JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
This content downloaded from 150.200.1.16 on Mon, 12 Mar 2018 19:26:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
THE PHILOSOPHY OF LINGUISTIC ANALYSIS AND THE
PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS
The main, if not the only proper business of philosophy is the detection of the
sources in linguistic idiom of recurrent misconceptions and absurd theories.'
Gone are the days when philosophers were trying to prove all sorts of things:
that the soul is immortal, that this is the best of all possible worlds and the
rest, or to refute, by 'irrefutable' argument and with relish, materialism, posi-
tivism and what not. Proof, refutation - these are dying words in philosophy.3
329
This content downloaded from 150.200.1.16 on Mon, 12 Mar 2018 19:26:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
330 PHILOSOPHY AND PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH
attempts by linguistic analysts in this area must cast doubt on the sound-
ness of the bold claims indicated above which have so often been can-
vassed by linguistic philosophers.
Linguistic analysts have now applied themselves to the problem of
universals for more than a quarter of a century, yet they seem not to
have dealt with the problem in a satisfactory way, although it is no doubt
true that most of the writings which bear on this problem contain points
of real worth. However, valuable as these contributions are, they seem
neither to answer nor to dispose of the problem to which theories of uni-
versals are advanced as solutions; and, more imnportantly, these contri-
butions seem not to admit of development along the lines of satisfactorily
dealing with the problem. It is impossible to consider all the contributions
of the linguistic analysts which bear on the problem of universals, and I
propose to confine my attention to three contributions, namely those of
Ryle (Systematically Misleading Expressions),4 Wittgenstein (family
names discussion in Philosophical Investigations 5 and Bambrough's
recent restatement of it 6) and Pears (Universals).7 It is not clear to what
extent Ryle in his discussion, and Wittgenstein in his, think of themselves
as making substantial contributions towards dealing with the problem of
universals - they may have felt that what they wrote was relevant but
only a small part of the whole story - but because they are so often
thought by others (e.g., Wittgenstein by Bambrough) 6 to have made
important contributions in this area, it is desirable that their contributions
be examined in conjunction with that of Pears. In any case, there is little
doubt that Ryle did at least think that he was disposing of one of the
main arguments of one of the most notable exponents of the doctrine of
real universals, Plato.
If we may then, for convenience, assume that Wittgenstein's discussion
of family names is part of his treatment of the problem of universals, we
may characterize all these three discussions; as discussions which proceed
by regarding the problem to which theories of universals are advanced
as answers, as the problem of naming i.e., the problem of explaining how
it is that names such as, abstract and common names function in the
language. Ryle speaks as if the theory of Forms was advanced by Plato,
at least partly and apparently chiefly, as an account of the way in which
This content downloaded from 150.200.1.16 on Mon, 12 Mar 2018 19:26:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
THE PHILOSOPHY OF LINGUISTIC ANALYSIS 331
This content downloaded from 150.200.1.16 on Mon, 12 Mar 2018 19:26:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
332 PHILOSOPHY AND PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH
It is strange and significant that hardly any of the words we use with the
exception of those called 'proper names' stand for particular things. They stand
for kinds of things, or for qualities, relations or actions, which do not exist
by themselves at all. But, while one sees plenty of particular tables or parti-
cular men, one never sees a table in general or a man in general. For what
then do such universal terms stand; and if they do not stand for anything in
the world, what is the point of using them? This is the problem of universals.
The natural answer to the question is that they stand for what a number
of particular things have in common, and it is this common element which
is called by philosophers a universal.
This content downloaded from 150.200.1.16 on Mon, 12 Mar 2018 19:26:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
THE PHILOSOPHY OF LINGUISTIC ANALYSIS 333
At first sight these seem to be on all fours with 'Jones merits reproof' and
'Smith has given himself the prize'. So philosophers, taking it that what is
meant by such statements as the former is precisely analogous to what is
meant by such statements as the latter, have accepted the consequence that
the world contains at least two sorts of objects, namely, particulars like Jones
and Smith, and universals like Unpunctuality and Virtue.'0
66: Consider for example the proceedings we call 'games'. I mean board-
games, card-games, ball-games, Olympic games, and so on. What is common
to them all? - Don't say: 'There must be something common, or they would
This content downloaded from 150.200.1.16 on Mon, 12 Mar 2018 19:26:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
334 PHILOSOPHY AND PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH
not be called 'games'' - but look and see whether there is anything common
to all. - For if you look at them you will not see something that is common
to all, but similarities, relationships, and a whole series at that. To repeat:
don't think, but look! - Look for example at board-games, with their multi-
farious relationships. Now pass to card-games, ---. Compare chess with
noughts and crosses. --- Think of patience. --- Think now of games like
ring-a-ring-a-roses ---. And we can go through the many, many other groups
of games in the same way; can see how similarities crop up and disappear.
And the result of this examination is: we see a complicated network of
similarities overlapping and criss-crossing: sometimes overall similarities, some-
times similarities of detail.
67: I can think of no better expression to characterize these similarities than
'family resemblances'; for the various resemblances between members of a
family --- overlap and criss-cross in the same way. - And I shall say: 'games'
form a family.5
This content downloaded from 150.200.1.16 on Mon, 12 Mar 2018 19:26:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
THE PHILOSOPHY OF LINGUISTIC ANALYSIS 335
This content downloaded from 150.200.1.16 on Mon, 12 Mar 2018 19:26:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
336 PHILOSOPHY AND PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH
And:
This content downloaded from 150.200.1.16 on Mon, 12 Mar 2018 19:26:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
THE PHILOSOPHY OF LINGUISTIC ANALYSIS 337
This content downloaded from 150.200.1.16 on Mon, 12 Mar 2018 19:26:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
338 PHILOSOPHY AND PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH
H. J. Mc CLOSKEY.
UNIVERSITY OF MELBOURNE.
This content downloaded from 150.200.1.16 on Mon, 12 Mar 2018 19:26:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms