunbaum is of lieved in the overwhelming influence of the Wolf Man's primal
course right when he says that the patient is in one way as scene not because of its therapeutic effect but because of its
ignorant as the therapist about the causal links he embodies, and narrative power - its ability to confer intelligibility on the data.
has to resort to theoretical clarification even to identify, let alone For the tally argument to have any credibility, Freud would
confirm them. But this raises the central question I want to pose have to have been in a position to assert not only the superiority
(and, given the limitations of this commentary, must leave of his therapeutic achievements to that of his rivals but the
largely unresolved): What kind of theory does the patient have dependence of this superiority on the content of his disputed
at his disposal? The desirable answer would seem to be a etiological and dynamic theses. He knew that he could assert
natural-scientific theory resting on hypotheses about the sort of neither and he had a juster appreciation of the limitations of the
patient he is and confirmed by clinical experience. Grunbaum tally argument than Grunbaum who describes it as "brilliant."
shows that no such thing is currently available. But I would like The tally argument thus depends on a premise which Freud
to suggest another possibility, one I do not think Freud could have had no reason to believe true and which he might
entertained. have had some reason to believe false.
In making this suggestion I do not wish (like Habermas Would not Freud's therapeutic successes while holding the
or Ricoeur) to try to save Freud from what Habermas mistaken seduction theory undermine the tally argument?
calls "scientists self-misunderstanding" (Grunbaum, p. 42): I Grunbaum attempts to deal with this difficulty by quoting from a
think he really did mean psychoanalysis to have natural-scien- letter to Fliess in which Freud complains of his therapeutic
tific status and to be true of the class of human beings, and I results (p. 159), but we are entitled to suspect that he might not
think Grunbaum is right in saying that that claim fails. The have found the state of these patients so unsatisfactory had he
direction in which I believe we have to go (and I can only point to not already decided that the assumptions on which he had
it here) is to say that psychoanalysis is a natural science all right, treated them were mistaken. In any case, within months of the
but the natural domain of which it is the science is the idiosyn- seduction debacle, Freud was speaking of his "countless suc-
cratic world of the individual patient, not the class of human cesses. " It can hardly have escaped his notice that these suc-
beings over which the natural science of psychology applies. In cesses were achieved while he held erroneous views.
other words, I think that clinical findings cannot reliably be
extrapolated beyond the case from which they are drawn. Every Freud's tally argument was too weak to give him what he
new patient who walks into the analyst's office is a new world to needed because even his developmental claims far outstripped
be explored - that is why treatment takes a long time - and the the validating power, such as it was, of favourable therapeutic
outcome. These claims pertained to normal character structure

230 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Com??ientarj//Grunbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis

as well as to pathological conditions over which Freud believed Psychoanalysis as hermeneutics


no therapeutic influence could be exerted. Furthermore, the
tally argument could not be invoked when it was a question of
Freud's interpretations of dreams and errors where there was no Morris N. Eagle
therapeutic upshot to vouch for their veridicality. Department of Psychology, York University, Downsview, Ontario, M3J 1P3,
Canada
If Freud really believed his tally argument rendered the
analysts' suggestions "epistemically innocuous," why would he I believe that Grunbaum's book represents a major contribution
have gone to such lengths to deny (untruthfully) that he antici- not only to thinking about psychoanalysis but also to a number of
pated the patients' productions? Grunbaum notes Freud's prac- broader issues. In this limited space I cannot enumerate, let
tice of anticipation but not Freud's repeated denials that he alone discuss, the various contributions the book makes. I want
engaged in it. Of the Rat Man, Freud tells us, "I got him to agree to focus on Grunbaum's discussion of the hermeneutic concep-
that I had not led him to the subject of childhood or sex but that tion of psychoanalysis because, for reasons I will try to show, I
he had raised them of his own free will" (Freud 1925, p. 320). In think its importance goes well beyond an evaluation of psycho-
"The Question of Lay Analysis," "the analyst never entices his analysis. However, I want to state my view that if at least some of
patients on to the ground of sex" (Freud 1962, p. 118). Nor does the critical questions Grunbaum raises regarding psycho-
Grunbaum's thesis square well with Freud's remark, "It is often analysis are not dealt with, it will be difficult to justify, on
just in those cases where treatment fails that most discoveries rational grounds, its continued influence and growth.
are made" (the lengthy footnote to the Rat Man case.) And isn't it Were Grunbaum's book limited to his long introductory
strange that Freud should think his most irrefragable proof came critique of the hermeneutic conception of psychoanalytic theory
from just those conditions, for example, dementia praecox, and therapy, it would represent a major contribution, not only
which are resistant to psychoanalytic treatment? Is this the to clear thinking about psychoanalysis, but to clear thinking
behaviour of someone who is convinced he has rendered sug- about human behavior in general. Because of its purported
gestibility "epistemically innocuous"? emphasis on interpretation and meaning rather than causal
Another device for meeting the suggestibility argument explanation, reasons rather than causes, "narrative truth" rather
which goes unnoticed by Grunbaum is the attempt to shift the than "historical truth," psychic reality rather than objective
evidential basis of Freud's theories to his extraclinical explanato- reality, psychoanalysis has been "selected" by hermeneutic
ry triumphs (Oedipus, Hamlet, totem and taboo) in which thinkers to serve as a prototype for the hermeneutic approach to
suggestion could not operate. the "human sciences" or Geisteswissenschoften, as envisioned
Grunbaum is also mistaken to say that if challenged as to the by Dilthey (1961) and others. Hence, the concerns here are
grounds for his theory of infantile sexuality Freud "would" have much broader and larger than the proper construal of psycho-
appealed to his tally argument. We know what he "would" analysis. Although psychoanalysis is the case in point and the
appeal to because we know what he did appeal to: direct arena in which the battles are to be fought, the broad issue at
observation. "My surprising discoveries as to the sexuality of stake is nothing less than the question of the proper account of
children were made in the first instance through the analysis of human phenomena - human behavior, feelings, cognitions, and
adults. But later, from about 1908 onwards, it became possible so on. With regard to human behavior, we are told by her-
to confirm them in the most satisfactory way in every detail by meneuticians that "actions have no causes" (Schafer 1976); that
direct observation upon children." (Freud 1935, p. 70). "there are no facts" (Ricoeur 1974); that both science and causal
A plethora of illustrations of the independence of Freud's explanation entail ontological reduction to the physical; that
confidence in his etiological and dynamic constructions from "the patient himself is the final authority" in regard to psycho-
their therapeutic effects is to be found in the case histories. analytic interpretations (Habermas 1971); that the success and
Freud often expresses certainty as to the correctness of an failure (of a psychoanalytic interpretation) cannot be intersub-
interpretation in which there is no question of therapeutic jectively established (Habermas 1971); that when a formulation
effect, such as Dora's playing with her reticule, her pseudoap- or statement is persuasive and convincing, it thereby acquires a
pendicitis, her limp, and so on (Freud 1905). Such examples special kind of "narrative truth" (Spence 1982; 1983); that
seem more frequent than those in which Freud appeals to "because [a] newly composed [analytic] story of the analysand's
therapeutic effectiveness. It is arguable that even in these cases life is more beautifully wrought, it works better. The truth of
Freud's conviction that his interpretations were therapeutically this story is thereby contingent on aesthetic and pragmatic
effective was based on their thematic affinity with the symptom considerations" (Geha 1984); and a host of other things so vague
content which remitted. Freud's allusions to the Wolf Man case and fuzzy that merely repeating them here would serve no
after it became apparent that he was once more deranged are purpose - their meaning would not be clear. The programmatic
untouched by any trace of uncertainty or tentativeness. aim of hermeneuticians seems to be nothing less than to render
human behavior exempt from causal accounts and scientific
One is curious as to how Grunbaum will deal with Freud's explanation. In this regard, it continues the until now futile
complacency once his therapeutic pessimism precluded his efforts of the post-Kantian idealists who issued promissory notes
appealing to the tally argument. He cites a consilience argument toward the establishment of epistemologically and meth-
put forward in 1937 and explains that, because Freud no longer odologically unique and independent "human sciences."
felt he could fall back on the tally argument, he now had to resort
to considerations of consilience. But considerations of con- Over the years, psychoanalysis has been subjected to crit-
silience had been, from the child's picture puzzle analogy of icisms and basic questions having to do with the need for
1896 (Freud 1924) to the jigsaw puzzle analogy of 1925 (Freud empirical testing, the validity of interpretations, the problem of
1950), the principal basis adduced by Freud in support of his suggestibility, and adequate demonstrations of therapeutic
reconstructions. efficacy. These questions and criticisms, all of which have in
Grunbaum's emphasis on the tally argument is not only common the central issue of accountability, have not been
mistaken in itself but is a great strategic error. The right adequately confronted, let alone dealt with successfully. One
procedure would have been to examine the specimens of con- irresistible appeal the hermeneutic construal of psychoanalysis
silience put forward by Freud and to have shown that not only has had for some psychoanalytic thinkers is that in one fell
do they fail to surpass that of rival accounts but they generally philosophical swoop psychoanalysis is immunized against these
fail to meet the standards of plausible story telling (vague as various persistent and troubling problems of accountability and
these are) current in good historical, biographical, or forensic need no longer be troubled by them. Thus since "there are no
practice. facts" and "actions have no causes," psychoanalysts need only

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 231


Commentary /Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
generate self-consistent and persuasive accounts and they will There can be little question about the cogency of Griinbaum's
thereby acquire a special kind of truth, "narrative truth." The detailed demonstrations that psychoanalysts have argued fall-
most striking example of avoidance of accountability is that in aciously when they have concluded that data obtained in the
the whole corpus of hermeneutic literature on psychoanalysis, psychoanalytic situation provide scientific support for in-
there is, remarkably enough, little or no recognition of the ferences that a particular causal event (whether situational or
compelling need to evaluate and test, systematically and intrapersonal) has occurred and furthermore (assuming one is
rigorously, claims concerning the therapeutic efficacy of psy- willing to grant that this event has occurred) that it bears a causal
choanalysis and psychoanalytic psychotherapy. Hermeneutic relation - is causally relevant - to the clinical phenomenon of
writers are fond of speaking of the transformative powers and interest. Examples are his documentation of psychoanalysts'
effects of psychoanalysis - Habermas (1971) writes about the dependence on the tally argument (with its empirically un-
therapeutic power of self-reflection, for example. But nowhere justified premises), on "confirmation" of hypotheses by enu-
in their writings do they appear to recognize that merely meration of mere positive instances of them, and on post hoc
asserting repeatedly that psychoanalysis has transformative ergo propter hoc reasoning. Yet, as should be clear from my
powers and effects bears no connection to whether or not it does recent book, Hypothesis and Evidence in Psychoanalysis (1984),
in fact have these powers and effects. Nor do they appear to whereas I do agree with Griinbaum that the canons of elim-
recognize the need for controlled and systematic studies to test inative inductivism are the canons of scientific reasoning and
these grand claims. Even if psychoanalysis were entirely a method, that the case study investigations of psychoanalysis
hermeneutic discipline, one can test empirically the claim that it have involved serious violations of these canons, and that it is
has such and such specifiable effects on human behavior and the responsibility of contemporary psychoanalysis to bring its
experiences (just as one could test empirically the claim that investigations into conformity with these canons, I cannot agree
reading the New Testament has such and such specifiable effects with his conclusion that any reliance by psychoanalysis on data
on human behavior and experiences).
obtained from the psychoanalytic situation to support its causal
Griinbaum's devastating critique of hermeneutic conceptions inferences according to these canons is by the very nature of
and formulations - for example, his demonstration of the embar- things doomed to failure and that psychoanalysis must turn
rassingly fallacious thinking underlying Habermas's "causality
instead entirely to epidemiologic and experimental research for
of fate"; his reminder that causality can link events of diverse
such support.
ontological sorts; his equally important reminder that, contrary
Of course, I would have no trouble agreeing with Griinbaum
to hermeneuticians, science is defined methodologically rather
that epidemiologic and experimental studies should be at-
than via ontological reduction to the physical; his demonstra-
tempted. What one looks for in psychoanalysis as in any science
tions of the incredibly fuzzy and sloppy thinking behind many
hermeneutic formulations - all of these constitute vital contri- is a convergence of conclusions based on tests of the same
butions not only to clarity regarding the psychoanalytic enter- hypotheses carried out in different ways - intraclinically, epide-
prise, but to attempts to think clearly and fruitfully about how miologically, and experimentally; each way has its advantages
human behavior can be meaningfully explained. It is vitally and disadvantages with respect both to internal and external
important to respond to hermeneutic arguments and to expose validity (Edelson 1984, pp. 125-26). Yet, Griinbaum seems to
their weakness and essential emptiness. This alone represents a me to be uncharacteristically ingenuous in recommending car-
major contribution. rying out epidemiologic and experimental studies to test psy-
choanalytic hypotheses (while also maintaining that it is fruitless
to turn to clinical data to test these hypotheses), without at the
same time emphasizing:
The evidential value of the psychoanalyst's (1) the exceptional difficulties posed even in using such studies
to test nonpsychoanalytic hypotheses in the clinical realm;
clinical data (2) how much greater the difficulties are in psychoanalysis,
where causal variables are often intrapersonal (e.g. fantasies)
Marshall Edelson
rather than situational (e.g. parental behavior) and where it is
Department of Psychiatry, Yale University School of Medicine, New Haven, impossible, unfeasible, or unethical to mobilize the phenomena
Conn. 06519
of interest (e.g. intense and, for the subject, highly objection-
Griinbaum asserts that empirical warrant for the credibility of able sexual or aggressive impulses) in anything like the relevant
psychoanalytic hypotheses is, given scientific standards of meth- intensities outside the clinical situation.
od and reasoning, insufficient. (This is very different from This apparent ingenuousness is especially manifest in one
asserting, as some critics of psychoanalysis have been wont to rather startling lapse by Griinbaum from the scholarly apprecia-
do, that it is justifiable on present knowledge to dismiss psycho- tion he has shown throughout his book for what Freud is up to.
analytic hypotheses as either false or scientifically meaningless; Griinbaum seriously proposes that the putative causal link
the difference is a sign of the sophistication of Griinbaum's between paranoia and unconscious conflicts over homosexuality
critique.) According to Griinbaum, the inadequacy of the em- should be tested by comparing groups of subjects, one group
pirical foundation of psychoanalysis is in large part a conse- from a society with more and another from a society with less
quence of the stubbornness with which psychoanalysts have tolerant attitudes toward homosexuality, on the assumption that
fallaciously argued and mistakenly concluded that their clinical it follows from psychoanalytic theory that the former group
data, obtained in the psychoanalytic situation, provide sufficient should have a lower incidence of paranoia than the latter. But
and satisfactory empirical support for the scientific credibility of many psychoanalytic hypotheses cannot be tested in this way
their hypotheses. But in his view such data, because of the clash just because it may not be a situational variable such as "social
between essential characteristics of the psychoanalytic situation attitude" that is held to be causally relevant by psychoanalytic
and essential requirements of scientific method and reasoning, theory. What if the theory holds that unconscious conflicts about
cannot possibly test psychoanalytic hypotheses and thereby homosexuality develop in early childhood, more or less inde-
provide the required support. He challenges psychoanalysis, pendently of the rationalized social codes of adult life even as
therefore, to produce instead the extraclinical - epidemiologic these are translated into child-rearing practices, and that these
and experimental - data that are capable of testing the causal conflicts have their origin in the child's instinctual wishes,
claims made by psychoanalytic hypotheses, for passing tests unfolding and varying in intensity relatively independently of
such as these is necessary if a contemporary psychoanalysis is to the intrinsic features of actually and accurately experienced
build the strong empirical foundation upon which its scientific situations; and that these wishes are expressed in the child's
credibility must ultimately depend. fantasies about his own and others' bodies, about certain kinds of

232 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Commentary I'Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis

acts, and about the imagined consequences, both desired and particular occasion it is implemented, from the various kinds of
undesired, of carrying out these acts? This is a possible, interest- productions obtained when attempts are made to carry out the
ing theory, whether true or not, even if its testability by the procedure, and the properties these productions manifest on
methods Griinbaum urges upon psychoanalysis in place of its particular occasions of attempted use of the procedure (es-
reliance on clinical data is problematic. pecially those properties that bear on their evidential value).
For similar reasons, I am not happy with Griinbaum's treat- Theoretical presuppositions always underlie a procedure for
ment of free association. He argues that the method cannot bear obtaining data in science. What theoretical presuppositions
the weight Freud places upon it. Griinbaum questions the about the mental apparatus do in fact underlie free association
credentials of free association as a method that, it is claimed, (regarded now solely as an instrument for obtaining data rele-
warrants conclusions about causes. According to him, such vant to the assessment of the credibility of psychoanalytic
claims are based on a misextrapolation from the experiences hypotheses)? What empirical support exists independently of
described in Studies on Hysteria (Breuer & Freud 1893-1895); the use of the procedure itself for these presuppositions? We
the mere appearance of a content in a stream of associations psychoanalysts have not even precisely specified what variables
cannot provide warrant for the conclusion that an event has (e.g. suspension of conscious purposiveness) constitute the
occurred or has causal relevance. Despite Griinbaum's overall procedure itself; how to estimate the values these variables take
appreciative depiction of Freud as sophisticated and knowl- (e.g. the degree to which.such suspension is achieved); and how
edgeable about methodological issues (even granting that Freud to determine just what properties of communications change,
failed to solve methodological problems of which he was aware), and in what way, as these variables take different values. The
Griinbaum's portrayal of the reasoning Freud used in his meth- answers to such questions must be sought by psychoanalysis in
od of free association suggests that Freud was here guilty of the the years ahead if it is to refute convincingly Griinbaum's claim
most egregious errors in logic and gross causal fallacies. It seems that there is no way to differentiate among the mass of clinical
more likely to me that Freud believed his inferences from data material those communications having greater degrees of evi-
obtained by the method of free association were justified by a dential value from those having lesser degrees.
complex set of premises about the mental apparatus, adum- In short, I am not inclined to quarrel with Griinbaum's
brated, for example, in The Interpretation of Dreams (see diagnosis, whatever quibble we may have over details, but I am
Edelson 1984, pp. 134-35). I would prefer a criticism of Freud prepared to question his remedy. I have made my own proposal
that raised questions about the credibility of these premises, for dealing with the problems he has so compellingly identified
rather than one that here suddenly has him become a simpleton. (Edelson 1984, especially pp. 157-60), and this includes in part:
Because I want to argue for the potential evidential value of (a) clarification of just what the hypotheses are that require
the psychoanalyst's clinical data, I may pay more attention than testing; (b) exploitation of recent conceptual and methodological
it deserves, given the power of Griinbaum's overall perfor- developments in single subject research; (c) building upon the
mance, to his strange lapse (as he attempts to discredit the directions set by Luborsky (1962; 1973; Luborsky & Mintz
method of free association) from his usual high level of fairness, 1974), who has used his symptom-context method to test hy-
his masterly grasp of the complexity of the theory he critiques, potheses according to the canons of eliminative inductivism in
and the care and generosity with which he reads other passages single subject studies, and Glymour (1980), who has explicated
of Freud in the light of his knowledge of the context of the how a bootstrap strategy may be used to test hypotheses in such
passage and aim of its author. The lapse to which I refer is a case study as the Rat Man; and (d) exploitation of methods
apparent when, in writing about the Irma Dream as the paradig- recently developed in the social sciences for making valid causal
matic depiction offreeassociation, Grunbaum takes the associa- inferences when data are nonexperimental or qualitative.
tions Freud reports and on the basis of these mocks Freud's Grunbaum has every right (and perhaps from his point of view
claims for free association - to the effect that unconscious every reason) to remain skeptical that such a program can or will
infantile wishes can be discovered by free association that have be carried out and that taking such a direction will ever remedy
been and are active and which have played a causal role in the defects in the foundation of psychoanalysis he has identified.
dream-formation. Grunbaum zeros in on the fact that Freud's Here, of course, only time will tell. But, to my colleagues, I
reported associations involve recent conscious wishes only. suggest, let us make a hopeful beginning. What if we were to
Why, here, in particular, does Grunbaum ignore Freud's many adopt the following minimal set of standards to be met by clinical
explicit statements that on grounds of discretion he was giving a case studies in order to be accepted in our psychoanalytic
much edited approximation to the products of free association, literature? (I refer here of course only to that literature which
an imperfect illustration of what a patient's free associations purports to constitute a scientific body of knowledge.)
might sound like - wouldn't Freud have been the first to 1. What the author is asserting - his hypothesis, conclusion,
acknowledge that this patient was having a good deal of difficulty or generalization about a case or treatment - is clearly and
suspending judgment and conscious control over the direction prominently stated.
of her thinking and was very reluctant to utter aloud what she
was in fact consciously thinking? 2. The author shows how his hypothesis about the case or
treatment explains or accounts for the observations he reports;
Grunbaum should not be blamed for this particular lapse, he does not merely juxtapose them.
because Freud's unsolved problem in exposition is in part also 3. The author is careful to separate facts or observations from
conceptual and it has never been solved in the psychoanalytic his interpretations of them, which is to say he distinguishes what
literature. With respect specifically to the problem of the can be observed without knowledge or use of the theory being
evidential value of what is produced by free association, Grun- tested from interpretations based upon the very theory such
baum, with his customary perspicacity, seems here to have at observations are being used to test.
least touched a nerve. For surely the degree of success with 4. The author specifies what observations, if they had oc-
which any procedure is carried out must make a difference in the curred, he would have accepted as grounds for rejecting his
evidential value of what is obtained through its use. And just hypothesis.
what difference does the degree of success make, and how is this 5. The author reports at least some observations that appar-
difference to be detected and calibrated? About these matters, ently contradict his hypothesis, or that he has difficulty explain-
Freud and others in the psychoanalytic literature have very ing, and indicates how he plans to deal with such counterexam-
little to say. ples. If he does not reject his hypothesis, he makes clear his
In fact, neither Grunbaum nor the many discussions of free grounds for holding on to it or how these counterexamples limit
association in the psychoanalytic literature carefully distinguish its scope.
the procedure itself, and the degree of success with which on a 6. Since any set of observations can be explained in different

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 233


Commentary!'Grunbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
ways, the author gives some argument why his observations are others produced cures, it would still not follow logically that the
better evidence for his hypothesis than for at least one compara- curative insights are veridical. Before the turn of the century,
ble rival or competing hypothesis. Janet (1889) had pioneered a memory reconstruction therapy in
7. Even if the author's observations can be argued to favor his which traumatic memories were converted, under hypnosis,
own conjecture over a rival, he considers - as Freud himself did, into pleasant pseudomemories. These reconstructions were
for example, in the case of the problem of suggestion - what claimed to result in long-term cures. The right kind of false
factors operating in the situation in which he made his observa- memory or insight may be therapeutic - and not only because of
tions could have resulted in his obtaining these favorable data suggestion effects; actually, true insight, as some modern re-
even if his hypothesis were false. He presents some argument, search on depression implies, may be countertherapeutic. It
even though it be a nondesign argument, for dismissing at least seems, therefore, that there was good reason for the tally
one such factor as a plausible alternative explanation for his argument to have languished undiscovered. It does not have the
having obtained the data he would like to regard as favorable to power, even in principle, to validate insights without extra-
his hypothesis. clinical corroboration. This does not have the catastrophic con-
8. He makes clear to what extent he proposes to generalize his sequence that Grunbaum perceives for psychoanalysis, howev-
hypothesis about the case or treatment to similar cases or er, in part because psychoanalysis has a far wider scope than the
treatments, and presents some argument justifying such a retrospective discovery of etiologies.
generalization. Grunbaum does not sufficiently allow for the evolution of
Can we then not imagine a day when Grunbaum, faced just by psychoanalytic therapy from its turn-of-the-century form. What
case studies meeting these standards - we will not now imagine had been a hypermnesic instrument for recovering repressed
confronting him also with studies involving more complex or pathogenic memories became, through the medium of free
sophisticated single subject research methodologies - finds association and transference, a vehicle for insight. This insight is
himself compelled to acknowledge that clinical data not only not, as Grunbaum seems to conceive of it, merely the recovery
might but do contribute critically to the assessment of the of veridical memories from childhood, but the expanding
credibility of psychoanalytic hypotheses?
awareness - and emotional "working through" - of thematic
patterns in the patient's life. Much of the data base for such
insights are outcroppings from the here-and-now of the trans-
ference relation and of the patient's current life.
Psychoanalysis has a wider scope than the Furthermore, psychoanalysis is not merely a therapeutic
retrospective discovery of etiologies enterprise; it is also, as Freud emphasized, a branch of general
psychology. Its ambit extends far beyond psychopathology,
Matthew Hugh Erdelyi encompassing an incredibly rich network of propositions about
Brooklyn College and the Graduate Center, City University of New York,
unconscious processes, defense mechanisms, symbolism, trans-
Brooklyn, N.Y. 11210
formational processes, the distinction between manifest and
latent contents, jokes, development, fantasy, and the like.
The gist of Grunbaum's position on psychoanalysis is that Freud Etiology is hardly the ubiquitous preoccupation of psycho-
was much more sophisticated methodologically than he is cred- analysis. Nor need psychoanalysis be hobbled by an exclusion-
ited with having been; that he maintained - and not through any ary reliance on clinical data. Freud himself drew extensively
confusion - the natural science character of psychoanalysis; that from extraclinical materials over which he had no suggestive
he was acutely aware of the methodological problem of influence - for example, the autobiography of the psychotic Dr.
therapeutic suggestion contaminating, indeed creating, the Schreber (1911); even experimental work, such as Potzl's classic
clinical "data" that undergirded the "science"; that Freud had study of 1917 of the emergence of subliminal stimuli in dreams,
actually proposed a brilliant, hitherto undiscovered defense of formed an early part of the psychoanalytic tradition. Freud was
his clinical data, which Grunbaum calls the "tally argument"; not against experiments, only against silly experiments.
but that the defense failed to hold for a variety of reasons; and Grunbaum's undue emphasis on merely the clinical aspect of
that therefore the probative value of clinical data is after all psychoanalysis leads to the confounding of a number of the-
unavailing. oretical points. Since he devotes at least two chapters to the
The tally argument that Grunbaum attributes to Freud (I problem, it is worth underscoring that the cornerstone theory of
believe there is more Grunbaum in it than he allows) is some- repression (defense) is not the same as the hypothesis that
what complex, comprising, according to Grunbaum, two con- repression is the etiological determinant of certain neuroses.
clusions following from two premises (p. 140). Its essential Grunbaum seems to shrug off the former as either trivial or
Freudian ingredient is that although incorrect insights sug- unoriginal. This stance, however, is idiosyncratic. The etiology
gested by the therapist to the patient might be accepted for a tail need not wag the repression dog.
while, they eventually drop out because they do not lead to a Grunbaum's overriding concern with etiology seems to re-
cure. Thus, therapeutic success ensures that the insights that flect a commitment to a cause-and-effect conception of meaning.
led to the patient's cure "tally with what is real in him" (Freud Although Freud, as a determinist, often expressed this type of
1917). The problem that Grunbaum sees with the argument is view, his actual interpretations of the meaning of dreams, slips,
that other types of therapy that do not depend on insight also symptoms, and so on, belie such a narrow approach. Typically,
produce cures and that, moreover, remissions regularly occur the meanings that Freud uncovered were not deterministic but
with no therapy. Because cures can arise with no insight, cures determinate relationships, ones involving coherences, inter-
cannot be the warrantors of insight. Hence there is no protec- connections, patterns (cf. Erdelyi 1985). When one establishes
tion against the possibility that the patient's "insights" are the the meaning of an unknown word from its context, one does not
therapist's creations via suggestion, and that, therefore, the establish that the context has caused the unknown word. One
therapist's theory solipsistically manufactures the clinical data need not know the cause of a joke to understand its meaning. It
that validate it. may be true that free associations do not necessarily yield causes
My problem with the tally argument is not Grunbaum's (and therefore etiologies) by retracing the cause-and-effect
criticism, but his original enthusiasm for it. Even if research had chain; but that may be the wrong model. Rather, free associa-
shown that psychoanalysis and no other treatment modality was tions may yield meanings, and they may therefore function after
effective, that there were no spontaneous remissions of symp- all as microscopes/telescopes of the mind, by providing the
toms (which are not an embarrassment for psychoanalysis, as contextual ecology from which meanings may be derived (Er-
Grunbaum seems to believe), and that some insights but not delyi 1985).

234 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Commentary/Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
Grunbaum emphasizes some of the methodological defects have recently reviewed most of the important experimental
of the clinical method (which has many, but then so do the lab- studies, those cited in support of Freudian theory by Kline
oratory methods of experimental psychology and of the neuro- (1981), Silverman (1976), and Fisher and Greenberg(1977), and
sciences). The issue is not either-or or all-or-none. The scien- I have concluded that they fail to provide strong support for any
tist is not an armchair methodologist: He must make the best of part of Freud's theory (Erwin 1985). Finally, those who agree
imperfect (if improvable) tools. The clinical method has not that existing experimental studies are weak might look to future
only weaknesses but also strengths. Questions concerning exis- experimental work to vindicate Freudian views. I would agree
tence, for example, can be answered through the clinical meth- with this, but it fails to show that anyone now has any rational
od. Thus, it is not necessary to refer to modern experimental grounds for thinking Freudian theory true or the therapy
studies of hypnotic hypermnesia to assert that hypnotic recall is efficacious.
often confabulatory. The phenomenon of hypnotic paramnesia 3. A third reply, one likely to be made by most confirmed
was painfully brought home to Freud by his clinical data and is Freudians, is to try to show that the clinical data do warrant
an important empirical contribution from the clinic. The clini- acceptance of significant parts of Freudian theory. As far as I
cian can also use a variety of within-subjects strategies in which know, Marshall Edelson (1984) has made the only detailed
the patient serves as his own control (cf. Freud 1892-1893). response of this kind to Grunbaum, although Flax (1981) makes
Clinical sessions can be videotaped and subjected to rigorous a few brief comments in support of clinical confirmation, as does
and impartial analyses; thus, processes manifesting themselves Glymour (1982), but with much caution and qualification. Be-
in therapy sessions may be exactingly investigated within a cause Grunbaum replies to both Flax and Glymour in his book, I
clinical framework. Moreover, because clinical work often ex- will concentrate on the issues raised by Edelson.
tends over many years, long-term phenomena are elicited On two points I agree with Edelson, and I suspect that
(such as transference) which the typical laboratory approach Grunbaum would too, although he might wish to qualify his
would not even contact. Implicit between-subject designs are agreement. I agree with Edelson (1984, p. 121) that it is possible
also possible when base rates are available. And, ultimately, in principle to obtain clinical confirmation of Freudian theory, if
clinical situations can be treated in an experimental fashion - this means that there is at least some possible world in which
as when comparing different kinds of therapeutic intervention. clinical confirmation is feasible. I also agree that, under certain
In the last 30 pages or so of his book, Grunbaum begins to favorable conditions, disconfirmation is possible in our world in
touch on such possibilities and, it seems, to back off somewhat a clinical setting. Edelson, however, also wants to argue that (a)
from his disparagement of clinical data; but this really seems an clinical confirmation is possible in our world and that (b) it has
afterthought, one not reflected in his main conclusions. Grun- already occurred. As to the second claim, Edelson offers exactly
baum does suggest that "serendipity" might account for the two examples. One is Freud's Rat Man case. Grunbaum dis-
possible validity of some psychoanalytic propositions. This may cusses this case extensively in his book and, in my view, shows
be so, but it may also be the case that the clinical method, with that it is not an example of clinical confirmation. The other
all its imperfections, had something to do with it. example is the case of Miss X, discussed earlier by Luborsky
(1973).
While undergoing psychoanalysis, Miss X sometimes mo-
mentarily forgot what she had wanted to say to her analyst. In
Defending Freudianism approximately 300 sessions, this occurred only 13 times.
Edelson contends that a statistical correlation was found be-
Edward Erwin tween intensification of conflict and momentary forgetting (p.
Philosophy Department, University of Miami, Coral Gables, Fla. 33756
146). What Luborsky (1973) actually found, however, was a
correlation between references to the therapist and momentary
Grunbaum's work presents a serious challenge to those who forgetting. Edelson assumes without evidence that if the client
believe that they have rational grounds for accepting Freudian referred to the therapist in any way, this was a sign of emotional
doctrines. Freudians are likely to respond in any of several involvement with the therapist. Furthermore, neither
ways. Luborsky nor Edelson rules out a non-Fruedian explanation of
1. First, it might be argued (Flax 1981) that contemporary the correlation found by Luborsky. One possibility is that when
psychoanalysts have made significant modifications in Freudian Miss X referred to her therapist, she was distracted either by
theory; so, attacking Freud's views does not necessarily damage him or by some conscious thought, and this distraction caused
current psychoanalytic theories. As Grunbaum points out in his the momentary forgetting. (In one session in which she referred
book, there are at least two difficulties confronting this re- to the therapist, and forgetting occurred, session 36, she was
sponse. First, he is challenging the evidential support for struck by the disquieting thought that he was not really listen-
certain Freudian hypotheses that are common to almost all ing; in another session, 20, it occurred to her that the analyst
variants of psychoanalytic theory. An example is the hypothesis believed he could not help her.) Edelson, however, concedes
that repression plays a key causal role in the development of (p. 146) that Luborsky found only a statistical correlation and
neurotic problems. If one rejects this hypothesis and all of the obtained no evidence of a causal relation. If that is true, and if
others said by Grunbaum to be unfounded, then it is unclear Grunbaum is right about the Rat Man case, then Edelson is left
why one's theory should be counted as a form of psychoanalysis. with no example whatsoever of a clinical confirmation of a
Second, the epistemological problems that Grunbaum raises for Freudian causal hypothesis. (It may be that Edelson does not
the clinical confirmation of orthodox Freudian theory are also intend that either the Rat Man case or the case of Miss X be
problems for newer versions of the theory. construed as an example of clinical confirmation, but then he has
2. A Freudian may concede the weaknesses of the clinical data no examples, unless he wishes to count Breuer's treatment of
but still appeal to experimental studies of Freudian theory. This Anna 0, which is discussed below.)
response, however, would not vindicate Freud's confidence in Edelson also suggests that psychoanalytic theory can be
his theory, for Freud relied almost entirely on clinical evidence. confirmed in a clinical setting through the use of single subject,
That is also true of most contemporary analysts. So, pointing to experimental and quasi-experimental designs. As an example,
the experimental evidence, even if it is cogent, fails to show that he cites Hersen and Barlow's (1976) discussion of a multiple
most Freudians have a rational basis for their theoretical beliefs. baseline design. These authors do say (p. 9) that Breuer used
Those who appeal to experimental evidence might agree, but such a design in establishing the effectiveness of his treatment of
reply that their goal is only to show that firm evidence for Anna O. However, they also note that Breuer failed to rule out
Freudian theory does exist. Even on this point I am skeptical. I the possibility that the patient improved because of suggestion

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 235


Commentary/Grunbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
and not because of Breuer's interpretations. The problem that methods of treatment, like behaviour therapy, may succeed,
Breuer faced will arise in other cases: Anyone who wishes to use resulting in neither relapse nor symptom substitution.
a single subject multiple baseline design to establish the effec- Grunbaum turns the argument into a philosophical disquisi-
tiveness of a therapy must explain how a placebo hypothesis is to tion, stating Freud's own position in terms of a syllogism, called
be ruled out. Other single subject designs may be more suitable by him Freud's "master proposition." From the conjunction of
for that purpose, but it still needs to be shown that they can be two causally necessary conditions he derives two conclusions,
used to establish the effectiveness of a therapy such as psycho- and this "tally argument" is then mercilessly criticised in the
analysis, which involves several components and typically lasts main portion of the book. Griinbaurn certainly has no doubt
two years or more, or that they can be used to resolve the very about the point that therapeutic success played a pivotal role in
complex problems that arise in trying to confirm Freud's the- Freud's tally argument, and I feel that this is indeed the core of
oretical hypotheses. the whole book. The first part, dealing with the attempts of
If Edelson were to show how single subject designs could be hermeneutic philosophers to capture psychoanalysis from
used to test Freudian hypotheses, this demonstration would Freud, and the final portions dealing with various smaller
warrant the rejection, or at least a modification, of Griinbaum's points, are important but much less central than Griinbaum's
conclusion (p. 278) that confirmation of Freud's ideas must come very careful delineation and criticism of the tally argument.
from extraclinical studies. Such a demonstration, however, Is this kill, or overkill? Seeing that psychoanalysts have
would not refute his major contention: Insofar as the psycho- argued against the conclusion that therapeutic success was
analytic corpus is based on current clinical data, the warrant is indeed of pivotal importance for Freud's theory, clearly the
remarkably weak. answer must be that a detailed examination of the case was
I close with a question that Grunbaum does not address in his required, and no one could have done it better or have come to
book. If there is nofirmevidence in support of Freudian theory, more clearcut conclusions than Grunbaum. It is difficult to see
what should our present epistemic attitude be? Should we how psychoanalysts can continue this argument, other than by
disbelieve the theory or should we merely suspend judgment? I having recourse to the hermeneutic principles which Freud
agree with Grunbaum that future studies might confirm central himself would have rejected, and which, as Grunbaum points
parts of the theory and that the absence of evidence does not, by out, remove psychoanalysis completely from science. To many
itself, warrant disbelief. There are, however, two considerations psychoanalysts, eager to rescue what they can from the burning,
that incline me toward a tentative belief that much of the theory this may not matter much; psychoanalytic pretensions to scien-
is wrong. First, there are clinical and experimentalfindingsthat tific respectability have always been slight, but if we want to
are difficult to explain using Freudian theory. An example is the judge Freud's opus in any reasonable manner, then we must
success of certain behavioral and cognitive techniques, and the keep in mind what Freud himself was claiming for it. He was in
failure to find that symptom substitution generally follows suc- no doubt that psychoanalysis was aiming to be a science in the
cessful symptomatic treatment (Erwin 1978; Rachman & Wilson traditional mould, even though in his presentation, mode of
1980). Even apart from these findings, most of Freud's hypoth- argument, and in many other ways he certainly departed from
eses are implausible given our background evidence; that is one tradition (Eysenck 1985a).
reason they are interesting. Most are neither trivial nor self- It is curious that psychoanalysts themselves have not looked
evident. Of course, they are not all equally implausible, and at this tally argument in detail or discovered its weaknesses.
some may have indirect support even if the evidence does not They seem to have been motivated more by a desire to come to
yet warrant their acceptance. Nevertheless, for those that are favourable conclusions about the status of psychoanalysis than
implausible, all things considered, does not the absence of by a concern for logical argument and factual outcome. All this
evidence warrant a harsher verdict than "not proven"? Are we makes it particularly important, of course, that the argument
not entitled to say, although tentatively, "there is some reason should once and for all be stated in its logical form, with proper
to think them false"? deductions from the syllogisms involved, and with due regard to
the factual evidence available at the moment. When I first
pointed out in 1952 that "the emperor had no clothes," I took it
for granted that the relevance of the therapeutic outcome
Failure of treatment - failure of theory? argument to Freudian theory would be obvious; clearly I was
mistaken, and it needed Griinbaum's patient unravelling of the
Hans J. Eysenck skein to drive the point home. For that, many thanks!
Department of Psychology, Institute of Psychiatry, London SE5 8AF,
England
In my own writings (Eysenck 1985a; Eysenck & Wilson 1973) I
have always taken it for granted that the obvious failure of The probative value of the clinical data of
Freudian therapy to significantly improve on spontaneous re-
mission or placebo treatment (Rachman & Wilson 1980) is the psychoanalysis
clearest proof we have of the inadequacy of Freudian theory,
B. A. Farrell
closely followed by the success of alternative methods of treat-
ment, such as behaviour therapy (Kazdin & Wilson 1978). My Corpus Christ! College, Oxford 0X1 4JF, England
reason was simply that Freud clearly predicted two things, on Did Freud vindicate his method of clinical investigation? This
the basis of his general theory. The first of these was that question is central to Grunbaum's book; and, in effect, he boils
psychoanalysis would succeed in curing neurotic disorders, down Freud's argument to the following. Consider a psycho-
which clearly it does not, and the second was that no other, neurotic patient, P, who, we will suppose, has been successfully
purely "symptomatic" therapy would succeed as well, or better, analysed. It is causally necessary for therapeutic success for the
which behaviour therapy clearly does. In other words, we have patient P to obtain correct insight into the pathogenic aetiology
here one of the few points where Freud makes definite predic- of his difficulty, and into the unconscious dynamics of his
tions, which can be falsified; hence, their actual falsification is of character. Only through psychoanalytic interpretation and
considerable importance in judging the general theory. treatment can the patient obtain this correct insight. But patient
This argument has not on the whole been favorably received P has been successfully analysed. Therefore, patient P has
by psychoanalysts, who continue to state that the theory may obtained the correct insights into his difficulties and his char-
very well be right, even though the treatment may fail and other acter. Therefore, Freud's method of clinical investigation has

236 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Commentary/Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
yielded valid results in this case, and will also yield valid results patient. For a recent example of this, see Hanna Segal's answer
in all similar cases. to Jonathan Miller (cf. Farrell 1976; 1981; Segal 1983). It is quite
Griinbaum challenges the soundness of this argument. I find clear that Griinbaum's objections to Freud will not affect Segal
his challenge a little vague and obscure, but I think it can be one whit!
summarised not unfairly as follows: The clinical data are irre- 5. It may be very tempting for Grunbaum to retort that if
mediably contaminated epistemically through suggestion by the analysts cannot justify the validity of their method via Freud's
analyst. The data are therefore unreliable guides to the nature of early argument then they cannot justify or establish it in its
patient P and his problem. So, even in a case where we suppose contemporary form either. Hence analysts are not warranted in
the treatment to be successful, we cannot explain this cure by disregarding his objections. But this retort will not do. For the
claiming that the patient has arrived at any correct insights, this points made in (1) to (4) suggest that there is something very
arrival having been causally necessary for the cure. We have to wrong with Griinbaum's case against Freud.
explain the therapeutic success in some other way. Hence Grunbaum has shown that Freud cannot validate his method
Freud has not shown that his method validly uncovers the in that he cannot prove or demonstrate that it is valid. But it does
nature of the patient's psychoneurosis, and the dynamics of the not follow from this that the clinical data or material can tell us
patient's personality. nothing about the patient's disorder. The data may still have
Let us suppose that Griinbaum has got the text of Freud right probative value, small or great. It is, therefore, very misleading
on this matter. Then, if Griinbaum's claim that the clinical simply to concentrate on Grunbaum's anti-Freud argument.
material is contaminated is correct, Freud does fail to prove that For to do so is to lead the reader to overlook the very important
his method is valid, and hence fails to vindicate it. Freud's point that the clinical material may still have probative force.
argument fails even if it is merely the case that the clinical data What is more, this force may be strong enough to support quite a
or materials are contaminated in some small part for some of the reasonable defence of the claim that psychoanalytic method can
time, rather than in toto for all of the time. Now I have argued help us to discover the truth about human nature. Accordingly,
elsewhere (Farrell 1981) that the material produced by psycho- psychoanalysts may be inclined to accuse Griinbaum of making
analytic method is perspective- and method-dependent, and the same sort of misleading moves about method as Nagel and
therefore liable to be artifact-infected. So I think Griinbaum's others have made in the past about psychoanalytic theory. It is
empirical claim is correct - the material is contaminated, and in not difficult to convict the theory of being unscientific, and
some relevant ways. It is useful for Griinbaum to bring this out, convict it in a way which misleads us into supposing that the
especially, no doubt, in view of the fact that so many psycho- theory is unrespectable and worthless. What Grunbaum has
analysts still treat Freud's writings as Holy Writ, rather in the done here, analysts may say, is to expose the uncertainties of the
way that academics and others in some countries of the Eastern method in a way which misleads the reader into believing that it
bloc seem to treat the writings of Marx. is worthless. (Again, Grunbaum is liable to be accused of
However, I confess I have misgivings about Griinbaum's overlooking the role and force of clinical material - and being
criticism, for I think it has serious limitations. And it is these quite misleading in consequence - when he argues that even if,
which will make psychoanalysts refuse to give up Freud's claim, per impossible, the clinical material were uncontaminated, it
and their claim, that by means of psychoanalytic method, they could not establish the causal propositions from the aetiological
can, and do in general, uncover the truth, or part of the truth, story of analytic psychopathology.)
about their analysands. What is obviously required at this juncture, I think, is for
1. Psychoanalysts will say that Freud's argument for the students to underemphasise what psychoanalysts say about
validity of the method was built around his early "traumatic" what they do (Freud included) and instead study what they
view of the psychoneuroses, and not around the later, fuller one actually do. We may then be in a better position to exhibit the
of conflict between id and ego. The significance for Grunbaum of suggestive force of their clinical material and thereby to assess
this change of view by Freud is that analysts are not especially its epistemic weight. This is a constructive job, which Griin-
interested in Freud's original defence of his method. They are baum does not attempt. This is a pity because its omission leaves
concerned with the defence of present-day psychoanalytic theo- a gap which makes the book negative and lopsided.
ry and work. However, I suspect that Grunbaum may be handicapped
2. Freud's original defence is tied to the notions of therapeutic when he attempts the constructive job of assessing the probative
cure and success. But analysts are chary today of bandying these weight of the clinical data or material. For he seems to be
words about, in view of all the doubts and complexities that controlled by a picture of epistemic relevance and legitimacy, in
surround the notions involved. They are consequently not which the concepts of falsification and demonstration play cen-
interested in tying the defence of their method to notions whose tral roles. Such a picture is quite inappropriate when we try to
application is so uncertain. Again, therefore, they would say that get to grips with the character of psychoanalytic work. For it is
Freud's defence and Griinbaum's concern are out of date. liable to prevent us from appreciating the contribution psycho-
3. Although it is always likely that the influence of analysts will analysis may be making to our understanding of human nature.
contaminate the clinical material, examination of their work
makes it commonsensical to say that this influence can vary -
from great to small. Consider, then, a "traumatic" case which
fits Freud's argument and early views. Suppose we have good
reason to believe that the analyst's influence was small in this Grunbaum on Freud: Three grounds for
case. Griinbaum's objection to Freud's argument will do little or dissent
nothing to stop the analyst from claiming that he has uncovered
some important truth about this patient. And common sense Arthur Fine and Micky Forbes
will say that he is right. (For examples of such cases, see Malan, Department of Philosophy, Northwestern University, Evanston, III. 60201
1979.) Grunbaum tells a story about the character of clinical evidence
4. Something similar applies to other sorts of patients. Ana- in psychoanalysis. The moral of his story is that the amount of
lysts make use of clinical material which is internal to the charity required to accept the arguments for Freudian theory
psychoanalytic situation to try to arrive at a view of the nature of would deplete the intellectual reserve and force a general
the patient's difficulties, and so on. In doing this, they are lowering of scientific standards. We would like to suggest three
guided by criteria to help them identify interpretations which aspects to this story that point to its being rather more fabulous
are correct, and which they rely on to construct their view of the than real.

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 237


Commentary/Grunbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
Griinbaum wants to show that the clinical data and the For Freud saw psychoanalysis as a refinement and extension of
patterns of Freudian argument based on them do not support these common explanatory modes. By depriving Freud's in-
the fundamental tenets of psychoanalysis, in particular, the ferences of their natural background in everyday psychology,
posited causal connection of repression with neurosis and the Grunbaum can make even the most cogent patterns of reasoning
use of free association to locate repressions as causal agents. In seem implausible. This is just what happens when Grunbaum
comparing Grunbaum's various detailed discussions, we find puzzles over how the technique of free association could lead to
him using a common central strategy. This is to show that in the repressed material qua "cause of subsequent behavior." For
analytic setting the causal hypotheses used by Freud to explain although Grunbaum argues in favor of Freud's view that reasons
and collate the clinical data have competitors, that is, alter- are causes, his atomistic construal of causes strips those reasons
native, non-Freudian hypotheses that explain and organize the which are causes of their usual ideational components. If we
data almost as well. From the existence of such alternatives, restore these components then Grunbaum's puzzle dissolves.
Grunbaum concludes that Freud's posited causal hypotheses For when we follow a chain of associations we see, along the
are not supported by the clinical data. And this is the first of our way, what the connections are, and there is no additional
problems with Griinbaum's story. For the availability of alter- question, in the causal mode, as to the relation between one end
native explanatory hypotheses for a given body of data is a well- of the chain and the other. The chain of reasons that guides the
known feature of every reasonably complex scientific investiga- associations encompasses the causal connection as well.
tion. Moreover, one is generally not able to eliminate all the We think that these three problems with Grunbaum's cri-
plausible rivals to a particular hypothesis. It followsfromthe fact tique (the methodological myth, the skepticism, and the atom-
that science goes on in this situation that for data to count as ism) indicate that Grunbaum's pessimistic moral about psycho-
supporting a hypothesis it is not necessary to first rule out all analysis and the clinical data is drawn from a fable and not from
competitors. Thus Griinbaum's strategy of pointing to possible real life. Still, cautionary fables are important too.
alternatives to the Freudian hypotheses does not actually pro-
vide a sufficient basis for his strong conclusion concerning the
failure of the clinical data to support Freudian theory. Rather,
Grunbaum's strategy embodies the methodological myth that Psychoanalysis as a social activity
support accrues only in the absence of rivals. Owen J. Flanagan, Jr.
To succeed in the project of assessing clinical support would
Department of Philosophy, Wellesley College, Wellesley, Mass. 02181
require a more sensitive treatment of the concept of evidence
than Grunbaum offers. Because there is no good and general Suppose one accepts, as I do, Grunbaum's central claim that the
theory of evidence (or support), the required sensitivity would scientific merits of psychoanalysis have not been remotely
probably have to come about comparatively; for example, by established. What implications does such an assessment have
comparing the evidential structure of Freud's clinical argument for the actual practice of psychoanalysis? How should practicing
with similarly complex structures that form the clinical back- psychoanalysts conceive of and represent their activity? What
ground for theory and therapy in, say, somatic medicine. Per- kind of activity should the larger culture take psychoanalysis to
haps detailed comparative studies of this sort would offer a be? Such questions are farfromtrivial. They connect straightfor-
realistic basis for judging the standards of evidence in wardly to issues of integrity and professional responsibility, to
psychoanalysis. issues of how psychoanalysis is best understood as a social
Our second problem with Grunbaum's story concerns the activity, and how much it ought to be valued from an economic
character of the rivals to Freud's causal hypotheses. For, where- point of view.
as Grunbaum is quite happy to call attention to any possible rival Consider the following three models of psychoanalytic prac-
that he can find, he almost invariably falls back on one in tice and die implications of Grunbaum's diagnosis with regard to
particular. It is the hypothesis of suggestibility, that what what can honestly be asserted on behalf of each.
transpires in the analytic setting is a result of suggestion (of one 1. The misery alleviation model. On this model, psychoanalysis
sort or another) from the analyst to the analysand. What we find is devoted in the first instance to the alleviation of the human
problematic is that this generic possibility, like Descartes's misery caused by psychoneuroses. The orthodox version of the
demon, relies on a general, always-available doubt, indepen- theory claims first that such misery can only be alleviated if the
dent of any specific mode of instantiation or mechanism of analysand achieves veridical insight into the repressed material
operation. Used in this generic way, suggestibility, like its which is the source of his neurosis, and second that such insight
Cartesian counterpart, is just a place-holder for skeptical doubt, can best be brought about by standard analytic techniques: free
or fallibility. Real science has evolved a strategy to deal with it: association, dream analysis, and so on. The temporal and mone-
(1) Admit the possibility; (2) see whether in context it can be tary commitments involved in psychoanalysis are commonly
articulated (i.e. made specific, concrete, and testable); (3) if not, defended on the basis of these claims, as costs we are wisely
then bracket it off as a mere possibility and proceed with your willing to pay for a very valuable commodity.
work, returning periodically to (2). We would suggest that this is But there are serious problems with the latter claims. First,
how one should deal with Grunbaum's skepticism as well. many studies have shown that for a wide array of psychological
Certainly it cannot be ruled out diat what we think of as maladies some therapy is better than none, but no one type
psychoanalytic work is the result of suggestion only. But until stands out (except behavior therapy in some studies) as more
that possibility can be articulated and tested, the customary effective than any other. Second, Grunbaum has shown that
norms of investigation require that we consider it a mere there is virtually no reliable evidence for any of the distinctive
possibility. Thus if skeptical doubts about suggestibility (or ontological, etiological, or curative claims of orthodox psycho-
"placebo effect" or "contamination" - to use their promotional analysis, in large part because psychoanalysts, following Freud,
labels) were the major obstacle to accepting Freud's clinical have depended almost exclusively on clinical evidence as a
arguments, as Grunbaum's critique suggests, then indeed we source of theoretical support, despite its inherently problematic
would have to conclude, contra-Griinbaum, that psychoanalysis status.
is supported "in the clinic." If these criticisms are correct, then, pending extraclinical
A third problem results from Grunbaum's atomism; that is, vindication of the theory, simple honesty requires psycho-
his policy of submerging context and background, and judging analysts to refrain from claiming unique curative powers, in-
individual causal hypotheses separately. This disregards deed even relative superiority, for their theory as a technique
Freud's practice of leaning on the parallels between everyday for alleviating misery or as a vehicle for understanding human
psychological explanatory modes and those of psychoanalysis. personality. Grunbaum helps us understand why analysts want

238 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Commentary/Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
to make these claims, while at the same time making it perfectly potentially problematic theories. Second, recent evidence from cog-
clear why, given ordinary standards of intellectual and profes- nitive psychology undermines the view that powerful feelings of certain-
sional integrity, they shouldn't. 1 ty necessarily or, even usually, bespeak veridicality.
2. The eclectic model. The eclectic is also concerned with the - 3. The effects here could be considerable. Many psychologists,
alleviation of human misery and is sensitive to some of the latter psychiatrists, psychiatric social workers, and clinical psychologists in-
corporate psychoanalytic assumptions into their practice. Furthermore,
issues. He claims superiority for his particular brand of analysis, the majority of analytic patients are themselves mental health workers
however, on grounds that it selectively incorporates only some or related to mental health workers. See Fisher and Greenberg (1977,
elements of the orthodox theory alongside elements of self- pp. 298-99 on both points. [See also Prioleau et al.: "An Analysis of
psychology, objects-relations theory, and perhaps even non- Psychotherapy Versus Placebo Studies" BBS 6(2) 1983. J
psychoanalytic theories. The trouble with this strategy is that it
can only help support claims of relative therapeutic superiority
and deeper-than-usual insight into persons if the eclectic adap-
tations were made in response to extraclinical data rather than in Warranting interpretations
response to what the particular therapist or his mentors have
found effective in clinical situations. This is important and worth Alan Gauld and John Shorter
emphasizing. It is common in my experience for mental health Department of Psychology, University of Nottingham, Nottingham NC7
2RD, England
professionals of both Freudian and non-Freudian persuasions
(many behaviorists excluded) to respond to the worries of Along with the other hermeneuticians he castigates for their
philosophers of science by citing their own clinically motivated "multiple ontological and epistemic blunders," Griinbaum lists
eclecticism against the thoughtless orthodoxy of others. Such a us (to an extent correctly) as "quondam behaviorists," but also
defense, however, misses the central point about the contami- (quite incorrectly) as overlooking "that conversion to her-
nated status of such evidence. The eclectic analyst is in effect no meneutic psychology does not provide absolution from the
better off than the more orthodox analyst so long as his eclec- stated imperative to validate the causal hypotheses tacitly invok-
ticism is purely clinically motivated. ed by their avowed enterprise" (p. 56). And he goes on to
3. The self-knowledge model. This model is increasingly fash- characterize us as "insouciantly endorsing psychoanalytic im-
ionable. The basic idea is that regardless of how one assesses putations of hidden motives" (p.56) in our discussions, giving
psychoanalysis from the point of view of alleviating misery, it is force to his claim by (twice) gratuitously inserting into a phrase
uniquely fitted to the deepening of self-knowledge for both of ours - in which we say it is the task of a hermeneutical
neurotic and nonneurotic types. There is something prima facie psychologist "to elucidate by any method he can the 'meanings'
plausible here. The plausibility can be explained, however, in which . . . actions had for agents" (Gauld & Shotter 1977,
terms of the common-sense intuition that the more time one p. 80) - the word "unconscious" in square brackets before the
spends talking about and reflecting on oneself the greater the word "meanings," thus modifying the sense in which we use it in
likelihood of discovering or remembering things about oneself.2 an unwarranted (and, as we shall show, quite unwarrantable)
But there is nothing specifically about psychoanalysis (except way.
possibly the amount of time it takes), as far as we currently Thus Grunbaum contrives to place us among those he accuses
know, which uniquely fits it to the project of deepening self- of producing a "contrived reading" of Freud, when in fact, not
knowledge. Indeed, if the self-knowledge model is put forward only do we make no reference at all in our text to Freud, and
on specifically psychoanalytic grounds - for example, on only passing references to the unconscious and psycho-
grounds that the project of self-knowledge necessarily involves pathology, but we have been criticized by others for the omis-
recognition and reexperiencing of certain types of repressed sion. It is therefore both amusing and baffling to find ourselves
material, or that it is essential for initiates into the profession to condemned for doing what others have in fact condemned us for
gain psychoanalytic self-knowledge so that they will not defen- not doing.
sively obstruct the transference process - we are faced again Elsewhere we also fail to recognize ourselves in the refer-
with the essential point that it is these very hypotheses and the ences Grunbaum makes to us. Although he is right in saying that
assumptions embedded in them that have yet to be tested. we argue for the ineradicably hermeneutical nature of psycho-
The upshot of my remarks is this: Unless Grunbaum's argu- logical investigations, there is no way in which we feel he has
ments are effectively answered, neither orthodox analysts, properly portrayed our views. In short, we claim that Griin-
eclectics, nor advocates of the self-knowledge model can claim baum has misread us. But in so saying we raise issues beyond a
to be in possession of either a well-tested theory of human mere attempt to set the record straight. The problem bears
personality or a uniquely effective, indeed a more effective than some relation to the problem Grunbaum raises with psycho-
average, therapy - the intuitive pull to want to claim both analysis itself: If he has found something in our text which we
notwithstanding. Simple honesty requires members of the psy- certainly did not intend to be there and contend is not in fact
choanalytic community to acknowledge this much unless they there, but which he says is there, perhaps not "unconsciously"
have some convincing responses to Grunbaum's critique up but certainly "tacitly invoked," how can we warrant our claim
their sleeve. This simple honesty, if it occurs, will affect the way against his? Whose version of what our text conveys is correct,
the actual practice of psychoanalysis is viewed from within the not so much in some absolute sense of rightness or wrongness (as
profession and without, and it might quite reasonably require Grunbaum seems to require of insights or interpretations), but
adjustments in how valuable psychoanalysis is viewed from an in the sense of the most "fitting"?
economic point of view. 3 The problem is, as we see it, a hermeneutical one, a matter
first of providing an interpretation and then of deciding how that
NOTES interpretation can be validated or warranted. As we have said
1. Amos Tverslcy and Daniel Kahneman's (1974) well-known work on above, there is no single, special method for elucidating people's
the availability bias would help some in understanding why clinical sayings and doings, for clarifying the meaning of their actions.
evidence is so gripping and so convincing to clinicians. [See also Cohen: We do suggest, however, that agents often carry out their
"Can Human Irrationality Be Experimentally Demonstrated?" BBS 4(3) actions to fill a place in some wider scheme of things, and that
1981.] obscure actions are to be elucidated by describing the wider
2. One has to be careful even here of assuming some form of the "tally schemes of things and what the function of their actions is. In
argument." Folk psychology assumes that the agent knows best when, this we are in something of an advantageous position. Unlike
in the course of ordinary reflection, he has hit on some true insight into
Freud or other psychoanalysts, our problems are not ones
himself. There are two problems with this assumption. First, it is
doubtful that "ordinary reflection " is itself untutored or unguided by occurring in a relatively private interpersonal situation; our text

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 239


Commentary/Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis

exists publicly, as at least a vague or partial specification of our lead clinicians to observe significant relationships in their data
meaning. But like any other human activity, it is still open to even when the relationships are absent in the material present-
further specification, to different interpretations in fact - but ed (e.g. Chapman & Chapman 1967; 1969). Research has also
not to just any interpretation one pleases; interpretation is not, demonstrated that when observers enter into transaction with
as Grunbaum suggests, a matter of "mere fancy." He spurns the object of their observations, as in psychotherapy, they are
"thematic affinity" as a ground for elucidating "the 'meanings' likely to create the behavior they are looking for in a manner
which actions had for the agents." But he is too hasty. The analogous to a self-fulfilling prophecy (Rosenthal 1966). [See
vague, partially specified meanings of utterances, sentences, or also Rosenthal & Rubin: "Interpersonal Expectancy Effects"
arguments can only be given a proper, "fitting" interpretation BBS 1(3) 1978.] Thus the psychoanalyst's theoretical commit-
by being properly "placed" within the whole text of which they ment is iikely to influence both the patient's statements them-
are a part. Thus, when it comes to the interpretation of a text, selves and the manner in which they are organized, interpreted,
our text, others can consult it to see whether, as a whole, it and presented in writing.
would still have a coherent sense if the sections Grunbaum cites Even if we lay aside the question of therapist distortion and
or mentions were to have the meanings he claims for them. suggestion in the treatment, there are still problems with the
Freud, however, is not so well off Although at an interper- substantiation of Freud's ideas from his own presentations. For
sonal level it would be difficult to frame a more powerful example, Grunbaum is right in stating that Freud implied in his
criterion of the correctness of his interpretations than the early essays that the success of his treatment constitutes cogent
requirement that they must affect his patients' illnesses not their evidence for his psychoanalytic theory of personality. Yet no-
intellects (what Grunbaum calls the "tally argument"), Freud where in Freud's writings do we get an overview of his practice
cannot claim to be a merely neutral cipher in his exchanges with that would enable us to come to some objective conclusions
his patients. Actively, his treatment of them is informed by his about whether his treatment achieved better results than other
interpretations. Thus, he cannot avoid the charge that to an approaches or no treatment at all. In fact, over the course of his
extent he is producing the phenomena he claims merely to be career Freud himself seemed to become more doubtful about
observing. This is the character of the critique, a hermeneutical the results of his treatment and moved away from linking
critique, we would mount were it our task, not Griinbaum's, to theoretical truth with outcome. Probably Freud's most com-
criticize the foundations of psychoanalysis. Thus the foundations plete statement regarding his conclusions about therapy occur
of psychoanalysis are, we agree, shaky; patients probably are in his late career essay "Analysis Terminable and Interminable"
influenced by "suggestions" from the analyst. But if they are, (Freud 1937a). In this paper Freud begins to downplay the idea
one should not because of this be misled into dismissing it as that the results of analysis are unusually durable or powerful. As
unworthy of serious attention; on the contrary, one should stand he remarks, "One has the impression that one ought not to be
back in amazement at the peculiar properties of interpersonal surprised if it should turn out in the end that the difference
relations - a special study is required of such phenomena. between a person who has not been analysed and the behaviour
So, although Grunbaum finds difficulties with hermeneutical of a person after he has been analysed is not so thorough-going as
"reconstructions" of psychoanalysis, this does not mean that we aim at making it and as we expect and maintain it to be . . . 1
hermeneutical considerations (matters to do with the framing really cannot commit myself to a decision on this point nor do I
and warranting of interpretations) can be ruled out of investiga- know whether a decision is possible at the present time" (p.
tions into psychoanalysis. But the problem is, whose interpreta- 228). A similar reserved conclusion is exemplified by Freud's
tions are "fitting"? As Humpty-Dumpty put it: "Who's to be (1933a) remark, "I do not think our cures can compete with
master?" Who is to be the authority on people's meanings: first- those of Lourdes. There are so many more people who believe
person "patients," second-person analysts, or third-person out- in the miracles of the Blessed Virgin than in the existence of the
siders? In practice, decisions are of course made, and it is an unconscious" (p. 152).
interesting practical problem to study how they are or might be It is noteworthy, too, that a reading of Freud's cases reveals
arrived at. But the fact seems to be, contra Grunbaum, that no that relatively little stress was placed on describing outcome.
one single a priori principle, intraclinical or extraclinical, can be The aim was much more to detail and explain theoretical points.
formulated by which those decisions should be warranted. Furthermore, the described cases come from an early period in
Freud's career when his theories were undergoing significant
change. Elsewhere we have presented a detailed analysis of
Freud's case load and the outcome of his treatment (Fisher &
Greenberg 1977; 1985). This analysis shows that Freud sup-
The case against Freud's cases ported his theories through the detailed written discussion of
only 12 cases and the mention of 133 minor cases. He presented
Roger P. Greenberg minimal data except in a handful of select cases, and many of the
Department of Psychiatry, State University of New York, Upstate Medical presented cases would not be considered adequate examples of
Center, Syracuse, N.Y. 13210 psychoanalysis, either in terms of the techniques employed or
Grunbaum has produced a densely written, painstaking analysis theoretical explanations given. Thus, when Sherwood (1969)
tried to examine Freud's cases as a group he was impressed by
of the arguments Freud presented to justify his theoretical the fact that there were only six extended accounts of individual
hypotheses. Griinbaum's attack focuses not on the validity of patients. Almost all the accounts had basic shortcomings. Two
Freud's theoretical statements but on the idea that the psycho- were not really examples of Freud's therapy since he had no
analytic method, as applied in psychotherapy sessions, can be direct contact with either patient and two other cases, both with
used to generate credible, objective evidence to substantiate negative outcomes, were terminated in a brief period of time. Of
psychoanalytic theory. In recent years Seymour Fisher and I the remaining two cases, one was described as an unfavorable
have similarly struggled with the question of the scientific case of interminable analysis. The case of Paul Lorenz (the Rat
validity of Freud's thinking, and we have presented an extensive Man) represents Freud's only published record of a complete
review and analysis of all the empirical evidence bearing on and successful treatment.
Freud's ideas (Fisher & Greenberg 1977; 1985). Like Grun-
baum, we too concluded that it is extremely questionable to In sum, Freud's own writing describes in detail only four
assess the validity of ideas solely on the basis of case study cases he had seen using psychoanalytic treatment. Of these only
material. Such material is subject to multiple sources of bias and one showed any evidence of significant improvement. It is both
distortion. For example, it has been empirically demonstrated striking and curious that Freud chose to demonstrate the
in studies of illusory correlations that theoretical biases tend to usefulness of psychoanalysis through the presentation of largely

240 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Commentary7'Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
unsuccessful cases. Indeed, we were forced to conclude that (Goleman 1984). I must admit that I do not see how our work
Freud never presented any data, in statistical or case study could definitively refute Freud's idea, but I accept the spirit of
form, that demonstrated that his treatment was of benefit to a Reiser's remark, which I take to mean that we have indeed
significant number of the patients he himself saw (Fisher & "rendered Freud's repressed infantile wishes idea dubious by
Greenberg 1977; 1985). Equally puzzling, if one wishes to evidence suggesting a simpler alternative to the genesis of
equate theoretical validity with therapeutic success, is Freud's dreams" (Goleman 1984).
warning of the dangers in displaying too great an interest in In my opinion, Vogel is flatly wrong in stating that the
patient change. A caution against "furor therapeuticus" appears forebrain, as well as the brainstem, is "also necessary for the
in numerous places in Freud's writings (Oberndorf, Greenacre instigation, maintenance, and timing of most D episodes' (p.
& Kubie 1949). 1534). Jouvet's early work (1962) showed that this is not so; cats
Do all of these concerns about Freud's methodology for with only pons, medulla, and spinal cord intact generate REM
proving his assertions mean that his theoretical statements are states on schedule. In this experimental preparation the fore-
incorrect? Obviously not. We have demonstrated that there are brain (and all of its infantile wishes) are in the suction bottle! But
literally hundreds and hundreds of objective studies attesting to even if it were admitted that it is the whole brain and its whole
the merits of many Freudian postulates (Fisher & Greenberg mind that creates the dream, it could not weaken the essence of
1977; 1985). However, these ideas need to be evaluated inde- our basic argument: REM sleep (and therefore dreaming) are
pendently and cannot be successfully defended simply by point- automatic and nonmotivational processes! Developmental stud-
ing to Freud's case presentations. ies indicate that REM sleep may even predate the possible
occurrence of infantile wishes (since it occurs in utero).
I do not deny - rather I affirm most emphatically - that such
choices as dream plot, setting, dramatic personae, and scenario
Repressed infantile wishes as the instigators selection are the business of the forebrain. Enter personally
significant meaning. Enter emotionally significant interactions.
of all dreams Enter displacement, symbol formation, and the whole bag of
cognitive tricks that make dreams the delightful and strange
J. Allan Hobson
psychic experiences that they are. But the house lights are
Department of Psychiatry, Harvard Medical School, Boston, Mass. 02115
turned on in the brainstem basement and important cue-lines
In this epochal work Adolf Griinbaum devotes his Chapter 5 to a (most of them misleading) also issue from the nether promptings
review of Freud's dream theory. There are three aspects of this of the brainstem. The state of the brain-mind in REM sleep
review that may benefit from commentary: The first is Griin- dreaming is thus more analogous to the open, plastic situation of
baum's summary of data and the current status of the alternative the modern theater of the absurd than the fatalistic determina-
activation-synthesis theory of dreams advanced by our group tion of Sophocles's drama.
(Hobson & McCarley 1977); the second is Griinbaum's own I agree with Vogel (a priori) that it is the formal state of the
substantive analysis of the evidential basis for infantile wishes as forebrain that determines the formal state of the mind (by the
the instigators of all dreams; and the third is the more general general principle of isomorphism). It thus follows that there may
problem that surrounds anyone's attempt (Freud's or ours) to be more than one way to reach any given set of isomorphic
establish causality in the psychophysiological domain. The third states. For example, the occurrences of dreamlike mentation at
issue was discussed in our paper on the neurobiological origins sleep onset (or even in waking) when the pons is not in the REM
of psychoanalytic dream theory (McCarley & Hobson 1977). sleep promoting condition is easily accepted and explained as
Griinbaum's summary of the activation-synthesis hypothesis. the forebrain's capacity to achieve REM-state conditions with-
Griinbaum is generous in ascribing to us "the first theory out the pons. But such independence of forebrain (and, by
genuinely attempting to integrate the recent discoveries in the implication, dream mentation) from pontine control neither
neurophysiology of dreaming with the peculiarities of dream gainsays the power and significance of such control in REM
mentation" (p. 216). Our general strategy of isomorphism - the sleep (and its associated dreams) nor has any bearing whatsoever
mapping back and forth between mind (dream state) and brain on the role of repressed wishes (if any) in determining the formal
(REM state) forms - is all represented appreciatively and state of mind in waking, in sleep, or at its margins. It is simply
accurately. Recently I have presented new evidence on the irrelevant to this argument.
dream form commonly called "bizarreness" (Hobson, Hoffman, The more parsimonious explanation that I would favor is that
Helfand & Kostner 1983). I attribute bizarreness not to the as the brain-mind becomes increasingly input-independent
censor's effort to disguise acceptable wishes, as Freud assumed, (less data driven) it will become increasingly revelatory of its
but to such unusual and state-specific operating properties of own programmatic character: Image generation will increase (as
the brain in REM sleep as external sensory input blockade, in fantasy); fabulous narrative frames for these images and ideas
internal stimulus enhancement, and parallel channel activation. will be created; and associative fluidity will increase. One set of
Griinbaum recognizes that ours is not a simple nonsense theory conditions maximizing these operations - and adding its own
of the sort that flourished in the nineteenth century. Rather, we preemptive drive and informational confusion - is REM sleep.
suppose that the effort to create coherence and meaning by the REM sleep is caused by an explicitly detailed set of physiological
brain-mind in REM sleep-dreaming is substantial but unsuc- conditions in the pons.
cessful; both day residue and motivationally important themes This leads us naturally to Vogel's third argument, which is the
do enter into, and may even shape, dream content, but neither most problematical by far: Grunbaum writes that "purely neu-
is causal of the dream process itself or of its form. rophysiological findings cannot serve to test a posited lawlike
Griinbaum then turns to the counterarguments to activation- connection between purely psychological attributes, unless an
synthesis, by way of prelude to his own substantive critique of important condition is met: There must be an empirical ascer-
Freud's theory. With respect to the sleep researcher Vogel's tainment of the character of the correlation, if any, between the
(1978) paper, I would first point out that in a face-to-face debate pertinent physiological states and the hypothesized psychologi-
we convinced two-thirds of an audience of 2,000 of our peers cal ones" (p. 218).
that there were now substantial grounds for revising Freud's I agree of course with this premise. From a philosophical
dream theory (McDonald 1981; Roche Reports 1981). Since that point of view, isomorphism assumes that such correlations must
debate, Vogel's codebater, the psychoanalyst Morton Reiser, exist. Does Vogel doubt this? In making what Labruzza (1978)
has publicly stated that "Hobson and McCarley's work refutes has correctly chacterized as programmatic assertions, we were
Freud's idea that a dream is instigated by a disguised wish" trying to create a paradigm shift: from the ad hoc, ad hominem,

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 241


Commentary/Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
and post hoc narrative level of analysis of the particular dreams theory by measuring REM sleep before, during, and after
of particular individuals by particular psychoanalysts to the psychoanalysis to see whether the purported derepression of
predictive, generic, and formal level of analysis of any dream infantile wishes achieved in analysis - leads to decreased
from any person by any scientist. Vogel, Labruzza, and others pressure to dream. Here the philosophical and the physiological
are free to remain in the retrospective tradition if they like - but critique unite in a scientific test of the theory.
they should understand that what we are proposing is something Grunbaum supposes that this idea was overlooked because it
radically new and different. Since enunciating activation-syn- has not appeared explicitly in the published scientific literature.
thesis in 1977, our research program has produced three em- But such an idea was current in the early days of the modern
pirical studies showing the strongly and reliably predictive sleep research era when several related assumptions were put to
character of activation-synthesis with respect to formal dream the test and all gave negative results: The first was that REM
features: movement typology (McCarley & Hoffman 1981); sleep deprivation would specifically and inevitably lead to
spatial trajectory of movement (Hobson & Hoffman 1984); and psychosis (Dement 1960). It did neither (Kales, Hoedemaker,
bizarreness (Hobson et al. 1983). Jacobson & Lichtenstein 1964). The second was that patients
Griinbaum blurs a related but distinctly different issue raised with schizophrenic psychoses would have more (or less) REM
by Vogel, namely, the possibility that pontine activation of the sleep because of increased primary process drive. They had
forebrain may indeed be "the neural correlate of emergent, neither (Wyatt, Termini & Davis 1970). The third was that
archaic unconscious yearnings" (p. 1534). In other words, Vogel normal individuals with greater amounts of conflict would have a
would have us claim discovery of the physiological basis of greater need to dream (Snyder 1965). If anything, stress was
Freud's primary process! I accept Vogel's kind suggestion if he associated with decreased levels of REM sleep (Kales, Healey,
will agree with the following implication: The physiological Monroe, Bixler, Chamberlain & Soldatos (1981). Although no
activation of the brain, by the pons, in REM sleep is not only a one systematically compared analyzed with unanalyzed sub-
strong correlate of the distinctive mentation of dreaming, it is an jects, it can be assumed that at least one analysand was recorded;
obligate, i.e. causal correlate. We will come back to this point. had that subject been REM-sleep free, you can be sure you
GrQnbaum's critique of Freud's dream theory. Accepting would have heard about it!
Vogel's animadversions for his own rhetorical reasons, Griin- It is not widely appreciated that one of the reasons that the
baum then focuses his philosophical microscope on Freud's early enthusiasm for sleep science faded was because it failed to
science. His critique, which I find devastating for Freud's substantiate psychoanalytically derived claims. So ubiquitous
arguments, includes the following points: and deep were the psychoanalytic assumptions that clearly
1. Freud's claim that "the meaning [motive force for the contrary evidence had virtually no impact upon even em-
formation] of every dream is the fulfillment of a wish" (p.219) pirically rigorous sleep researchers such as Vogel (1978), Fisher
relies upon "the trustworthiness of his method of free associa- (1978), and Foulkes (1966). Thus, although Grunbaum's experi-
tion as a means of certifying the motivational causes of any and Tnentum crucis has not been done, one can safely predict that if it
all dreams" (p. 220). Elsewhere in his book, Griinbaum exposes were, and the results showed no change in REM sleep percent,
the methodological flaws of free association. the negative findings would be ignored or explained away by
2. To deal with the obvious exceptions of repetitive traumatic psychoanalysis. If, as Grunbaum avers, psychoanalysis never
dreams and nightmares, Freud acknowledged that the volitional was a rigorous science, why should it now want to become one,
impetus frequently miscarried but that "the attempt at the especially if preliminary but mounting evidence is all against it?
fulfillment of a wish" was ubiquitous. Although Griinbaum does
not chide him on this point, I myself find Freud's backtracking
tantamount to emphasizing the banal truism that self-interest is
a factor in all psychological transactions.
Some reflections on testing psychoanalytic
3. Griinbaum shows the inadequacy of both free association
and the exploration of dream symbolism as a probative tool in hypotheses
understanding the causation of dream mentation. Having dis-
pensed with the issue of symbolism via Freud's own downplay- Robert R. Holt
ing of the so-called manifest content, Grunbaum shows that free Department of Psychology, New York University, New York, N.Y. 10003
association played no cogent role in Freud's own approach to the The power and subtlety of the analysis and arguments Adolf
interpretation of dreams. Grunbaum presents in this book far surpass those of any pre-
4. The tour deforce of Griinbaum's argument is to show that vious philosophical evaluation of psychoanalysis. Moreover, it is
in interpreting his own "Irma dream," Freud failed to identify a real pleasure to encounter a critic who has Grunbaum's respect
any repressed motive, let alone an infantile one. Instead, the for his target, an admiration for Freud's gifts and contributions
putative motive was an aggressive impulse of which Freud had that does not blind him to defects but impels him to study his
been fully conscious only the day before. Activation-synthesis subject's works as extensively and intensively as is necessary to
would deal with the incorporation of this material (which even do the job. The result is a work of such substance that it must be
by Freudian standards is defined as day residue and not as a carefully studied by all serious students of psychoanalysis. It
repressed unconscious impulse) by the simpler concepts of contains so much that a review of the brevity needed here can
recency and intensity of experience. touch on only a few issues among many that cry out for extended
5. Grunbaum then goes on to show that in his dream theory discussion. (See Holt, 1985, for some further discussion.)
Freud was essentially repeating the argument that he used to Grunbaum's method is to concentrate on the clinical theory of
establish the repression of etiology of neuroses, and all the flaws psychoanalysis as Freud formulated it, although his frequent
of that argument were likewise repeated. But if no new evidence reference to the works of other, subsequent analysts leaves no
was actually adduced, then the dream theory adds nothing doubt that he has read widely and that his knowledge is not
substantial to the fabric of the work. It is in this way that the confined to the Freudian canon. Nevertheless, his method does
unified structure of Freud's thought is at once a strength and a have some perhaps unintended consequences. The book will be
weakness: If any part is fundamentally in error, all the parts are read by many who are concerned with evaluative judgments; yet
in doubt. Grunbaum, for his philosophical reasons, and I, on those may be of two rather different kinds. First, a historical
psychophysiological grounds, thus believe Freud's dream theo- judgment about Freud and his theorizing. Here there can be no
ry to be essentially groundless. doubt: Grunbaum produces the most substantial indictment of
6. The reservations that accumulate additively now lead Freud as a scientist that we have yet seen. But the second kind of
Grunbaum to a genial proposal: Why not experimentally test the judgment is probably of interest to far more readers; it pertains

242 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Commentary/Grunbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
to contemporaneous psychoanalysis as a whole. It will take a As to method, Griinbaum has done an undoubted service in
particularly judicious reader not to jump to the conclusion that pointing out the danger that suggestion of various sorts may
Griinbaum has dealt psychoanalysis a body blow if he has not seriously contaminate the data yielded by psychoanalytic pa-
fatally wounded it. Yet I don't believe that he set out to do a tients in their misnamed "free associations." He would put it
hatchet job; it is quite evident that he is not driven by hostility or much more strongly, however- too strongly, in my view. With
spite. the collapse of the tally argument, Griinbaum seems to say, the
True, Crunbaum punctures the complacency of many a psy- data of the clinical hour become hopelessly biased by sug-
choanalyst of today, who takes for granted a great many proposi- gestion. He gives the impression that he overgeneralizes from
tions that have been destroyed by this book - notably, the the weakness of the traditional clinical method to the
beliefs that Freud's method of clinical research enabled him not uselessness of the data generated in the psychoanalytic hour for
only to make important discoveries and to frame bold hypoth- more rigorous research. As Luborsky, Dahl, Gill, Weiss &
eses, but to verify them scientifically. I believe that Griinbaum Sampson, Silberschatz and others have shown, once the ses-
exaggerates the dearth of supportive evidence for Freud's theo- sions are tape-recorded and transcribed, their data can be
ries, but it must be acknowledged and clearly understood that subjected to carefully controlled, hypothesis-testing research.
the traditional method of clinical research - simply treating Griinbaum has not yet acknowledged this point in print, though
patients by the standard psychoanalytic method, reflecting on in conversation he generally concedes it. Moreover, one can
what one recalls of the process and what little a psychoanalyst then set about examining the extent to which therapists do
usually knows of the outcome, and writing papers about one's demonstrably "lead " their patients or in effect shape their
conclusions - has one and only one scientific value: serving as a productions by a kind of operant conditioning.
source of hypotheses. Furthermore, I hope that this book drives Griinbaum's argument about suggestion is based on the
home to every psychoanalyst who reads it the absolute necessity demonstration that the psychoanalytic hour is logically faulty as
that psychoanalytic hypotheses be tested. Psychoanalysis will an investigative method - that contamination can take place.
not survive, let alone progress and prosper, unless the profes- Granted, it can; but how far are the productions of any particular
sion takes major responsibility to encourage and make possible patient biased by the analyst's gross or subtle suggestions? That
the controlled and rigorous forms of research that can provide is an empirical matter, one that very much needs to be studied.
validating evidence for the clinical theory, the only testable part It is quite possible for a patient to be much affected by sug-
of Freud's output. gestion in one respect and for the analytic data to be adequately
Psychoanalytic theory and research are in serious trouble, but "clean" in many other respects. As Cook and Campbell (1979)
the outlook is not as hopeless as Griinbaum at times seems to show, in actual research on important human problems we can
believe. As to the theory, one of its defects is easily remediable. rarely approximate the cleanliness and epistemic irre-
Freud believed that one made a generalization into a scientific proachability of laboratory experiments; yet quasi experiments
law by stating it in the most universal and dogmatic terms. are none the less useful ways to contribute to knowledge. Any
Hence, he sought to produce a theory of all human behavior one of them has flaws, demonstrable vulnerabilities to a loss of
regardless of time or place by generalizing from what he ob- internal validity. Nevertheless, progress toward truth is possi-
served within the four walls of one Viennese consulting room ble if we use multiple routes, each of which is fallible, but in a
during the first third of the twentieth century, and from what he different way. Hence, if the results of nonclinical investigations
was told by a demographically very restricted sample of people. converge with the findings from clinicians especially from
But quite aside from errors traceable to his unrepresentative therapists of rather different persuasions - we may end up with
sample, he sought to explain human behavior by postulating an approximative conjoint method with some epistemic defen-
universal rather than probabilistic laws. As Benjamin Rubin- sibility. That would increase if the different methods' vul-
stein (1975) has demonstrated, the latter alone are appropriate nerability to error were carefully explored and turned out to be
for the clinical theory, and he has set about the necessary task of complementary. For it can happen that despite apparently
reformulating it accordingly. Trained as a physician, Freud major differences in method, clinical and nonclinical investiga-
assumed that hysteria and obsessive-compulsive neurosis were tions might share one or more of the same threats to internal
true diseases, which therefore must be caused in important part validity, in which case the replicated result would be moot.
by specific pathogens. Today, it seems doubtful that 'mental Griinbaum is mainly concerned with what Cook and Camp-
illnesses' exist in the realm of neurosis with etiologies as specific bell (1979) call internal validity - the degree to which an
as that of tuberculosis, where the role of the specific bacillus is investigation yields unambiguously interpretable findings. Yet
crucial, important though other considerations may be in deter- it is worth stressing that laboratory experiments often show up
mining the seriousness of the illness. At the least, in the realm of as short on external validity: They can be generalized safely only
mental health the disease theory is controversial, and there to peculiar and limited populations of people and situations. As
appear to be no serious problems in converting what Freud Brunswik (1956) put it, they lack ecological validity, in that their
thought to be specific etiologies into probabilistic form. sampling of "objects" or behavior settings is nonrepresentative.
Hence, to take one of Griinbaum's favorite examples, the Griinbaum devotes most of his attention to etiological hypoth-
presumed pathogenicity of repressed conflicts concerning ho- eses, but there are many other kinds in the clinical theory of
mosexuality for paranoia needs to be reformulated something psychoanalysis. Thus, though I fully agree that retrospective
like this: Persons who experience conflict about homosexual data are inadequate for the testing of etiologies, recorded
wishes and/or cross-sexual identifications, and who repress such analyses can be used and are being used in the relatively
thoughts from awareness, are more likely than others to develop rigorous testing of a variety of other kinds of psychoanalytic
paranoid symptoms. And further: Persons who have paranoid hypotheses.
symptoms, particularly delusional thoughts of being per- In an important paper that usefully complements Griin-
secuted, are more likely than others to have a history of re- baum's arguments, Rubinstein (1975) distinguishes several
pressed conflicts concerning homosexual wishes and/or cross- kinds of propositions that make up the clinical theory: In de-
sexual identifications. Unfortunately, such propositions are scending order of abstractness, they are general, special, and
more difficult to test, for a single contrary case cannot refute particular clinical hypotheses. The first class includes, for exam-
them as was true of Freud's universalistic formulation. They ple, propositions concerning the existence and functioning of
require statistical research of a kind for which psychoanalysts unconscious motives and fantasies. Even propositions as broad
generally lack training, much less experience. Nevertheless, and basic as those on the pathogenicity of repressed conflicts,
they are clearly testable in a straightforward way, albeit not in cited by Griinbaum as making up Freud's theory of repression,
the analytic hour. fall into the class of special clinical hypotheses.

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 243


Commentaryi'Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
It needs to be pointed out that most of the research so far by the clinical knowledge accumulated within the frame of this
conducted on recorded and transcribed psychoanalyses tests Socratic enterprise.
particular clinical hypotheses, which concern individual pa- (b) The psychoanalytic collective thinking method: The expe-
tients and are most amenable to testing. As Rubinstein argues, riences gained by each psychoanalyst in the analytic setting are
at this level the higher-level hypotheses are treated as assump- pooled together in a highly unsystematic way, comparable to
tions. To the extent that such particular hypotheses are con- ethnologists coming home from their field work and trying to
firmed, he points out, our faith in the credibility of the more systematize their collected data. This process is heavily influ-
abstract clinical hypotheses tends to be supported. Unfortu- enced by the prevailing conceptions - theoretical and clinical -
nately, the linkage between the general and the special clinical of the group in which the individual psychoanalyst has been
hypotheses is loose enough that the validity of the latter does not trained and with which he works. This feature accounts for the
necessarily entail the validity of the former. Indeed, Rubinstein academic aspects of psychoanalytic groups, which have been an
is at pains to demonstrate that the special hypotheses are object of criticism from prominent outsiders within the psycho-
consistent with a variety of general theories; hence, it is ex- analytic movement from very early on. However, if science
tremely difficult - Rubinstein says, impossible - to test the must also be regarded as a social enterprise, this kind of collec-
general clinical hypotheses with any psychological data what- tive thinking can be found in all kinds of scientific endeavours. If
ever. Data from such disciplines as neurophysiology may, how- the concept of clinical science has any meaning at all, it refers to
ever, eventually prove adequate to the task. this process of mutual stabilizing of intervention procedures and
Reverting to my above distinction between historical and interpretations. For psychoanalysis as a method to be more than
contemporary implications of Griinbaum's critique, I'd like to a mere observational technique, aiming to achieve change in
argue that it is neither desirable nor important to put psycho- patients, it must share with many other respectable scientific
analytic theory on an imaginary prisoner's block and try it in a enterprises the epistemic problems of intervention paradigms.
methodological court, seeking a verdict of innocent or guilty. One would wish that philosophers of science like Griinbaum
Obviously, it has serious shortcomings. The more interesting would devote more attention to the epistemological evaluation
question is what can be done about it. Can the theory be of such processes of joint collaboration of many people over
salvaged? Can we not find ways of using the data yielded by many decades. To belittle clinical wisdom as Griinbaum does
psychoanalytic treatment, which have impressed so many as when he quotes Luborsky and Spence (1978) on the present
uncommonly rich and revealing? If Griinbaum could be per- state of quantitatively controlled knowledge versus the vast
suaded to apply his formidable talents to these questions, all body of clinical knowledge bypasses the fact that psychoanalytic
who still hope for a scientific psychoanalysis would be even more therapy, although probably built on epistemically weak founda-
in his debt. tions, has proven to be as effective as other psychological
treatment modalities. Why does it work at all, and why has
ACKNOWLEDGMENT behavior therapy, originally claimed to be rooted in experimen-
Preparation of this commentary was supported by a United States Public tal psychology, nowadays been reduced to a synonym for "meth-
Health Service Research Career Award, Grant 5-KO6:MH-12455, from odologically controlled psychotherapy," rejecting any simplistic
the National Institute of Mental Health. theoretical embedding in learning theory?
(c) The extraclinical method: A small number of psycho-
analysts have engaged in systematic research on therapeutic
processes based on careful documentation of the transactions of
Validating psychoanalysis: what methods for the analytic session. Considering the complex issues involved in
what task? building up a research methodology that can claim to capture
the decisive features of the therapeutic process, the results as
Horst Kachele compiled by Luborsky and Spence (1978) or Masling (1983) are
Department of Psychotherapy, University of Ulm, D 7900 Ulm, Federal highly encouraging; research begins to influence therapy, as
Republic of Germany reflected in Luborsky's own reversal of his 1969 opinion that
To clarify the various issues involved in Griinbaum's critical "research cannot influence practice" (Luborsky 1984, p. 22).
appraisal of psychoanalysis it is imperative to differentiate Griinbaum's repeated plea for experimental studies may be
among three methods used by psychoanalysts: pertinent for selected parts of the clinical theory.
(a) The psychoanalytic method, a clinical technique for ob- We have been able to show in a recently completed experi-
serving a patient by listening to him in a state of evenly mental study on the relation between trait anxiety measured by
suspended attention and influencing him by giving him "an- Spielberger's test and free association measured with Bordin's
swers" to his "questions." This takes place within a dialogue; it scales that there is an inverse linear relationship which over-
has been a self-misunderstanding of psychoanalysts to conceive rides the impact of analyst/patient physical positions (face to face
their interpretative activity, including the so-called preparatory versus lying on a couch). The results will have therapeutic
actions such as confrontations, clarifications, and even some- relevance to the extent that the analogue character of such
times questions, to be similar to an independent variable intro- experiments can be demonstrated by parallel investigations of
duced by an experimenter in a laboratory setting. Research on transference-resistance features (Kachele, Holzer, Heckmann
actual tape recordings of sessions has amply shown that psycho- & Robben 1985).
analytic dialogues are but a highly technical and rule-specified We agree with Griinbaum that the final validation of the
variant of discourse. Discourse analysis has only to spell out causal hypothesis concerning neurogenesis would require large-
the specifics of the conversational rule system that underlies scale epidemiological studies like Schepanck (1984), twin-stud-
the manifold clinical recommendations. The "questions" of the ies (Schepanck 1974) and developmental studies such as Emde's
patient are represented by the sections of his personality he work on the psychobiology of emotions in infancy (1980). There
does not understand and are initially presented in the form of is a vast amount of work before us, and it may turn out that
symptoms, which are then transformed into relational patterns psychoanalysis as founded by Freud will undergo major changes
(transference neurosis). These enable the analyst to elucidate for or even dissolve into a new frame of reference. This possibility is
the patient what he is asking for. The "answers" of the analyst echoed in Griinbaum's repeated observation that "It may per-
consist of metaeommunications about what the patient wants haps still turn out that Freud's brilliant intellectual imagination
(e.g. see Flader, Grodzicki & Schroter 1982). was quite serendipitous for psychopathology and other facets of
human conduct." In this statement he comes very close to an
We agree with Griinbaum's verdict that the causal role of any
intuitive understanding of why psychoanalysts are not so dis-
agent in the etiology of neurosis cannot be definitely established

244 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Commentaryi'Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
turbed with the epistemic weakness of their enterprise as so Accepting Griinbaum's argument, as this commentator does,
brilliantly exposed by Griinbaum. one is then left with the question, "What types of experimental
evidence are appropriate for testing psychoanalytic proposi-
tions?" The conventional wisdom among psychoanalysts has
been that only data derived from the psychoanalytic treatment
The scientific tasks confronting situation, "from the couch," are suitable for testing these hy-
potheses. Here again Griinbaum tackles a difficult issue with
psychoanalysis insight and persistence, and, in my opinion, convincingly dem-
onstrates that the psychoanalytic treatment situation cannot by
Gerald L. Klerman itself be an adequate arena for gathering data to test the scien-
Department of Psychiatry, Harvard Medical School; Stanley Cobb tific validity of psychoanalytic hypotheses.
Research Laboratories, Department of Psychiatry, Massachusetts General
Hospital, Boston, Mass. 02114
After finishing Griinbaum's book I was left with the distress-
ing conclusion that the scientific status of psychoanalysis re-
Griinbaum's important book deals with a controversy of long mains to be established and that its establishment will require
standing - the scientific status of psychoanalysis. This topic has evidence from investigations outside the psychoanalytic treat-
been the subject of controversy for almost 100 years, ever since ment situation. Important issues remain: the nature of appro-
Freud's first psychoanalytic publication in the mid-1880s after priate control groups, sampling problems, use of quantitative
his return from studying with Charcot at the Salpetriere in measures, development of reliable and valid measures of intra-
Paris. Psychoanalysis, particularly the Freudian form, has had psychic functioning such as defenses, conflicts, self-representa-
great acceptance in literary circles, among social theorists and tions.
among mental health professionals, including psychiatrists, There is one important topic related to the scientific status of
clinical psychologists and social workers. However, its accep- psychoanalysis that Grunbaum does not address - the evidence
tance among scientists has been mixed, at best. for efficacy of psychoanalysis as a therapy. To the extent that
"Is psychoanalysis a science?' This question has reemerged in psychoanalysis makes claims for therapeutic value for patients
the past few years, particularly because of the discord around with conditions such as obsessive-compulsive disorder, hys-
the secrecy surrounding the Freud archives and the biographi- teria, borderline personality disorder, and narcissistic person-
cal studies of Freud's changing position on the seduction theory ality disorder, it should be subject to the same requirements for
(Malcolm 1984a; Masson 1984). Furthermore, the major ad- evidence as any other medical or psychiatric procedure, such as
vances in neuroscience require a realignment of psychoanalytic pharmacologic agents, surgery, or other forms of psychotherapy
theory (Reiser 1984). (Klerman 1983). In all fields of medicine, including psychiatry,
Freudians have claimed that psychoanalysis has three the randomized controlled trial has become the standard mode
aspects: of testing claims about the efficacy of interventions, most often
1. Psychoanalysis is a unique method for gaining access to treatment interventions, but also preventive and rehabilitative
unconscious mental processes as manifested in free association, interventions. In the past two decades, the controlled trial
dreams, slips of the tongue, and neurotic and psychotic symp- design has been applied to the evaluation of social interventions,
tom formation; such as the negative income tax plans and types of health
2. Psychoanalytic theory is a corpus of multiple theories insurance payments (Seidman 1984). On this issue, psycho-
about normal and abnormal mental functioning. Theories about analysis, along with the other psychotherapies, is the subject of
normal psychological functioning include the development of current scientific and public policy controversy, not only be-
mental processes, particularly during childhood, and the impact cause of the absence of available evidence as to its efficacy for
of childhood experiences upon adult functioning. In addition, specific conditions but, more important, because of disagree-
there are a complex of psychoanalytic theories about different ment over the types of research designs and evidence that would
mental disorders, such as schizophrenia, obsessive-compulsive be considered valid. [See Prioleau et al: "An Analysis of Psycho-
neurosis, depression, melancholia, and hysteria. therapy versus Placebo Studies" BBS 6(2) 1983.]
3. Psychoanalysis is a form of psychotherapy. Its derivative, Grunbaum correctly titles his book The Foundations of Psy-
psychodynamicaily oriented psychotherapy, has been the domi- choanalysis. Having demonstrated that psychoanalysis is a natu-
nant mode of treatment within American psychiatry and related ral science and potentially capable of verification, but in need of
mental health fields. evidence from sources other than the psychoanalytic treatment
The current scientific criticism is mainly focused on the setting, he has laid the foundation for a psychoanalytic research
second aspect, the theories and hypotheses about normal and program. It remains for the psychoanalysts and their colleagues
psychopathological mental functioning. The criticism comes in the philosophy of science, psychology, neurobiology, and
from two sources. First, from within psychoanalysis, the her- epidemiology to construct upon this foundation a scientific
meneutics view has disclaimed any possible scientific value of structure based on empirical evidence.
psychoanalysis and focuses instead on the special meanings that
experience and thought has for the individual. The her-
meneutics view denies the possibility that psychoanalysis can
contribute to a general psychology of human functioning.
Second, many philosophers and practitioners of science,
relying heavily on Popper's principle of falsification, have chal- Griinbaum's philosophical critique of psycho-
lenged the status of psychoanalysis as a science by questioning analysis: Or what I don't know isn't knowledge
whether psychoanalytic propositions are capable of verification
by empirical methods. Paul Kline
Department of Psychology, University of Exeter, Exeter EX4 4QG, England
Griinbaum addresses both of these sources of criticism. He
refutes the hermeneutics view and argues convincingly that In this most carefully reasoned attack on psychoanalysis, Griin-
psychoanalysis from the time of Freud claims to be a natural baum shows that Freud's clinical methods failed to support his
science and is entitled to be judged on this basis. Having dealt theorising, especially in the case of the theory of repression, the
with the hermeneutics critique, Griinbaum examines the issue cornerstone of psychoanalysis. In addition, he demonstrates
of the potential verification of scientific propositions and dis- that modern hermeneutic interpretations are equally inconsis-
agrees with Popper's assertion that psychoanalysis is intrin- tent. He concludes that Freudian theory is essentially an unsup-
sically untestable. ported dogma that requires extraclinical evidence for its asser-

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 245


Commentary/Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis

tions. This is a task for the future, and what experimental ence for male pictures. I cannot believe that Grunbaum se-
evidence there is, Grunbaum argues, fails to support the theory. riously supports these ad hoc arguments.
In my view, however, these conclusions are flawed by omis- In summary, I accept the philosophical analyses of Grunbaum
sions and weaknesses in Griinbaum's arguments and these I concerning the lack of real evidence for Freud's theory in the
shall now examine. Grunbaum admits that he is relatively Freudian corpus and his attack on the hermeneutic interpreta-
inexperienced in the field of psychotherapeutic process and tion. However, his conclusions, for reasons I have shown, do not
treatment outcome and that he was assisted by Rachman and seem to survive careful scrutiny.
Eysenck at the Maudsley. These unswerving opponents of
psychoanalytic theory have indubitably coloured his approach,
as shall be seen below.
First, these conclusions are not new. Farrell (1961), Kline
(1972; 1981), and Fisher and Greenberg (1977) have all made Psychoanalysis: Science or hermeneutics?
these points - that the theory is not well supported per se but
requires objective experimental evidence. Valerii Leibin
Griinbaum's case, however, is not well made because he has Institute of Methodological Research and Academy of Sciences, Moscow,
U.S.S.R.
assumed that if the theory of repression can be invalidated
psychoanalytic theory will come tumbling down. However Far- An understanding of the essence of Freud's psychoanalytic
rell (1961), whose work, surprisingly, is not referred to (is this an teachings is always accompanied by a variety of interpretations,
influence of the Maudsley?), has shown that Freudian theory is which sometimes directly oppose one another. It is no accident
not one coherent theory at all but rather a collection of theories that a multicolored mosaic of diverse opinions about both the
some of which may turn out to be true, others false. Thus an theory and the practice of psychoanalysis can be observed in the
attack even on a central tenet such as repression cannot make literature devoted to discovering the conceptual structures of
Grunbaum's point. Freud. Grunbaum's book, which contains a critical analysis not
But what about this attack itself? Has Grunbaum really shown only of psychoanalysis but also of current ways of looking at
that there is nothing to the Freudian theory of repression? I psychoanalysis, clearly demonstrates the extreme diversity of
accept his point that Freudian observations per se cannot interpretations in research on Freud's psychoanalytic teachings.
support the theory. However, let us examine Grunbaum's No matter what aspects of Freud's psychoanalytic teachings
rejection of the experimental evidence. are studied, discussions usually center on the question of
First Grunbaum attacks my own arguments (Kline 1981) for whether or not psychoanalysis is a science. The point of depar-
the existence of repression on the grounds that this is a far cry ture for these reflections is Freud's own assumption that psycho-
from showing that repression is involved in the aetiology of analysis is a part of psychology and as such could be nothing but a
neuroses. However, I never claimed the latter. My point (as a natural science. As far as the status of psychoanalysis is con-
careful reading of my book would show) is that the theory of cerned, two points of view can be detected: Some researchers
repression requires (a) that there be a mechanism of repression believe that psychoanalysis really is a science; others think it
and (b) that this be involved in neurosis. My claim involved (a) does not thus qualify and can be viewed rather as a kind of
only - see p. 226 - "Perceptual defence studies have shown that hermeneutics having to do with the interpretation of psycholog-
there is a mechanism of repression." ical phenomena.
As to the claimed aetiology of repression in respect of neu- Throughout his book, Grunbaum subjects the arguments of
rosis, I agree with Grunbaum that there is no definitive evi- the advocates of both points of view to critical scrutiny. He
dence. However, the work of Silverman (1980) and Percept comes out most sharply, however, against the methodological
genetics (Kragh & Smith 1970) cannot be discussed without errors in the hermeneutical interpretation of psychoanalysis
even a mention. There is something in the work that requires (reflected in the works of Habermas, Ricoeur, and Klein (1976),
refutation. as well as in Popper's (1974) treatment of the subject) as a
In his conclusions Grunbaum claims that the experimental discipline which does not meet the criteria of a true science. At
evidence is poor. Now Fisher and Greenberg (1977) and Kline any rate, his polemics with Habermas, Ricoeur, and Klein, on
(1981) cite more than 1,000 objective studies of psychoanalytic the one hand, and with Popper on the other, gives specialists a
theories. Few of these are even referred to by Grunbaum. chance to weigh all the "pros" and "cons" in the consideration of
Those he does cite are experimentally weak, using, for example, psychoanalysis as a natural science.
the Mosher guilt scale, of unknown validity. To cite such work However, it seems to me that Grunbaum's polemic, which in
reveals that Grunbaum has a poor grasp of experimental psy- many ways he formulates clearly and carries to its logical conclu-
chology. This is indeed hardly surprising, for he is trained as a sion, is conducted within the framework of those "rules of the
philosopher not as a psychologist, and there are limits to the game" set by the traditional view of psychoanalysis, in spite of
knowledge even of philosophers as distinguished as Grunbaum. the new shifts in thinking which are certainly present in the
This limitation is strongly brought home by Grunbaum's citing
book. I have in mind particularly the initial thesis of this book as
as a good experimental study the work of Eysenck and Wilson
(1973). This work consists of a number of papers already cited in well as the studies with whose authors Grunbaum is carrying on
Kline (1972), printed in full and interpreted anew by these his dispute. This thesis is clearly expressed in the very way the
authors so that Freudian theory remains unsupported. question regarding the status of psychoanalysis as a science is
posed. After all, Griinbaum is disputing the arguments which
In his book Grunbaum shows himself to be a master of deny the status of a natural science to the clinical theory of
philosophical disputation and detailed argument. It seems to me psychoanalysis. He also opposes the criteria for truly scientific
that citing Eysenck and Wilson indicates either that he has not status advanced by Popper. And here is where we are con-
read it carefully or that the rigorous standards of argument he fronted with a kind of circular reasoning: No matter what
uses against Freudian theory, he fails to use on work with which arguments are adduced, either in defense of or against the
he agrees. For example, Eysenck and Wilson explain the finding evaluation of psychoanalysis as a science, in the final analysis,
that paranoids look longer at pictures of men (as predicted in each researcher is left with his own opinion. Habermas,
Freudian theory) as follows: Paranoids are suspicious because Ricoeur, or Popper can, of course, be criticized for their inade-
they are more suspicious of men who pose a greater threat. In quate, one-sided conception of psychoanalysis, all the more so
addition, they are alert to the "shrink's" attempt to label them since there are substantial reasons to feel this way. For their
homosexual, and this explains their emotion in showing prefer- part, in answering Grunbaum's criticism, these researchers

246 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Commentary IGrunbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
could probably have cited less substantial counterarguments in not in the sense of the traditionally understood philosophy of
defense of their own views. The detached, nonprofessional science, but in the sense of whatever exactly it is that can be
observer is left simply to accept whichever point of view seems called a psychoanalytical philosophy.
to him best-founded and free of contradictions. But the spe- A critical understanding of psychoanalytical philosophy is, in
cialist in psychoanalysis will most probably be impressed pre- my opinion, one of the little-studied but promising directions of
cisely by those arguments which confirm his own view, irrespec- research. The methodological difficulties of such research lie in
tive of whether or not he recognizes psychoanalysis as having the fact that, in contradistinction to the clearly expressed pro-
the status of a science. nouncements on psychoanalysis as a science, Freud sought in
Be that as it may, the question of whether or not psycho- every way possible to dissociate himself from any kind of philos-
analysis is an authentic science is in most cases decided in ophy which he identified with metaphysics. However, the
advance by the criteria applied. The focus of the question "psychoanalysis of psychoanalysis" allows us to speak of the fact
remains Freud's own definition of psychoanalysis as a science. that psychoanalytical philosophy was always a hidden intention
In his philosophical critique of the foundations of psychoanalysis and goal of Freud's teachings. Such research can become an
and its various interpretations, Griinbaum rejects precisely this indispensable supplement to Grunbaum's philosophical cri-
definition. But is Freud's definition of psychoanalysis really the tique, thereby contributing to a satisfactory discovery of the
only one? Even though in a number of his works Freud did foundations of psychoanalysis. In particular, it can prove useful
strive to emphasize the natural science status of psychoanalysis, in clarifying Grunbaum's thoughts as to Freud's rejection of his
did he not give other definitions of it as well? Unfortunately, to "ontologically reductive" concept of the scientific status of
judge by the existing literature, scholars do not pose these psychoanalysis in favor of its "epistemological status" (see [3]
questions at all. Griinbaum's book is no exception in this above), and his notion that Freud's criterion for being scientific
respect. was "methodological and not ontologically reductive" (see [6]).
Nevertheless, Freud's works themselves offer extremely var- But this requires a thorough exposure of the essence of psycho-
ied definitions of psychoanalysis. His treatment of it as a natural analytical philosophy in its ontological, epistemological, and
axioiogical perspectives.
science is but one. One can distinguish at least ten other
definitions of psychoanalysis provided by Freud, which can be
reduced to the following. Psychoanalysis in Freud's own words NOTE
is: (1) a part of psychology as a science; (2) an indispensable tool Translated by Rebecca Park, Slavic Studies Department, Princeton
of scientific research; (3) an impartial instrument, such as, for University.
example, the calculation of infinitely small parameters; (4) a tool
that enables the ego to master the id; (5) any research that
recognizes "transference " and "resistance" as basic premises of
his work; (6) an auxiliary method of investigating the most Evidence to lessen Professor Grunbaum's
diverse areas of a person's mental life; (7) one of the ways to
attain self-cognition (8) the art of interpretation; (9) not a scien- concern about Freud's clinical inference
tific or tendentious investigation but a therapeutic device; (10) a method
method of treating the mentally ill.
As can be seen, the range of Freud's own definitions of Lester Luborsky
psychoanalysis is rather extensive. It is absolutely clear that for Department of Psychiatry, University of Pennsylvania, Philadelphia, Pa.
19104
some researchers who accept definitions 1 and 2 psychoanalysis
emerges as a genuine science, whereas for others, who are Professor Griinbaum is a satisfying person to engage in discus-
inclined toward definitions 7 and 8, it can be perceived as a sion because of the probity of his evaluations as well as a rare
henneneutics which has nothing in common with the natural responsiveness to cogent evidence. I offer evidence that bears
science methods of cognition. For this reason, the numerous on the first two of his three "fundamental questions."
and unceasing debates that have been going on for decades Grunbaum's first fundamental question. Is the retrospective
about just what the psychoanalysis founded by Freud really is, clinical method of psychoanalytic investigation in the treatment
in what direction it should be developed, and what future awaits setting critically crippled by an artifact - the patient's com-
it are far from irrelevant. And it isn't just that a polysemous pliance to the analyst's expectations? (I believe the question can
interpretation of psychoanalysis is a function of the natural also be asked in this way: Is the apparent accuracy of the
scientific and philosophical dispositions of the researchers who therapist's inferences about the patient's past and present func-
"read" and interpret Freud in various ways. We must reckon tioning a product of the patient's compliance to the analyst's
with the real fact of ambiguities in the definition of psycho- expectations?)
analysis by its very founder. The question is framed as though a yes or no answer were
Griinbaum's book, in my view, aids in clarifying certain possible. Actually, there are several answers, depending on the
aspects of psychoanalysis which might help determine its scien- several kinds of inferences from the session, and all of these
tific status. In this sense it contributes to the critical interpreta- should be a matter of degree rather than all or none. I will
tion of the foundations of psychoanalysis and, it must be sup- discuss three kinds of inferences from sessions corresponding to
posed, will stimulate further research, since specialists in this three facets of the question.
field of theory and practice will hardly be able to develop their Facet A: To what extent are the therapist's inferences accu-
own ideas fruitfully without having first thought through their rate about the parallel between the patient's current rela-
positive and negative stances on the arguments of the author. tionship patterns and past parental relationships?
However, other aspects of the psychoanalytic teachings of This question is framed purely in terms of the degree of
Freud connected with other definitions of psychoanalysis re- parallel between current relationship patterns and past rela-
main underresearched. It seems that Grunbaum's thorough and tionship patterns/rom material provided by the patient (i.e. not
accurate philosophical critique must be supplemented by a from extrasession data). Even though such parallels have been
critical analysis which goes beyond the limits of traditional drawn by psychoanalytically oriented psychotherapists for at
problems of defining the scientific status of psychoanalysis with least 80 years, there has never been an objective study of the
the aim of discovering the philosophy of psychoanalytical teach- evidence for this drawing-of-parallels in the sessions. But now
ings. As I see it, a philosophical critique of the foundations of evidence is available from the method of core conflictual rela-
psychoanalysis requires a thorough critique of its philosophy, tionship theme as applied by independent judges for the delin-

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 247


Commentary7'Grunbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
eation of the transference pattern (Luborsky 1977; 1984; shown to have a high probability of being temporally associated
Luborsky, Crits-Christoph & Mellon, in press; Luborsky, with the development of a symptom when that high degree of
Mellon, Alexander, van Ravenswaay, Childress, Levine, Co- association could be, and probably is, causal. The method
hen, Hole & Ming, 1985). The pattern is extracted from ac- entails marshalling data from sessions by first locating recurrent
counts of interactions of the patient with the therapist and of the symptoms enacted, experienced, or reported in the sessions,
patient with others both in the present and in the past. From then demarcating the context in which the symptoms appear,
this evidence (Luborsky, Crits-Christoph & Mellon, in press) of and finally having the context judged by blind independent
a clear parallel between present and past patterns of rela- judges. To further increase the probability of accuracy of the
tionships we are able to conclude that therapists are responding inferences, comparisons are also made with "control symptom"
to information provided in the session. However, we cannot say contexts, i.e. arbitrarily selected points within sessions whose
from this evidence alone whether the therapist might have contexts are evaluated by the same blind judges in a manner
induced some of the parallel. similar to the one used in the real symptom context. Several
Facet B: To what extent can it be shown that these central other characteristics of the symptom-context method add to its
patterns of relationship (of a kind that are involved in the value in establishing causes: (1) At times (e.g. for the momentary
transference) are an intrinsic characteristic of the patient rather forgetting symptom) the therapist has no hypothesis about any
than being engendered by the influence of the therapist (i.e. are causes related to the symptom or does not respond in-
they just an artifact of patient compliance to therapist terpretively to the symptom, and (2) the controlled evaluation of
expectations)? the data is by blind independent judges who come from varied
A powerful method for discriminating the contribution- of theoretical backgrounds.
these two sources is now available. It shows that this central The results of the symptom-context research have shown that
pattern of relationship was evident before the therapy began for each type of symptom some high-frequency concomitants of
(van Ravenswaay, Luborsky & Childress 1983). Data were the symptom were discovered. For the momentary forgetting
gathered by a special interview method applied outside the symptom, for example, the forgetting is highly associated with
therapy - the Relationship Apperception Paradigms Test (RAP) heightened involvement in the relationship with the analyst and
(Luborsky 1978). Because the core conflictual relationship that involvement is in terms of the patient's transference pattern
themes are evident apart from the treatment as well as within (Luborsky, in press; Luborsky, Sackheim & Christoph 1979). In
the treatment, the parallel nature of the pattern provides evi- a recent study (in press) I describe one patient in the sample who
dence that the pattern is characteristic of the patient rather than happened to have had a change from a male analyst in the first
generated by the expectations of the therapist. part of the analysis to a female analyst in the second. The same
More generally, if psychotherapy sessions are so contami- contents were found to be associated with the momentary
nated by the therapist's expectations as to be useless pro- forgetting in the treatments by each analyst, i. e. a change in the
batively, then predictions made on the basis of these sessions analyst did not mean a change in the conditions for the
should not be a substantial predictor of anything outside the symptom.
session. That is obviously not the case, however: Predictions It is further proof of Grunbaum's openness to evidence that
based on sessions have dozens of highly significant and substan- when the cogency of the symptom-context method for his
tial correlations with measures outside the treatment. A large second fundamental question was pointed out (in a discussion in
class of such session-based inferences are those having to do the Rapaport-Klein Study Group, June 1983) he acknowledged
with positive relationship qualities such as the helping alliance the relevance of the method and its results. However, he did
which correlates with outcome measures anywhere from .4 to .6 add a qualifying opinion that the symptom-context method
(Luborsky & Auerbach 1985). could not be applied to "Freud's grandest clinical hypotheses."
Facet C: How accurate are the therapist's inferences about This open-handed acknowledgement on his part of course opens
the patient's past and present behavior when these behaviors the way for the method as being capable in principle of dealing
are understood in terms of the patient's response to actual early with some of the grandest of Freud's hypothetical constructs; if a
parental behavior? method is able to test a minor hypothesis it is only a matter of the
Freud, and many therapists since then, have made inferences investigator's ingenuity to provide it with a major hypothesis to
about the patient's past and present responses to past parental test.
behavior, e.g. "Your father did this to you and so you reacted in It should be pointed out that one of these major hypotheses
this way then and now." has in fact already been the subject of evaluation by the symp-
I agree with Grunbaum's view that such inferences by the tom-context method, namely, the hypothesis about the causes
therapist have shaky evidence to support their accuracy. They of neurotic symptoms in Freud's genera] theory of symptom
are usually limited in having only the patient as the primary formation (Freud 1926) - that helplessness or the anticipation of
source of information, although often the parents and relatives helplessness is the most central cause. The symptom-context
are interviewed. The views of others based on data collected method has been applied to a variety of symptoms including
through concurrent early observation of the parent-child in- momentary forgetting (Luborsky et al. 1979), petit mal seizures
teraction could provide evidence of the level of accuracy of such (Luborsky, Docherty, Todd, Knapp, Mirsky & Gottschalk
inferences by the therapist. Of course, such information is rarely 1975), precipitously emerging depressive states (Luborsky,
available, except from longitudinal research studies such as Singer, Hartke, Crits-Christoph & Cohen 1984), and migraine
those in an ongoing study for the past 30 years on one patient headaches and stomach pain (Luborsky & Auerbach 1969). In
(Engel & Reichsman, in preparation) and in the long-term data fact, the symptom-context results on all of the symptoms studied
collection of the "Berkeley" studies (Block 1971). so far show that helplessness is the most prevalent "cause" of the
psychological symptoms ("cause" being taken to mean, as stated
Grunbaum's second fundamental question. Do psychotherapy earlier, a factor associated with the development of a symptom
sessions provide data that permit verification of the causes of that recurrently appears in the material prior to the appearance
symptoms, including "Freudian slips"? of the symptom).
One sort of evidence that disagrees with Grunbaum's nega-
tive answer to his question is provided by the symptom-context Grunbaum might respond further in this way: "Yes, you have
method (Luborsky 1970). The recent book by Edelson (1984) a point, but some of the methods you apply to the session bring
expresses the same view about the cogency of my method in in extrasession data and bring in procedures not ordinarily used
answering Grunbaum's challenge. By means of my method, the by the clinician and never by Freud himself." I would reply in
"causes" of neurotic and psychosomatic symptoms can be dis- turn, "Yes, but the extrasession data and the procedures for
cerned. I use the word "cause" in the sense of a factor that is analysis of sessions (for example, in the symptom-context meth-

248 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Commentary/Grunbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
od) show that Freud's hypotheses can be shown to have high to idealize the analyst in the course of a positive transference
probability of accuracy, i.e. that certain inferences based on gives analysts' interpretations enormous persuasive power.
sessions have some validity. Just as with the validity procedures Thus, it is not surprising, as I have pointed out elsewhere, that
for any validated test, one does not have to repeat the validity patients of each school (of psychoanalysis) seem to bring out precisely
study every time a test is applied. The session, too, when the kind of phenomenological data which confirm the theories and
evaluated in a particular way, is then considered to have shown interpretations of their analysts. Thus, each theory tends to be self-
some potential for validity. Furthermore, many clinicians can validating. Freudians elicit material about the Oedipus complex and
undoubtedly make judgments that are like those that the guided castration anxiety, Adlerians about masculine strivings and feelings of
clinical judgment methods (CCRT [core conflictual relationship inferiority, Horneyans about idealized images, Sullivanians about
theme] and symptom context) can achieve. disturbed interpersonal relationships, etc. The fact is that in so
The thrust of Grunbaum's subsequent conclusion is that complex a transaction as the psychoanalytic therapeutic process, the
verification of inferences from psychotherapy sessions will have impact of a patient and therapist upon each other, and particularly of
to come from extraclinical studies because intrasession in- the latter upon the former, is an unusually profound one. What the
ferences cannot soar to the level where they can prove anything. analyst shows interest in, the kinds of questions he asks, the kinds of
He affirms this even though he says he must admit that some data he chooses to react to or to ignore, and the interpretations he
powerful insights have, or probably have, been generated by makes, all exert a subtle but significant suggestive impact upon the
analyses of sessions. For applications to the analysis of intrases- patient to bring forth certain kinds of data in preference to others.
sion data I have pointed to two guided judgment methods which (Marmor 1974b)
demonstrate reasonable levels of accuracy of verification of It follows from this that even free association - that sacred
clinical inferences. Verification of hypotheses can come from cornerstone of the psychoanalytic method - has serious limita-
both intrasession and extrasession studies and in fact the two, tions. Both clinical and experimental evidence (Krasner 1958;
when taken together, strengthen each other's accuracy of Mandler & Kaplan 1956; Marmor 1974a; Salzinger 1959) have
verification. demonstrated that the "free associations" of the patient are
strongly influenced by the values, expectations, and verbal
comments of the therapist.
One wonders, however, whether the causal significance of
conflict in the genesis of at least some psychopathology - also
The question of causality one of the basic elements in psychoanalytic theory - does not
still retain much of its validity. Grunbaum does not deal with
Judd Marmor
this issue, yet the fact that conflictual situations are relevant to
70889 Wilshire Blvd., Los Angeles, Calif. 90024 the development of neurotic disturbances has been experimen-
Grunbaum's book is a tour deforce. The depth and breadth of tally validated in a wide variety of approach-avoidance studies in
his knowledge of psychoanalytic literature in general, and of lower animals.
Freud's works in particular, are most impressive. He propounds One final point that perhaps might have received additional
his thesis with vigor and conviction, but one cannot help wishing attention is the issue of causality as a multifactorial rather than a
that his writing style were less turgid and had more of the unifactorial phenomenon. It seems to this commentator that one
elegant simplicity that has made Freud's ideas so seductive. of the major fallacies of classical psychoanalytic theory is the fact
Sentences such as "Freud claimed the status of a natural science that Freud, in keeping with the thinking of his time, kept
for his clinical theory by misextrapolation from its envisaged looking for a single cause for neurosis (akin to the tubercle
reduction to the primordially scientific metapsychology," (p.7) bacillus), such as an infantile sexual trauma or castration anxiety.
make reading Grunbaum unnecessarily arduous! Causality in the genesis of neurosis is now understood to be
The essential point that Grunbaum makes is that the scientific multifactorial and to have biological and sociological roots as
pretensions of classical psychoanalytic theory are seriously well as psychological ones. Even the tubercle bacillus is no
flawed, although he does not deny the therapeutic potential of longer assumed to be the sole sufficient cause of tuberculosis
psychoanalytic treatment. Freud and his classical followers have without also considering the contributory role of the host's
long insisted that psychoanalysis is a "basic science" akin to immune system as well as sociological factors such as poverty,
physics, but Grunbaum demonstrates convincingly that the malnutrition, and overcrowding. Recognizing the complex sys-
basic tenets upon which psychoanalytic theory rests - the temic context in which psychopathology originates eliminates
theory of repression, the validation of psychoanalytic hypoth- the tendency toward psychological reductionism that charac-
eses by the presumptively privileged cognitive reactions of the terizes both the theory and the treatment methodology of
patient, and the method of free association - all fail to meet the classical psychoanalysis.
tests of scientific methodology. These criticisms have been
made by others, both within and outside of the psychoanalytic
profession, but never with as much detail and overwhelming
logic as Grunbaum displays in this volume.
Psychoanalysis, case histories, and
As long ago as 1955, in a panel on the validation of psycho-
analytic technique, I argued that analytic theory must be subject experimental data
to consensual validation by findings extrinsic to the psycho-
analytic method itself. I was astonished (perhaps naively) to hear Joseph Masling
other participants in that symposium argue that such external Psychology Department, State University of New York at Buffalo, Buffalo,
verification was unnecessary and irrelevant and that so long as N.Y. 14226
psychoanalytic theory was internally consistent, it had scientific Psychoanalytic theory has influenced Western thought more
validity. A large body of contradictory findings, ably docu- profoundly than almost any other idea, but the data on which the
mented by Grunbaum, have long since demolished that argu- theory rests have been limited to the voluntary disclosure by the
ment. No serious scientist today would assert that the success of analyst of selected case histories. Any number of scholars have
any therapeutic method constitutes proof of the correctness of criticized severely the lack of interest on the part of psycho-
the theory on which that therapeutic technique was based. The analysts in providing adequate empirical evidence in support of
fact is that the existence of the "transference" phenomenon that the theory. Sherwood's description of the self-contained world
Freud was the first to describe renders the internal validation of of psychoanalysis puts it well: "The situation is almost unique: in
the psychoanalytic method highly questionable. The tendency perhaps no other field has so great a body of theory been built

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 249


Commentary7'Grunbaurn: Foundations of psychoanalysis
upon such a small public record of raw data" (1969, p. 70). Even sion in the book is the failure to discuss the several studies that
25 years ago, Scriven was forced to conclude about psycho- have directly examined the process of psychoanalytic therapy by
analytic theory: "As a set of hypotheses [it] was a great achieve- using verbatim typescripts of analytic sessions (Dahl 1972; 1983;
ment 50 years ago; as no more than a set of hypotheses it is a Luborsky 1973; Luborsky & Auerbach 1969; Spence 1969). It
great disgrace today" (1959, p. 226). would have been extremely instructive to have had Griinbaum's
Psychoanalysts claim that their case histories produce data comments on the importance of such quantitative investigations
that not only are more than mere hypotheses but constitute of the transactions between analyst and patient. Finally, Griin-
scientifically respectable evidence, a claim most objective ob- baum makes no mention of a potentially important source of
servers reject: "Certainly the self-congratulatory clinical histo- evidence for psychoanalytic theory - the experiments by cog-
ries in the analytic literature cannot be accepted as evidence of nitive psychologists on unconscious perception. An excellent
anything beyond the writer's self-regard" (Malcolm 1984b, p. review article (Nisbett & Wilson 1977) summarizes much of this
18). Griinbaum makes an invaluable contribution to this issue by work, and in addition other studies (Fowler, Wolford & Slade
his careful, meticulous analysis of the logic of the case history 1981; Marcel 1980) present data that bear directly on psycho-
method, concluding that it is not an acceptable scientific method analytic notions of levels of awareness. [See also Holender:
and that it cannot serve as the sole source of data relevant to "Semantic Activation Without Conscious Identification" BBS
psychoanalytic theory. Among its other flaws, the case history 9(1) 1986.] In brief, considerable evidence, some from the
method relies on highly fallible memories, accounts, and re- clinical situation itself, most from extraclinical sources, relevant
cords by the analyst and may overlook the influence of the to the validity of the theory is already available. The evaluation
analyst on the verbal productions of the patient: of psychoanalytic theory is well under way. Griinbaum's book,
The clinical use of free association features epistemic biases of selec- which so clearly refutes the argument that the case history
tion and manipulative contamination asfollows:(1) the analyst selects method is a sufficient means of generating data, makes the
thematicaUy from the patient's productions, partly by interrupting collection of appropriate experimental evidence all the more
the associations either explicitly or in a myriad more subtle ways at important.
points of his or her own theoretically inspired choosing; and (2) when
the Freudian doctor harbors the suspicion that the associations are
faltering because of evasive censorship, he uses verbal and also subtle
nonverbal promptings to induce the continuation of the associations
until they yield theoretically appropriate results. (1984, pp. 210-11) Is Freudian psychoanalytic theory really
Freud, of course, was aware of the charge that the analyst falsifiable?
somehow suggests some of the content of the patient's speech
and memories, and he stoutly denied this possibility. Griin- Mark A. Notturno and Paul R. McHugh
baum quotes Freud's denial (on p. 275) and then closely dissects Department of Psychiatry and Behavioral Sciences, Johns Hopkins
Freud's argument, concluding that "insofar as the evidence for University School of Medicine, Baltimore, Md. 21205
the psychoanalytic corpus is now held to derive from the pro- In The Foundations of Psychoanalysis, Griinbaum argues that:
ductions of patients in analysis, this warrant is remarkably weak" (1) psychoanalytic theory qualifies for scientific status; (2) the
(1984, p. 278). Psychoanalysts might not like Griinbaum's book, clinical evidence claimed by psychoanalysis is "remarkably
but they will have a difficult time demonstrating that he is either weak" (p. 278); and (3) "the validation of Freud's cardinal
naive about psychoanalysis or unsympathetic to it. If psycho- hypotheses has to come, if at all, mainly from well-designed
analysts are going to be at all responsive to serious intellectual ertraclinical studies" (p. 278). He then concludes that "while
challenges from outside the system (they could continue to psychoanalysis may thus be said to be scientifically alive, it is
stonewall as they have for so many years), they will have to face currently hardly well" (p. 278). WefindGriinbaum's arguments
Griinbaum's charges directly and explicitly. for (2) and (3) to be rigorous and cogent. Their significance,
Griinbaum's solution to the insubstantial scientific base for however, depends upon the truth of (1). Despite his vigorous
psychoanalysis is essentially that it should join the rest of the critique of Popper, Griinbaum has failed to convince us that
scientific community and encourage empirical data: "In view of psychoanalysis is falsifiable.
my account of the epistemic defects inherent in the psycho- Griinbaum sharply criticizes Popper's view (q. v.) that psy-
analytic method, it would seem that the validation of Freud's choanalysis is nonscience, only to censure it himself as bad
cardinal hypotheses has to come, if at all, mainly from well- science, or science not yet shown good. But how sharp is the
designed extraclinical studies, either epidemiologic or even distinction between bad science and nonscience? Explanatory
experimental" (1984, p. 278). My only disappointment with theories that falsely claim to be scientific are sometimes called
Griinbaum's book is its failure to make explicit how much "pseudosciences." Pseudosciences should be carefully dis-
experimental evidence relevant to the merit of the theory is tinguished from false scientific theories (Popper 1962a; p. 33).
already available. In passing, Griinbaum notes that some ex- The latter are clearly false; the former might well be true.
perimental work has been done, but his primary purpose evi- According to Popper, the distinction is not even one of justifica-
dently was not to dwell at length on the several reviews of tion or confirmation. For no theory is or can be justified or
empirical data on psychoanalytic theory (Fisher & Greenberg confirmed. Popper's distinction is one of testability (1983, p.
1977; 1978; Kline 1972; Masling 1983; Masling & Schwartz 1979; 159). Scientific theories admit of severe and sincere empirical
Silverman 1976). Psychoanalytic theory has proved, perhaps testing; pseudosciences, for one reason or another, do not.
unexpectedly, to be extraordinarily heuristic. The least interest-
ing of these studies are those that intend only to test the validity This is the germ of Popper's demarcation between science
of the theory. More interesting and more important are the and nonscience: In order to be scientific a theory must be
experiments that originate in the theory but go beyond it to help falsifiable. One reason why a theory might not be falsifiable is
clarify issues that the theory either never considered or viewed that it conflicts with no conceivable observations. Another and
incorrectly. Silverman's work on the process of unconscious more common reason is that the theory's proponents refuse to
perception and unconscious arousal of motives falls into this acknowledge falsifications as such. For this reason, Popper
latter category (Silverman 1976; 1983), as do Blatt's studies of maintains that any theory can, through the assumption of ad hoc
thought disorder (Blatt & Ritzier 1974) and object relations hypotheses or other evasive tactics, immunize itself against
(Blatt & Lerner 1983), Beebe's research on early infant behavior falsification (1974, p. 32). By the same token, any theory can be
and object relations (Beebe & Stem 1977), and Mayman's regarded as scientific so long as its proponents are willing to
investigations of object relations (1967). A more serious omis- acknowledge conflicting observations as falsifications. In this
vein, Popper supposes that Freudian psychoanalysis is "a pro-

250 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Commentary/Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis

gramme for a psychological science" (1983, p. 172) and that was open to the possibility of falsification. But the fact that
"much of what they [Freud and Adler] say is of considerable Freud makes certain comments about refutability should not, in
importance, and may well play its part one day in a psychological itself, convince us that Freud would actually be willing to
science which is testable" (1962a, p. 37). Moreover, Popper is acknowledge refutation. Jung, Adler, and Rank learned that
convinced that "Freud could have vastly improved his theory, lesson the hard way. Grunbaum, however, writes that "even a
had his attitude towards criticism been different" (1983, p. 168). casual perusal of the mere titles of Freud's papers and lectures in
Simply put, Popper regards his falsifiability criterion as "vague, the Standard Edition yields two examples of falsifiability. The
since it is a methodological rule, and since the demarcation second is a case of acknowledged falsification, to boot. Thefirstis
between science and nonscience is vague" (1974, p. 984). the paper 'A Case of Paranoia Running Counter to the Psycho-
Scientific theories like Marx's became pseudoscientific due to a analytic Theory of the Disease" (S.E. 1915, 14: 263-272); the
failure to acknowledge falsification. And nonscientific theories second is the lecture 'Revision of the Theory of Dreams' (S.E.
like Freud's can become scientific simply by specifying what 1933, 22:7-30, especially pp. 28-30)" (1984, p. 108). But you
would count as a falsification-and sticking to it. can't judge an article by its title, and Griinbaum's "casual
According to Popper, the scientific nature of an empirical perusal" fails to convince us.
theory depends in part upon its logical form. But it also depends The first case Grunbaum cites is one in which Freud thought
upon the attitude that the proponents of a theory assume toward about revising his theory and entertained the possibility of
criticism. This is important. What Popper is criticizing in claim- refutation, but neither actually acknowledged refutation nor
ing that psychoanalysis is unfalsifiable is primarily "Freud's way revised his theory. In this case, Freud is troubled by the
of rejecting criticism" (1983, p. 168). Scientific inquiry is often possibility of a paranoia not caused by repressed homosexual
likened to a mystery story. And Freud is often more ingenious desires for one psychoanalytic session, only to "discover" the
than Sherlock Holmes. Holmes begins only with phenomena expected homosexual repressions in the next. But it is not so
and the mystery is in finding a theory that truly explains them. much the fact that Freud here denies refutation that is bother-
Freud begins with both theory and phenomena. Beginning with some; it is the way in which he does so. Through an array of
both theory and phenomena is not necessarily bad - not, for questionable associations and ad hoc assumptions (including the
example, if the phenomenon is used to test the theory in assumption that his patient's account of the events that led to her
question. But in Freud's case, it is not so much the theory as the suspicion is, on several points and for various reasons, false!),
phenomenon that is in question. His mystery more often con- Freud "deduces" the presence of homosexual desires in a way
sists infindinga way to fit the latter to the former, and this is not that would make any scientist blush. Grunbaum considers this
always simple. In some cases it is necessary for Freud to paper to be indicative of Freud's openness to refutation. In our
"deduce" what the phenomena really are, i.e. what they must view, it was this very style of reasoning that led Popper to claim
be if his theory is correct. Although such reasoning requires psychoanalysis is unfalsifiable.
ingenuity, Freud always proves adequate to the task. This, But perhaps Griinbaum's second example is more to the point -
however, is the point of Popper's critique. for this, after all, is a case of acknowledged falsification. More-
Grunbaum claims that Freud's characterization of paranoia as over, the issue pertains to Freud's theory of dreams, undoubt-
a defense against homosexual impulses is falsifiable vis-4-vis edly a central plank of psychoanalytic theory. Popper (1983, pp.
epidemiological evidence, namely, paranoia in an avowed ho- 163-74) discusses this case, but here it might be more instruc-
mosexual. This is interesting, but problematic. Freud's theory tive to learn from Grunbaum. After deferring comment on this
of paranoia is hardly a central plank of psychoanalysis, and example for 108 pages, Griinbaum's "acknowledged falsifica-
Freud himself held that paranoia is "not usually amenable to tion" is suddenly reduced to a "rather minor modification"
analytic investigation" (1922, p. 234). But if the existence of an (Grunbaum 1984, p. 220). And upon returning to the subject
avowedly homosexual paranoid were to be considered a possible from yet a second deferral, Grunbaum concludes by quoting
falsification, then it would at least be necessary for Freud's from Freud:
theory to claim that paranoia is always accompanied by homo- We should not, I think, be afraid to admit that here the function of the
sexual impulses. It is not, however, clear that this is what dream has failed. . . . But no doubt the exception does not overturn
Freud's theory in fact claims. In the Schreber case, for example, the rule. You can say nevertheless that a dream is an attempt at the
homosexual impulses are said to be "so frequently (perhaps fulfillment of a wish. In certain circumstances a dream is only able to
invariably) to be found in paranoia" (1911, p. 464). And in "A put its intention into effect very incompletely, or must abandon it
Case of Paranoia Running Counter to the Psycho-Analytic Theo- entirely. Unconsciousfixationto a trauma seems to be foremost
ry of the Disease," Freud writes, "We had not, it is true, among these obstacles to the function of dreaming. (Grunbaum 1984,
asserted that paranoia is always without exception conditioned p.238)
by homosexuality" (1915, p. 153). So before raising the question Nothing conflicts more sharply with Popper's attitude than
whether Freud's theory of paranoia is falsifiable, we should at Freud's claim that the exception does not overturn the rule.
least determine exactly what the theory claims. Nevertheless, this "rather minor modification" is minimized
Now Grunbaum claims that paranoia in an avowed homosex- further by Freud's retreat from wish fulfillments to attempts at
ual would refute Freud's theory. How would Freud respond? wish fulfillment. But does Freud really acknowledge this falsi-
Freud would undoubtedly want to look at the homosexual in fication as Grunbaum claims? Upon checking Freud's "Revision
question. But Freud would most probably say that behavior of the Theory of Dreams" we found reason to believe that he
alone is unrevealing about the nature of repression (Freud 1904) does not. For part of what Grunbaum deletes from this passage
and would thus insist upon using free association to seek the reads as follows: "we say that a dream is the fulfillment of a wish;
hypothesized homosexual repressions. It would be difficult to but if you want to take these latter objections into account, you
demonstrate the absence of some homosexual repressions by can say nevertheless that a dream is an attempt at the fulfillment
free association. But even if we acknowledge the possibility of of a wish. No one who can properly appreciate the dynamics of
avowedly homosexual paranoids as a potential falsifier of Freudi- the mind will suppose that you have said anything different by
an theory, the point to be made is that Popper has acknowledged this" (1933b, pp. 26-27; italics added).
it too (1983, p. 169). Although Popper is willing to accept the Earlier we asked the question "How sharp is the distinction
existence of avowedly homosexual paranoids as falsifying Freud- between bad science and nonscience?" There we suggested
ian theory, he is still skeptical whether Freud would be so that, according to Popper, the distinction is not too sharp at all.
willing. And this is the crux of our disagreement with For good metaphysical theories, like Freud's, provide a pro-
Grunbaum, gram for a psychological science. Grunbaum considers the
Grunbaum cites numerous passages that suggest that Freud above passage to be an acknowledged falsification. But if Pop-

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 251


Commentary/Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
per's point is to criticize Freud's way of rejecting criticism, we (Schafer 1980, p.29). Once again, this "way" is that of consider-
consider it grist for his mill. In any event, Freudians beware! ing psychoanalysis an "interpretative discipline," using "nar-
Falsifiability is a mixed blessing. False scientific theories are a ratives" that are not necessarily bound to objective existential
dime a dozen, but a genuine pseudoscience is rather hard to realities and to causal commitments of any sort. Its aim is to
find. induce change (both in the patient and in the analyst) within the
practice of a Sprachspiel (language game), the validation of
which is only internal and never ultimate, owing to the intrinsic
character of meanings.
In a recent work which reads like a summing up of the
The persistence of the "exegetical myth" epistemological status of psychoanalysis, the philosopher Hilary
Alessandro Pagnini Putnam likewise seems to share Shafer's opinion:
If Father Freud and his rebellious sons (Jung, Adler, Lacan, etc.)
Department of Philosophy, University of Florence, 50139 Florence, Italy
wished to be viewed as the producers of scientific "theories," that is a
In Griinbaum's critique of psychoanalysis there is a basic tenet fact for cultural historians to note, I am suggesting, but not one to stop
of historical character: Freud, who lived and molded his ideas in us from considering that their "theory " is of value just to the extent
the hectic years of the dispute of methods (Methodenstreit), that what it becomes for us is not theory but observation. Indeed,
decided, with no hesitation, to attribute psychoanalysis to the much of Freud's work has a curious double form; it is, or pretends to
Naturwissenschaften or natural sciences rather than the be, at one and the same time, science and narrative. Freud tells us a
Geisteswissenschaften or "sciences of the spirit". My intention story, and then he proceeds to generalize, often in a dogmatic way.
is to integrate Griinbaum's already exhaustive documentation The stories are of value, I am suggesting, just to the extent that they
on the subject (pp. 1-9) with some remarks (which I will only suggest ways of constructing other narratives which help us to
sketch, for brevity's sake) drawn from a recent and interesting understand individual people; the alleged "universal laws" are simply
survey on the genesis and cultural reference of Freudian "epis- the recurrent illusion I have been describing, the claim of "science."
temology" (Assoun 1981). (Putnam 1984, p. 6)
According to Assoun, (and supporting Griinbaum's argu- Putnam, as a matter of fact, sounds critical towards the
ment): (a) For Freud, Wissenschaft is identified with Natur- rhetoric of the "Copernican revolutions," even though he ac-
wissenschaft, to which he attributes psychoanalysis prima facie, knowledges that psychoanalysis is an inescapable mode of deal-
(b) Freud, although not directly participating in the debate on ing with neurotic behavior ("We are not free to inhabit the pre-
methods, is informed about it and refers to the Geistes- Freudian world" [p. 1]). Besides, he doesn't seem to undervalue
wissenschaften only to point out a few crucial differences from those experimental studies that aim at verifying the effective-
psychoanalysis (Freud 1924, German ed., G.W, XIV, p.84; ness of psychoanalytic therapy (but he stresses that, in order to
G.W., XIV, pp.294-95). (c) Freud's methodology is heavily be "objective," they always forget the "ethical" dimension of
influenced by Haeckel's works (as Assoun writes, "all Freud's notions such as "cure" or "recovery"). So he finally concludes
claims on the subject [of the human sciences] are expressed with that "it would be fine . . . to recognize that psychoanalytic
an identical vocabulary as Haeckel's" [p. 45]), and influenced by therapy cannot be 'objectively validated,' provided we also
the antidualistic culture of German physicists, physiologists, recognize that this opens, rather than forecloses, discussing
and psychologists, by the empiricism of Mill (whose works what there is and what there is not of value in it" (p. 6).
Freud partially translated in his youth), and by the physicalistic I have quoted Putnam's words at length as they seem to me to
research program which, since the years 1830-1840, continued be emblematic of an attitude which would in a sense render
to be a strong "paradigm" in the psychophysiological and psy- superfluous Griinbaum's critical efforts regarding psycho-
chiatric sciences of the time, (d) In light of a close philological analysis. Such an attitude implies that: (a) Psychoanalysis is not
and conceptual analysis, it can be argued that the very Freudian "a large and systematic theory" but "a new technique of obser-
"meaning," often tendentiously emphasized by the her- vation" (and, by the same token, it is rather a "narrative" than a
meneutic contingent, never betrays an underlying causal and "science"), (b) The problem of its validation is secondary and
deterministic pattern; thus Freudian interpretation always re- jeopardizes the real value of Freudian findings, (c) This value
sults in explanation. ("Far from transferring psychoanalysis into consists in the fact that "Freud discovered neurotic patterning."
the field of the hermeneutic sciences, the Traumdeutung does Since then we have been, so to speak, compelled to understand
not modify at all the identity of the Naturwissenschaft. It is in in a Freudian way the motives and behaviors, conscious and
any case grounded in erklaren as its strictly privileged pro- unconscious, of other people. Yet the Freudian way of under-
cedure" [Assoun 1981, pp.42-43].) standing does not provide us with "mechanical rules, ' and does
Although he does consider the different phases and the not force on us any sort of "guarantee," particularly of the kind to
complex interaction of models and influences (Fechner, Mach, be found in science ("The idea that a fact is either ascertainable
Helmholtz, Mayer, Ostwald, Haeckel, etc.) present in Freud's in the way the analysis of a compound in a chemical laboratory is
work, Assoun nevertheless concludes that Freud never re- ascertainable or else a mere myth is not a form of scientism but
nounces a substantial reductivism and an epistemological scientism itself' [Putnam 1984, p. 6]).
monism. Finally, Assoun comes to the conclusion that, contrary To come to my conclusion (with apologies for this "indirect"
to Wundt, who shifted toward a spiritualistic dualism, "Freud approach to Griinbaum's book, to which I have devoted more
appears therefore . . . as the founder of a scientific psychology concern in Pagnini, in press): Waiting for Putnam to tell us on
which has never abandoned such a monism" (p.49) (a meth- what basis we can discuss the value of psychoanalysis (a theme
odological monism, as Griinbaum points out). he considers "open"), and for what reasons (the fatalistic as-
Notwithstanding the wealth of historical and analytical data sumption of its "irrevocability" doesn't seem to be a good one)
that do not support the interpretation of the alleged Freudian we must accept psychoanalysis, if only as a technique of observa-
"scientistic self-misunderstanding," hermeneuticians and like- tion (but how is it possible to "observe" - according to Putnam's
minded thinkers are not willing to give up. For instance, Schafer peculiar sense of the word - in the absence of a "theory"?), I
writes that "Freud established a tradition within which psycho- think that such contributions as Grunbaum's book, soberly
analysis is understood as an essentialist and positivist natural equipped only with logic and analytical austerity, do more to
science. One need not be bound by this scientific commitment, stimulate and promote our "rational conversation" concerning
however; the individual and general accounts and interpreta- psychoanalysis than do thousands of promises or as many elusive
tions Freud gave of his case material can be read in another way" metaphors.

252 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Commentary/Grunbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
Is there a "two-cultures" model for same. To appreciate him along with his foibles is more mature
psychoanalysis? and consistent with a scientific approach. Psychoanalysis was
and is the field of his discovery. It is constantly evolving,
George H. Pollock
changing, subject to tensions and struggles - new theories, new
approaches, new dimensions encounter resistances and reluc-
Institute for Psychoanalysis, Chicago, III. 60601
tances which become incorporated into the theoretical con-
I admire philosophy and find it challenges me to think in a way structs of the field, and these can then be examined clinically as
that is different from my clinical experiences, which are more well as by observation [e.g. through cross-cultural comparisons,
direct, involve more imagery and feelings, are less tersely follow-up and outcome studies based on earlier written predic-
organized, and do not focus primarily on finding flaws, contra- tions, child observations, longitudinal studies, cohort analyses,
dictions, and inconsistencies in theory. Keats has noted that one etc). Change occurs, but it is slow and conservative. I am
can strain at seeing particles of light in the midst of great suggesting a "two-cultures' model within the field itself. The
darkness without knowing the bearing of any one assertion or inspirational or intuitive and the experimental-logical testing -
opinion until perhaps much later. Keats did not feel this to be a both have their place, their use, their methods, and their
disadvantage; rather, it appeared to him that this ability to pitfalls.
remain "in the midst of a great darkness without laboring in In the last forty years, the clinical disciplines of medicine have
search of ultimate explanations" was an essential aspect of his increasingly used quantitative methods in evaluating
character as a poet (Pack 1984, p. 179). What I am suggesting is therapeutic agents and in elucidating possible etiologic factors
that the approach of the sensitive clinician is closer to that of the in disease. These are now being utilized to a greater extent than
poet than of the tightly organized philosopher who attempts to ever in psychiatry. However, statistical methods are only very
use a "null hypothesis" in his approach to a field that is very rarely used in studying the propositions of clinical psycho-
human and less abstract and propositional. analysis. Psychoanalysis as a clinical discipline still relies mainly
To return to Keats, who writes that the quality of achievement on observation, experience, a collection of life history and
in literature, for example Shakespeare, is "Negative Capability, psychobiographical facts. The theoretical systems that have
that is when a man is capable of being in uncertainties, myste- been used are, like all theory, subject to revision, rejection, or
ries, doubts, without any irritable reaching after fact and rea- affirmation in varying degrees. Facts or confirmed realities may
son . . . with a great poet the sense of Beauty overcomes every remain unexplained and require theory change. As more experi-
other consideration, or rather obliterates all consideration" mental and carefully controlled observational studies are under-
(quoted in Pack 1984, pp. 179-80). Keats believed that at the taken, it will be possible to examine some clinical psychoanalytic
heart of his conception of "Negative Capability" was the ideal of explanations statistically. The applications of clinical psycho-
"disinterestedness," the ability to empty oneself of one's own analytic observations to prevention and early intervention in
identity, to immerse oneself through identification in the lives of high risk individuals may allow predictions to be made before
others and so to attain a greater purpose than the "irritable outcome is known and may thus give us more precision in
reaching after fact and reason." It is true that I am addressing checking our hypotheses. As psychoanalytic epidemiology de-
one aspect of the work of the psychoanalyst - one of the ways velops we may find newer ideas coming to the fore which relate
that one obtains information about the other as well as about to psychopathology and efficacy of therapy.
oneself- but this is not the entire psychoanalytic process; it is I believe Griinbaum's scholarly examination should more
only the beginning. As doors of understanding open up, there is carefully differentiate between Freud's work and psycho-
a sharpening of one's vision into the heart and nature of man analysis. The two are not the same. Furthermore, one must
(Pack 1984, p. 181), and with this comes the attempt to under- differentiate between Freud's clinical observations and his ex-
stand that which was felt. This is the origin of theory. planations for these clinical phenomena. The theories of psycho-
The work with patients is one aspect of psychoanalysis that analysis are constantly being revised and these theories deal
may be protoscientific, but it is a very essential ingredient of with different phenomena, some clinical and some far removed
what we call the psychoanalytic engagement, the precursor to from illness. The use of clinical data is a time-honored method of
the formulation of more scientific explanations which can then obtaining data that can be used to test hypotheses. Unless
be examined in a tighter fashion in a variety of ways. The "controlled," these data may be flawed, but this can challenge
examinations of higher level theory, though necessary for scien- the researcher to be more precise and more accurate. Freud
tific testing, are at a different level from the one I have been recognized that theory revisions would have to be made, and he
emphasizing above. The logic of the metaphorical structure himself changed his own explanations when they did not fit his
requires a different mode of thinking than that which examines own observational data or those of others. The major tenet of
higher level hypotheses. The latter can and should be stated in Freud's discovery was that of the dynamic unconscious. Extra-
such fashion as to allow for refutation or confirmation. clinical studies (e.g. in anthropology, biography, neuroscience,
I am suggesting the possibility of two separate but parallel endocrinology, immunology, literature) are providing us with
paths, each existing in relative independence but eventually newer perspectives and novel ways of testing hypotheses. Out-
converging. Subjective, intuitive, empathic psychological sen- come and follow-up studies are additional ways of testing clinical
sitivity characterizes one; the careful, terse, abstract, tightly predictions.
organized and reasoned and controlled characterizes the other. Griinbaum has previously written that "Freud's repeated
Each has merit, each has value, and if explanations that are modifications of his theories were clearly motivated by evi-
universal to some degree emerge from the former, these can be dence" (1979, p. 135). As Marshall Edelson has recently noted
subjected to scrutiny and testing by the latter. in a careful discussion of Griinbaum's work, "Griinbaum em-
Freud and psychoanalysis are not the same. Psychoanalysis as phasizes that psychoanalytic hypotheses are confirmable and
a discipline is less than a century old. Freud, the discoverer of, falsifiable" (1984, p. 42). However, Grunbaum argues that
and not the inventor of, the dynamic unconscious, sought "while psychoanalytic hypotheses may be falsifiable, they have
explanatory meanings of what he observed in himself, his not achieved scientific credibility from data obtained outside the
patients, and in his study of man and his works. In some of these psychoanalytic situation and cannot achieve such credibility
he was exceedingly insightful, in others fanciful, in others from data obtained in the psychoanalytic situation" (Edelson
poetic, and in some, in error. To condemn him for his monu- 1984, p. 46). So how can psychoanalytic hypotheses be "confir-
mental efforts when they appear to have been somewhat incon- mable and falsifiable"?
sistent is unrealistic; to idealize him beyond question is the Marshall Edelson's new book, Hypothesis and Evidence in

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 253


CommentaryVGriinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
Psychoanalysis, answers some of Griinbaum's arguments in an they had confined themselves to insisting that psychological
elegant fashion. It is healthy for a discipline to examine itself and theory, if it claims scientific status, must be testable by predic-
for others from outside to similarly scrutinize its methods, tions of overt behavior.
theories, evidence, proofs, and refutations. Griinbaum, in his This is what psychoanalysis fails to do: Its so-called predic-
latest writings, has performed such a service for psychoanalysis. tions are not predictions of overt behavior but of hidden psycho-
In his scholarly works he attempts to look at the entire field of logical states. This is why they are untestable. The famous
psychoanalysis from the viewpoint of the outsider - the philoso- psychoanalyst Siegfried Bernfeld (who was a friend of mine and
pher of science. His is a worthwhile effort, one that can, should, of Freud's) once wrote: "Psychoanalysis cannot predict whether
and has already stimulated many to think and rethink the you will repress or sublimate. But whether you repress or
questions he raises. However, his "analysis" does suffer from an sublimate will make all the difference to your behavior."
apparent lack of direct knowledge and experience with psycho- In 1957 I wrote that "every conceivable case [of human
analysis itself. behavior] could be interpreted in the light of Freud's theory.
Many erudite and scholarly discussions of Griinbaum's work This can be illustrated by two very different examples of human
have already appeared in the daily press and popular magazines. behavior: that of a man who throws a child into a river (with the
More detailed critiques are sure to appear soon in professional intention of drowning him); and that of a man who sacrifices his
journals. Revolution is usually followed by a counterrevolution life in an attempt to save a child. Each of these two cases can be
and then a synthesis. Today Freud, Marx, Einstein, and Darwin explained with equal ease in Freudian terms: According to
are challenged. These challenges are healthy and will lead to Freud the first man suffered from repression (say, of some
more rigorous explanations. However, in an existential world, component of his Oedipus complex), while the second had
the quest for scientific validity may be applauded and pursued achieved sublimation." (I gather that it was this passage that first
but as yet be unattained. Perhaps in some fields scientific provoked Griinbaum to examine the testability of psycho-
validity may never be obtained, but that need not diminish the analytic theory.) Since a psychoanalyst cannot predict whether
discipline's utility and service to man. Perhaps psychoanalysis is anybody will repress or sublimate, he cannot predict overt
not a science, just as there is no basic science of internal behavior. On the other hand, a psychological theory can be put
medicine, or psychiatry, or surgery, although scientific methods to the test only if it can predict overt behavior.
can still be used in testing ideas. Perhaps our attempts to prove I have not read the work in which Grunbaum has attempted to
or disprove the proposition that psychoanalysis is or is not a refute this argument; however, the New York Times asked me
science address the wrong questions. What we need are careful by telemessage to answer an argument (allegedly Griinbaum's)
clinical studies; these are the bedrock of theory, and the applica- that in a simplified form can be put as follows: From the very first
tions of theory may be the area that can now be most fruitfully paper on psychoanalysis that Freud wrote, together with Josef
addressed. Finally, the question has recently been raised about Breuer, one can derive the following predictions: (A) If people
"Just how objective is science?" (Hetherington 1983). do not repress traumatic experiences, then they will not become
Hetherington suggests that we should question the supposed victims of neurosis. (B) If in childhood people are protected from
objectivity of science. He points out that the use of double-blind traumatic experiences, then they are not expected to become
procedures is difficult in observational astronomy. "The most neurotic. Grunbaum says (I am informed by the New York
interesting observations are often those at the very limits of the Times) that a host of other scientifically testable hypotheses
instruments available. It is difficult to achieve repeatability of likewise follows from the theories of Freud and Breuer. (Here
observations, impossible to enjoy the luxury of double-blind ends the information I received from the New York Times about
measurements" (1983, p. 729). Could this also apply to observa- the content of Griinbaum's counterexamples to my theory that
tions in psychoanalysis? Furthermore, observation in the psy- psychoanalysis is not a testable field.)
choanalytic therapeutic situation involves the observations I now turn to my reply to this criticism. I assert that neither
made of the many dimensions of the analysand, but also involves (A) nor (B) are testable predictions. For assume that a child has
the observations, self-made, of the analyst in the interaction. been protected from trauma by every conceivable device (this
These phenomena are not as easily measured as are some in the includes protection from physical injury) and therefore could
traditional natural sciences. not have been in the situation of repressing any trauma. Howev-
er, suppose that at age 20 this individual feels frustrated and
visits a psychoanalyst. It is practically certain that the analyst
will find that his prospective patient is neurotic and has there-
fore repressed a trauma received in childhood, hence that the
attempts to protect him had been unsuccessful (for whatever
Predicting overt behavior versus predicting reason). Or, to put it more sharply, (A) and (B) are if-then
hidden states sentences, but it is impossible to test them, for this would
demand that we make sure that the "if" part (the antecedent) is
Karl Popper true (which is hardly possible) even if the "then" part is false
Fallowfield, Manor Close, Manor Rd., Penn, Bucks. HP10 BHZ, England rather than true (which psychoanalysts are likely to assert
Editorial Note: The following contribution from Professor Karl anyway).
Popper is not a review of Professor Griinbaum's book but a So we have two problems: (1) Who decides whether or not the
critique of an argument from the book as conveyed to Popper by prospective patient has suffered and "repressed" a "trauma"?
Daniel Goleman of the New York Times/Science Times. The Clearly there is no overt behavioral way of doing so. The other
Times has suggested, and Popper and Griinbaum have agreed, problem is of course: (2) Who decides whether the prospective
that this exchange would be more appropriate in the context of patient is or is not at present neurotic? Only if he is not neurotic
the present BBS multiple book review. Professor Popper in- is the prediction testable. Now I admit that there may perhaps
forms us that he has not seen the book. be definite cases of so-called "neurosis." But who has ever met a
For over sixty years, I have been an opponent of both behav- prospective patient who was told by his prospective psycho-
iorism and psychoanalysis. Behaviorism is mistaken in its un- analyst that he was not neurotic? That he was suffering, say,
willingness to attribute psychological states to people. Such from bad teeth? (There is a terrible story of psychoanalytic
states as envy, jealousy, or the fear of poverty were excluded (as misdiagnosis that every interested person ought to read in an
unscientific) from behaviorist attempts to explain people's ac- important book entitled The Victim's Always the Same, written
tions or behavior. But the behaviorists would have been right if by the great neurosurgeon I.S. Cooper [1974]).

254 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Commentary/Grunbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
I know very well indeed that diagnostic mistakes unfortunate- other facets of human conduct, despite the clear-cut failure of his
ly occur in all branches of medicine. But psychoanalysis, includ- clinical arguments. . . . I maintain that psychoanalysis is thus alive,
ing Freud, has often asserted that everybody is neurotic (to a but at least currently hardly well, as it were.
greater or lesser degree). So how can (A) or (B), whose testability Clearly he declares himself to be a friendly critic.
depends on the prediction of nonneurosis, be clearly testable? Whereas I do not consider it warranted to conclude that there
[Incidentally (1) and (2) could be greatly improved: See Popper, is no possibility of obtaining probative intraclinical data (indeed
1983, Section 18 especially p. 169. But I do not think that (1) and Edelson, 1984, has already issued a vigorous and formidable
(2) can be improved sufficiently for the prediction to become challenge to that conclusion), I do find myself in accord with a
testable.] major thrust of Griinbaum's argument. It does seem to me that
To judge from (A) and (B) it seems that people have not yet ultimate validation will have to comefromextraclinical findings.
grasped the fact that scientific testability is a question of overt But does such a view disenfranchise psychoanalytic process
behavior. It cannot be achieved by speaking of alleged or hidden from participating in the search for the truth or falsity of Freud's
states such as "repression" or "trauma" or "neurosis," states theory? I think not, and want now to say why, and also to
whose hypothetical presence or absence cannot be tested (and of indicate how I think it may participate, indeed may be indispen-
which it even remains questionable whether they are ever sible, in a good part of the search. In the limited space available
absent). For who has never been hurt, never suffered a trauma? here I can only touch the surface of the cogent issues raised by
And who has not tried to get over it by forgetting about it this question. I have discussed them intensively and in depth
which means "trying to repress" it? But if so, (A) and (B) and all elsewhere (Reiser 1984).
similar so-called predictions are untestable. First, the "why." The process of psychoanalysis provides a
method of immense power for the study of human mental
function, a method that is unique in its capacity to provide
access to quintessential aspects of the human's inner life -
aspects currently inaccessible to any other method. But what
Griinbaum's critique of clinical about its methodological defects? In addition to the problem of
suggestion discussed so extensively by Grunbaum, there are
psychoanalytic evidence: A sheep in wolfs other methodological troubles: The method as traditionally used
clothing? yields subjective data acquired by introspection and communi-
cated in the context of private dyadic relationships; hence the
Morton F. Reiser data cannot be consensually validated or pass criteria of reliabili-
Department of Psychiatry, Yale University School of Medicine, New Haven, ty. Still, if we want to know about the important aspects of
Conn. 06519 mental life that it can access, it is the best and only way to start,
As a serious psychoanalyst I must say (like the man in the despite its serious flaws. Here then is a challenge! Those who
astringent shave lotion commercial) "Thanks! I needed that." believe that unique valuable information is contained in the
Professor Grunbaum minces no words in asserting that Freud "crude ore" of clinical psychoanalytic data must develop meth-
failed to vindicate his method of clinical investigation. In a series ods to extract and refine it. (Grunbaum might in a similar vein
of salvos he lays to rest the central "tally argument" upon which ask for methods that can "sift" probative bits of data from a
Freud based his defense of the "cornerstone" theory of repres- surfeit of flawed material.)
sion. Accordingly, this theory, along with the general body of Next, the question of "how." There are several promising
psychoanalytic hypotheses that rest upon it, can lay no claim to approaches, some already tried with some (limited) success (see
scientific credibility. And, in the absence of a tenable "em- references cited above). One, a "dual track approach" that I
pirically plausible" alternative to the crucial but "well nigh favor as most promising, is to start by studying the psycho-
empirically untenable" tally argument, Grunbaum convincingly analytic process itself, recording, describing, arranging, and
argues that the conclusions drawn from it by Freud (and by later studying the "crude ore" data it yields in naturalistic clinical
psychoanalytic theorists) are "devastatingly" undermined. He rather than metapsychological terms. Metapsychological ab-
further concludes that it is impossible to obtain probative data in stractions are distant from the observed phenomena themselves
the intraclinical psychoanalytic situation. This is a challenge that and, being hypothetical constructs, have no potential for artic-
cannot fail to provoke responses - one hopes that many of them, ulating directly with measurable phenomena studied by the
such as Edelson's (1983; 1984), will be pointed in plausible and natural sciences. From such clinical work it should be possible
empirically tenable directions. progressively to refine psychologically framed questions and
I feel impelled, however, to begin with the assertion of a hypotheses, for example, about memory, anxiety, and percep-
crucially important point: The epistemic issue - the truth or tion - mental functions about which psychoanalytic process can
falsity of Freud's ideas - is not what is under direct critical attack have much to say and in which biological disciplines have shared
in Griinbaum's book; rather, it is the methodological issue - the interest. Progressively and deliberately refined psychological
probative value of the psychoanalytic method. Grunbaum is not hypotheses developed step by step in the clinical situation, and
saying that Freud's theory is untrue in an absolute sense, but stemming from questions that originate there, should then be
that it is not (and cannot be) supported by the clinical data amenable to extraclinical experimental testing by methods of
gathered in the psychoanalytic context; the clinical data do not natural science - neuroscience on one hand and cognitive
provide valid empirical evidence for it and hence do not furnish psychology on the other (psychoanalysis as an intellectual disci-
a warrant for believing it. But those who may be impatient to pline lies between these two). These should not and need not be
bury psychoanalysis itself willfindno warrant for doing so in this trivial hypotheses, since the ideas behind them would have
book, at least not just yet. On page 189 Professor Grunbaum originated in immediate observations of the core processes
states: under investigation. And the ideas they carry would have issued
I am concerned to forestall a potential misunderstanding of a central from thoughts that developed in the minds of clinicians accord-
thesis of this book. I do claim to substantiate herein the poverty of the ing to usual patterns of clinical reasoning and inference. A major
clinical credentials of the foundations on which Freud's edifice problem in this "distillation" process would be to retain enough
avowedly rests. Yet I emphatically allow for a weighty possibility: of the clinical essence to render the hypotheses relevant, and at
Future extroclinical evidence (e.g., epidemiologic or experimental the same time to frame them in paradigms that would be
findings) may turn out to reveal after all that Freud's brilliant intellec- amenable to experimental testing by methods of the related
tual imagination was quite serendipitous for psychopathology and disciplines with which psychoanalysis can articulate.

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 255


CommentaryI'Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
One further caution needs to be sounded here. Since psychol- passage through the years of Oedipal strife and that those so
ogy and biology represent different domains (i.e. the mental and inclined lie fixed back in an immature stage of development.
the physical), composite units within each can only be studied Since normal sexual growth involves a kind of switching back
independently and can only be described in different terms and and forth between the ends of the male-female gender scale,
different languages. Descriptions and concepts are not inter- the homosexual is one who has inclinations more appropriate to
changeable between the two realms (see also Rose 1978). Be- the members of the opposite sex.
cause of this it would be important to track data from the two Now, with Grunbaum we can agree that this seems to be a
domains independently and in parallel (the "dual track ap- genuine scientific hypothesis (as regards the possibility of falsi-
proach") when approaching phenomena of common interest to fiability). Yet, also with Grunbaum, we must agree that there is
both domains. This would be in order to avoid the pitfalls of much that is very suspect about the testing that has been done of
inappropriately psychologizing physiology or physiologizing this hypothesis. Freud argues that (in the case of males) failure
psychology while at the same time allowing for generating
intermediate concepts that could serve as "transducers" be- to mature, or regression to an earlier stage, is often caused by an
tween the two domains. overwhelming mother and hostile father - with the sissy, soon-
to-be homosexual son sitting at the third point of the "classic
Admittedly we are far from realizing a well-developed pro- triangle." But since much of the so-called testing involves only a
gram of this sort, but some beginnings have been effected, the few people, and reports are frequently obtained through ana-
direction to go seems reasonable and clear, and the aims are lysts (who are hardly disinterested observers), there is more
certainly worthwhile. As Grunbaum says in his discussion of than a small element of faith which enters into much that has
Edelson - "it remains to be seen" (p.94). Fair enough. One been claimed positively for the hypothesis (most particularly in
hopes that his book will stimulate serious analysts to respond
constructively. In any event, it's good to know that we have at the well-known study by Bieber, Dain, Dince, Drellich, Grand,
least one friendly critic - to paraphrase the familiar saying, we Gundlach, Kremer, Rifkin, Wilbur & Bieber 1962). Moreover,
won't then need an enemy. Freud's own theory is most suspect; he was crippled by some
very odd ideas about the biology of our species (as Frank
Sulloway, 1979, has shown definitively), believing that much
that we do and experience today represents Lamarckian kinds of
inherited traces of actual actions of our ancestors.
Griinbaum on psychoanalysis: Where do we I ask (not concealing unspoken criticism but in a genuine
go from here? sense of inquiry) whether Grunbaum would have us turn our
backs on Freud at this point? For surely, despite what certain
Michael Ruse gay activists would argue, it is legitimate to inquire into the
Departments of History and Philosophy, University of Guelph, Guelph, causes of the sexual orientation of 10% of the population. Does
Ontario N1G 2W1, Canada Grunbaum (even as he defends Freud against Popper and
Like many professional philosophers of science, I have long felt cohorts) really want us to leave psychoanalytic theory back at the
extremely uneasy about Freud and his work (Ruse 1981). On the beginning of this century? Would he have us search for alter-
one hand, we seem not to have done him full justice. On the native explanations, for example, imprinting (Money 1961), or
other hand, one wonders if there is something really there hormones (Dorner 1976), or perhaps even something outrightly
which merits full justice. Now, in his brilliantly insightful biological as suggested by the sociobiologists (Wilson 1978)?
critique Grunbaum shows fully that the sense of unease has a (Actually, in defense of Freud against some of his followers, I
solid foundation. note that he always thought that some people are simply in-
nately what they are.)
I see Griinbaum as having done two things. First, he has
Hoping to stir response from Grunbaum, let me say flatly that
shown beyond all doubt that the philosophical critics of Freud
I should be sorry if he were to take this anti-Freudian line or if
and of psychoanalytic theory simply have not done their home-
his critique were to point him in this direction. Perhaps we
work. For instance, Popper's (1962; 1974a) pretend-stories and
should fall back on a distinction that was popular in the last
contemptuous back-of-the-hand dismissals are grotesquely un-
century (e.g. Whewell 1840) and for much of this one. (e.g.
fair to all students of the human mind and behaviour. It is hard
Nagel 1961), although it has come under attack in recent years:
enough to make progress in this field without the savage mis-
The distinction is one between the phenomenal or formal part of
representations of those who should know better.
a science and its causal underlying theory. Can we not save
Indeed, one would be tempted to say that Popper's "refuta- Freud - continuing to illustrate our discussion with the specific
tion" of Freud, not to mention the enthusiastic endorsement of instance of sexual orientation - by agreeing that he pointed to
Popper's sycophants, is self-refuting - evidence in itself for the some of the broad principles or generalities governing human
worth of Freud's work - were it not for Griinbaum's second behaviour? At the same time, however, we can concede that
point. Ill-founded criticisms aside, there really are severe con- Freud gave no true explanation of why things are as they are.
ceptual problems with Freud's ideas. Furthermore, the quality Recently, there have been extensive empirical studies di-
of testing to date has been pitifully inadequate. You simply rected toward uncovering possible links between human sexual
cannot encourage someone on the couch to talk about mother attitudes and the environmental influences on development.
and expect to get control and evidence of the kind demanded by Furthermore, these have striven - I believe successfully - to
science, let alone demanded by good science. avoid many of the earlier fallacies and flaws. One thinks, for
But, of course, as Grunbaum himself fully recognizes, what instance, of the latest Kinsey study (Bell & Weinberg 1978; Bell,
he has offered us thus far is a critique. What he has shown us is Weinberg & Hammersmith 1981). Moreover, significantly,
what is wrong. The all-important question which Grunbaum these surveys do pick out Freudian kinds of correlations be-
inspires, but which he does not (yet) answer is: Where do we go tween familial situations and adult sexual orientation, backing
from here? What is to be done next? Take (to put some substance thefindingswith evidence of expected cross-gender attributes.
in our discussion) the question of homosexuality, or (to put it in If these studies are well-founded - unlike so much of the
the form favoured by sex researchers) the question of homosex- earlier work, regrettably of the kind that Grunbaum discusses -
ual orientation. As Griinbaum's constant references acknowl- then perhaps we can now truly give Freud full credit, at least, at
edge, this is a phenomenon much discussed by Freud, and lies the level of the phenomena. What we must therefore set to
at the heart of his thinking about our psychosexual constitution doing next is finding full causal backing, relying on far-more-
(see, especially, Freud 1905). Briefly, Freud thought that a sophisticated biological and social scientific theories than were
homosexual orientation was (usually) due to an inadequate available to Freud himself. We must turn to biochemistry, brain

256 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Commentary I Grunbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
science, evolutionary biology and much more. Then, we can ing primitive societies. Consider Child Training and Person-
hope to uncover the full causal reasons for those empirical ality Q. Whiting 1953) and Six Cultures (B. Whiting 1963), in
patterns which Freud first spotted. which psychoanalytic theory is the organizing viewpoint.
In short, I suggest that Grunbaum has undoubtedly shown In these works, the approach is not, as some would hold
that Freud was no Newton of the mind. I invite Griinbaum to against the late Margaret Mahler, dogmatic and self-confirmato-
respond to the suggestion that Freud may nevertheless have ry; both explicitly anthropological and psychoanalytic hypoth-
been its Kepler. eses are rather thoroughly tested. In a more recent work, The
Oedipus Complex, William N. Stephens (1962) breaks down the
specific components of the Oedipal hypothesis and tests each
one individually. If the results of these investigators (not to
mention Malinowski (1927a; 1927b) and others) hold up - and I
Some gaps in Grunbaum's critique of think they do - then they would go a long way toward establish-
psychoanalysis ing an epistemological groundwork for psychoanalysis.
A second area of difference has to do with Freud's relevance to
Irwin Savodnik the contemporary neurosciences. It is clearly impossible to
Department of Psychiatry, University of California, Los Angeles, Calif. establish this relevance in a short review, but I would like to
90024; Southern California Psychoanalytic Institute, Los Angeles, Calif.
suggest it and indicate its significance. Freud's neurological
In The Foundations of Psychoanalysis Adolf Grunbaum offers foundations permeate his entire corpus, as Richard Wollheim
the most exhaustive and powerful critique of psychoanalysis to (1971) and Karl Pribram and Merton Gill (1976) have indicated
date. He attacks both the hermeneutic accounts of psycho- in their writings. Of particular importance is the new work on
analysis and those accounts that treat psychoanalysis as a sci- hemispheric laterality by Geschwind (1974) and others es-
ence. His strategy is clear. If he destroys both sets of defenders pecially when it deals with such things as propositional speech
then psychoanalysis has no place to go and must of necessity lose and intentional action. I would suggest that Freud's analysis of
all or most of its legitimacy. He dismisses the hermeneutic dreams, his distinction between the primary and secondary
school in a scathing opening chapter and then settles down to a modes of mental functioning, and his theory of affects bear
long critique of the scientific status that psychoanalysis claims it extraordinary similarity to the neurological findings concerning
deserves. the differences between the cerebral hemispheres. If psycho-
Grunbaum, while vituperatively critical of psychoanalysis, is analysis fits in, even points the way at times - and I think it does
not out to destroy the field. Rather, his target is that group of - to the greater structure of science, then it will have enhanced
analysts and their followers who promulgate the scientific ac- its stature and legitimacy a great deal. Human behavior being
count of psychoanalysis because the reward for such scientific what it is, psychoanalysis is a poor predictor of what people will
status is increased prestige within the wider intellectual com- do in the future. Like evolutionary theory, which has a similar
munity, not to mention increased fees. Thus, he does not have problem, it indicates fertile areas for further investigation and
much regard for psychoanalysis as a branch of medicine and gives us a broader three-dimensional perspective of human life.
attacks the analysts for not launching longitudinal, controlled Finally, it is well to keep in mind James's (1967) distinction
studies in their field as the other branches of medicine do. between those who seek truth and those who avoid error. As
His critique centers upon what he calls Freud's necessary James points out, the two groups are not the same. It strikes me
condition thesis: that the sphere of human action and conflict is so complex as to
(1) Only the psychoanalytic method of interpretation and treatment represent something of a special case. It is not enough to assure
can yield or mediate to the patient correct insight into the uncon- ourselves that we have made no mistakes. We may have to be
scious pathogens of his psychoneurosis, and (2) the analysand's correct more creative and countenance other ways of seeking the truth.
insight into the etiology of his affliction and into the unconscious Perhaps Grunbaum has fallen into that group about which James
dynamics of his character is, in turn, causally necessary for the warns us. He has held up his concept of scientific method (and
therapeutic conquest of his neurosis (pp. 139-40). far from a narrow-minded one, as some would hold) and given
Grunbaum draws a number of conclusions from this construal the impression that it is the only way to reach the truth. Even if
of Freud's theory. His central goal, though, is to deny to he is entirely right about the failure of psychoanalysis to meet
psychoanalysis epistemic legitimacy for what he sees as a highly the criteria for correct scientific procedure there is still the
dubious and idiosyncratic methodology. He argues that Freud's Jamesian imperative to seek the truth even at the expense of
attempt to make psychoanalytic method the only way to arrive at some caution. I think psychoanalysis, for all its foibles and
the truth or falsity of psychoanalytic hypotheses fails. He does mistakes (which Grunbaum clearly identifies), does reach the
not believe that psychoanalysis enjoys some sort of privileged truth and contributes a great deal to our culture.
status that frees it from being held to the same rigorous criteria
of scientific research as the rest of science. He doesn't like
Freud's approach for just that reason and also because it rules
out the very possibility that other ways of achieving therapeutic An argument for the evidential standing of
success (e.g. placebo, behavior therapy, suggestion) are even
possible. Therefore, for Grunbaum, psychoanalysis secures its psychoanalytic data
position by seeming to justify its own peculiar method and at the
Howard Shevrin
same time eliminating the opposition almost by fiat. If Griin-
Department of Psychiatry, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, Mich. 48105
baum is right then psychoanalysts have a lot of explaining to do.
In spite of the power of his attack, Grunbaum's critique has As a psychoanalyst and researcher I am grateful to Professor
not demolished the psychoanalytic edifice. He certainly has Grunbaum for his searching critique of the psychoanalytic
encouraged a good deal of rebuilding, perhaps, but that is all to clinical method. I have learned much in the course of following
the good. Consider his claim that psychoanalysis should not be his tightly reasoned arguments. But I am greatly concerned that
exempt from longitudinal controlled studies of human develop- his critique will be grievously misconstrued in some quarters as
ment and conflict. As a matter of fact, a substantial body of a coup de grace to psychoanalysis rather than as a sympathetic
literature on just this set of issues goes a long way toward effort to point the way to creating a solid empirical foundation for
establishing the sort of legitimacy that Grunbaum feels psycho- the science. In more than one passage Grunbaum pays homage
analysis lacks. The work of cultural anthropologists has, for a to the powerful heuristic value of psychoanalytic hypotheses,
long time, used psychoanalysis as a framework for understand- both within and beyond the treatment situation. He is not

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 257


Commentary/Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis

attacking the theory as such, but the status of its current states the truth when he says, "I see blue," that is, if we grant
probative standing. Unfortunately, Gardner, as quoted on the the truth of his experience, then why doubt the truth of the
book jacket, overlooks this repeated demurrer, proclaiming that following statement, which is more complex but, in principle,
the study is "a major contribution to the growing groundswell of no different: "I was not conscious of X before I made that slip
attacks, by informed thinkers, on one of the most persistent but now I am (because of free associations) and furthermore, I
dogmatic establishments of recent times." And Hobson, on the recall that I once thought X (days, weeks, years before) and was
same book jacket, compliments Grunbaum on his "inexorable made uncomfortable by it and stopped thinking about it from
and compelling critique of the science of Freud," which in effect that time on until a moment ago"? Grunbaum tells us that the
will undermine the beliefs of those who "looked to psycho- statement can be doubted because it could have been influ-
analysis for a general scientific theory of the human mind." enced by the patient's knowledge of psychoanalytic theory,
Grunbaum has undertaken no such task, and his conclusion direct suggestion on the part of the analyst, or by the force of the
should strengthen and not weaken psychoanalysis. positive transference.
Why should Grunbaum's critique strengthen and not weaken All this is possibly true, but it is based on the supposition that
psychoanalysis? Because he demonstrates that if psychoanalytic the patient's reality testing is altogether in abeyance, unlike that
theory, of admitted substantial heuristic value, is to survive and of any living organism in its traffic with its surroundings. Grun-
flourish, its probative value must be pursued on the basis of a baum might in fact grant that some patients' statements are true;
variety of extraclinical methods. Issue can be taken with Grun- however, there is no way of knowing which statements are true
baum in his wholesale rejection of the clinical method as a and which are false and one can only be sure if their truth value is
proving ground and in his apparent overestimation of the pro- tested in an extraclinical setting. But is there such a final or
bative value of other methods. Here Grunbaum takes aim at the crucial test for the truth? No method is perfect, and all must
psychoanalytic clinical method but may have inadvertently hit assume that subjects make true statements about their experi-
reason itself. ences (e.g. "I see blue").
Let us suppose I conduct an experiment in color perception It may also be that with the addition of various controls one
and present my subjects with various color discs; after each disc can increase the certainty with which one believes the rela-
I ask them to tell me what they saw. They respond with tionship found in an experiment, but, as Grunbaum points out,
statements such as, "I saw red" or "It was blue this time." I note this belief remains contingent on the overall status of the theory
that there is a systematic relationship between discs that reflect being tested in the experiment and - I would add - on certain
different frequencies and the verbal responses elicited. I have presumed regularities and reality testing, true for all subjects.
established a relationship between a physical parameter and Thus it would seem that the matter comes down to one of degree
perception. Or have I? Yes, if you will grant me that (1) subjects rather than one of kind.
report their experience accurately and (2) there is a regular and It is inescapable that experimental subjects and analytic
invariant relationship between the meaning of words and their patients, like scientists, possess the capacity to know truth from
referents. Suppose that when blue light frequencies activate the falsity and that their statements are acceptable as truths of
brain a red experience occurs but that the word "blue" refers for experience at face value. This is not the same as ascribing to the
that particular person to a red experience. His report "I see patient the ability to explain what lies behind the truths of his
blue" will be entirely misleading. (Some color-blind people experience. Thus, the patient can report, as did Elizabeth von
have a comparable experience because they use the words "red" R. to Freud, that at her sister's deathbed, with her attractive
and "blue" to refer to qualities of experience other than color.) brother-in-law standing nearby, the thought, "Now he is free
But let us suppose further that the disjunction between report again and I can be his wife," shot through her mind and was
and experience was universal, in which case the verbal state- immediately banished (Breuer & Freud 1895). This is an ac-
ments would be meaningless for conveying the actual nature of count of motivated forgetting or repression. Why should this
the experience. account not have evidential status as much as the statement, "I
This kind of "inverted-spectrum" argument is a reductio ad see blue," once we take into account that the capacity for reality
absurdum of the radical behaviorist position. What it calls testing in and out of the transference is not limited to experi-
attention to is the implicit assumption in all science that there mental subjects? Moreover, if you deny reality testing to neu-
are assured regularities: The universe is not totally random and rotic patients, you cannot maintain it for experimental subjects.
chaotic, although, as Prigogine (1984) has pointed out, random If Grunbaum is altogether right about the analytic clinical
processes may play a significant role. Furthermore, it is cer- method, then there is no relying on reasonableness in any
tainly the case that organisms have evolved in order to adapt to context.
the regularities in their environment (e.g. light, heat, food, In short, the clinical method gives us access to certain phe-
conspecifics, etc.). Indeed, various organs and internal pro- nomena as no other method can. Freud's admirable heuristic
cesses have evolved in order to ensure this fit between the hypotheses did not come out of thin air or simply out of his
organism and its surroundings. imagination. Rather, these hypotheses were created in order to
In the case of human beings, psychoanalysts refer to this account for statements of the kind made by Elizabeth von R.
capacity as the analysand's reality testing; without it, as with any These phenomena are no more compromised than any self-
organism, he could not survive. Reality testing may be compro- reports of an experience once it is assumed that regularities
mised by neurosis, but it can never be entirely vitiated by it. In exist, that words can convey them, and that patients have the
fact, only patients with intact capacity for reality testing are capacity to test reality. However, to establish the existence of
considered suitable for psychoanalysis and they are carefully repression or its role in pathogenesis is not the same as knowing
screened - much more carefully than most experimental sub- how repression works or exactly how it produces neurosis or
jects, who are usually recruits from student subject pools put- what factors contribute to certain kinds of early experiences.
ting in obligatory time with that consideration in mind. In Grunbaum is right in asserting that patients (like the rest of us,
other words, the neurotic patient is capable of reality testing including the subject in the color experiment) do not have
within the special environment of relevance, the analysis, as is privileged access to the causes of their experience. As an
any organism, from the ameoba on up, within its relevant analysis progresses, patient and analyst fashion an increasingly
environment. complete and likely explanation for the neurosis on the basis of
The neurotic patient is as concerned with and finds it as much mutual sifting of the evidence, from past and present,
necessary to test the reality of the analysis as any organism in any some of the evidence becoming available because of the pro-
environment, and he is to a greater or lesser extent capable of it. gress of the analysis itself in diminishing resistances. It often
If we grant that my subject in the color perception experiment happens that with increased understanding the patient experi-

258 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Commentary/Grunbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
ences a wider array of life choices than before, when crippled by the evidence. Examples of overt suggestion or too-docile com-
the neurosis: that is, he is "cured. " But this process is in pliance would be the first kind of data to be excluded and thus
principle no different from what happens in an experiment the tradition of narrative smoothing may account for the small
which we consider successful to the extent that a certain hypoth- amount of evidence cited by Grunbaum.
esis is not refuted by the evidence; it is not proven by the But the argument cuts both ways. Because we have almost no
results, although with more such favorable results we begin to information about what really goes on in the consulting room,
believe the hypothesis to be true, belief remaining a personal Grunbaum's charge must be held in abeyance until more data
matter and not subject to final proof. are in. We simply do not know (a) the amount of contamination;
Elizabeth von R. knew she had banished a painful thought; (b) the spread of infection within the session; and (c) the extent to
she did not know how she did it or what the consequences would which suggested responses (which appear to support the theory
be (Breuer & Freud 1895). It was at this juncture that Freud but which are evidentially worthless) are balanced by unex-
introduced his pathetically misconstrued metapsychology to pected confirmations which support the theory and take the
account for these mechanisms in a language that obviously had analyst by surprise. Until we have more adequate methods for
to be different from the language of experience. "unpacking " the clinical interchange and canfinda new genre to
Certainly other extraclinical methods must, as Grunbaum take the place of the traditional case report, Grunbaum's charge
advocates, be brought to bear on helping us reach a fuller may remain moot - but it is certainly not proven.
understanding of these clinically adduced phenomena brought In the second place, it should be noted that psychoanalysts
to light but not invented by the psychoanalytic clinical method. are particularly sensitized (in the course of their training) to the
However, these extraclinical methods must be drawn upon in dangers of suggestion, and schooled in a tradition which places
addition to the clinical method because the clinical method is an emphasis on minimal comment and redundant examples.
the only way we can be in touch with certain phenomena. The Edelson makes the same point: "Many features of the psycho-
probative value of the clinical method can be enhanced by analytic situation, in contrast to those of other psychotherapies,
appplying various systematic techniques to the clinical data, are in fact designed to control extraneous external influences on
such as random and representative sampling, matched pairs, the analysand's productions" (1984, p. 129). Of course, these
prediction, postdiction, and so on. But the value of these observations do not settle the question; answers will only come
systematic procedures is based on the supposition that clinical from close examination of the clinical dialogue, and for that we
statements have evidential standing, a position Grunbaum de- need verbatim transcripts which have been supplemented by
nies but which one can defend. the analyst's private thoughts and feelings (see in this regard Gill
and Hoffman, 1982, Edelson, 1984, and Spence, 1982).
Just because we are not always aware of the original texture of
the clinical dialogue and just because it is perfectly possible for
certain kinds of suggestion to appear does not mean that they
Are free associations necessarily present us with an impossible methodological obstacle, or that
contaminated? the effects of suggestion cannot be isolated, when and where
they occur, and their influence kept separatefromother aspects
Donald P. Spence of the psychoanalytic process. As more verbatim transcripts are
Department of Psychiatry, University of Medicine and Dentistry of New made available, it should become increasingly possible to iden-
Jersey Rutgers Medical School, Piscataway, N.J. 08854
tify instances of suggestion and to study, in turn, their effect on
Griinbaum argues that free associations are neither free nor other parts of the treatment. As of early 1985, plans are under
independent because they may be influenced by suggestion way to formulate new standards for case reporting in the major
from the analyst, contaminated by a knowledge of theory, or psychoanalytic journals which would address themselves to
otherwise epistemically impaired. "For example," he writes, "a issues of documentation and find ways to minimize inadvertent
'confirming' early memory may be compliantly produced by the narrative smoothing. Significant progress on these issues could
patient on the heels of giving docile assent to an interpretation" easily change the face of the clinical literature and make possible
(p. 277). If the clinical data are thoroughly confounded by a more considered response to Grunbaum's challenge.
suggestion and expectation then one can only agree with Griin- It will also make possible another kind of discovery. More
baum's conclusion: "The validation of Freud's cardinal hypoth- transparent reporting will bring to light specimens of clinical
eses has to come, if at all, mainly from well-designed extra- work in which an interpretation produced a significant piece of
clinical studies . . ." (p. 278, author's italics). insight or change in behavior. These effects may or may not
What is the evidence for possible contamination? Only one correspond to what was predicted from theory, but at least we
clinical interchange is cited - which greatly weakens Griin- will have moved beyond the anecdote. This kind of conscien-
baum's case. He provides us with an excerpt from a case study tious unpacking should provide an estimate of how much cre-
by Blanck and Blanck which clearly suggests that the analyst was ative, insightful, and uncontaminated clinical work is buried
leading the patient and providing the motivation which should behind the usual kinds of narrative smoothing that appear in the
have been present, according to theory, but was not necessarily literature. Only when that day arrives can the standing of
what the patient had in mind (pp. 212-14). But if the danger of Grunbaum's challenge be adequately assessed.
suggestion is as great as Grunbaum claims, it is a little surprising
that more evidence is not provided. Is there more smoke here
than fire?
As it turns out, the paucity of evidence may be a clue to a more Human understanding and scientific
basic problem. At issue is (a) evidence that the analyst makes
leading suggestions to the patient; (b) evidence that these validation
suggestions influence the patient's response; and (c) evidence
Anthony Storr
that compliance is accepted at face value. But it should be kept
45 Chalfont Road, Oxford, 0X2 6TJ, England
in mind that this evidence is largely unavailable because of
established conventions of case reporting in the psychoanalytic Freud was trained in the laboratories of Ernst Briicke, a hard-
literature. Beginning with Freud, who saw no need to provide headed experimental scientist who was dedicated to the propo-
all the data, the history of case reporting has been anecdotal sition that only physicochemical forces were active within the
rather than archival, selective rather than complete. Each case organism. For fifteen years, Freud conducted research into the
tends to rely more on argument by authority than on appeals to anatomy and physiology of the nervous systems,firstoffish, and

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 259


Commentary)Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
then of human beings. Even after he had begun to formulate I think he isflogginga dead horse. Only a few fundamentalist
psychoanalytical ideas, he looked back with regret to his neu- psychoanalysts of an old-fashioned kind think that Freud was a
roanatomical days, published a monograph on aphasia in 1891, scientist or that psychoanalysis ever was or could be a scientific
and a major work on childhood cerebral palsy in 1897. It was enterprise. Philosophers like Dennett, Strawson, and Berlin
only because he wished to get married, and therefore needed have demonstrated that, although it may still be possible to
more money than pure research could furnish, that Freud took regard some isolated, neurotic symptoms from a detached,
his medical degree and engaged in medical practice. deterministic point of view, to understand persons cannot be a
It is entirely understandable that Freud at first approached strictly scientific enterprise. Isaiah Berlin puts it with his cus-
the study of neurosis in exactly the same way as he approached tomary clarity when he writes: "Understanding other men's
the study of organic disease, and that he treated neurotic motives or acts, however imperfect or corrigible, is a state of
symptoms with the physical methods of treatment then avail- mind or activity in principle different from learning about, or
able. However, his period of study with Charcot convinced him knowledge of, the external world." Freud was a man of genius
that ideas could be causal agents in neurosis, and that hypnosis whose expertise lay in semantics. That is, he was able to take the
could be effective in counteracting such ideas. Later, Freud's apparently inexplicable problems with which his patients con-
collaboration with Breuer led him to use hypnosis as a means of fronted him and make both sense of their symptoms and co-
helping the patient to recall forgotten (repressed) origins. For herent narratives out of their lives. Others, like Jung and Adler,
Breuer had discovered that if a hysterical patient could be tell different stories which are equally convincing. Making sense
persuaded to recall the very first moment of the appearance of a of a person's life is no mean achievement, but, like history, it is
given symptom and to relive the emotions connected with it, the an enterprise which can be approached from different points of
symptom could be made to disappear. Thus, it became estab- view, and which can never be either completed or scientifically
lished that hysterical symptoms could be caused by unpleasant validated.
ideas or memories of which the patient had become uncon-
scious. Freud formulated the theory of repression, and on this
cornerstone the whole edifice of psychoanalytic theory was
subsequently erected. Although traumatic memories are not Transference: One of Freud's basic
physical entities, like bacteria, it is still possible to think of them discoveries
as causal agents of hysteria, and thus to put neurosis into the
same category as physical disease. This, clearly, was what Freud Hans H. Strupp
thought he had done, and partly accounts for the fact that, Department of Psychology, Vanderbilt University, Nashville, Tenn. 37240
throughout the rest of his life, he continued to affirm that In this commentary I shall be primarily concerned with psycho-
psychoanalysis was, or would become, a science. analysis as a particular form of psychotherapy and with the data
Adolf Griinbaum, over the past few years, has produced a generated within the psychotherapeutic framework. Indeed,
number of papers criticizing psychoanalysis from the philosoph- clinical observations are the context in which Breuer and Freud
ical point of view. The learned book under review represents made their revolutionary discoveries, and they remain the
the culmination of his endeavor. He begins by criticizing the fundament on which the psychoanalytic theory of psycho-
work of his fellow philosophers, Jurgen Habermas and Paul therapy rests. There would be less confusion about psycho-
Ricoeur, and goes on to examine the work of the late George S. analytic theory today if Freud had confined himself to the
Klein. In the chapter titled "Is Freud's Theory Empirically therapeutic enterprise; his fame would surely be secure if he
Testable?" Griinbaum cogently exposes the inadequacy of had. Regrettably, his ambition drove him to develop a universal
clinical observation as proof of psychoanalytic theory. He rightly theory to account for all aspects of human behavior. In this effort
criticizes Karl Popper for possessing an inadequate knowledge he often engaged in speculation and, as Griinbaum and earlier
of Freud's actual writings, which are both less dogmatic and writers have shown, many of his formulations are questionable,
more aware of potential objections to psychoanalytic theory than if not untenable.
most people suppose. It is even the case that, in his "Auto-
biographical Study" of 1925, Freud admitted that "the personal Let me concentrate on what I consider one of Freud's most
emotional relation between doctor and patient was after all important and empirically grounded discoveries - transference.
stronger than the whole cathartic process," thus raising the If one creates a clinical situation in which one person, the
possibility that psychoanalytic "cure" has nothing to do with therapist, assumes a benign and expectant attitude and attends
psychoanalytic interpretation. closely to the verbalizations and the behavior of a person who
Griinbaum forcefully argues that "free association" is neither has come for help, it soon becomes apparent that the patient will
free nor validating evidence for psychoanalytic theory, as is enact with the therapist scenarios that are not in keeping with
generally claimed by psychoanalysts. He affirms, with good the professional relationship between two adults in the present.
reason, that future attempts to validate psychoanalytic hypoth- The patient will unwittingly assign particular roles to and endow
eses must come from extraclinical testing rather than from data the therapist with qualities not actually present; other qualities
obtained in clinical psychoanalytic sessions. He makes pertinent will be distorted. That is, the patient will transfer to the
criticism of Freud's theory of dreams, which, in spite of Freud's therapist wishes, fantasies, fears, frustrations, and so on, that
belief that this represented his greatest insight, has failed to are not grounded in "reality" but derive their meaning from the
stand the test of time. patient's life experience, notably early childhood. Further-
From this brief account, it might be concluded that Griin- more, it is a common observation that when the anachronistic
baum is merely destructive. This is not the case. He recognizes character of these misattributions is systematically explored and
that Freud was a man of genius, and he is far better informed clarified ("interpreted"), a therapeutic benefit results.
about what Freud actually wrote than most of Freud's critics. For reasons to be elaborated below, Freud attached undue
My difficulty in wholeheartedly recommending what I recog- weight to the mutative effect of interpretations. However, he
nize to be a work of considerable scholarship is twofold. First, also recognized that, in the course of therapy, the therapist
Griinbaum's style of writing is densely turgid. One's difficulty in becomes an important role model ("mentor") for the patient;
disinterring what he actually has to say is compounded by his that therapy requires the formation of a viable working rela-
use of words like "scientificity," "retrodictability," "rejec- tionship ("therapeutic alliance"); and that the patient must
tionism," "misextrapolation," and "diphthography," none of reexperience ("work through") old conflicts, traumas, and mal-
which are to be found either in Chambers Twentieth Century adaptive patterns of behavior that still interfere with present-
Dictionary or in the Oxford English Dictionary of 1971. Second, day adaptation.

260 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Commentary/Grunbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
The foregoing is the substance of all forms of psychotherapy who then unwittingly confirm the therapist's privately held
based on psychoanalytic principles. To be sure, the therapist theories. On the other hand, transference phenomena, which I
becomes part of the two-person system of psychotherapy, and it consider the fulcrum of modern psychoanalytic theory, are so
is undeniable that one cannot participate in interpersonal trans- well documented and require so few theoretical assumptions
actions without influencing them. Thus, although the that, realistically, they meet the criteria for basic observational
therapeutic enterprise may, in a strict sense, be "epistemically data. In addition, any therapist worthy of the name attempts to
flawed," as Grunbaum insists, it is possible to keep it reasonably collect convergent evidence before presenting a patient with an
close to empirical observations. Furthermore, it is possible to interpretation. Such evidence comes from the patient's observ-
conduct psychotherapy without many of Freud's metapsycho- able behavior in therapy, the reported interactions with signifi-
logical speculations. Indeed, I consider this the direction of cant others in the present and the past, verbalizations of various
future work in this area (Strupp & Binder 1984). By the same kinds in which may be embedded particular themes, and - yes -
token, I question whether one can "validate" clinical observa- also dreams, fantasies, and the like.
tions in the laboratory, and, in contrast to Grunbaum, I do not In conclusion, Freud's seminal discoveries originated in the
see this as a necessary requirement. However, it is essential for clinical situation, and he related many of his constructs to the
therapists to deal continually with their own emotional reactions therapeutic setting. In his expectations of what psychoanalytic
to the patient's productions (formerly, but somewhat mis- therapy could accomplish (particularly in comparison with other
leadingly, called countertransference). modalities) he wavered between unbridled enthusiasm and
Freud elevated interpretations to a position of preeminence disillusionment. The farther he strayed from clinical data and
because he was intent upon demonstrating the uniqueness of the more he engaged in abstract theorizing, the more he became
psychoanalytic therapy, particularly vis-4-vis hypnosis. Thus he vulnerable to the charges Griinbaum levels against his theories.
attempted, but basically failed, to show that "suggestion" plays In my judgment, the future of psychoanalytic psychotherapy
no part in his system of therapy. From there it is but a short step lies with the transactions between patient and therapist in the
to the "Necessary Condition Thesis" (NCT) (Foundations, pp. here-and-now. Thanks to videotaping and other modern record-
139-140). If for no other reasons, NCT is untenable because ing techniques, these transactions can be observed and studied
psychoanalysis is not a unique form of psychotherapy. In this by external judges. It may turn out that Freud's insights gained
respect I fully agree with Grunbaum. from psychotherapy are greater and more lasting than his work
By this I mean that in all forms of psychotherapy the therapist in other areas. However, even with respect to psychotherapy,
exerts a psychological influence. As my friend the analyst Freud's theories, like all scientific theories, must be regarded as
Hartvig Dahl (personal communication) points out, psycho- provisional and subject to reformulation as knowledge
therapy can do only two things: (1) persuade the patient to give advances.
up unrealizable wishes and (2) promote cognitive changes in
how the patient views himself and the world. The trained
psychoanalytic therapist can approximate these objectives in
skillful ways, but these operations are by no means unique.
Freud felt compelled to denigrate this influence by calling it
"suggestion." Grunbaum commits a comparable error when he Grunbaum, homosexuality, and
labels the therapist's influence a "placebo effect" (pp.178 ff.), contemporary psychoanalysis
thereby implying that there must be "special" psychological
mechanisms in formal psychotherapy. Other contemporary Frederick Suppe
writers have sought to differentiate between specific (tech- Committee on the History and Philosophy of Science, University of
nique) and nonspecific or common (interpersonal) factors in Maryland, College Park, Md. 20742
psychotherapy. That, too, is a pseudodistinction (Butler & Grunbaum is a hermeneutical tour deforce. I know of no better
Strupp, in press). job of rendering Freud's reasoning patterns plausible while
Nor can therapeutic successes (or failures) be invoked to displaying their fundamental defects. Challenging Griinbaum's
adjudicate the correctness of any theory of psychotherapy, exegesis is left to those more expert on Freud than myself.
including psychoanalysis. Partly this is so because any Rather, I will explore some of the implications of Grunbaum's
therapeutic outcome is a multifaceted and complex phe- account for contemporary psychoanalysis, using its treatment of
nomenon (Lambert, Shapiro, Bergin & Berman, in press). It is homosexuality as a case in point.
also true that researchers have not been able to link particular In 1973 the American Psychiatric Association eliminated the
outcomes to particular therapeutic interventions. In other classification of homosexuality as a disorder. A group of neo-
words, therapeutic change can be achieved in a variety of ways, Freudian psychoanalysts headed by Irving Bieber and Charles
and one cannot precisely ascertain the transactions to which Socarides challenged this and forced a referendum vote of the
change is attributed (not to mention extratherapy influences, APA membership. Although a majority supported removal,
measurement errors, etc.). For the most part, however, the today nearly all psychoanalysts still believe that homosexuality
"true" therapeutic influence of psychotherapy is, by definition, per se is a mental disorder rooted in faulty identifications,
a psychological influence whose nature must be explained infantile fixations, or defenses against unconscious impulses
(Strupp 1977). On the other hand, we learn little about the such as castration anxiety exacerbated by the Oedipal conflict.
character of therapeutic change when we attribute it to "sug- With very few exceptions analysts agree that homosexuality can
gestions" or "placebos," which are merely synonyms for lack of be treated successfully by psychoanalytic means.
scientific knowledge. Against this we have Freud's own position on homosexuality:
In my view, Freud also undertook an essentially fruitless task Although he did offer accounts of its etiology he denied homo-
when he attempted to explain why a patient "chose" a particular sexuality per se was an indication of degeneracy, opposed
neurosis and when he sought to identify specific "pathogens" for automatically barring homosexuals from psychoanalytic work,
a person's difficulties in living. The latter are always multideter- and believed there were many types of homosexuals and that
mined and almost inextricably woven into a person's "character" most were not amenable to psychoanalytic treatment (Bayer
as it has evolved over many years. The term "neurosis" itself is 1981, pp. 21-27):
of questionable scientific value. This problem is not resolved by Homosexuality is assuredly no advantage, but it is nothing to be
replacing "neurosis" with "disorder," as is attempted by DSM- ashamed of, no vice, no degradation, it cannot be classified as an
III (American Psychiatric Assn. 1980). illness; we consider it to be a variation of the sexual function produced
There is no doubt that therapists may indoctrinate patients by a certain arrest of sexual development. . . .

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 261


Commentary/Grunbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
By asking me if I can help, you mean, I suppose, if I can abolish Hatterer 1970; Socarides 1968), these claims are so conceptually
homosexuality and make normal heterosexuality take its place. The confused and questionable (Suppe 1984) as to be worthless in
answer is, in a general way, we cannot promise to achieve it. In a legitimizing the invocation of the tally argument. On p. 258
certain number of cases we succeed in developing the blighted germs Grunbaum displays a flaw in addition to client suggestibility that
of heterosexual tendencies which are present in every homosexual, in pervades the design of psychoanalytic research such as Bieber et
the majority of cases it is no more possible . . . . The result of al. (1962).
treatment cannot be predicted. I have tried to show the applicability and crucial relevance of
What analysis can do for your son runs in a different line. If he is Griinbaum's epistemological arguments to contemporary
unhappy, neurotic, torn by conflicts, inhibited in his social life, "Freudian" psychoanalysis even under circumstances in which
analysis may bring him harmony, peace of mind, full efficiency there is gross infidelity to Freud's own views by showing the
whether he remains a homosexual or gets changed. (Freud 1951) devastating relevance of Griinbaum's work to psychoanalytic
Despite efforts of psychoanalytic societies to enforce Freudian treatments of homosexuality. What is unclear is whether such
doctrinal purity (e.g. they forbid teaching Jungian analysis), on critiques will have any impact on psychoanalytic theory or
homosexuality psychoanalysis largely ignores or repudiates practice - hence on whether psychoanalysis has substantive
Freud's own teachings. respect for evidence and intellectual rigor.
This raises my first question. Griinbaum does a meticulous
job showing the epistemic inadequacy of Freud's own epis-
temological position, with the obvious belief that his objections
tell against contemporary "Freudian" analysis as well. Yet if Grunbaum's challenge to Freud's logic of
contemporary analysis plays so freely and selectively with argumentation: A reconstruction and an
Freud's positions as it does in the case of homosexuality, can it addendum
not blunt Griinbaum's attack by simply disavowing those epis-
temological views of Freud's that Grunbaum so effectively Barbara Von Eckardt
challenges? Against such a move Grunbaum maintains that "no Department of Philosophy, Colgate University, Hamilton, N.Y. 13346
empirically warranted alternative premise that could take its
Grunbaum deserves nothing but praise for his masterly and
place and yield the desired sanguine conclusions seems to be in
extensive treatment of the question of the scientific status of
sight. Hence, currently no viable surrogate for the defunct Tally
Freudian psychoanalysis. If there is a weakness in Griinbaum's
Argument appears on the horizon" (p. 166; cf. also p. 250) and
work, it lies in the area of style. The prose is so dense and the
that "the attribution of therapeutic success to the removal of
arguments so complex that I fear the forest will often be lost for
repressions . . . remains to this day, the sole epistemic under-
the trees. In the interests of elucidation, then, I would like to
writer of the purported ability of the patient's free associations to
propose the following "map" (Figure 1) of Grunbaum's discus-
certify causes" (p. 185, italics deleted). Grunbaum understands
sion of the epistemological problems inherent in Freud's use of
this response to apply to both the Freudians I am concerned
clinical data to validate his theories. (For a much more extensive
with and the post-Freudians he discusses in Chapter 7.
review of Grunbaum's arguments, see Von Eckardt 1985.) By
Grunbaum further argues that "lacking a viable alternative to
emphasizing that there are four critical epistemic levels in the
the aborted Tally Argument with comparable scope and ambi-
evidence-hypothesis hierarchy rather than simply two (clinical
tion, the future validation of Freudian theory, if any, will have to
"data," on the one hand, and theories, on the other), the "map"
come very largely from extraclinical findings" (p. 129; ch. 8). For
allows us to see not only how thorough Grunbaum's treatment of
homosexuality such extraanalytic evidence has been over-
this problem is but also where there may be minor gaps or
whelmingly disconfirmatory of the orthodox "Freudian" psy-
omissions.
choanalytic position (which Freud did not share), and some of it
The four epistemic levels are the following: At the lowest
provided the very basis for removing homosexuality per se as a
level, we have what can be called the patient's productions.
disorder. Virtually all psychoanalysts regard such evidence as
These include his dream reports, slips of the tongue, memory
irrelevant. As leading spokesman Charles Socarides (1970) puts
reports, free associations, and assent or dissent to interpreta-
it:
tions made by the analyst. At the second level, we have the
Only in the consultation room does the homosexual reveal himself and
interpretations provided either by the analyst or by the patient
his world. No other data, statistics, or statements can be accepted as
himself of individual productions as expressions of unconscious
setting forth the true nature of homosexuality. All other sources may
wishes, resistance, and so on. Third, we have what Freud
be heavily weighted by face-saving devices or rationalizations or, if
(1937b) called a construction, a whole psychoanalytic story
they issue from lay [i.e. nonpsychoanalytic?] bodies, lack the scien-
about the patient's psyche from his early infantile history to his
tific and medical background to support their views. The best that can
present state, including, of course, an etiological account of the
be said for the well-intentioned but unqualified observer is that he is
patient's symptoms. Finally, there are the universal generaliza-
misguided because he does not have and cannot apply those tech-
tions of psychoanalytic theory, including, again, claims about
niques which would make it possible to discern the deep underlying
the etiology of the neuroses, dreams, slips, and so on. The
clinical disorder or to evaluate the emotional patterns and interper-
arrows on the map represent the relation "is considered evi-
sonal events in the life of a homosexual, (p. 1199)
dence for"; numbers next to an arrow stand for epistemological
These epistemic claims are not defended. Freud's tally argu-
liabilities pertaining to that step discussed in Grunbaum's text.
ment provides the needed justification; no alternative has been
advanced. Griinbaum's refutation of that argument undercuts Such a diagram is useful not only for elucidation but also as a
contemporary psychoanalytic grounds for resisting extraclinical tool for detecting points in Freud's logic of argumentation where
test. But his arguments against the tally argument invoke Grunbaum's discussion could be elaborated. I see two such
precisely the sorts of extraclinical evidence that Socarides re- points. The first is so obvious that there is perhaps nothing much
jects (pp. 162ff.). Does not reliance on Griinbaum's critique thus to be said; nevertheless, it pertains to a crucial link in Freud's
beg the question against Socarides? No. For Griinbaum's other inferential process. I have in mind the jump from individual
arguments succeed in refuting the tally argument without re- constructions to universal generalizations. Suppose that none of
course to such extraclinical evidence. Furthermore, ap- the epistemic difficulties pertaining to patient productions,
plicability of the tally argument depends essentially on docu- interpretations, or constructions existed. Suppose, in other
mented cures (p. 140; ch. 2 passim). Despite claims of such words, that we accepted Freud's individual constructions as
cures of homosexuality (e.g. Bieber, Dain, Dince, Drellich, true. There would still be a question concerning the truth of the
Grand, Grundlach, Kremer, Rifkin, Wilbur & Bieber 1962; universal generalizations of psychoanalytic theory, for we are

262 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Commentary/Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
becomes readily apparent that his theoretical commitments
universal generalizations strongly influence the kind of interpretations and constructions
he comes up with. In particular, in arriving at interpretations
construction that satisfy the gestalt constraints, the fundamental guiding
principle that Freud seems to use is "closeness of fit" with his
theory. That is, what makes the separate interpretative pieces fit
together is nothing other than that they all fit the theory. (See
Cioffi 1970, Timpanaro 1975, and Wolpe and Rachman 1963 for
examples.) Thus, Freud's method clearly seems theoretically
interpretations biased in a scientifically unacceptable way.
However, it is open to Freud at this point to argue that,
although his theory plays a significant role in the generation of
interpretative claims, this alone is not sufficient to undercut the
objectivity of his interpretations. For it is perfectly legitimate to
generate candidate interpretations in the light of one's favorite
slips of the tongue theory so long as they will be subject to procedures capable of
dream reports ruling out the incorrect interpretations on independent
symptoms grounds. Thus, insofar as Freud supplements his internal con-
associations straints with some theory-independent check, he can save
himselffromthe charge that the interpretative claims arrived at
reports of conscious by the method of interpretation fail the scientific requirement of
feelings toward objectivity. It is at this point that the tally argument could again
analyst 81 others be invoked; for it is precisely therapeutic success that is sup-
posed to function as the called-for theory-independent check.
But, of course, because (as Griinbaum has argued) the tally
introspection argument is unsound, it will be no more successful at undermin-
once analyzed ing the charge of theoretical bias than it is at eliminating concern
over nongenuine productions. Hence, the problem of the-
oretical bias at the second level of Freud's inferential hierarchy
Figure 1 (Von Eckardt). Epistemological problems in Freud's remains.
use of clinical data as discussed by Griinbaum. Problems: (1)
suggestibility (pp. 130-35); (2) failure of tally argument (pp.
135-72); (3) weakness of consilience argument (pp. 273-78); (4)
Nisbett & Wilson findings (pp. 147-48); (5) problems with
Breuer-Freud argument (pp. 177-89); (6) problems with ex- Early Freud, late Freud, conflict and
trapolation to slips and dreams (pp. 190-239); and (7) problems intentionality
with establishing causal claims by retrospective testing (pp.
177-89). Paul L. Wachtel
Department of Psychology, City College of the City University of New York,
New York, N.Y. 10031

dealing here with an inference from a relatively small sample to Griinbaum's book is an impressive, closely reasoned contribu-
the entire human population. And it is far from clear that the tion of lasting value. I will concentrate here, however, on some
sample has the appropriate properties to permit such a gener- points of demurral for him to respond to.
alization. Theorists who have argued that Freudian theory is Griinbaum devotes a large proportion of his argument to the
culturally biased have had precisely this sort of point in mind. logic of Freud's earliest formulations, in particular, those from
A second elaboration of Griinbaum's challenge concerns the the period when Freud believed that repressed traumatic
inferential step from patient productions to interpretations of events were the cause of neurosis. To be sure, the early theory
those productions. Because of his focus on Freudian exegesis, did have a fateful effect on the development of even those of
Griinbaum stresses the epistemological liability posed by the Freud's formulations that seem to contradict it (Wachtel 1977).
presence of suggestion. But there is another difficulty as well, a But there are also significant differences, which Griinbaum does
difficulty that would arise even if suggestion were not an ever- not always address. When he says, for example, that "even"
present threat. I have in mind the theoretical bias that Freud during its formative years psychoanalytic methodology defies
introduces in his "method of interpretation." Popper's criticisms (p. 124), this is misleading. It was especially
If we study what Freud had to say about his method of in the early years that Freud stuck close to empirical observa-
interpretation through the years, the picture that emerges in tions and framed his hypotheses in ways that were readily
Freud (1937b) is this: Individual interpretations are arrived at disconfirmable. Later his formulations became much more
by insight, usually on the part of the analyst. To be correct, complex and ambiguous. Griinbaum does address Popper's
however, such interpretations must satisfy two sets of con- criticisms in terms of some later Freudian formulations (e.g. the
straints, one internal and the other external. The internal relation between unacceptable homosexual impulses and para-
constraints are what we might call "gestalt constraints." Rough- noia), but greater attention to the differing epistemological
ly, individual interpretations are correct only if they fit together problems presented by the earlier (trauma) theory and the later
into a meaningful whole, that is, a construction, which makes (fantasy and conflict) theory would be useful.
sense of all the clinical material. But this is not sufficient, for Grunbaum tends to evaluate psychoanalytic conceptions in
Freud now admits that such an internally coherent construction terms of whether "etiology" and "pathogenicity" are demon-
might be false. Thus, as a further guarantee of its correctness, it strated. This again, in a different way with differing implica-
must satisfy an external constraint: It must be a construction tions, seems to reflect his blurring of the distinctions between
that, roughly speaking, plays a central role in a successful the early and later versions of psychoanalytic thought. Although
analysis. the later theory too builds upon conceptions of psycho-
The difficulty is this. If we look carefully at the interpretations pathology, it differs significantly from the earlier theory in that it
that Freud offers us in the course of his various case studies, it is no longer just a theory of neurosis but more generally a theory

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 263


Commentary/Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
of personality and character development. It is not clear if fact therapeutically superior to other modalities. But why Griin-
Griinbaum regards all causal propositions in psychology as baum couples this line of argument with a virtual ode to the tally
appropriately described as "etiological" or whether his use of argument (albeit one that includes a depiction of a tragicflaw)is
this term reflects something specific about Freud's theory and incomprehensible to this reviewer.
its origins in a theory of psychopathology. To be sure, there
were affinities between Freud's causal explanations of everyday
behavior and character on the one hand and of psychopathology
on the other, but it would be instructive for Griinbaum to Psychoanalysis: Conventional wisdom, self
describe the limits of the term "etiology" as he uses it. knowledge, or inexact science
At times Griinbaum pays insufficient attention to the cen-
trality of conflict in Freudian theory. Thus, in contesting the Murray L. Wax
view that maladaptive behavior fulfills unconscious intentions, Department of Sociology, Washington University, St. Louis, Mo. 63130
he argues that it implies that were the person to be made
conscious of his previously repressed wish he would have to see Counterpoint to Grunbaum's work is provided by such essays as
his maladaptive behavior as a means to its fulfillment and those of Bruno Bettelheim, published under the title Freud and
therefore to continue the behavior; the paranoid, if made aware Man's Soul (1982). Where the one evaluates the work of Freud
of his homosexual wishes, should continue his paranoia as a under the strict canons of a (positivistic) philosophy of science,
perceived way of gratifying them. That this is not the psycho- the other attacks those responsible for the English language
analytic expectation seems to Griinbaum to gainsay the notion translations on the ground that they violate the humanism of
that the symptom has a wish-fulfilling function. But Griinbaum these writings. Such are the riches of the Freudian legacy that
overlooks the psychoanalytic position that the repressed wish is the most knowledgeable and competent scholars give plausibly
but one of the wishes that are (partially) gratified by the symp- different interpretations: With scrupulous objectivity, Griin-
tom, which is a compromise gratification of several wishes. The baum judges it according to the norms of clinical and biomedical
paranoia, according to Freud, is a way of partially gratifying both research; with abundant clinical experience initiated in the
the homosexual wish and the wish not to know about it. As a Vienna where Freud practiced and taught, Bettelheim reminds
means of gratifying the homosexual wish alone it would be an us that this stylist of German prose wrote oiSeele (soul), rather
unlikely choice. But it can be seen as a plausible means of than of "mind " or other behavioristic euphemisms.
achieving partial gratification of the homosexual wish - looking Grunbaum, Bettelheim, and other critics and interpreters
at and thinking about the other a great deal is, after all, one of the (Habermas, Ricoeur, Sulloway, Popper) focus our attention on
things that one likes to do when one is in love - while at the same Freud rather than on how psychoanalysis has evolved and how it
time providing oneself with "proof that one does not like the has been influencing psychiatry, psychology, and kindred disci-
other (indeed that one hates him). Of course the paranoid plines. Theirs is a valuable endeavor, but the punctilious analy-
solution would not be chosen if the repressed wish were con- sis by Grunbaum is so overdue that we may forget the context.
scious, because it would no longer have the possibility of Sociologically viewed, science is not the set of definitive state-
simultaneously fulfilling the wish for the homosexual wish not to ments of the immutable truths of nature discovered by an
be conscious; a more direct and complete gratification of the aggregate of isolated and intrepid investigators; it is instead a
remaining fulfillable wish (the homosexual wish) would be special kind of interplay and conversation: intrinsically social
chosen instead. I concur with most of Grunbaum's arguments and critical, yet ultimately progressive; spiritually cooperative,
for the necessity of causal propositions in psychoanalysis yet marked by the harshest of mutual criticism and rivalry.
(Wachtel 1969), but I believe this particular one is flawed. Thus, to evaluate any particular body of work, we must view it in
Grunbaum's respectful treatment of the logic of what he calls its context. We cannot fairly judge the achievement of Newton
Freud's "tally argument" and his disagreement with Suther- by regarding his work - including his errors and his (religious)
land's claim that it begs the question is puzzling. Freud had fantasies - against modern criteria, even though this might be
argued, disputing claims of suggestive compliance by patients, an interesting exercise for a historian of science. Likewise, it
that "[the patient's] conflicts will only be successfully solved and becomes difficult for us today to evaluate fairly the work of
his resistances be overcome if the anticipatory ideas he is given Freud, because so many of the ideas which then were consid-
tally with what is real in him" (Freud 1917). But here Freud ered revolutionary have today become conventional wisdom for
counters the critics of his theory by assuming the theory to begin both scholars and the educated public. With these caveats, I
with. On what grounds are we to assume that cure will come salute this wonderfully rich critique of Freud's lifetime work;
only if what the analyst suggests "tallies with what is real?" If one Grunbaum exhibits a magisterial combination of sympathetic
does not begin from psychoanalytic premises, there is no reason exposition and impartially severe critique.
to give this assertion credence. Grunbaum argues that "if A generation ago, and in accord with the Popperian principle
psychoanalytic treatment does have the therapeutic monopoly of falsification, philosophers challenged analysts to describe the
entailed by the Tally Argument, then it can warrantedly take (male human) child who had not experienced the Oedipus
credit for the recoveries of its patient without statistical com- complex. At the turn of the century that challenge would have
parisons with the results from untreated control groups, or from had a different significance than it does today. At that time, the
controls treated by rival modalities" (p. 142, italics in Griin- basic notions of the complex - infantile sexuality, castration
baum). But how can one know if it has such a monopoly unless anxiety, love for the mother, hostility toward the father; that
one does the comparisons? Elsewhere Grunbaum himself crit- whole set of phenomena encompassed by the notion of "the
icizes a similar "viciously circular bootstrap operation" by Freud family romance" - were novel. Today, many of those who think
(p. 144). of themselves as opponents of psychoanalysis nevertheless ac-
To be sure, as Grunbaum demonstrates, Freud often showed cept the significant elements of the romance; it has become
keen methodological sophistication. Nonetheless, the tally ar- conventional wisdom. I do not mean that all students of child
gument appears to be an instance, not uncommon in Freud's development would reach a consensus on the Oedipus complex,
writings, in which overreaching assertion gets the best of but rather that they and we have been highly sensitized to the
Freud's methodological superego. emotional drama of infancy and early childhood and accepting of
Grunbaum's discussions of how much Freud did implicitly its psychosexual dimensions: A boy who had not experienced
rely on the tally argument are provocative and illuminating; that drama could only be autistic or fatally handicapped or the
they cast an interesting light on the problems posed for psycho- victim of gross neglect.
analytic theory by the failure to show that psychoanalysis is in In his evaluation of Freud's theories, Grunbaum asks repeat-

264 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


CommentarylGriinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis

edly and severely, what kind of confirmation is provided "from analytic theory, although they are less than clear about how the
the couch"? How subject to the influences of the analyst are the validity of the theory is determined. Habermas and Ricoeur
"free associations" of the analysand? The question and its chal- assume that psychoanalysis presents an accurate account (in the
lenge seem so reasonable that we overlook their limitations. scientific sense) of the workings of the mind; they explicitly
When the world's only analyst was Sigmund Freud, that chal- acknowledge that it contains causal, explanatory elements.
lenge differed from the one today, when we may instead be These philosophers assume that much of psychoanalysis (e.g.
asking questions such as what is the nature of debate among repression theory) has already passed the scientific test and
psychoanalysts concerning differences in the validity of clinical many of their formulations are predicated on this assumption.
interpretations? Does such debate lead to consensus of the Appropriation of their positions to argue against the need for
informed? Does it at least lead toward clarification of issues? psychoanalysis to pass such tests is thus a self-defeating logical
Alternatively, we might ask whether in the decades since the move. For Ricoeur and Habermas, psychoanalysis is a viable
original formulation of Freud's theories there has been change, interpretive framework partly because it possesses independent
progress, evolution, of the sort that is distinctive to a scientific epistemic authority, and not solely because its self-described
enterprise? And also, we might ask about the auxiliary types of aim is to make manifest through interpretation what is hidden or
evidence that have been generated by psychoanalysis, e.g. distorted.
those from anthropology, child development, folklore, and 2. Even if one is prepared to grant that psychoanalysis is a
literary studies. retrospective, historical science, it is also a set of social prac-
An alternate mode of responding to Griinbaum's critique is to tices, a technology of healing, and, as such, must be held
take the humanist position to its logical and spiritual extreme. accountable to some pragmatic predictive criteria. At the very
When (and to the extent that) analyst and analysand labor least, its efficacy can and should be evaluated. Such evaluations
together, the latter can achieve a radical self-knowledge that would generate actuarial predictions concerning the likelihood
conduces toward a more integrated, harmonious, and produc- of benefit or harm for someone entering treatment. [See Pri-
tive psyche (Seek). Being the fallible, limited and diverse oleau et al.: "An Analysis of Psychotherapy Versus Placebo
creatures that human beings are, not every analytic dyad will Studies" BBS 6(2) 1983.]
achieve its goal, but, to the extent that it does, the analysand will 3. The hermeneutic turn of psychoanalysis is a move toward a
gain increased control over the self and thus be better able to kind of relativism. If the historical truth of interpretations can be
deal with what are termed "symptoms." This mode of present- ignored, yet interpretations are still of the form of propositions
ing psychoanalysis is not clinically tidy, and not faithful to Freud that have truth value, what kind of odd cynicism is required of
in his persona as scientist. Yet it is faithful to the more pessi- the analyst? (Presumably shamans perform their curative rituals
mistic and limited vision of his later writings. Because so much with more conviction in the particulars of their crafts, if not with
of Freud's work has been accepted by scholars, an implicit but greater scientific support for their theories.) What if the patients
major issue is occupational. Clinical and scientific orientations get wind of all this? How efficacious will an interpretation be if it
do not easily meld, and the psychoanalytic movement has found is regarded as a somewhat arbitrary personal myth rather than
it difficult to deal with the kinds of innovation customary in a something true? Will distressed individuals still come to ana-
purely scientific discipline. The requirements of clinical probity lysts for treatment given that psychoanalysis may declare itself
and competence lead to a form of training and a mode of qualitatively different from surgery for appendicitis or behavior
professional organization (especially in the United States) that
are not hospitable to the challenge of radical paradigm shift that therapy for phobias? Will insurance companies still pay? What
has become normal to the pure sciences. This is not the kind of about the quasimedical pretentions of the analytic community?
issue faced by Griinbaum, but the skill and knowledge of his Why then do we need psychoanalytic theory anyway? Psycho-
critique force those sympathetic to psychoanalysis to reexamine analysis has never demonstrated superiority over other forms of
its status as science. therapy in empirical studies, far from it. Why use the analytic
system to generate our stories? If a good narrative is all it takes,
why not turn to other departments of Western culture or turn
the job of constructing such narratives over to the many dis-
placed holders of doctorates in the humanities who desire work
within their fields?
One might have wished for greater comprehensiveness in
Hermeneutics and psychoanalysis Grunbaum's discussion of whether one should apply to psycho-
analysis standards by which the natural sciences are evaluated.
Robert L. Woolfolk
Addressing one aspect of this question, in his discussion of the
Department of Psychology, Rutgers University, New Brunswick, N.J. 08903
reason-versus-cause debate, Grunbaum effectively exposes the
Adolf Grunbaum has proved himself an inspired and meticulous misconceptions and spurious logic of various opponents of causal
critic of the recent trend in psychoanalysis to abandon preten- formulations in psychoanalysis. He could have called upon the
sions to scientific testability and effect reconstitution as a hu- further support offered in the works of Davidson (1980) and
manistic discipline analogous to literary criticism. According to Searle (1983), who suggest that intentional phenomena can
this "psychoanalytic hermeneutics" position, the objective ac- function as a species of cause. Grunbaum is not concerned here
curacy of the psychoanalytic reconstruction of the past and the with cultural analysis, the sociology of knowledge, or with the
interpretations thereof cannot be supported. Nor is their corre- critique of the ideological foundations of psychoanalysis. Yet
spondence with past occurrences deemed necessary to produce some elucidation of the moral dimensions of psychoanalysis
therapeutic impact. The task of the analyst is simply to decipher seems pertinent to a determination of the extent to which a
the realm of subjectivity by fashioning meaningful and coherent natural science framework fits it.
narratives that are consistent with psychoanalytic theory. Psychoanalysis is clearly a form of mixed discourse, both
Armed with precise arguments and a Freudian scholarship describing the workings of the psyche and adumbrating a moral
superior to that of most analysts, Grunbaum uncovers a number vision. Theories of personality and psychopathology are inevita-
of problems with this position. He fails to develop some other bly prescriptive and normative. Such theories not only reflect
criticisms, however: and influence standards of conduct but seem to provide the
1. The hermeneutic model derives, in large part, from contemporary cultural equivalent of descriptions of virtue and
Ricoeur (1981), who views action as a text analogue, and Haber- peccability. Viewed through this lens, psychoanalysis has much
mas (1971), who sees psychoanalysis as a model for critical social in common with Marxism, in that each not only provides an
science. These philosophers assume the validity of psycho- ambitious philosophical anthropology but also a theory of libera-

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 265


Response/Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
tion. It is perhaps this aspect of psychoanalysis that makes it one to (1) had been positive, my unfavorable overall conclu-
of our most intriguing and influential cultural products. sion would be adequately supported by my treatment of
(2). Some of the commentators, however, seem to have
mistaken my critical account of the tally argument in Part
I to be the gist of the book (Erdelyi; Farrell; Savodnik;
Editorial commentary and Eysenck - although elsewhere Eysenck [1985b, p.
90] does recognize the autonomy of my arguments in Part
There is still a point of inductive strategy in the face of Grun- II).
baum's critique that no commentator appears to have raised.
Even if one grants that, in principle, some of Freud's claims can The falsifiability of psychoanalytic theory. Freud's hy-
be reformulated in such a way as to be testable ("extraclinically," pothesis that strongly repressed homosexuality is a neces-
let us say), is there not still a question as to whether or not it sary causal condition for the occurrence of paranoid
would be worthwhile to do so? As a scientific and therapeutic delusions (S.E. 1915, 14:265) has figured prominently in
project, psychoanalysis has had enormous attention and influ- the literature on the testability and falsifiability of psycho-
ence for well over a century now, despite the fact that its analysis. The causal factor is supposed to be a conflict
scientific and therapeutic validity remain, if not entirely un- between homosexual desires and the need to banish them
testable, then largely untested. By way of analogy, one might from consciousness to avoid anxiety. According to Freud,
ask whether we ought to assign a high priority to testing for paranoia can be present in one or more delusional forms:
possible "serendipitous" truths in some still more venerable
theories, such as astrology or creationism, even if they can be delusions of persecution, of jealousy, of grandeur, and of
tortured into testability, rather than allowing our research to heterosexual erotomania. Holt wants to make the connec-
continue to be guided by their more plausible rivals. Finally, tion between the cause and the syndrome probabilistic in
there is the question of prima facie plausibility itself. It is not just both directions. But even according to the received
that psychoanalytic ideas have always seemed farfetched. psychoanalytic view, it is only probable, rather than
(There are many scientific precedents for not underestimating certain, that latent homosexuality will produce paranoia,
farfetched ideas.) It has more to do with the relation between although every paranoiac is assumed to be a latent homo-
the nature of the ideas and the means of testing them; with the sexual. (Kline's account of Zamansky's 1958 experimental
fact that they remain today as farfetched as they ever were. All
scientific theories can resort to ad hoc strategies to protect them test of Freud's etiologic hypothesis will be discussed in
from negative evidence, but few of them can claim such "immu- the next section of this Response).
nizing" strategies as took of their trade. Symbolization, in- At a 1980 conference in honor of Popper (and in
terpretation, and reinterpretation in terms of (rather than in test Foundations, pp. 38-39, 110-11), I pointed out that
of) a given symbolic system is a psychodynamic process: The Freud's paranoia hypothesis yields a quasi-statistical epi-
"unconscious" does it, the patient does it, the analyst does it. In demiologic prediction, one that qualifies as "risky" in
the end, the problem seems to be not so much the suggestibility Popper's sense (with respect to any rival "background"
of the patient as that of the theorist. (Is this Grunbaum's theory denying a causal connection between latent homo-
"thematic affinity fallacy"?) Whether or not the hermeneuticists
are right in their explicit appropriation of the project, does a
sexuality and paranoia). Hence, by Popper's standards, I
theory that has such an essential hermeneutic dimension built in claimed, failure of the prediction would tell against
still deserve the benefit of the inductive doubt so late in the day? Freud's hypothesis, and success would corroborate it.
Is that sound inductive strategy? What was my psychoanalytic rationale for the relevant
prediction? A significant decline in the social taboo on
homosexuality (as in San Francisco) should reduce the
anxiety generated by homosexual desires as well as the
need to repress them, which should result in a decrease in
the incidence of paranoia.
Author's Response As I have noted, "the first impetus for my inquiry into
the intellectual merits of the psychoanalytic enterprise
came from my doubts concerning Karl Popper's philoso-
phy of science" (p. xii). Asked by Daniel Goleman of the
Is Freud's theory well-founded? New York Times for a brief statement of my disagreement
with Popper on psychoanalysis, I claimed that the Breuer
Adolf Griinbaum - Freud hypothesis (that hysteria is caused by a specific
Departments of Philosophy, Psychiatry, and History and Philosophy of kind of repression) was indeed testable. (In Foundations
Science, University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh, Pa. 15260 [pp. 179-84]) I recount how Freud abandoned this hy-
Logically and historically, clinical1 evidence from the pothesis because its therapeutic prediction had failed.)
couch has been considered the principal foundation of the This prediction is quoted from the interview with me in
psychoanalytic enterprise, serving both as its heuristic Goleman's article (1985, p. 15). For journalistic sim-
guide and its empirical support (Jones 1959, p. 3). The plicity, however, I also agreed to let him quote, as an
order of inquiry in Foundations was accordingly dictated example of a testable Freudian statement, the briefer
by two questions: (1) Are the analyst's observations in the general claim: "Repression of traumatic experiences is
treatment setting reliable as "data" and (2) if so, do they essential for neurosis to develop." This vaguer version
actually support the theory of repression, "the cor- took the place of Freud's so-called specific etiologic hy-
nerstone on which the whole structure of psychoanalysis potheses (S.E. 1895, 3:135-38) - such as the paranoia
rests" (S.E. 1914, 14:16)? hypothesis - for which I had actually claimed falsifiability
In Foundations I gave negative answers to both ques- (Foundations, pp. 109-10).
tions, stressing, however (p. 172), that even if the answer Each of these specific hypotheses concerns the particu-

266 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Response! Qrunhaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
lar sort of repression - e.g. of a thematically connected fies the "if"part ("antecedent") of (A), and delusions of
trauma, experienced just before the onset of a particular (say) persecution contradict the "then"part ("conse-
hysterical symptom (S.E. 1896, 3:193-96) - that is quent") of (A). Popper, however, claims that it is "hardly
needed to cause a particular syndrome. Thus, in the possible" to establish the truth of the antecedent, because
example of the paranoia hypothesis, latent homosexual "Freud could say of any apparently paranoid active homo-
desires would take the place of the "repressed traumatic sexual" that he is harboring some repressed homosexual
experiences" in the vaguer formulation transmitted to impulses after all (Popper 1983, p. 169). Notturno &
Popper by the New York Times, and the "neurosis" would McHugh even speculate, in support of Popper, that
be paranoia. Freud would "insist upon using free association to seek
Fisher and Greenberg (1977) have pointed out that the hypothesized homosexual repressions."
"the appearance of overt homosexual . . . acting out in I suggest that Freud's theory precludes the use of
the paranoid would represent a contradiction . . . of Popper's strategy. As Freud tells us explicitly (S.E. 1922,
Freud's theory of paranoia" (p. 259). Popper (1983), who 18:228), in paranoia (as well as in hysteria, the example I
reports that W. W. Bartley made him aware of this used for the New York Times), quantitatively intense
consequence in 1980, tells us, "But this [paranoia hypoth- ("hypercathected") repressions, rather than just repres-
esis] is not part of the basic theory I was criticizing. sions per se, are the necessary conditions for developing
Besides, Freud could say of any apparently paranoid the syndrome. Thus, statement A must be understood as
active homosexual that he is not really paranoid, or not applying to a person who does not strongly repress
fully active" (p. 169). The latter of these two sentences is homosexual impulses, a quantitative refinement I had
the one to which Popper now refers in his commentary, explicitly built into my statement (pp. 38, 40). Even an
when he writes that even in a "greatly improved" version, ordinarily active (paranoid) homosexual would satisfy this
the predictions (A) and (B) discussed in his commentary condition, not to mention a highly active, flamboyant
do not become testable. Before 1983, however, Popper one.
had always claimed, without any qualification, that Popper's claim that nobody could satisfy the anteced-
Freud's theory was simply nontestable, irrefutable (e.g. ent is hence incorrect, and his rhetorical questions "Who
1962, p. 37; 1974, p. 1004). In dealing with the example has never . . . suffered a trauma? And who has not tried
given by Bartley, Popper (1983, p. 169) oddly says noth- to get over it by forgetting about it - which means 'trying
ing about just what is part of the "basic" theory of to repress' it?" are wide of the mark. As I said relatedly
psychoanalysis. Nor does he provide grounds for exclud- (Grunbaum 1983): "Surely the mere traumaticity of an
ing the paranoia hypothesis from it. event does not itself attest to its etiologic relevance. The
In defense of such an exclusion, Notturno & McHugh human condition would be much worse than it already is,
misleadingly cite Freud's assertion that "cases of paranoia if every psychic blow became the specific pathogen of a
are for well-known reasons not usually amenable to ana- neurosis" (p. 20).
lytic investigation" (S.E. 1922, 18:225). But, as I noted in As to Notturno & McHugh's conjecture that in order to
Foundations (p. 141), the "well-known reasons" which dodge refutation by the existence of homosexually active
Freud had given elsewhere (S.E. 1917, 16:438-39, 445- paranoiacs Freud would "insist" on finding homosexual
47; also 16:255) make this disavowal by Freud unhelpful repressions in such persons' free associations: Surely
to Popper. Freud had said that paranoia was refractory to Freud would not resort to this, because everybody's free
analytic therapy, but he insisted that this in no way associations could be interpreted as indicating some la-
invalidated his inferences about its causes. The un- tent homosexual feeling or other; hence such feelings
treatability of paranoia was attributed to the inability of would not affect the probability of becoming paranoid.
paranoiacs (among others) to develop a libidinal attach- Could Freud still say, as Popper (1983, p. 169) sug-
ment to the analyst, a positive "transference" that Freud gests, that the active homosexual is "not really paranoid,"
considered essential for resolving the patient's conflicts no matter how delusional his behavior? True, even patent
(S.E. 1914, 12:154). Moreover, the paranoia hypothesis is delusions and intense feelings of persecution are only
part of Freud's theory of psychopathology, which is the probabilistic evidence of paranoia. But Popper's appeal to
most "basic" part of his theory of repression. Popper's the fallibility of differential diagnosis, and to the pos-
elusive 1983 use of the notion of "basic theory" is not sibility of rediagnosis is misleading: As he well knows, in
clarified by his contrast elsewhere (1962, p. 38, n. 3) physics no less than in somatic medicine or psychology,
between "psychoanalysis itself" and "a particular analytic empirical data are not deductively sufficient conditions
diagnosis." for the presence of hypothesized states, though they are
Notturno & McHugh are quibbling when they point taken as indicators of such states. Even in physics, em-
out that in Freud's initial 1911 paper on the Schreber case pirical evidence underdetermines theoretical states, in-
he had spoken of repressed homosexuality as "perhaps" a dicating their presence only more or less proba-
universal cause of paranoia. As noted in Foundations (p. bilistically. Thus, as Hempel has remarked, even a
Ill), Freud subsequently made it clear that he was circular array of iron filings does not deductively guaran-
committed to universality (S.E. 1915, 14:265). tee the presence of a magnet. And as Popper (1974, p.
1004) has acknowledged, immunizing maneuvers are
In its universal form, Freud's hypothesis predicts, as in
always possible in physics as well. Besides, as I have
Popper's conditional statement (A): If a person does not
illustrated (pp. 121-23), when Freud did retract a differ-
repress homosexual impulses, then he will not be para-
ential diagnosis to preserve a specific causal hypothesis,
noid. I have maintained (pp. 40; 109-10) that the behav-
he was sensitive to the need for independent evidence in
ior of an avowed, active homosexual paranoiac refutes (A)
favor of the alternative diagnosis.
because the behaviorally overt homosexual activity satis-

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 267


Response/Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
Popper considers it to be very likely that a practicing ment of a falsification, though it did not go nearly far
analyst, faced with an obviously frustrated person, would enough. Earlier (p. 220) I had called his revision "rather
beg the causal question by inferring from having judged minor" when I meant to convey that the modification
the patient "neurotic" that there had to have been a prior pertained to the dreams of only a small subclass of people
trauma. The falsifiability of Freud's theory, however, is - the war neurotics - whereas Freud's hypothesis of
logically independent of such practices on the part of wish-fulfillment had referred to the whole human race.
clinical or even research analysts. Moreover, as shown by Notturno & McHugh mention only my phrase "rather
the case of paranoia, it is a straw man argument against minor." Oddly, they see as somehow unfair to Popper the
the falsifiability of the prediction stated in Popper's (A) to purely expository deferral of my appraisal of Freud's
cite the difficulty of ruling out the presence of any and revision to the end of the pertinent chapter.
every sort of neurosis, rather than confirm just paranoia. Finally, Notturno & McHugh equivocate on the term
Thus, Popper was quite mistaken to claim that "Only if he "science," when they object that I criticize Popper's
[the patient] is [altogether] not neurotic is the prediction account of psychoanalysis as nonscience, only to censure
testable." Finally, Popper asks rhetorically: "But who has it myself as "bad science." When Popper declared it to be
ever met a prospective patient who was told by his nonscience, he meant that it was empirically unfalsifiable
prospective psychoanalyst that he was not neurotic?" Yet by any conceivable behavioral evidence. When I argued
people who actually expect to incur the pain, expense, that, at least with respect to the available clinical evi-
and duration of an analysis are presumably troubled, are dence, psychoanalytic theory is bad science, I explicitly
they not? So on what evidence would a scientifically said that it is empirically ill-supported by that evidence.
sensitive analyst make an initial judgment of good mental Given that his claim is quite distinct from mine, there is
health? nothing odd in my contention that, in Popper's falsi-
Far from supporting his nonfalsifiability thesis, Pop- fiability sense of "science," psychoanalysis does qualify as
per's (1983) account of the case of the homosexual para- science, whereas in my sense of the term it does not.
noiac unfortunately relies on just the kinds of immunizing Wax contrasts my empirical assessment of psychoanal-
maneuvers he is quick to reject when others engage in ysis with Bettelheim's complaint that Strachey's English
them. In any case, his account seems incoherent: Only a translation of Freud's writings from German had scien-
few pages after discussing the paranoia example, he deals tistically obscured the "humanism" they contain. One
with Freud's dream theory and declares it to be a "simple need only read Freud's thirty-fifth 1933 Lecture "Uber
fact . . . that anxiety dreams constitute a refutation of the eine Weltanschauung" in the German original to appreci-
general formula of wish-fulfillment" (Popper 1983, p. ate that Bettelheim's case is a hermeneutic red herring.
173; italics in original). Thus, by Popper's own appraisal, For example, whether one refers to Freudian slips in
the dream theory is not only falsifiable but had already German familiarly as "Fehlleistungen," as Freud himself
been falsified by anxiety dreams, when Freud first pro- did, or as "parapraxes," using Strachey's English neolo-
posed it! This apparent inconsistency is not remedied by gism, the fact remains that Freud claimed scientific status
the fact that Popper offers this falsification as evidence of for his theory of slips. Ditto for "Seele" and "psyche."
Freud's improper methodological conduct. Edelson, who comments on my proposed epi-
After all, throughout his career, Popper has repeatedly demiologic test of the paranoia hypothesis, is under the
published two relevant claims: (1) Logically, psycho- impression that I regard it as prototypic for the extra-
analytic theory is irrefutable by any human behavior, and clinical testing I advocate. I did not claim that this test
(2) in the face of seemingly adverse evidence, Freud and could be readily generalized; but surely my empirical
his followers always dodged refutation by resorting to critique of purely clinical testing does not place the
immunizing maneuvers. Clearly, (1) is logically indepen- burden of coming up with additional extraclinical tests on
dent of (2). My principal objection to Popper pertains to me. That responsibility, I should think, belongs to psy-
his thesis (1), although I argue in Foundations that he also choanalysts, unless they can show that Edelson's hopes
used gross oversimplification to make the case for (2). for the testing potential of the treatment setting can be
Notturno & McHugh insist on conflating Popper's (1) realized.
with (2), incorrectly believing that they have upheld (1) in It is likewise not my problem that the epidemiologic
the face of my critique, if they succeed in showing that I design I proposed would lose its relevance, if - as
somehow mishandled (2). Foundations actually includes Edelson suggests - psychoanalytic theory were to claim
many detailed objections to Freud's methodological con- that the repression of homosexual desires was caused by
duct, although I defend him against some of the crude, internal developmental factors independent of social ta-
simplistic strictures in the literature. boos. As is, however, Freud's account of ego-function in
As evidence of my mishandling of Popper's (2), Nottur- repression does not seem to rest on such internal pro-
no & McHugh point to my use of Freud's 1933 "Revision cesses (S.E. 1911, 12:65-68). Thus, Freud speaks of a
of the Theory of Dreams," which I offered as an example "multiplicity of mechanisms of repression proper." The
of Freud's acknowledging an actual falsification (pp. 112, ego is presumably also responsive to the demands of
220, 238). The revision was prompted by the dreams of external reality, such as strong social prohibitions, rather
war neurotics, who regularly relive their traumas in their than merely to internal developmental influences.
dreams. Referring to these dreams, Freud issued a re- Wachtel sees my discussion of the paranoia hypothesis
traction: "According to our hypotheses about the function as an indication of my "insufficient attention to the cen-
of dreams this should not occur" (S.E. 1933, 22:28). trality of conflict in Freudian theory." He refers to how I
After quoting this concession of Freud's at the end of used this hypothesis when I tried to show that the
Chapter 5,1 wrote: "This important, if limited, modifica- "practical syllogism" (see Precis) cannot be applied to
tion is only to be welcomed' (p. 238) as an acknowledg- psychoanalytic explanations. Also, he thinks that this

268 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Response!Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
contention on pp. 78-79 "seems to Griinbaum to gainsay 196). But this definitional inclusion of an etiologic role in
the notion that the [delusional] symptom has a wish- Kline's definition begs the causal question as to whether
fulfilling function." Wachtel claims that I draw this im- mental acts of repression are, in fact, neurosogenic"
plication. Furthermore, he suggests, I overlook the fact (Foundations, p. 188) because his experimental evidence
that, according to psychoanalytic doctrine, the delusional (Kline 1981, pp. 226, 436) "relates to the existence of the
symptoms represent compromise gratifications of two mechanism of repression, but does not bespeak any
conflicting wishes: the wish for homosexual fulfillment etiologic role at all" (Foundations, p. 188). Kline now
and the desire to banish this wish from conscious indicates that, on his p. 226, he was claiming only experi-
awareness. mental support for the mechanism of repression. Yet it is
Yet I neither drew the implication that prompted perhaps understandable that I read his definition of
Wachtel's correction, nor is it a logical consequence of "repression proper" as implying that if there is "irrefuta-
what I did say. As for recognizing that Freud took the ble [experimental] evidence for the Freudian concept of
delusional symptoms to result from two conflicting wish- repression" - as he told us there was (1981, p. 208) - then
es, my account of the causal role of anxiety (p. 76) does there is support for its causal role as well. In any case, I
just that: The anxiety aroused by the homosexual feelings stand corrected by Kline's current disclaimer concerning
generates the desire to banish the thought of them. My what he actually meant by "the Freudian concept of
point in the passage disputed by Wachtel was rather the repression."
following: Though each of the conflicting wishes may be I cannot agree with Kline's suggestion that because
said to be an unconscious "intention," the ensuing para- prior authors, including himself, have criticized Freud's
noid symptoms do not qualify as "intentional actions" in theory as clinically ill-supported, my "conclusions are not
the sense of the "practical syllogism," because the syllo- new." If police were to indict a defendant and then a
gism calls further for a belief in a means-ends connection. district attorney strengthened the case enough to secure a
No such belief is assumed by the paranoia hypothesis. conviction, Kline would evidently pooh-pooh the at-
torney's contribution on the grounds that the charge had
Experimental and "quantitative" studies of psycho- already been made by others! Marmor knows better.
analysis. Freud wrote: "In analysis, however, we have to I will now provide some further reasons why the
do without the assistance afforded to [other] research by extraclinical evidence for psychoanalytic theory reported
experiment" (S.E. 1933, 22:174). Kline, Masling, and by Kline (1981), Fisher and Greenberg (1977), and Mas-
Greenberg, however, point to a wealth of what they ling (1983) fails to uphold Freud's major hypotheses. Note
regard as important experimental, "objective" or "quan- first that Kline (1981, p. vii) himself downgrades the
titative" studies. Why, then, though I did cite Kline's valuable and exhaustive labors of Fisher and Greenberg:
(1981), Eysenck and Wilson's (1973), Fisher and Green- "In our view, Fisher and Greenberg are quite uncritical:
berg's (1977), Marmor's (1970), and Masling's (1983) they accept results at their face value with almost no
work, did I not include any systematic discussion of this consideration of methodological adequacy. Their book
material in Foundations? And why did I claim that the reads like a bibliographic listing of results." However,
extraclinical appraisal of Freud's "cardinal hypoth- both Kline (1981, pp. 334-35) and Fisher and Greenberg
eses . . . is largely a task for the future" (p. 278)? (1977, pp. 260-61) think that Zamansky's (1958) experi-
An evaluation on the basis of available studies would mental test of the paranoia hypothesis yielded favorable
not have altered my conclusion about the empirical sup- results, whereas Eysenck and Wilson (1973, p. 314) deny
port for psychoanalysis, because the extraclinical data this on the ground that Zamansky's experiment lacked a
gathered so far, even when favorable, fail to support any "vital control" to rule out a plausible rival explanation.
of the major Freudian hypotheses whose clinical evi- Just what were Zamansky's findings, and how should we
dence I criticized as inadequate. Kline offers stereotypes interpret them?
about academic disciplines by way of explanation for my Freud's hypothesis that latent homosexuality is
omission of nonclinical studies, but he inadvertently causally necessary for paranoia entails the much weaker
acknowledges that I cited his (1981) work - as well as the generalization: All paranoiacs are latent homosexuals.
writings of others - to justify my selectivity when I spoke Zamansky states what he takes to be the upshot of his test
of "alleged experimental support for 'the theory of re- of Freud's hypothesis as follows: "Though the present
pression' " (pp. 188-89). experiment has demonstrated a greater degree of homo-
Freud characterized "the theory of repression" as "the sexuality in men with paranoid delusions than in non-
cornerstone on which the whole structure of psycho- paranoid individuals, those results tell us nothing about
analysis rests" (S.E. 1917, 14:16). He did so immediately the role which homosexuality plays in the development of
after having made it clear (p. 15), by reference to these delusions" (quoted from Zamansky's study, as re-
Schopenhauer's "explanation of insanity," that this cor- printed in Eysenck and Wilson, 1973, p. 308). In Fisher
nerstone comprises at least the hypothesis that repres- and Greenberg's account of the experiment (1977, pp.
sions cause psychopathology, rather than just the far 261, 269), they endorse Zamansky's causal disclaimer,
weaker claim that there exists a mechanism of repression. along with his view of what he did demonstrate. Here are
Hence in Foundations I was concerned with evidence for the main details of Zamansky's investigation:
the causal role of repression in the formation of neuroses, With a tachistoscope-like viewing apparatus,
dreams, and Freudian slips (p. 277). Zamansky presented his paranoid male subjects with
Thus, speaking critically of Kline's (1981) book, I wrote: pairs of pictures (e.g. of males, females, inanimate ob-
"When giving the definition of'repression proper,' Kline jects, or male-male homosexual encounters, such as men
includes in it the claim that 'repression [is] a pathogenic kissing). He asked subjects to rank each pair of pictures
or unsuccessful mechanism of defense' (Kline 1981, p. according to size. This task was just for distraction,

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 269


Response/Grunhaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
however, since his actual objective was to determine tasies (a criticism offered by Eagle as well; private
whether the experimental group (male paranoiacs) gazed communication).
relatively longer than control groups (nonparanoid males) In light of Greenberg's commentary, note Fisher and
at pictures of males compared to females. Finding that Greenberg's (1977) conclusions about the evidence for
the paranoiacs did look at males longer, he interpreted one version of Freud's dream theory. On the construal
this time difference as evidence of stronger latent homo- they consider most reasonable, its central thesis is that
sexuality. Eysenck and Wilson (1973, p. 314), however, dreams express (vent) not only wishes, but various drives
point out the need to test the rival hypothesis that or impulses that originate in the unconscious (pp. 46-47).
paranoiacs gazed longer at males because it is part of their However, besides opting for some revisions, Fisher and
syndrome to be generally suspicious and to feel more Greenberg make two sobering points: (1) Even if one can
threatened by males than by females. Hence Eysenck & show that a dream does express a certain impulse, there is
Wilson predict that if such people were presented with still no scientifically reliable way to confirm that the
"other forms of threat not involving homosexuality, impulse originated in the unconscious part of the psyche
e.g., . . . flying saucers carrying sexless space mon- (p. 47), and (2) the available "findings are congruent with
sters," the subjects would take more time looking at such Freud's venting model. But . . . they do not specifically
nonhuman pictures as well. document the model" (p. 63; italics in original). More-
Kline (1985, p. 231) makes no mention of this proposed over, "the data . . . are encouraging but not definitively
further test, dismissing the rival hypothesis as "arbi- validating with respect to Freud's venting model" (p. 63).
trary . . . idle speculation." He asks rhetorically: "Why Yet, despite issuing these important qualifications,
the connection between suspicion and length of looking, Fisher and Greenberg permitted themselves to begin
between men and threat?" Erwin (1985, p. 198) and I their summary by declaring that Freud's model "seems to
both reply, in effect: It is not obvious to us that Eysenck be supported by the scientific evidence that can be
and Wilson's rival hypothesis is less justified on the mustered" (p. 63). By thus sliding from compatibility
evidence than Zamansky's view that repressed homosex- ("congruence") with the theory into "support" for it,
uality accounts for the longer duration of looking. I do not these friends of psychoanalysis have lent further sub-
belittle Zamansky's imaginative investigation, however. stance to Popper's criticism of the methodology of
In fact, suppose for argument's sake that the prediction Freud's sympathizers.
made by Eysenck and Wilson's alternative explanation Masling regrets my failure to comment on such works
were to fail. Thus, assume for now that Zamansky did find as his anthology (1983), which includes the Greenberg
evidence of more latent homosexuality in paranoiacs than and Fisher chapter I have already discussed. Let me note
in nonparanoiacs. Even then, his own explicit causal accordingly that Eagle's (1983b) contribution to it tells
disclaimer agrees precisely with my thesis in Founda- against Freud, and that in the same volume, Sackheim
tions. Indeed, so does one of Kline's own helpful admis- (1983) argues that people deceive themselves for reasons
sions (1981, p. 437): "Many of the Freudian claims con- other than those given by Freud. Nor do I see that any
cerning the neuroses have simply never been put to the other studies Masling cites call for a change in my conclu-
objective test. . . . Thus, the hypotheses which have sion. For example, the "quantitative investigations of the
been put to the test are usually those where convenient transactions between analyst and patient" of which Masl-
measures are at hand rather than those most crucial to the ing speaks have not, so far, strengthened Freud's clinical
theory." arguments; rather, they merit a "wait-and-see" attitude.
Both Kline and Farrell note that, though central, the Finally, far from overlooking the results from cognitive
theory of repression is not all of psychoanalysis. Howev- psychology presented by Nisbett and Wilson (1977), I
er, when I examined the evidence for Freud's theory of referred to them several times in assessing the evidence
psychosexual development, for example, I found (as did from introspection (pp. 29-30, 147-48, 208).
Erwin, 1985, that it called at best for a conclusion similar Marmor mentions experimental approach-avoidance
to the one about Zamansky's findings. Greenberg and studies in lower animals as evidence that conflict can
Fisher (1983) discuss the evidence for (1) the existence of cause pathology. Although I am unfamiliar with this
penis envy in women (p. 257), and (2) the existence of a work, I wonder about his claim that its results can simply
causal link between preoccupation with penis envy be extrapolated to humans.
themes and "the predicted feelings of inadequacy, de- All in all, those who point to the volume of extraclinical
pression, hostility, and the need to achieve" (p, 274). work already available have given me no reason to change
They do present some perhaps plausible evidence for (1), my assessment, a conclusion apparently shared by
but they offer no good grounds for (2). Again, the result Erwin.
does not alter the conclusion I had drawn from the clinical
evidence for Freud's causal hypotheses (pp. 55-56, 212- The significance of Freud's tally argument. The "Analytic
14). Therapy" Lecture in which Freud developed his tally
Kline does have a point in mentioning Silverman's argument (S.E. 1917, 16:448-63) is the last of his 28
experiments, (e.g., 1976), but it seems too early to assign Introductory Lectures. Published when he was 60 years
positive significance to these. As Erwin (1985, pp. 193- old, they contain his mature account of each major facet of
94) has indicated, there have been repeated failures to his clinical theory. The final lecture addresses the most
replicate Silverman's results. In any case, even if they are fundamental challenge to his entire enterprise, namely,
replicated, the problem remains that Silverman has given that suggestion is the only effective ingredient of psycho-
no independent evidence to justify the crucial assump- analytic therapy and it irremediably contaminates the
tion that his subliminal stimuli stir up unconscious fan- free-association method. Speaking of Freud's rejoinder to

270 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Response/Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
this, Ernest Jones (1955, p. 224) says: "There exists no would instead have been positive. One wonders about
more complete answer to this criticism than that which the basis for this expectation, as Farrell himself seems to
Freud gave at length in his concluding lecture." To have abstained for decades from the very kind of research
evaluate this reply formally, I teased out the tally argu- that he criticizes me for having neglected since starting to
ment from this very lecture. study Freudian theory less than one decade ago. For my
In Foundations, starting with the title of Chapter 2, I part, I shall be glad if Foundations does serve as a catalyst
was repeatedly at pains (e.g. on pp. 135, 167) to charac- for well-conceived investigations (whose outcome I
terize the tally argument as Freud's proposed "vindica- would not presume to anticipate).
tion," that is, his attempt to re-establish the validity of his Cioffi concludes that "Griinbaum's emphasis on the
data and method in the face of the suggestion/contamina- tally argument is not only mistaken [in its interpreta-
tion critique (as distinct from his attempts to validate the tion] . . . but is a great strategic error." This complaint
clinical theory directly, by providing supporting evi- ignores Parts II and III of Foundations, as if my case
dence). Several commentators misunderstood or over- against Freud rested only on Chapter 2. In addition, in
looked this key distinction. questioning my reading of Freud, Cioffi seriously distorts
Farrell seriously misrepresents my reasoning. He sees my claims, countering my painstaking textual documen-
me as begging the question with respect to Freud's tation with what appear to be peremptory speculations.
rebuttal of the charge of contamination by suggestion. In Some of his exegetical attributions to Freud are demon-
fact, my answer to Freud's tally argument was not to strably of his own manufacture, and when he does at-
repeat the contamination critique but to show that there tempt to substantiate his point by giving a reference, it
was no empirical support for the Necessary Condition seems to be with a serious disregard of the context.
Thesis (NCT), a premise on which Freud's tally rebuttal To avoid my "strategic error," he counsels, "the right
relied. Only then did I cite the empirical evidence from procedure" would have been to concentrate on case
Marmor (1970) and others to claim that the contamination histories such as that of the Wolf Man, and to show that
challenge still haunts the psychoanalytic enterprise. not only are they no better than rival accounts, but that
Farrell proceeds to predict that present-day post- they are not even adequate narratives. Cioffi's criticism of
Freudian analysts will dismiss my critique as outdated. my strategy, however, is based on his objection to my use
This prediction is not borne out by the recent editorial in of the tally argument. My Chapter 8 happens to have
the Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association been devoted largely to Freud's case of the Rat Man;
(Shapiro 1985). Furthermore, Farrell ignores Chapter 7 nevertheless, I prefer to recommend to Cioffi that he
of Foundations, where I point out, largely on the basis of himself pursue the strategy he urges on me, leaving only
Eagle's important work (1984b), just why the charge of the role of the tally argument to be considered.
anachronism would be invalid, if analysts were to level it Cioffi raises two distinct, though related questions: (1)
(see also Eagle 1983a, especially pp. 32 and 49-50). Will Did I misstate (or overstate) in Part I (Chapter 2) the
Farrell tell us, for example, how the late Heinz Kohut significance that Freud himself assigned to his tally argu-
(1959) could possibly claim stronger clinical support for ment (with respect to validating his clinical method and
his pre-Oedipal version of unconscious causes of neurosis data)? (2) Did I misrepresent in Part II the evidential role
than Freud could for his sexual ones? Or how Hanna that Freud assigned to primary therapeutic outcome, as
Segal's (1983) writings, which Farrell cites, improve on support for his theory of psychopathology?
the clinical arguments I criticized in Freud? Farrell Cioffi suggests that Freud himself could not have taken
seems instead to beg the question in a credulous ipse the tally argument seriously, because he knew better
dixit: Analysts "are guided by criteria to help them than to believe in its NCT premise that truthful psycho-
identify interpretations which are correct." analytic insight is indispensable to a cure. I was careful (p.
Farrell goes on to erect a straw man in declaring that 149) to say that I did not accept the reasoning that seems
my conclusion about Freud's method does not entail to have led Freud to espouse this crucial premise of the
"that the clinical data . . . can tell us nothing about the argument. But, in addition to the insight requirement of
patient's disorder." I had explicitly disclaimed such a his "tally" statement (p. 138), I quoted (p. 142) most of the
wholesale rejection (pp. 245, 265-66). Nor did I write following from his "Analytic Therapy" lecture: "We
that psychoanalytic theory was "worthless." On the con- achieve successes which are second to none of the finest
trary, I bent over backwards more than once to suggest in the field of internal medicine; and I can now add
that it was still possible that Freud had discovered some something further - namely that they could not have
truths serendipitously (pp. 189, 278). Erwin has justly been achieved by any other procedure" (S.E. 1917,
criticized this expectation as unduly optimistic in the face 16:458). This assertion of unique therapeutic potency, I
of the current evidence, as did the late Ernest Nagel pointed out (p. 142), is a 1917 reiteration of his much
(private communication). earlier claim: "I . . . have accomplished some things
Farrell concludes by shifting to me a burden of proof which no other therapeutic procedure would have
that rightfully belongs to those who are as sanguine about achieved" (S.E. 1895, 2:266;cf. also S.E. 1933, 22:153).
psychoanalysis as he is. It is a pity, he says, that I looked at Is Cioffi suggesting that Freud knew his Analytic
what analysts have said, instead of undertaking the "con- Therapy lecture to be at best mere pious cant? Did his
structive job" of going out to study what they actually do. abandonment of the original seduction theory of hysteria
This failure (to do the work of a whole phalanx of investi- show that he knew better? I cited (p. 159) Freud's famous
gators), he complains, makes Foundations "negative and private 1897 letter (#69) to Fliess in order to point out
lopsided." As an apologist for psychoanalysis, he expects that the unsatisfactory therapeutic outcome he had
that the findings from such a mammoth investigation achieved while still using the seduction theory did not

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 271


Response/Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
contradict his NCT, which claims that cures depend on Why, Cioffi asks, if Freud actually believed in his tally
truthful insight: Using the pseudo-insights of the (subse- argument, did he repeatedly go out of his way to deny that
quently) rejected theory, there was, as Freud wrote to he indoctrinates his patients? Cioffi replies that I took no
Fliess, a "lack of the complete success on which I had notice of these denials. I did so explicitly, at least twice
counted, and the possibility of explaining my partial (pp. 158, 275). As to the question itself, I complained
successes in other, familiar ways" - that is, by suggestion. several times that Freud was not above engaging in pure
To challenge my interpretation and its documentation, salesmanship, in addition to giving arguments (pp. 141,
Cioffi asks: "Would not Freud's therapeutic successes 145-46).
while holding the mistaken seduction theory undermine Cioffi misreads my text, apparently unaware that I
the tally argument?" He further suggests that one is depicted the tally argument as primarily an attempt to
entitled to "suspect that he [Freud] might not have found support the scientific validity of psychoanalytic methods
the state of these patients so unsatisfactory had he not and evidence in general, not as the support for specific
already decided that the assumptions on which he had hypotheses. Without any page reference to Foundations,
treated them were mistaken." Such speculation hardly Cioffi writes: "Grvinbaum is also mistaken to say that if
seems sufficient to outweigh my textual documentation. challenged as to the grounds for his theory of infantile
Moreover, Cioffi seems to be rather free with the text in sexuality, Freud 'would' have appealed to his tally argu-
the service of his own interpretations. Here are two ment." I did not say that. On the relevant page (p. 170), I
examples: was not discussing Freud's validation of the specific
1. Giving no references, Cioffi asks: "Isn't it strange infantile sexual hypotheses; instead, I was concerned
that Freud should think his most irrefragable proof came with how he would defend the use of the retrospective
from just those conditions, for example, dementia psychoanalytic method itself - as distinct from using
praecox, which are resistant to psychoanalytic treat- prospective causal inquiries - as a means of validating the
ment?" On the contrary, the 1980 computer-researched specific causal inferences. Thus, I said: "In the case of the
Concordance to the Standard Edition (ed. Guttman, psychoneuroses, the Tally Argument is the epistemic
Jones & Parrish) shows that the only context in which underwriter of clinical validation by means of the psycho-
Freud ever spoke of "irrefragable proof," in any of the 24 analytic method of etiologic investigation, whereas no
volumes, turns out to be a therapeutic one that is grist for such underwriter is available to permit dispensing with
my mill. The relevant passage reads: "The fact of the the prospective methods of controlled causal inquiry in
emergence of transference in its crudely sexual form, in the case of the actual neuroses" (p. 170; italics in original).
every treatment of a neurosis . . . has always seemed to Although it is irrelevant to my thesis, Cioffi remarks
me the most irrefragable proof that the source of the that Freud appealed to direct observation of children as
driving forces of neurosis lies in sexual life" (S.E. 1914, confirmation of his theory of infantile sexuality. This is
14:12; italics added; cf. also S.E. 1923, 18:247; 1926, true, but it matters that Freud's ultimate court of appeal
20:268 re "transference"). Ironically, it is precisely the remained the psychoanalytic study of adults. As Freud
formation of the artificial transference neurosis - whose tells us, "Such a certain conviction of the existence and
resolution is regarded as a major ingredient of successful importance of infantile sexuality can, however, only be
therapy! - that Freud cites as his "irrefragable proof." obtained by the method of analysis, by pursuing the
Cioffi seems to be confusing this with Freud's (compati- symptoms and peculiarities of neurotics back to their
ble) claim that the so-called narcissistic neuroses (includ- ultimate sources" (S.E. 1914, 14:18).
ing paranoia) are untreatable, just because they do not In Part II (Chapters 3-6), which Cioffi neglects, I had
tend to allow the transference. Moreover, I had pointed emphasized that Freud did not and could not directly
out (p. 141) that in the case of the latter neuroses, "the adduce any therapeutic evidence for his theories of
tally argument is, of course, unavailable to authenticate dreams and slips. These theories, I noted (pp. 187-88,
[validate] his clinically inferred etiologies by means of 224, 231), were based on an incorrect extrapolation of the
therapeutic success." method of free association from its role in making in-
2. Cioffi says: "Nor does Grtinbaum's thesis square ferences about etiology for use in therapy, to a similar role
well with Freud's remark 'it is often just in those cases in inferring the causes of dreams and slips. Freud did use
where treatment fails that most discoveries are made."' interpretations of the patient's dreams and slips obtained
But Cioffi has misleadingly truncated Freud's innocuous by this method, however, as a way to determine what
point here. In the full context of his quotation (S.E. 1909, insights the patient would need for the therapy to be
10:207-8), we find that Freud says nothing at all damag- successful (e.g. S.E. 1900, 4:100-1; 1937, 23:264). Fur-
ing to my thesis. There he reports that the successful thermore, speaking of psychoanalytic theory as a whole,
termination of the Rat Man's analysis, and the latter's he used the tally argument to provide indirect support for
need to turn to other pursuits, prevented the collection of "all that it tells us about what influences our lives, the
further data that would have served to "unravel this tissue dynamics of the mind or the unconscious" (S.E. 1917,
of phantasy thread by thread" (p. 207n.). When the 16:452). Clearly, the ambitious purview of this statement
analysis is not going well therapeutically, continuing it includes not only the theories of dreams and slips, but
allows one to collect more (potentially heuristic) data. In also the theory of psychosexual development, all three of
short, therapeutic failure enhances the data base. But which are mentioned by Cioffi.
such a connection between therapeutic failure and "dis- Cioffi reasons that since "favourable therapeutic out-
covery" - as distinct from validation or proof - is hardly come" could not have given Freud grounds for all this,
tantamount to a dissociation of therapeutic success from the tally argument could not have done so either. But he
the validation of specific etiologic hypotheses. overlooks the fact that whereas one premise of the argu-

272 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Response/Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
ment asserts the existence of cures, the other (NCT) yield any such solution (Chapter 10) was not concerned
predicates the achievement of a cure on the patient's with reliance on therapeutic results. Cioffi misrepresents
correct insight into "the unconscious dynamics of his what I said when I mentioned the tally argument. My
character" (pp. 139-40), which includes not only the pertinent passage reads as follows:
repressions that cause his neurosis but also those that In view of the demise of the Tally Argument, the
instigate his dreams and slips. Moreover Cioffi's claim purported consilience of clinical inductions has the
that the tally argument does not apply to Freud's theory presumption of being spurious, and this strong pre-
of psychosexual development boomerangs. The basis for sumption derives from the fact that the independence
this claim is that the developmental theory also "per- of the inferentially concurring pieces of evidence is
tained to normal character structure." But in this theory, grievously jeopardized by- a shared contaminant: the
the account of the "normal" developmental process is of a analyst's influence . . . . it is precisely in the context of
piece with the explanation of how it goes awry! And the claimed consilience that the epistemic defects of
Freud had inferred virtually all of his hypotheses from the free association that I have discussed come home to
(long-term) clinical responses or other behavior of neurot- roost; for these liabilities ingress alike into each of the
ic - rather than "normal" - patients to begin with. Why three major areas of clinical inquiry in which free
then would he have hesitated to believe that this part of association serves to uncover purported repressions:
his system too could be justified by the cures of these etiologic clinical investigation of the pathogens of the
"abnormal" people? Needless to say, in view of my patient's neurotic symptoms, and the interpretation of
massive doubts about the psychoanalytic method as a his dreams as well as of his parapraxes. By depending
means of validating causal hypotheses, I have no confi- alike on free association, the clinical data from these
dence in the clinical support for Freud's developmental three areas forfeit the independence they require, if
theory. their prima facie consilience is to be probatively
Statements by Freud, made at widely separated stages cogent, (p. 277; italics in original)
of his career, illustrate his own view of the central Plainly, I do not "explain," as Cioffi would have it, that
evidential role played in his theoretical system by the "because Freud no longer felt he could fall back on the
dynamics and outcome of his therapy. These statements tally argument, he now had to resort to considerations of
are quoted, as least partly, in Foundations (pp. 146, 167). consilience." I merely point out that since the tally
Cioffi pays no heed to them. At age 70, Freud declared: argument had failed, Freud could no longer use it to
In psychoanalysis there has existed from the very first defend his jigsaw puzzle reasoning against the criticism
an inseparable bond between cure and research. that only pseudoconsilience caused by suggestion was
Knowledge brought therapeutic success. It was impos- involved.
sible to treat a patient without learning something new; All in all, Cioffi has provided no convincing support for
it was impossible to gain fresh insight without perceiv- his critique of my reading of Freud. It is Von Eckardt who
ing its beneficent results. Our analytic procedure is the puts into proper perspective what I view as the useful
only one in which this precious conjunction is assured. aspect of Cioffi's (1970) appeal to case history material.
(S.E. 1926, 20:256) However, as she makes clear, thus rendered, it is a valid
At the very start of his psychoanalytic career, Freud said: supplement rather than a difficulty for my theses.
"Breuer learnt from his first patient that the attempt at I appreciate the very positive things that Caplan says
discovering the determining cause of a symptom was at about my reconstruction of the central role played by
the same time a therapeutic manoeuvre" (S.E. 1893, therapeutic evidence in Freud's enterprise. I must dis-
3:35). And in a 1909 case history, he wrote: "We are sociate myself, however, from his considerable overstate-
enabled to discover the structure of the pathogenic mate- ment of what I claimed. Thus, I certainly did not assign a
rial and simultaneously to dissipate it" (S.E. 1909, central role to therapeutic success in every assessment of
10:104-5). psychoanalysis, only in those assessments that depend
It is undeniable, I suggest, that Breuer and Freud crucially on using evidence from free association to estab-
offered a therapeutic justification for the cathartic method lish causation. The reason is that the validity of the
of finding and confirming the causes of neurosis (S.E. method of free association ultimately rests on demon-
1893, 2:6-7). By the same token, there is every reason to strating therapeutic success. My conclusion was that this
think that when, soon thereafter, Freud substituted free validity had not been demonstrated and that extraclinical
association for hypnosis, his rationale for regarding the tests are called for (p. 278, item (2); see Precis, summary
data yielded by the new method as valid evidence for the of Chapter 3). I must also distance myself from those of
causes of psychopathology remained therapeutic (Chap- Caplan's other attributions that he derives from this
ter 3, esp. p. 185). Then, of course, free association was overstatement.
gradually assumed to be an autonomous source of causal Caplan gives three reasons for hoping to salvage some-
information, without reference to its initial therapeutic thing from the Freudian clinical research strategy. As to
basis - or appeals to treatment gains in individual case the first, I did not write that "there is no difference" in
histories - providing the etiologic pieces of the jigsaw treatment outcome between long-term psychoanalysis
puzzle model referred to by Cioffi. and its rivals, nor that there is ubiquitous spontaneous
Aware of this fact, I did note (p. 237) that Freud likened remission for all types of neurotic disorder. I claimed only
the interpretative task in psychoanalysis to solving a that the available evidence has "failed to reveal any sort of
jigsaw puzzle that has a unique solution. For the same superiority of psychoanalysis" (p. 161). (Kachele in-
reason, my argument that cross-corroboration ("con- terprets this result as a demonstration' of equal
silience") through converging clinical findings fails to therapeutic effectiveness, and then regrets that I "by-

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 273


Response/Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
passed" it.) I would remind Caplan in regard to all three of and hence irrelevant to its merit. (Incidentally, even if
his reasons that the burden of proof remains on those who the modern results on depression mentioned by Erdelyi
entertain the hopes he outlines. were contrary to (a), how was Freud to have known
Caws suggests that in the context of the insights re- them?)
quired for analytic therapy, Freud's requirement that the Erdelyi's other objection to (a) is that the pleasant
interpretations "tally with what is real" in the patient pseudomemories Janet gave hypnotically to traumatized
(S.E. 1917, 16:452) should not be taken to mean "what patients "were claimed to result in long-term cures." Is
was true about" the patient. Sometimes, Caws writes, I Erdelyi suggesting that Freud believed these purported
make the former mean the latter. But, I submit, Caws's paramnesic cures to be genuine, but simply disregarded
suggestion is appropriate only if Freud himself - rather them, when espousing (a) above? Or that, in view of the
than Caws allowed that it may be therapeutically claims made for Janet's interventions, anyone reading
irrelevant whether the interpretations given to the pa- Freud's "Analytic Therapy" lecture after 1917 should not
tient also tally with "what was true about him." Freud have taken it seriously? Freud repeatedly discussed the
actually insisted on the opposite: "What we are in search relation of Janet's work to the Breuer - Freud cathartic
of is a picture of the patient's forgotten years that shall be method. It seems clear from these accounts that he
alike trustworthy and in all essential respects complete" simply did not believe in the durability of hypnotically
(S.E. 1937, 23:258). achieved results (S.E. 1923, 18:237; 1925, 20:21). Be-
Caws complicates the issue he raises by going on to sides, Erdelyi himself seems to have stopped short of
interpret the phrase "what was true about him" as refer- actually endorsing the permanence of Janet's hypnotic
ring to the patient's past "external" history and the phrase cures. What then is the force of his reference to Janet?
"what is real in him" as referring to the patient's current Erdelyi's only other comment on (a) is a red herring.
"internal" psychic structure. I am puzzled by Caws's Suppose, he says, that we assume the truth of (b) and (c)
mistaken impression that I ever took Freud's phrase and also of (d) that "some insights but not others produced
"what is real in him" to require that the patient's insight cures." Even then, he points out, (a) "would still not
into his past conform to the external facts of his history, at follow logically." In a private communication (January 30,
the expense of recognizing the psychological role of 1985), Erdelyi informs me (without providing textual
pseudomemories and repressed infantile fantasies. Had I evidence) that he is imputing this deductive blunder to
done so, I would obviously have misinterpreted Freud's Freud, not to me.
revised seduction theory, according to which hysteria Thus, Erdelyi's claim that the tally argument was
could be caused not only by actual seductions during deservedly neglected seems to rest exclusively on the
childhood but also by imagined ones. The fact remains supposed durability of Janet's paramnesic cures. He adds
that real childhood events, either external or internal, are that the collapse of the argument is not as serious for
presumed to play a vital causal role, and insight into them Freudian theory as I think. Erdelyi overlooks the fact
is considered therapeutically crucial. that, for Freud, the tally argument was intended to
Erdelyi, whose own research is on the mechanism of revalidate not just specific hypotheses about the causes of
repression itself, finds it odd that I focus on the multiple neuroses, but all clinical data and everything that psycho-
causal role Freud assigned to this mechanism. Thus, he analysis teaches us about the unconscious (S.E. 1917;
16:446-52). Otherwise, how does Erdelyi propose to
considers it "idiosyncratic" to treat the theories of neu-
answer my criticism of the validity of the clinical evidence
rosis, dream-formation, and slip-generation as the car- for the psychoanalytic theories of dreams and slips (chaps.
dinal hypotheses of Freud's clinical system. In his view, 4 & 5)? Apparently Erdelyi would subscribe to the acausal
the mechanism of repression is the "dog," whereas the hermeneutic version of these hypotheses, thus ignoring
etiologies are only the "tail." As if I had not devoted my explicit objections (pp. 57-60) to such a limiting
separate chapters to dreams and slips, he writes: "Etiolo- reconstruction.
gy is hardly the ubiquitous preoccupation of psycho-
analysis," and "psychoanalysis has a far wider scope than Erdelyi also seems to ignore some of my own conten-
the retrospective discovery of etiologies." tions, but then to affirm them himself, as if they could
Erdelyi starts by trying to diminish the significance of serve as objections. In this vein, after stating the truism
the tally argument. He offers three reasons for declaring: that psychoanalysis is not just a therapy, and that it makes
"My problem with 'the tally argument' is not Griinbaum's "the distinction between manifest and latent content," he
criticism, but his original enthusiasm for it." He thence says: "Nor need psychoanalysis be hobbled by an exclu-
concludes that "there was good reason for 'the tally sionary reliance on clinical data" (cf. Foundations, p.
argument' to have languished undiscovered." The follow- 278).
ing three consequences from the premises of the argu- Wachtel observes that I depict "a tragic flaw" in the
ment are relevant to his complaint: (a) All curative in- tally argument. But he is baffled because I couple this
sights are true, (b) If there are any genuine cures of rejection "with a virtual ode" to the argument. I did
neuroses at all, only psychoanalytic treatment can indeed say that if its premises were empirically true, then
achieve them, (c) There is no spontaneous remission of it would be a "magnificent" argument (p. 141). This
neuroses. conditional tribute is prompted entirely by the scope and
Erdelyi offers two reasons against (a). One is that "true importance that the consequences would have had if the
insight, as some modern research on depression implies, premises had been tenable. But Wachtel is then also
may be countertherapeutic." This result, however, clear- puzzled, fairly enough, by my declaration that "if psycho-
ly does not tell against (a), but only against its converse analytic treatment does have the therapeutic monopoly
"All true insights are curative." Freud did assert (a), but entailed by the Tally Argument, then it can warrantedly
its converse is not a consequence of the tally argument, take credit for the recoveries of its patients without

274 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Response/Grunbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
statistical comparions with the results from untreated statements about independence were met by subtle ap-
control groups, or from controls treated by rival proval, whereas none were disapproved. On the other
modalities" (p. 142). How, he asks, can one know, with- hand, 16 client statements about sex were met with
out comparative studies of treatment outcome, that disapproval and only 2 were approved. By the end of the
Freud's therapy does have such a monopoly? My reason therapy, the patient was concerned with independence
for pointing to the monopoly was surely not to claim that and seemed unconcerned with sex.
the NCT premise makes comparative studies, unneces- Hence I fail to see the force of Kachele's remark that
sary! It was rather to explain - though not to justify! - the "research on actual tape recordings of sessions have
complacent attitude taken by Freud toward the end of his amply shown that psychoanalytic dialogues are but a
"Analytic Therapy" lecture. As I put it: "Small wonder, highly technical and rule-specified variant of discourse."
therefore, that Freud concluded his 1917 Analytic Thera- The less so, since I do appreciate the aptness of his choice
py paper by blithely dismissing doubts as to the of words, when he himself describes the analyst-patient
therapeutic efficacy of analysis, after merely alluding to dialogue as question-answer discourse, having the char-
the difficulties of statistical comparisons of treatment acter of a "Socratic enterprise." As is well-known, in the
outcome with results from untreated control groups, let Socratic method, answers to leading questions can be
alone with the results from rival therapies" (p. 142). elicited according to the interlocutor's expectations.
Furthermore, it should be borne in mind that when I Speaking of the coaching of patients by their analysts,
offered a reconstruction of the reasoning Freud used to Masling (1986, p. ix) rightly wonders what Freud would
justify NCT to himself, I explicitly did so "with- have said "had he lived to see the ease with which verbal
out . . . countenancing" (i.e. without accepting) that rea- behavior can be operantly conditioned." Yet Holt is
soning (p. 149). It did not, however, simply beg the confident that tape-recorded, transcribed analytic ses-
question (149-159). (Klerman overlooked my discussion sions will permit a determination of "the extent to which
of treatment efficacy [p. 161].) therapists do demonstrably 'lead' their patient," and
effects "a kind of operant conditioning." He encourages
How good are the clinical data as data? The received me to share that optimism, so I must now explain why,
psychoanalytic tenet that "clinical studies . . . are the and in what sense, I expect less from these welcome
bedrock of theory" is reaffirmed by Pollock, but with the investigations than Holt does, and why I maintain that the
admonition that they should be "careful." treatment setting has delivered a great deal less than
In Foundations (pp. 211, 265), I cited Marmor, who Luborsky already claims for it.
gives an account of experimental and clinical studies that It is significant that the word Freud used in German to
show the contamination and bias inherent in the free- refer to the interpretations given to the patient was
association method (1970, p. 161; 1962, p. 289). Erwartungsvorstellungen, i.e. anticipatory ideas as to
On occasion, Freud's own writings illustrate this bias, what the analyst expects the patient to discover in him-
as in the following passage criticizing the findings of self. Freud made no bones about the fact that the two
analysts belonging to rival schools: parts of his therapy are (1) "what the physician infers and
. . . one hears of analysts who boast that, though they tells the patient," and (2) "the patient's working-over of
have worked for dozens of years, they have never found what he has heard." As Freud explains unambiguously,
a sign of the existence of a castration complex. We must "We give the patient the conscious anticipatory idea [the
bow our heads in recognition of the greatness of this idea of what he may expect to find] and he then finds the
achievement, even though it is only a negative one, a repressed unconscious idea in himself on the basis of its
piece of virtuosity in the art of overlooking and mistak- similarity to the anticipatory one" (S.E. 1910, 11:142; the
ing. (S.E. 1925, 19:254n.) interpolation in brackets appears in the S.E. text).
It would seem that Freud's own error here was "to Besides the studies cited in Marmor (1970), to which
mistake a mirror for a window," as Masling (1986, p. viii) Spence apparently turned a blind eye, I gave a detailed
put it so well. illustration of regimentation of patient responses by the
In his commentary, Marmor recalls the upshot of his analyst (pp. 212-14): In a 1974 book by two teaching
1970 paper. He now reports that as early as 1955, he had analysts on how their therapy ought to be practiced, it is
tried to persuade his fellow psychoanalysts "that analytic made evident how they orchestrated a female patient's
theory must be subject to consensual validation by find- "discovery" of penis envy in herself. For considerable
ings extrinsic to the psychoanalytic method itself." Yet, as additional illustrative material I referred to a recent book
one might expect, contamination by suggestion is not by the psychoanalyst Peterfreund (1983, Part I). There,
confined to clinical data from psychoanalysis in particular. Peterfreund provides case studies from six well-known
Carl Rogers's therapy is another case in point. Though analysts, and two analyses he himself conducted under
not psychoanalytic, it displays the same kind of thematic supervision as a beginner, all of which are replete with
unabashed coaching and coaxing of the patient to produce
regimentation for which I criticized the typical analyst's
stereotypically expected responses.
interventions in the patient's "free" associations (pp.
209-10). Summarizing a 1956 study by Murray, Masling In the light of this evidence, Spence is unconvincing
(1986, p. viii) relates that "Rogers' theory led him to when he quotes Edelson (1984) to the effect that analysts
intervene for some themes but not for others; in due time are trained to be sensitive to the dangers of suggestion,
the client talked only about the issues in which Rogers when in fact they fail to avoid these dangers (p. 212).
seemed interested." From the very outset of therapy, Spence ignores the evidence I gave from Marmor (1970)
some content areas are reinforced explicitly or tacitly, and Peterfreund (1983), saying that I cited "only one"
whereas others are not. Thus, using a tape of Rogers's clinical interchange in which the analyst is leading the
own treatment sessions, Murray showed that 68 client patient. This supposedly narrow evidential base, he sug-

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 275


Response/Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
gests, "greatly weakens" my case. In fact, he conjectures analyses tests particular clinical hypotheses, which con-
that "the tradition of narrative smoothing" of the case cern individual patients" (second emphasis added). That,
histories "may account for the small amount of evidence I observe, is still a long way from testing explanatory
cited by Griinbaum." The eight case histories marshaled psychoanalytic hypotheses as to the causal role of uncon-
by Peterfruend, however, show clearly even after narra- scious motives or fantasies in neuroses, dreams, or slips.
tive smoothing that there is orchestration of patient assent! Luborsky subdivides the question about the extent of
Just what did I in fact make of contamination as a contamination by the therapist's self-fulfilling expecta-
liability of clinical data in Foundations? I will quote my tions into questions pertaining to (1) the accuracy of the
carefully worded conclusion, since its bleakness has been therapist's inferences as to "the parallel between the
crudely overstated by Farrell, and enormously exagge- patient's current relationship patterns and past parental
rated by others, such as Shevrin, who thinks I believe relationships," (2) the availability of evidence that these
that "the patient's reality testing is altogether in "parallel" or "central patterns of relationship (of a kind
abeyance." Holt too thinks I have overgeneralized "from that are involved in the transference) are an intrinsic
the weakness of the traditional clinical method to the characteristic of the patient," and (3) the accuracy of "the
uselessness of the data generated in the psychoanalytic therapist's inferences about the patient's past and present
hour for more rigorous research." What I actually said behavior when these behaviors are understood in terms
was the following: of the patient's response to actual early parental
I do not maintain that any and all clinical data are behavior."
altogether irrelevant probatively. Instead, I hold that With respect to the past/present parallel referred to in
such findings cannot possibly bear the probative bur- (1), Luborsky points to evidence that "therapists are
den placed upon them by those who claim . . . that responding to information provided in the session," a
psychoanalysis can typically be validated or invalidated rather innocuous conclusion that I have not denied (pp.
"on the couch," using a clinical testing strategy that is 245, 265-66). It is innocuous, because Luborsky himself
mainly confined to the analytic setting. . . . I do not adds: "However, we cannot say from this evidence alone
deny at all that now and then clinical results "are whether the therapist might have induced some of the
contrary to the expectations and belief of the clinician." parallel." Moreover, he explicitly agrees with me regard-
But as a step toward vindicating clinical inquiry qua ing (3). Hence the question is what is to be made of his
epistemically autonomous testing strategy, I can only answer to (2), which is as follows: Data gathered by a
say, "One swallow does not a summer make." (p. 265) special interview method applied outside of therapy,
On the whole, data from the couch acquire probative combined with intratherapy findings, show that the "par-
significance when they are independently corrobo- allel relationship patterns were evident both before and
rated by extraclinical findings, or when they are induc- during treatment."
tively consilient with such findings, (p. 266) In general, I have not denied this quite vague conclusion either.
the epistemic devices confined to the analytic setting But to provide perspective on its contribution to the
cannot reliably sift or decontaminate the clinical data so validation of the clinical data needed to support major
as to identify those that qualify as authentic, (p. 245) psychoanalytic hypotheses, I draw on Eagle's (1986) most
Hence I do not see the justification for Shevrin's dismal instructive essay-review of Foundations. There, he com-
though constructively intended reductio ad absurdum ments on a paper coauthored by Luborsky, Mellon, van
that if I am "altogether right about the analytic clinical Ravenswaag, Childress, Levine, Alexander, Crits-
method, then there is no relying on reasonableness in any Christoph, Cohen, Hole & Ming (1985) and significantly
context." I shall also argue in the next section that no such entitled "A Verification of Freud's Grandest Clinical
dire consequence follows from my doubts about the caus- Hypothesis: The Transference." Eagle makes the follow-
al tenets of psychoanalysis, tenets which Shevrin puts ing key points: (t) the notion of transference invoked in
on par evidentially with "readiness in any context." their investigations, though clearly analogous to Freud's,
If future study of tape-recorded analytic sessions "does not include the distinctively psychoanalytic idea of
should turn out to be capable of disentangling contami- unconscious infantile instinctual wishes that the patient
nated data from valid data, as Holt surmises, then I shall unconsciously pushes for the therapist to gratify." (it)
appreciatively stand corrected, and will retract especially Shorn of this distinctive component, Luborsky's "paral-
the last of the statements from Foundations I just cited. I lelism" asserts the existence of strong similarities be-
have an important caveat, however. Suppose that Holt's tween the patient's early behavior toward his parents,
hopes materialize, so that the valid and invalid data are and his conduct toward the therapist or his spouse. (Hi)
separated. Even then, it may turn out that the vast Such a similarity, besides not being startling, is a matter
majority of data needed to support the central psycho- of developmental consistency, largely affirmed by non-
analytic hypotheses are not valid! What then? I do under- psychoanalytic therapists as well, (iv) The adult patient's
stand that recorded analyses can be, and are being, used reports in analysis do not reliably attest to his actual early
in a "relatively rigorous testing" of some kinds of psycho- behavior in the interaction with his parents, a point that
analytic hypotheses, but I call attention to Holt's own Luborsky concedes here, (u) To the extent that
stress on the very modest range of these particular hy- Luborsky's account of transference asserts causal connec-
potheses. Erdelyi too is unduly sanguine. tions beyond similarities, it tends to be "mere speculation
Thus, using the language of Benjamin Rubinstein's with little or no supporting evidence. "
(1978) illuminating typology of clinical hypotheses, Holt In the next section, I shall give my own reasons for
says: "It needs to be pointed out that most of the research agreeing with the last item in Eagle's appraisal by draw-
so far conducted on recorded and transcribed psycho- ing on Luborsky's comment on what he calls my "ques-

276 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Response/Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
tion two." For now, I claim that Luborsky's discussion of criteria. Typically, in the case of a causal hypothesis, my
my "question one" does not call for a modification of the demand for evidence of the existence of a causal connec-
response I gave above to Holt. tion takes the form of calling on Freud to rule out just one
Kachele reminds me that since psychoanalytic treat- eminently reasonable rival hypothesis, rather than all
ment aims to achieve change in patients, "it shares the such rivals! For example, when he claimed that the lifting
epistemic problems of intervention paradigms with many of the repression of a trauma should be given credit for the
other respectable scientific enterprises." I am unsure patient's subsequent improvement, what I deemed es-
what other scientific enterprises he has in mind, and how sential for validation was "comparisons with treatment
ambitious their hypotheses are, as compared to those of outcome from a suitable control group whose repressions
psychoanalytic theory. I suggest, however, that Kachele's are not lifted" (p. 180; cf. also pp. 214, 261). Clearly, I did
reminder needs to be addressed not to me, but to those not thereby call on Freud to show that the patient's
many analysts who continue to uphold the claim that the insight was the only explanation or possible cause of the
treatment setting is an arena par excellence not only for positive treatment outcome. It is standard scientific prac-
testing hypotheses about psychotherapeutic process or tice in research on therapeutic process and outcome to
outcome, but for testing Freud's general theory of human call for evidence, as I did, that the putative treatment
nature. As Fisher and Greenberg (1977, p. 363) put it variables are in fact causally linked to the outcome vari-
neatly: "Freud never really came to terms with the ables. Surely this demand is not a matter of "Descartes'
differences involved in trying to learn about people as demon," as Fine & Forbes think.
opposed to trying to change them." Commendably, Finally, Fine & Forbes say that "by depriving Freud's
Holzman (1986) has come to terms with that difference, inferences of their natural background in everyday psy-
and has pressed basic doubts about the use of data from chology," I was able to "make even the most cogent
the treatment setting. patterns of reasoning seem implausible." The penalty for
In view of Freud's own life-long struggle with the doing so, they claim, is visited upon me when I deny that
problem of suggestibility, as well as my preceding consid- free association is a bona fide method of causal validation.
erations, I do not understand why Fine & Forbes think My "atomistic construal of causes" prevents me from
that my concern with the very mundane role of self- seeing, they think, that "when we follow a chain of
fulfilling expectations in the production of clinical data is associations we see, along the way, what the connections
akin to conjuring up doubts about everything from the are, and there is no additional question, in the causal
specter of a Cartesian demon. As emerges from Robert mode, as to the relation between one end of the chain and
Merton's (1949) work, it is quite inappropriate to identify the other."
the bias arising from self-fulfilling predictions with the This criticism, too, rather amazes me, because it over-
general fallibility of all scientific knowledge, which Fine looks two elaborate discussions in Foundations: In the
& Forbes would have us do at least for now. Nor is it chapters on dreams and on slips, I explicitly discussed the
correct to describe the specific evidence for bias already role of common sense psychology in Freud's arguments.
at hand as raising a "mere generic possibility" that can be Rather than overlooking that role, I documented - in a
safely bracketed, while placing the burden of still further painstaking analysis of his attempt to use the Irma dream
evidence on skeptics such as the analyst Marmor, or on as a paradigm - that his appeal to common-sense psychol-
me. Why is it, for example, that the success or failure to ogy here was an outright sleight of hand. I dealt likewise
discover penis envy in women and castration anxiety in with both transparent slips - whose explanation comes
men is correlated with membership in a particular school from common sense psychology - and explanatorily
of psychoanalysis, as Freud knew? In any case, Fine & opaque ones, which Freud claimed to explain by latent
Forbes overlook all of Part II of Foundations in reading motives.
me as having supposed that "skeptical doubts about I never said that there was any question about the
suggestibility . . . were the major obstacle to accepting causal relation between the initial and terminal elements
Freud's clinical arguments." If need be, I could and in a chain of free associations. On the contrary, I explicitly
would rest my case on Part II alone. took this causal link for granted (pp. 186, 192), though I
emphasized (pp. 208-11) that associative causal chains
What would unbiased clinical data prove? It is now ger- can be influenced by the analyst. What I did criticize as
mane to cite the last sentence of Part I in Foundations fallacious was the fact that "Freud's conclusion as to the
where I anticipate the main conclusion of Part II: "The motivational cause had asserted an order of cause and
major pillars of the theory of repression will turn out to be effect that is the reverse of the causal order exhibited by
ill-founded, even if clinical data could be taken at face the free associations" (p. 233). The fallacy was to infer that
value as being uncontaminated epistemically" (p. 172; "a repression which emerges at the end of a chain of free
italics in original). Hence I shall now disregard the doubts associations - as its terminus ad quern - was actually the
I expressed in the preceding section. original cause of the symptom that initiated the chain as
Fine & Forbes's principal objection is the astonishing its terminus a quo" (pp. 186-87). I had also been careful
one that I have made a Utopian demand of psychoanalysis. to illustrate exactly how this causal inversion fallacy was
committed in Freud's explanation of the aliquis slip on
In evaluating Freud's evidence for his causal hypotheses,
the basis of the subject's fear of his girl friend's pregnancy
they contend, my central strategy is to demand that he (p. 233).
first rule out all rival explanations: "Griinbaum's strategy
embodies the methodological myth that support accrues Ifindnothing at all in what Fine & Forbes say about the
only in the absence of rivals." causal (or thematic) integrity of the associative chain itself
This is an incorrect depiction of my methodological that justifies inverting the direction of causation. Just that

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 277


Response/Grunbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
fallacious inference is drawn, however, whenever the cepting and rejecting the received psychoanalytic ac-
psychoanalytic method claims to have unearthed the count of the dynamics of its therapy. On the one hand, he
cause of a neurotic symptom, a dream-instigating wish, or seems to endorse "the substance of all forms of psycho-
a motive for a slip. therapy based on psychoanalytic principles." Thus he
Shevrin and Strupp make similar errors in reasoning. explicitly includes the emphasis on the patient's "working
Shevrin slides from accepting some of the patient's state- through" of his childish "transference" behavior toward
ments about the current content of his mind, to accepting the analyst. On the other hand, he chides Freud for
the analyst's causal interpretation of such reports, or his having "attached undue weight to the mutative effect of
imputations of causal knowledge to which the patient has interpretations." Strupp is content with the truism that
no access. "in all forms of psychotherapy the therapist exerts a
I noted that the client does have direct and generally psychological influence." In the context of the theory of
reliable access to the object of his momentary attention, therapeutic process, however, it may matter greatly
the affect he feels at the moment, and the like (p. 29). On whether or not therapeutic gain is actually caused by the
the basis of the work of such cognitive psychologists as particular treatment factors to which the therapist's theo-
Shevrin's Michigan colleague Nisbett (pp. 29-30, 147- ry attributes it. In the latter case, I have spoken of the
48, 208), however, I also said: "Though the subject often outcome as being a "placebo effect" with respect to that
does have direct access to the individual contents of his theory (1981; 1986). Hence, in saying that positive effects
mental states, he/she [sic] has only inferential access - of psychoanalytic treatment may be placebo effects, I am
just like outside observers - to such causal linkages as saying that Freud's theory of how the therapy works may
actually connect some of his own mental states" (p. 30). be erroneous, a conclusion that Strupp also seems to have
Initially, Shevrin seems alert to the difference between reached. Moreover, in claiming that a placebo effect may
the patient's report of, say, an affect, and his "ability to be involved, I surely was not saying, as Strupp mistakenly
explain what lies behind the truths of his experience." believes, "that there must be 'special' psychological
But when Shevrin turns to the concrete case of an episode mechanisms m_formal psychotherapy."
in the life of Freud's patient Elisabeth von R. (S.E. 1895, As indicated in Foundations (p. 259), Kazdin (1981, p.
2:156), he does not heed this difference. 185) has pointed out that in the study of the effects of
First, Shevrin says, uncontroversially enough: "The treatment, case studies and experiments fall on a con-
patient can report . . . that at her sister's deathbed, with tinuum with respect to their ability to cope with the
her attractive brother-in-law standing nearby, the challenge that the treatment may not in fact have pro-
thought, 'Now he is free again and I can be his wife,' shot duced the patient's gains. It needs to be emphasized,
through her mind and was immediately banished." This however, that there is no reason to believe that case
much asserts that the thought of marriage occurred and studies are capable of validating hypotheses about the
was then quickly forgotten, but it does not guarantee that causal role of true insight in successful psychoanalytic
the content of this thought - rather than, say, the intru- treatment (i.e. the account of how and why the treatment
sion of a further idea - was the motive for this rapid works). As I noted in connection with Caws, Freudian
forgetting. Yet Shevrin proceeds at once to equate the theory attributes the therapeutic success of the inter-
evidential validity of the self-report itself with that of the pretations given to the patient partly to the correctness of
account Freud then gave of the forgetting as a case of the insights to which they give rise. I argued (Chapters 3
repression caused by a particular motive. and 8), however, that there is no good reason to suppose
Thus Shevrin asks: "Why should this account not have that the case study method can provide independent
evidential status as much as the statement, 'I see evidence of correctness.
blue'. . . ?" I respond: Although in this particular case Regarding the substance of causal insights, Marmor
Freud's motivational explanation of the rapid forgetting criticizes Freud for always having looked "for a single
may well be entirely reasonable, its validity is simply cause for neurosis (akin to the tubercle bacillus), such as
more open to question than that of "I see blue." The an infantile sexual trauma." As I stressed (pp. 109-10),
former is a causal attribution, whereas the latter is a self- however, precisely when speaking of the causal role of the
report on a current state of mind. This difference is tubercle bacillus, Freud (S.E. 1896, 3:209) warned
essential here, because Shevrin makes it appear that if I against the unicausal model of either tuberculosis or
discount Freud's theory of hysteria as clinically ill-sup- neurosis, rejecting it in favor of a multifactorial one. In
ported, then I would also have to be skeptical of the self- Freud's early typology of causes (S.E. 1895, 3:135-37),
report "I see blue." From this misrepresentation of my the technical meaning of his term "specific cause" is not
position as wholesale skepticism, he tries to construct a unicausal, since the realization of other "preconditions" is
reductio ad absurdum of my thesis about psychoanalysis. also required. By the same token, his reference to "causal
Shevrin's disclaimers do not go nearly far enough, overdetermination" calls for a multifactorial model.
when he allows that "to establish the existence of repres- Luborsky asks: "Do psychotherapy sessions provide
sion or its role in pathogenesis is not the same as knowing data that permit verification of the causes of symptoms,
how repression works or exactly how it produces neu- including 'Freudian slips'?" He thinks that his affirmative
rosis." In any science there is always unfinished business. answer creates a problem for my view, because he can use
Hence, that much is surely not a liability of psycho- intraclinical data to discern the "causes" of symptoms in
analysis. It is a liability, however, to slide, as Shevrin just the following ad hoc sense: "I use the word 'cause,'" he
did, from establishing the existence of repression to explains, "in the sense of a factor that is shown to have a
establishing "its [causal] role in pathogenesis." Zamansky high probability of being temporally associated with the
(1958), as we saw, rightly avoided that pitfall. development of a symptom." In particular, in his vocabu-
Strupp apparently shifts back and forth between ac- lary, the term "cause" is explicitly "being taken to

278 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


Response/Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
mean . . . a factor associated with the development of a for analysts, including Edelson, to handicap themselves
symptom that recurrently appears in the material prior to with the do-or-die demand that their clinical arena must
the appearance of the symptom." He then notes that his carry the evidential burdens of their enterprise, over and
own symptom-context method has shown helplessness to above the heuristic ones. I do take Edelson's point,
be the most prevalent "cause" of psychological however, that the pertinent phenomena may be hard to
symptoms. generate extraclinically with sufficient intensity. All the
Most disappointingly, Luborsky's construal of the term same, I am loath to put a cap on the ingenuity- of extra-
"cause" begs the question by trivializing it. Plainly, an clinical investigators, any more than on that of the intra-
antecedent event can be the "cause" of a psychological clinical ones.
symptom in Luborsky's sense without making any dif- As Edelson sees it, I have been atypically and unduly
ference to whether the symptom occurs or not. That such harsh with Freud in my critique of his reliance on free
an antecedent does not contribute to the explanation of association as a method of validating causal inferences.
the symptom is evident, for, in his idiosyncratic sense of But I was hardly declaring him a "simpleton" when I
the term, even ordinary breathing qualifies as a "cause" of wrote: "Freud had enunciated his fundamental rule of
a neurotic symptom, since any post hoc argument is good free association as a maxim of clinical research, because
enough for Luborsky to confirm the causal relevance of he thought that associations governed by it had reliably
the antecedent. Perhaps Luborsky's findings will, howev- certified the unconscious pathogens of the neuroses" (p.
er, turn out to be heuristic. 185). This much of his reasoning I depicted as sophisti-
Speaking again of his symptom-context method, cated though not, in the end, successful.
Luborsky says: "The recent book by Edelson (1984) Then I turned to the analysis of his Irma Dream, where
expresses the same view about the cogency of my method Freud gives his justification for enlarging the role of free
in answering Griinbaum's challenge." However, in its association from a method of inquiry into etiology aimed
new paperback edition, Edelson has changed his own at therapy to a way of investigating dreams (Chapter 5). If,
1984 reconstruction (pp. 144-46) of a study that used as Edelson thinks, reasons of discretion prevented Freud
Luborsky's method. In either version, I claim, the con- from using this dream to make his case adequately, then
clusion / on his p. 145 - which states the expected he surely should not have offered Irma as "the" dream
empirical outcome of the pertinent study - simply does specimen of psychoanalysis. Instead, he should have
not follow from the conjunction of his psychoanalytic chosen a less sensitive one. As is, I believe that Edelson's
premises c, d, and e. The deduction fails, because it relies defense strains charity.
on an invalid hypothetical syllogism. Hence Edelson's I am inclined to think instead that Freud used the
(1984) reconstruction has offered no valid grounds for analysis of Irma partly because it had been heuristic for
believing that Luborsky's empirical confirmation of the him, but, more importantly, because he counted on it to
ill-founded conclusion/qualifies as an intraclinical test of be more persuasive than anything else he might offer. In
a psychoanalytic causal hypothesis. die case of the unwary, this expectation has been abun-
Envin has taken issue with other features of that dantly fulfilled. In short, perhaps uncharitably, I believe
reconstruction. Pollock, however, suggests that Edelson that Freud's Irma analysis was, at bottom, a mere piece of
(1984) has elegantly answered some of my arguments. I salesmanship. Yet Edelson overlooks the fact that pre-
have devoted a chapter of Griinbaum (1987) to a detailed cisely apropos of Freud's use of free association in dream
appreciative rejoinder to Edelson's answers. Alas, Pol- interpretation, I had nonetheless said: "Freud's fallacious
lack does not say in what way my critique "does suffer" causal inference is not quite the glaringly crude blunder
from my lack of direct clinical experience. that it appears to be" (p. 234). Thus, insofar as I expressed
Due to the benefit I have had from discussions with real scorn for unsound justifications of causal inferences
Edelson, Luborsky, and Erwin, I now gladly affirm the based on free association, I reserved it for Rapaport's
following: It is indeed foolhardy for me, or anyone else, to (1967, pp. 216-17) stance (pp. 186-87). The unanswered
declare it impossible that some future psychoanalytic questions Edelson goes on to raise regarding free associa-
researchers could come up with as yet unirhagined tion seem to me well taken, to the extent that I under-
clinical research designs capable of testing Freud's major stand them.
clinical hypotheses. To this extent, I can surely accede to
the opening reservation in Edelson's commentary, and Hermeneutics. In Foundations I raised three objections
also concur with Erwin's refinement of my skeptical to Gauld & Shotter's hermeneutic psychology, in its
stance. But I adhere to the view that, so far, neither bearing on psychoanalysis: (1) Their hermeneutic epis-
Edelson (1984) nor Luborsky have supplied good grounds temology cannot justify imputing explanatory uncon-
for actually expecting such a research possibility to scious motives (pp. 56-57). (2) They mistakenly denied
materialize. the compatibility of causal explanation of behavior with
Let me say specifically under what sorts of conditions I explanation of action by "reasons" (p. 69). (3) A causally
would be prepared to acknowledge that intraclinical tes- relevant antecedent of an event need be neither a suffi-
tability is feasible. Perrez (1979, Chapters 4-7) gives a cient nor a necessary condition for the occurrence of the
valuable, detailed statement of the array of hypotheses event (p. 73) (to the detriment of their case against causal
that Freud invokes in a single case history of the Wolf explanation of conduct.)
Man. I would change my view on intraclinical testability As to (1), Gauld & Shorter do not contest my citing (p.
if, for example, someone were to propose research de- 56) their statement that "after psychotherapy the patient
signs within the treatment setting, capable of testing even comes to understand that his strange action was a sym-
a fraction of this elaborate set of hypotheses. Until such bolic piece of aggression against his father." Was it there-
research plans are worked out, it does not seem sensible fore not reasonable for me to believe that they were

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 279


Response/Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
discussing explanation of neurotic action by unconscious philosophers take it for granted without ado (p. 9). Wool-
aggression? I accept their clarification that they were not. folk calls for "some elucidation of the moral dimensions of
And thus, I modify my challenge (1) so as to pertain psychoanalysis' vis-a-vis the natural science status to
instead to explanation by conscious motives. Further- which Freud aspired. Much has, of course, been written
more, I note that they say nothing at all that comes to about its social role, and about Freud as a moralist. Thus,
grips with my (2) and (3). as Suppe points out, Freud expressed himself ethically on
Leibin treats any sort of actual or alleged attribute of the attitude he took toward homosexuals. It may bear
psychoanalysis as a defining characteristic. In this way, he further elucidation to just what extent this attitude is
concludes that Freud himself has actually given "at least linked to his account of homosexuality as a "perversion"
ten" definitions of his enterprise, which are not only rather than a neurosis (S.E. 1905, 7:23, 165). I take Ruse
different but in some cases even pairwise incompatible. I to agree that developmental inquiry into homosexuality
suggest that the founding father told us otherwise. He need not itself be judgmental, although the technical
gave us a simple cluster of major attributes: term "perversion" unfortunately has negative moral
Psycho-Analysis is the name (1) of a procedure for the connotations.
investigation of mental processes which are almost Woolfolk also sees psychoanalysis as an emancipatory
inaccessible in any other way, (2) of a method (based gospel. To be sure, it holds out the possibility of freeing
upon that investigation) for the treatment of neurotic one from unconscious dictates and widening the options
disorders and (3) of a collection of psychological infor- in one's life. But did Freud not also teach that it is the
mation obtained along those lines, which is gradually patient, not the analyst, who must decide whether to
being accumulated into a new scientific discipline. translate the insight that his therapy promises into eman-
(S.E. 1923, 18:235) cipating options?
I urged a negative answer to the following basic ques-
tion: Did Freud's clinical arguments provide sufficient Quo vadis? The Editor's question about inductive strat-
support for the knowledge claims he made for his evolv- egy goes well beyond the confines of the current status of
ing theory in labeling it "scientific" (p. 94)? Leibin mis- psychoanalytic theory: Just what is the connection be-
casts this conclusion as being a rejection of "precisely" tween the evidential appraisal of a theory and heuristic
Freud's own "definition," as if I were proposing a rival advice concerning its investigative pursuit? Lakatos
definition. He also overlooks the fact that the focus of my (1971), Quinn (1972), Giere (1975), and Laundan(1977)
scrutiny was unambiguously on the clinical theory of have argued that the construction of a suitable decision
repression. Furthermore, in the face of my critique of the theory is much more complicated than the editorial
hermeneutic reconstruction of psychoanalysis, Leibin commentary seems to allow. Indeed, as Popper (1962, p.
gives no grounds for his claim that this version is viable, if 33) has emphasized: "Science often errs and . . . pseudo-
one-sided. As I argued in detail (pp. 1-94), the sense in science may happen to stumble on the truth."
which psychoanalysis is an "interpretative" endeavor Mindful of documented cases from the history of sci-
lends no support at all to the philosophical theses of those ence, in which initially very dubious hypotheses subse-
who offered the hermeneutic reconstruction. Physicists quently either proved fruitful or were validated after all,
too interpret phenomena, when they explain them. The Lakatos (1971, p. 104) wrote: "One may rationally stick to
big-bang theory offers a historical narrative for the large- a degenerating [research] programme until it is overtaken
scale features of the universe. Hence, as I put it: It is not by a rival and even after. What one must not do is to deny
informative to designate "the psychoanalyst's in- its poor public record. . . . It is perfectly rational to play a
terpretive stock-in-trade as being 'hermeneutic'" (p. 91). risky game: what is irrational is to deceive oneself about
It is hard to know what to make of Erdelyi's contention the risk." I appreciate that the resources available for
that "typically, the meanings that Freud uncovered were research are finite. Yet I believe that it would be an
not deterministic." Is he telling us that when Freud imprudent allocation strategy if the scientific community
provided explanatory motives, he did not say they were as a whole were to pull all of its research eggs into only
causally relevant? Or that the "meanings" he uncovered very few baskets, instead of hedging its bets (Feyerabend
were not held to be explanatory? To make his case, 1972). Since scientific inquiry is conducted by a commu-
Erdelyi declares: "When one establishes the meaning of nity of scientists, research policies or practices that would
an unknown word from its context, one does not establish indeed be irrational if adopted by that community as a
that the context has caused the unknown word." In the whole, or by a majority of it, need not necessarily be
latter case, however, it is semantic rather than explanato- irrational when only a certain gifted minority engages in
ry "meaning" that is at issue. In my argument against them. Thus, in my view, the heuristic rationality of the
Ricoeur's so-called "semantics of desire" (Introduction, further pursuit of research on a currently ill-faring theory
Section 3C) I was at pains to show that equating the does not conform to Kant's rule that the principle of ones
discernment of motives with the specification of the conduct must be such that one could consistently univer-
referents of linguistic signs is riddled with confusion. salize it to everyone. After all, in the hagiography of
Hence, how is my account contradicted or supplemented science, the encomium of prophetic genius has at times
by Erdelyi's comment that free associations provide "the been bestowed retroactively on individuals whose con-
contextual ecology" of meaning (though he grants that temporaries dismissed them as charlatans or cranks.
associations fail to validate Freud's explanatory hidden In this vein, Farrell (1981, p. 193) has pointed to a few
"meaning")? Similar objections apply to Storr's claim that historical episodes in physiology and physics to draw the
Freud's "expertise lay in semantics. " following moral for psychoanalysis: "Since scientific dis-
Like Woolfolk, I had emphasized that, "far from ques- covery so often startles us with surprise, it is unwise for
tioning . . . Freud's clinical theory," the hermeneutic anyone to bet on the contribution that psychoanalysis will

280 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


References/Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
ultimately make to the definitive account of human func- (1969) Illusory correlation as an obstacle to the use of valid psychodiagnostic
tioning which we may arrive at in the course of the next signs. Journal of Abnormal Psychology 74: 271-80. [RPG]
Cioffi, F. (1970) Freud and the idea of a pseudo-science. In: Explanation in
few centuries." Though I myself would not hazard a bet as the behavioural sciences, ed. R. Borger & F. Cioffi. Cambridge
to the value of the long-term explanatory residue from the University Press. [rACr, BVE]
Freudian legacy, I reject the Editor's comparison with Cook, T. D. & Campbell, D. T. (1979) Quasicxperimentation: Design and
the primitive fundamentalist doctrine of creationism, if analysis issues for field settings. Rand McNally. [RRH]
only because I find some empirical plausibility in the Cooper, I. S. (1974) The victim's always the same. Viking Press. [KP]
Dahl, H. (1972) A quantitative study of psychoanalysis. Psychoanalysis and
psychoanalytic theory of defense mechanisms, e.g. denial Contemporary Science 1: 237-57. [JMas]
and rationalization, reaction-formation, projection, and (1983) On the definition and measurement of wishes. In: Empirical studies
identification (Fancher 1973, pp. 217-23). of psychoanalytical theories, vol. 1, ed. J. Masling. Analytic
Instead of presuming to offer heuristic advice on the Press. [JMas]
Davidson, D. (1980) Essays on actions and events. Clarendon Press. [RLW]
basis of my evidential appraisal, I am content to leave the
Dement, W. C. (1960) The effect of dream deprivation. Science 131:1705-
betting to those inside and outside the psychoanalytic 08. 0AH]
community who forego immunizing strategies as regular Dilthey, W. (1961) Meaning in history, ed. H. P. Rickman. Allen and
tools of their trade, but whose expected utilities make Unwin. [MNE]
them willing to run the pertinent risks. (This is my reply D6rner, G. (1976) Hormones and brain differentiation. Elsevier. [MR]
to Ruse as well.) Eagle, M. (1983a) The epistemological status of recent developments in
psychoanalytic theory. In: Physics, philosophy and psychoanalysis, ed. R.
S. Cohen & L. Laudan. D. Reidel. [tarAGr]
Concluding remark. I did not respond to the very wel- (1983b) Interests as object relations. In: Empirical studies of
come commentaries by Eagle, Flanagan, Hobson, Pag- psychoanalytical theories, vol. I, ed. J. Masling. Analytic Press. [rAGr]
nini, and Reiser, all of which were highly gratifying and (1984a) Psychoanalysis and modem psychodynamic theories. In: Personality
supportive. I warmly thank these commentators as well, and the behavior disorders, revised edition, ed. N. S. Endler & J. McV.
Hunt. Wiley. ItarACr]
and trust that they will understand the necessity of
(1984b) Recent developments in psychoanalysis, A critical evaluation.
confining myself to points of criticism. McGraw-Hill. [rAGr]
(1986) Essay review of A. Grunbaum's Foundations of psychoanalysis.
NOTES Philosophy of Science 53, No. 1 (forthcoming). [rAGr]
1. For the definition of "clinical" and "extraclinical" data as Edelson, M. (1983) Is testing psychoanalytic hypotheses in the psychoanalytic
situation really impossible? The Psychoanalytic Study of the Child 38:61-
the terms are used throughout this symposium, see footnote 2 of
109. [MFR]
the pre'cis. (1984). Hypothesis and evidence in psychoanalysis. University of Chicago
Press. [rAGr, EE, ME, LL, GHP, MFR, DS]
Eissler, K. (1969) Irreverent remarks about the present and the future of
psychoanalysis. International Journal of Psycho-Analysis 50:461-
References 71. [taACr]
Emde, R. N. (1980) Toward a psychoanalytic theory of affect. In: The course
American Psychiatric Assn. (1980) Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental of life: Psychoanalytic contributions toward understanding personality
disorders, 3rd edition. [HHS] development. Vol. 1: Infancy and early childhood, ed. S. E. Greenspan
Assoun.,P.-L. (1981) Introduction a lipist&mologie freudienne. Payot. [AP] & G. H. Pollock. NIMH. [HK]
Bayer, K. (1981) Homosexuality and American psychiatry: The politics of Engel, G. & Reichsman, F. (in preparation) Trauma in infancy, personality
diagnosis. Basic Books. [FS] development and adult adjustment: A twenty-eight year longitudinal case
Beebe, B. & Stern, D. (1977) Engagement-disengagement and early object study. [LL]
experiences. In: Communicative structures and psychic structures, ed. N. Erdelyi, M. H. (1985) Psychoanalysis: Freud's cognitive psychology. W. H.
Freedman & S. Grand. Plenum Press. [JMas] Freeman. [MHE]
Bell, A. P. & Weinberg, S. (1978) Homosexualities - a study of diversity Erdelyi, M. H. & Goldberg, B. (1979) Let's not sweep repression under the
among man and women. Simon & Schuster. [MR] rug: Toward a cognitive psychology of repression. In: Functional
Bell, A. P., Weinberg, M. S. & Hammersmith, S. K. (1981) Sexual disorders of memory, ed. J. J. Kihlstrom & F. J. Evans. Erlbaum
preference: Its development in men and women. Indiana University Associates. [taAGr]
Press. I MR] Erikson, E. H. (1954) The dream specimen of psychoanalysis. Journal of the
Berlin, I. (1976) Vicoand Herder. Hogarth Press. [AS] American Psychoanalytic Association 2:5-56. [taAGr]
Bettelheim, B. (1982) Freud and man's soul. Random House. [MLW] Erwin, E. (1978) Behavior therapy: Scientific, philosophical and moral
Bieber, I., Dain, H. J., Dince, P. R., Drellich, M. G., Grand, H. G., foundations. Cambridge University Press. [EE]
Grundlach, R. H., Kremer, M. W., Rifkin, A. H., Wilbur, C. B. & (1985) Psychotherapy and Freudian psychology. In: Hans Eysenck: A
Bieber, T. (1962) Homosexuality: A psychoanalytic study. Basic psychologist searching for a scientific basis for human behavior, ed. S.
Books. [FS, MR] Modgil & C. Modgil. Falmer Press. [rAGr, EE]
Blatt, S. J. & Lerner, H. (1983) Investigations in the psychoanalytic theory of Eysenck, H. (1963) Uses and abuses of psychology. Penguin. [taAGr]
object relations and object representations. In: Empirical studies of (1982) The effects of psychotherapy: An evaluation. Journal of Consulting
psychoanalytical theories, vol. 1, ed. J. Masling. Analytic Press. [JMas] Psychology 16:319-24. [HJE]
Blatt, S. ]. & Ritzier, B. (1974) Thought disorder and boundary disturbances (1985a) The decline and fall of the Freudian empire. Viking Press. [HJE]
in psychosis. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology 42: 370- (1985b) Review of A. Grunbaum, The foundations of psychoanalysis.
81. [JMas] Behaviour Research and Therapy 23:89-90. [rAGr]
Block, J. (1971) Lives through time. Bancroft Books. [LL] Eysenck, H. & Wilson, G. D. (1973) The experimental study of Freudian
Brenner, C. (1982) The mind in conflict. International Universities theories. Methuen. [tarAGr, HJE, PK]
Press. [taAGr] Fancher, R. E. (1973) Psychoanalytic psychology. W. W. Norton. [tarAGr]
Breuer, J. & Freud, S. (1895) Studies in hysteria In: The standard edition of Farrell, B. A. (1961) Can psychoanalysis be refuted? Inquiry 4:16-36. [PK]
the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud, ed. J. Strachey, (1976) The criteria for a psychoanalytic interpretation. In: The philosophy of
1953-1974, vol. 2. Hogarth Press. [ME, HS] mind, ed. J. Glover. Oxford University Press. [BAF]
Brunswik, E. (1956) Perception and the representative design of psychological (1981) The standing of psychoanalysis. Oxford University Press. [rAGr,
experiments. University of California Press. [RRH] BAF]
Butler, S. F. & Strupp, H. H. (in press) Specific/nonspecific factors. Journal Feyerabend, P. K. (1972) Von der beschrankten Giiltigkeit methodologischer
of Consulting and Clinical Psychology. [HHS] Regeln. In: Neue Heftefur Philosophic (Heft 2/3), ed. R. Bubner, K.
Chapman, L. J. & Chapman, J. P. (1967) Genesis of popular but erroneous Kramer & R. Wiel. Cottingen. [rACr]
psychodiagnostic observations. Journal of Abnormal Psychology 72: 193- Fisher, C. (1978) Experimental and clinical approaches to the mind-body
204. [RPG] problem through recent research in sleep and dreaming. In:

THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 281


Re/erences/Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
Psychopharmacology and psychotherapy: Synthesis or antithesis?, ed. N. audio-recorded psychoanalytic sessions. International Universities
Rosenzweig & H. Griscom. Human Sciences Press. [JAH] Press. [DS]
Fisher, S. (1982) The scientific vitality of Freud's theories. Contemporary Glymour, C. (1980) Theory and evidence. Princeton University
Psychology 27:680-81. [taAGr] Press. [taAGr, ME]
Fisher, S. & Greenberg, R. P. (1977) The scientific credibility of Freud's (1982) Freud, Kepler and the clinical evidence. In: Philosophical essays on
theory and therapy. Basic Books. [rAGr, AC, EE, OJF, RPG, PK, Freud, ed. R. Wollheim & J. Hopkins. Cambridge University
JMas] Press. [EE]
ed. (1978) The scientific evaluation of Freud's theories and therapy. Basic Goleman, D. (1984) Do dreams really contain important secret meaning? Sew
Books. [JMas] York Times, July 10, p. C l . [JAH]
(1985) The scientific credibility of Freud's theories and therapy, paperback (1985) Pressure mounts for analysts to prove theory is scientific. New York
edition. Columbia University Press. [RPG1 Times (Science Times), January 15, pp. 15, 18. [rAGr]
Flader, D., Grodzicki, W. D. & Schroter, K. (1982) Psychoanalyse als Greenberg, R. P. & Fisher, S. (1983) Freud and the female reproductive
CesprSch. Suhrkamp Verlag. [HK] process: Texts and issues. In: Empirical studies of psychoanalytical
Flax, J. (1981) Psychoanalysis and the philosophy of science: Critique or theories, vol. 1, ed. J. Masling. Analytic Press. [rAGr]
resistance? Journal of Philosophy 78:561-69. [EE] Crunbaum, A. (1979) Is Freudian psychoanalytic theory pseudo-scientific by
Foulkes, D. (1966) The psychology of sleep. Scribners. [JAH] Karl Popper's criterion of demarcation? American Philosophical Quarterly
Fowler, C. A., Wolford, G. & Slade, R. (1981) Lexical access with and 16:131-41. [GHP]
without awareness. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 110: (1981) The placebo concept. Behaviour Research and Therapy 19:157-
341-62. [JMas] 67. [tarACr]
Frank, J. (1973) Persuasion and healing, revised edition. Johns Hopkins (1983) Freud's theory: The perspective of a philosopher of science. 1982
Press. [taAGr] Presidential Address to the American Philosophical Association (Eastern
Freud, S. (1892-1893) A case of successful treatment by hypnotism: With Division). Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical
some remarks on the origin of hysterical symptoms through "counter- Association 57:5-31. [tarACr]
will." In: The standard edition of the complete psychological works of (1984) The foundations of psychoanalysis: A philosophical critique.
Sigmund Freud, ed. J. Strachey, 1953-1974, vol. 1. Hogarth University of California Press. [taAGr, JMas, MAN, MR, FS]
Press. [MHE] (1986) The placebo concept in medicine and psychiatry. Psychological
(1904) The psychopathology of everyday life. W. W. Norton. [MAN] Medicine 16:19-38. [t&rACr]
(1905) Three essays on the theory of sexuality. In: The standard edition of (1987) Validation in clinical psychoanalysis: Disputations and appreciations.
the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud, ed. J. Strachey, Monograph in the Psychological Issues Series. International Universities
1953-1974, vol. 7. Hogarth Press. [MR] Press. [rAGr]
(1911) Psycho-analytic notes upon an autobiographical account of a case of Guttman, S. A., Jones, R. L. & Parrish, S. M. (1980) The concordance to the
paranoia (dementia paranoides). In: Sigmund Freud: Collected papers, standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud,
ed. Ernest Jones, vol. 3. Basic Books. [MAN] vol. 3. G. K. Hall. [rAGr]
(1915) A case of paranoia running counter to the psycho-analytical theory of Habermas, J. (1970) Zur Logik der Sozialwissenschaften. Suhrkamp
the disease. In: Sigmund Freud: Collected papers, ed. Ernest Jones, vol. Verlag. [taAGr]
2. Basic Booh. [MAN] (1971) Knowledge and human interests, trans. J. J. Shapiro. Beacon
(1917) Introductory lectures on psychoanalysis. In: The standard edition of Press. [taAGr, MNE, RLW]
the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud, ed. J. Strachey, (1973) Theory and practice. Beacon press. [taAGr]
1953-1974, vols. 15 and 16. Hogarth Press. [MHE, PLW] Hanson, N. R. (1958) Patterns of discovery. Cambridge University
(1922) Certain neurotic mechanisms in jealousy, paranoia and Press. [taAGr]
homosexuality. In: Sigmund Freud: Collected papers, ed. Ernest Jones, Hatterer, L. J. (1970) Changing homosexuality. McGraw-Hill. [FS]
vol. 2. Basic Books. [MAN] Hersen, M. & Barlow, D. (1976) Single case experimental designs.
(1896) The aetiology of hysteria. In: The standard edition of the complete Pergamon. [EE]
psychological works of Sigmund Freud, ed. J. Strachey, 1953-1974, vol. Hetherington, N. S. (1983) Just how objective is science? Nature 306:727-
3. Hogarth Press. [FC] 30. [GHP]
(1926) Inhibitions, symptoms and anxiety. In: The standard edition of the Hobson, J. A. & Hoffman, S. (1984) Picturing dreaming: Some features of the
complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud, ed. J. Strachey, 1953- drawings in a dream journal. Psychology of dreaming, CLUEB, Bologna,
1974, vol. 20. Hogarth Press. [LL] Italy, pp. 11-30. [JAH]
(1933a) New introductory lectures on psychoanalysis. In: The standard Hobson, J. A., Hoffman, S. A., Helfand, R. & Kostner, D. (1983) Dream
edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud, ed. J. bizarreness and the activation-synthesis hypothesis. Abstract and
Strachey, 1953-1974, vol. 22. Hogarth Press. [RPG] preliminary data presented at the Symposium on Dreaming, 4th
(1933b) New introductory lectures on psychoanalysis. W. W. International Congress of Sleep Research, Bologna, Italy, July
Norton. [MAN] 1983. [JAH]
(1935) An autobiographical study. Hogarth Press. [FC] Hobson, J. A. & McCarley, R. W. (1977) The brain as a dream state
(1937a) Analysis terminable and interminable. In: The standard edition of generator: An activation-synthesis hypothesis of the dream process.
the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud, ed. J. Strachey, American Journal of Psychiatry 134:1335-48. [taAGr, JAH]
1953-1974, Hogarth Press, vol. 23. [RPG] Holt, R. R. (1985) The current status of psychoanalytic theory. Psychoanalytic
(1937b) Constructions in analysis. In: The standard edition of the complete Psychology 2:289-315. [RRH]
psychological works of Sigmund Freud, ed. J. Strachey, 1953-1974, vol. Holzman, P. S. (1986) Psychoanalysis: Is the therapy destroying the science?
23. [BVE] Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association. In press. [rAGr]
(1923) Remarks on the theory and practice of dream interpretation. In: The James, W. (1967) The will to believe. In: The writings of William James, ed.
standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud, J. McDermott. Random House. [IS]
vol. 19, ed. J. Strachey, 1953-1974. Hogarth Press. [FC] Janet, P. (1889) De I'automatisme psychologique. Alcan. [MHE]
(1951) Letter to an American mother. American Journal of Psychiatry Jones, E. (1955) The life and work of Sigmund Freud, vol. 2. Basic
107:252. [FS] Books. [rAGr]
(1954) The origins of psychoanalysis. Basic Books. [taAGr] (1959) Editorial preface to S. Freud, collected papers, vol. 1. Basic
(1962) The question of lay analysis. In: Two short accounts of Books. [rAGr]
psychoanalysis. Penguin Books. [FC] Jouvet, M. (1962) Recherches sur les structures nerveuses et les mecanismes
Gauld, A. & Shotter, J. (1977) Human action and its psychological responsables des differentes phases du sommeil physiologigue. Archives
investigation. Routledge & Kegan Paul. [ACr] ltaliennes de Biologic 100:125-206. [JAH]
Geha, R. E. (1984) On psychoanalytic history and the "real" story of fictitious Kachele, H., Holzer, M., Heckmann, H. & Robben, H. (submitted) The
lives. International Forum for Psychoanalysis 1:221-91. [MNE] effects of trait anxiety on the capacity to free associate. [HK]
Ceschwind, N. (1974) Selected papers on language and the brain. Kales, A., Healey, E. S., Monroe, L. J., Bixler, E. O., Chamberlain, K. &
Reidel. [IS] Soldatos, C. R. (1981) Onset of insomnia: Role of life-stress events.
Ciere, R. (1975) The epistemological roots of scientific knowledge. In: Psychosomatic Medicine 43:439-51. [JAH]
Induction, probability and confirmation, ed. G. Maxwell & R. M. Kales, A., Hoedemaker, F. S., Jacobson, A. & Lichtenstein, E. L. (1964)
Anderson, Jr. University of Minnesota Press. [rAGr] Dream deprivation: An experimental reappraisal. Nature 204:1337-
Gill, M. & Hoffman, I. (1982) Analysis of transference. Vol. 2, Studies of nine 38. [JAH]

282 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2


References/Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis

Knzdin, A. (1981) Drawing valid inferences from case studies. Journal of psychoanalysis? Psychoanalysis and Contemporary Science 3:233-
Consulting and Clinical Psychology 49:183-92. [rAGr] 68. [ME]
Kazdin, A. E. & Wilson, C. T. (1978) Evaluation of behavior therapy. Luborsky, L., Sackheim, H. & Christoph, P. (1979) The state conducive to
Ballinger. [HJE] momentary forgetting. In: Functional disorders of memory, ed. J.
Klein, C. S. (1976) Psychoanalytic theory. International Universities Kihlstrom & F. Evans. Erlbaum Associates. [LL]
Press. [taACr, AC, VL] Luborsky, L., Singer, B., Hartke, J., Crits-Christoph, P. & Cohen, M. (1984)
Klerman, G. L. (1983) The efficacy of psychotherapy as the basis for Shifts in depressive state during psychotherapy: Which concepts of
psychotherapy. American Psychologist 38:929-34. [GLK] depression fit the context of Mr. Q's shifts? In: Patterns of change, ed. L.
Kline, P. (1972) Fact and fantasy in Freudian theory, 1st edition. N. Rice & L. S. Greenberg. Guilford Press. [LL]
Methuen. [PK, JMas] Luborsky L. & Spence, D. (1978) Quantitative research on psychoanalytic
(1981) Fact and fantasy in Freudian theory, 2nd edition. therapy. In: Handbook of psychotherapy and behavior change, ed. S. L.
Methuen. [tarAGr, EE, PK] Garfield & A. E. Bergin, 2nd edition, Wiley. [HK]
(1985) Kline replies to Erwin. In: Hans Eysenck: A psychologist searching Malan, D. H. (1976) Toward the validation of dynamic psychotherapy.
for a scientific basis for human behavior, ed. S. Modgil & C. Modgil. Plenum Press. [taAGr]
Falmer Press. [rAGr] (1979) Individual psychotherapy and the science of psychodynamics.
Kohut, H. (1959) Introspection, empathy, and psychoanalysis. Journal of the Butterworths. [BAF]
American Psychoanalytic Association 7:459-83. [rAGr] Malcolm, J. (1984a) In the Freud archives. Alfred A. Knopf. [GLK]
Kragh, U. & Smith, G. (1970) Percept genetic analysis. Lund (1984b) The patient is always right. New York Review of Books 31
Gleerups. [PK] (December 20): 13-18. [JMas]
Krasner, L. (1958) Studies of the conditioning of verbal behavior. Malinowski, B. (1927a) The father in primitive psychology. Norton. [IS]
Psychological Bulletin 55:148-70. [JMar] (1927b) Prenuptial intercourse between the sexes in the Trobriand Islands,
Labruzza, A. L. (1978) The activation-synthesis hypothesis of dreams: A N.W. Melanesia. Psychoanalytic Review 14:20-36. [IS]
theoretical note. American Journal of Psychiatry 133:1536-38. [JAH] Mandler, G. & Kaplan, W. K. (1956) Subjective evaluation and reinforcing
Lakatos, I. (1971) History of science and its rational reconstruction. In: PSA effect of a verbal stimulus. Science 124:582-83. [JMar]
1970, ed. R. C. Buck & R. S. Cohen. Reidel. [rAGr] Marcel, A. (1980) Explaining selective effects of prior context on perception:
Lambert, M. J., Shapiro, D. A., Bergin, A. E. & Berman, J. S. (in press) The The need to distinguish conscious and preconscious processes in word
evaluation of therapeutic outcomes. In: Handbook of psychotherapy and recognition. In: Attention and performance, vol. 8, ed. R. Nickerson.
behavior change: An empirical analysis, 3rd edition, ed. S. L. Garfield & Erlbaum Associates. [JMas]
A. E. Bergin. Wiley. [HHS] Marmor, J. (1955) Panel discussion on the validation of psychoanalytic
Laudan, L. (1977) Progress and its problems. University of California technique. Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association 3:496-
Press. [rAGr] 505. [JMar]
Lieberson, J. (1985) Review of The foundations of psychoanalysis: A (1968) New directions in psychoanalytic theory and therapy. In:
philosophical critique, by A. Griinbaum. New York Review of Books Modern psychoanalysis: New directions and perspectives, ed. J.
32:24-28. [AC] Marmor. Basic Books. [taAGr]
Loftus, E. (1980) Memory. Addison-Wesley. [taAGr] (1970) Limitations of free association. Archives of General Psychiatry
London, P. & Klerman, G. L. (1982) Evaluating psychotherapy. American 22:160-65. [tarAGr]
Journal of Psychiatry 139:709-17. [GLK] (1974a) Limitations of free association. In: Psychiatry in transition: Selected
Luborsky, L. (1967) Momentary forgetting during psychotherapy and papers ofjudd Marmor. Brunner/Mazel. [JMar]
psychoanalysis. In: Motives and thought, ed. R. Holt. (Psychological (1974b) Psychoanalytic therapy as an educational process. In: Psychiatry in
Issues, Monograph 18/19.) International Universities Press. [ME] transition: Selected papers ofjudd Marmor. Brunner/Mazel.
(1970) New directions in research on neurotic and psychosomatic symptoms. [JMar]
American Scientist 58:661-68. [LL] Masling, J. (1983) Empirical studies of psychoanalytical theories, vol. 1.
(1973) Forgetting and remembering (momentary forgetting) during Analytic Press. [tarAGr, HK, JMas]
psychotherapy. In: Psychoanalytic research, ed. M. Mayman. (1986) Empirical studies of psychoanalytic theories, vol. 2. Analytic
(Psychological Issues, Monograph 30.) International Universities Press. [rAGr]
Press. [EE, ME, JMas] Masling, J. & Schwartz, M. (1979) A critique of research in psychoanalytic
(1977) Measuring a pervasive psychic structure in psychotherapy: The core theory. Cenetic Psychology Monographs 100:257-307. [JMas]
conflictual relationship theme. In: Communicative structures and psychic Masson, J. M. (1984) The assault on truth: Freud's suppression of the
structures, ed, N, Freedman & S. Grand, Plenum Press, [LL] seduction theory. Farrar, Straus and Giroux. (GLK]
(1978) The relationship apperception paradigms test (RAP): A TAT-like Mayman, M. (1967) Object representations and object relationships in
method using actual narratives. Typescript. [LL] Rorschach responses. Journal of Projective Techniques and Personality
(1984) Principles of psychoanalytic psychotherapy: A manual for supportive- Assessment 31:17-24. [JMas]
expressive treatment. Basic Books. [HK, LL] McCarley, R. W. & Hobson, J. A. (1977) The neurobiological origins of
(in press) Recurrent momentary forgetting: Its content and context. In: psychoanalytic dream theory. American Journal of Psychiatry 134:1211-
Emotions and cognitive factors in unconscious processes, ed. M. 21. [taAGr, JAH]
Horowitz. University of Chicago Press. [LL] McCarley, R. W. & Hoffman, E. (1981) REM sleep dreams and the
Luborsky, L. & Auerbach, A. H. (1969) The symptom-context method: activation-synthesis hypothesis. American Journal of Psychiatry 138:904-
Quantitative studies of symptom formation in psychotherapy. Journal of 12. [JAH]
the American Psychoanalytic Association 17:68-99. [LL, JMas] McDonald, M. C. (1981) The dream debate: Freud vs. neurophysiology.
(1985) The therapeutic relationship in psychodynamic psychotherapy: The Science News 119 (June 13):378-80. [JAH]
research evidence and its meaning for practice. In: Psychiatry update: Merton, R. (1949) Social theory and social structure. Free Press. [rACr]
The American psychiatric association annual review, vol. 4, ed. R. Hales Money J. (1961) Sex, hormones, and other variables in human eroticism. In:
& A. Frances. American Psychiatric Press. [LL] Sex and internal secretions, ed. W. C. Young, 3rd edition. Williams &
Luborsky, L., Crits-Christoph, P. & Mellon, J. (in press) The advent of Wilkins. [MR]
objective measures of the transference concept. Journal of Consulting Motley, M. T. (1980) Verification of "Freudian slips" and semantic
and Clinical Psychology. [LL] prearticulatory editing via laboratory-induced spoonerisms. In: Errors in
Luborsky, L., Docherty, J., Todd, T., Knapp, P., Mirsky, A. & Gottschalk, linguistic performance: Slips of the tongue, ear, pen, and hand, ed. V. A.
L. (1975) A context analysis of psychological states prior to petit mal Fromkin. Academic Press. [taAGr]
seizures. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease 160:282-98. [ LL] Nagel, E. (1961) The structure of science. Harcourt, Brace, and
Luborsky. L., Mellon, J., Alexander, K., van Ravenswaay, P., Childress, A., World. [MR]
Levine, F., Cohen, K. D., Hole, A. V. & Ming, S, (1985) A verification Nisbett, R. E. & Ross, L. (1980) Human inference; Strategies and
of Freud's grandest clinical hypothesis: The transference. Clinical shortcomings of social judgment. Prentice Hall. [taAGr]
Psychology Review, 5:231-246. [LL] Nisbett, R. E. & Wilson, R. D. (1977) Telling more than we can know:
Luborsky, L., Mellon, J., van Ravenswaag, P., Childress, A. R., Levine, F. Verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review, 84:231-
J., Alexander, K., Crits-Cristoph, P., Cohen, K. D., Hole, A. V. & 59. [rAGr, JMas]
Ming, S. (1985) A verification of Freud's grandest clinical hypothesis: The Obemdorf, C. P., Creenacre, P. & Kubie, L. (1949) Symposium on the
transference. Clinical Psychology Review 5:231-46. [rAGr] evaluation of therapeutic results. Yearbook of Psychoanalysis 5:9-
Luborsky, L. & Mintz, J. (1974) What sets off momentary forgetting during a 34. [RPG]

THE'BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 283


Re/erences/Griinbaum: Foundations of psychoanalysis
Pack, R. (1984) Keats's letters: Laughter as autobiography. New England Searle, J. R. (1983): Intentionality. Cambridge University Press. [RLW]
Review and Bread Loaf Quarterly 7/2:175-91. [GHP] Segal, H. (1983) Kleinian analysis. In: States of mind, ed. J. Miller. Pantheon
Pagnini, A. (in press) La scienza dell'inconscio. Saggio su cpistemologia e Books. [rAGr, BAF]
psicoanalisi. Theoria. [AP] Seidman, E., ed. (1984) Handbook of social intervention. Sage
Perrez, M. (1979) 1st die Psychoanalyse eine Wissenschaft?, 2nd edition. Publications. [GLK]
Verlag Hans Huber. [rAGr] Sellars, W. (1961) The language of theories. In: Current issues in the
Peterfreund, E. (1983) The process of psychoanalytic therapy. Analytic philosophy of science, Ed. H. Feigl & G. Maxwell. Holt, Rinehart and
Press. [rAGr] Winston. [taAGr)
Popper, K. (1957) Conjectures and refutations. Basic Books. Rep. 1963 Shapiro, T. (1985) Psychoanalysis, philosophy and the public. Journal of the
Harper's Torch Books. [KP] American Psychoanalytic Association 33:5-9. [rAGr)
(1959) The logic of scientific discovery. Hutchinson. [taAGr, MAN] Sherwood, M. (1969) The logic of explanation in psychoanalysis. Academic
(1962) Conjectures and refutations. Basic Books. [tarAGr, MR] Press. [RPG, JMas]
(1962a) Conjectures and refutations: The growth of scientific knowledge. Silverman, L. H. (1976) Psychoanalytic theory: The reports of my death are
Routledge & Kegan Paul. [MAN] greatly exaggerated. American Psychologist 31:621-37. [rAGr, EE,
(1974) Replies to my critics. In: The philosophy of Karl Popper, Book I and JMas]
II., ed. P. A. Schilpp. Open Court. [tarAGr, IX, MAN] (1980) A comprehensive report of studies using the subliminal
(1974a) Intellectual autobiography. In: The philosophy of Karl Popper, ed. psychodynamic activation method. New York Research Center for Mental
P. A. Schilpp. Open Court. [MR] Health. [PK]
(1983) Realism and the aim of science, ed. W. W. Bartley, III. Rowman & (1983) The subliminal psychodynamic activation method: Overview and
Littlefield. [tarAGr, MAN, KP] comprehensive listing of studies. In: Empirical studies of psychoanalytical
P6tzl, O. (1917) The relationship between experimentally induced dream theories, vol. 1, ed. J. Masling. Analytic Press. [JMas]
images and indirect vision. Trans. J. Wolff, D. Rapaport, and S. Annin. Snyder, F. (1965) Progress in the new biology of dreaming. American Journal
Psychological Issues, 1960, Monograph 7, 40-120. [MHE] of Psychiatry 122:377-91. [JAH]
Pribram, K. H. & Gill, M. (1976) Freud's "project" re-assessed. Basic Socarides, C. (1968) The overt homosexual. Grune & Stratton. [FS]
Books. [IS] (1970) Homosexuality and medicine. Journal of the American Medical
Prigogine, I. & Stengers, I. (1984) Order out of chaos. Bantam Books. [HS] Association 212:1199-1202. [FS]
Prioleau, L., Murdock, M. & Brody, N. (1983) An analysis of psychotherapy Spence, D. P. (1969) Computer measurement of process and content in
versus placebo. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6:275-85. [taAGr] psychoanalysis. Transactions of the New York Academy of Science 31:
Putnam, H. (1984) Psychoanalysis: A Copernican Revolution or a 828-41. [JMas]
pseudoscience? Kos 10:3-6. [AP] (1982) Narrative truth and historical truth. W. W. Norton. [MNE, DS]
Quinn, P. L. (1972) Methodological appraisal and heuristic advice. Studies in (1983) Narrative persuasion. Psychoanalysis and Contemporary Thought
History and Philosophy of Science 3:135-49. [rACr] 6:457-81. [MNE]
Rachman, S. J. & Wilson, G. T. (1980) The effects of psychological therapy. Stephens, W. N. (1962) The Oedipus complex: Cross cultural evidence. Free
Pergamon. [EE, HJE] Press. [IS]
Rapaport, D. (1967) The collected papers of David Rapaport, ed. M. M. Gill. Strupp, H. H. (1977) A reformulation of the dynamics of the therapist's
Basic Books. [rAGr] contribution. In: Effective psychotherapy: A handbook of research, ed.
Reiser, M. F. (1984) Mind, brain, body: Toward a convergence of A. S. Gurman & A. M. Razin. Pergamon Press. [HHS]
psychoanalysis and neurobiology. Basic Books. [GLK, MFR] Strupp, H. H. & Binder, J. L. (1984) Psychotherapy in a new key: A guide to
Ricoeur, P. (1970) Freud and philosophy. Yale University Press. [taAGr] time-limited dynamic psychotherapy. Basic Books. [HHS]
(1974) The conflict of interpretations, ed. D. Ihde. Northwestern University Sulloway, F. (1979) Freud, biologist of the mind. Basic Books. [taAGr, MR]
Press. [taAGr, MNE] Suppe, F. (1984) Curing homosexuality. In: Philosophy and sex, revised
(1981) Hermeneutics and the human sciences, J. B. Thompson. Cambridge edition, ed. R. Baker & F. Elliston. Prometheus Books. [FS]
University Press. [taAGr, RLW] Timpanaro, S. (1975) The Freudian slip. New Left Review 91:43-56. [BVE]
Roche Reports: Frontiers of Psychiatry (1981) 11 (Nov. 15): 1, Is dream theory Tversky, A. & Kahneman, D. (1974) Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics
in need of an overhaul? 11 (Dec. 1): 4, Dream theory: The debate about and biases. Science 185:1124-31. [OJF]
revision continues. [JAH] van Ravenswaay, P., Luborsky, L. & Childress, A. (1983) Consistency of the
Rose, S. (1978) Mind-brain: Puccetti & Dykes' non-solution to a non-problem. transference in vs. out of psychotherapy. Paper presented at Society for
Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3:363-64. [MFR] Psychotherapy Research. Sheffield, England. [LL]
Rosenthal, R. (1966) Experimenter effects in behavioral research. Appleton- Vogel, G. W. (1978) An alternative view of the neurobiology of dreaming.
Century Crofts. [RPG] American Journal of Psychiatry 135:1531-35. [taACr, JAH]
Rubinstein, B. B. (1975) On the clinical psychoanalytic theory and its role in Von Eckardt, B. (1982) Why Freud's research methodology was unscientific.
the inference and confirmation of particular clinical hypotheses. Psychoanalysis and Contemporary Thought 5:549-74. [BVE]
Psychoanalysis and Contemporary Science 4:3-57. [RRH] (1985) Adolf Grunbaum: Psychoanalytic epistemology. In: Beyond Freud: A
(1978) Psychoanalytic hypotheses and the problem of their confirmation. In: study of modern psychoanalytic theorists, ed. J. Reppen. Erlbaum
Pathology and consciousness, ed. K. D. Irani, L. Horowitz & G. Myers. Associates. [BVE]
Haven Publishing. [rAGr] Wachtel, P. L. (1969) Psychology, metapsychology, and psychoanalysis.
Ruse, M. (1981) Medicine as social science: The case of Freud on Journal of Abnormal Psychology 74:651-60. [PLW]
homosexuality. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 6:361-86. [MR] (1977) Psychoanalysis and behavior therapy. Basic Books. [PLW]
Sackeim, H. A. (1983) Self-deception, self-esteem and depression: The Waelder, R. (1962) Review of Psychoanalysis, scientific method and
adaptive value in lying to oneself. In: Empirical studies of philosophy, ed. S. Hook. Journal of the American Psychoanalytic
psychoanalytical theories, vol. 1, ed. J. Masting. Analytic Press. [rAGr] Association 10:617-37. [taAGr]
Salzinger, K. (1959) Experimental manipulation of verbal behavior. Journal of Whewell, W. (1840) The philosophy of the inductive sciences. Parker. [MR]
General Psychology 61:65-94. [JMar] Whiting, B., ed. (1963) Six cultures. Wiley. [IS]
Schafer, R. (1976) A new language for psychoanalysis. Yale University (1953) Child training and personality: A cross cultural study. Yale
Press. [taAGr, MNE] University Press. [IS]
(1980) Narration in the psychoanalytic dialogue. Critical Inquiry 12:29- Wilson, E. O. (1978) On human nature. Harvard University Press. [MR]
53. [AP] Wollheim, R. (1971) Sigmund Freud. Viking Press. [IS]
Schepanck, H. (1974) Erb- und Umweltfaktoren bei Neurosen. Wolpe, J. & Rachman, S. J. (1963) Psychoanalytic evidence: A critique based
Tiefenpsychologische Untersuchungen an 50 Zwillingspaaren. Springer on Freud's case of Little Hans. In: Critical essays on psychoanalysis, ed.
Verlag. [HK] S. J. Rachman. Macmillan. [BVE]
(1984) Das Mannheimer Kohortenprojekt - Die PraValenz psychogener Wyatt, R. J., Termini, B. A. & Davis, J. (1970) Biochemical and sleep studies
Erkrankungen in der Stadt. Zeitschrift fur Psychosomatische Medizin und of schizophrenia: A review of the literature, 1960-1970. Schizophrenic
Psychoanalyse 30: 43-61. [HK] Bulletin 4:45-66. [JAH]
Scriven, M. (1959) The experimental investigation of psychoanalysis. In: Zamansky, H. S. (1958) An investigation of the psychoanalytic theory of
Psychoanalysis, scientific method, and philosophy, ed. S. Hook. New paranoid delusions. Journal of Personality 26:410-25. [rAGr]
York University Press. [JMas]

284 THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2

S-ar putea să vă placă și