Sunteți pe pagina 1din 7

The Four Principles of Biomedical Ethics: A

Foundation for Current Bioethical Debate


Dana J. Lawrence, DC, MMedEda

ABSTRACT
Objective: To provide an overview of the four principles originally developed by
Thomas Beauchamp and James Childress are now used in modern bioethical
decision-making and debate and to describe several challenges to their premier
status in bioethics.
Discussion: The four principles that form the core of modern bioethics discussion
include autonomy, beneficence, nonmaleficence and justice. The originators of
these principles claim that none is more important than another, yet challenges
have been laid against these principles on that basis as well as on other areas of
disagreement. This paper looks at the nature of the most significant of those
challenges.
Conclusion: The four principles have withstood challenge now for nearly 30
years and still form the basis for most decision making in both the research setting
and in clinical practice within the chiropractic profession. However, professional
understanding of the principles is not known and may provide a fertile area for
further investigation.
Key Indexing Terms: Biomedical Ethics; Chiropractic. (J Chiropr Humanit
2007;14:34-40)

INTRODUCTION both individuals have done a superb job in


revising this text in light of both modern
Over the years, the four principles that medical developments as well as directed
comprise the general working foundation for challenges against the form of ethics that has
modern American bioethics- beneficence, come to be known as principlism.
nonmaleficence, justice and autonomy- have
become associated with Drs. James One of the great critics of principlism is H.
Childress and Thomas Beauchamp. This is Tristram Engelhardt, author of a textbook
in part due to the long-term success of their that challenges principlism on philosophical
Principles of Biomedical Ethics1, now in its grounds arising from what Engelhardt
fifth edition and still highly influential. And describes as resulting from ethics occurring
in a content-free secular society2. What is
a. Associate Professor, Palmer Center for surprising is that it was Engelhardt himself
Chiropractic Research, 741 Brady Street, that initially proposed the concepts that led
Davenport, IA 52803. E-mail: to the development of principlism. As noted
dana.lawrence@palmer.edu
Paper submitted November 27, 2007, in revised
by Albert R. Johnson in his short chapter
form December 3, 2007, accepted December 4, that opens the textbook Belmont Revisited:
2007 Ethical Principles for Research with Human

Journal of Chiropractic Humanities 2007 © NUHS 34 Four Principles of Biomedical Ethics - Lawrence
Subjects3, Englehardt suggested three That misguided criticism seems to come first
principles as the basis for the developing and foremost from friend and critic
report: “respect for humans as free moral Engelhardt, who states that “authority for
agents, concern to support the best interests actions involving others in a secular
of human subjects in research, intent to pluralistic is derived from their
1,p122
assure that the use of human subjects of permission.” Given this, and the fact
experimentation will on the sum redound to that it is not possible to define what is good
the benefit of society.” Two of these would on anything but a secular content-free basis,
comprise essential planks of the Belmont all ethics flows first from the principle of
Report, though “respect for humans as free permission, or, as Beauchamp and Childress
moral agents” would later be transmuted have it, respect for autonomy. Feinberg
into the larger concept of “respect for notes that autonomy minimally requires the
autonomy,” later simply simplified to ability to decide for the self free from the
“autonomy.” While Engelhardt was offering control of others and with sufficient level of
his ideas, Johnson notes that Dr. Beauchamp understanding as to provide for meaningful
had drafted a paper on “Distributive Justice choice4. To be autonomous requires a person
and Morally Relevant Differences.” The to have the capacity to deliberate a course of
basic concept from Beauchamp was then action, and to put that plan into action. This
melded with the two accepted concepts from creates problems in the delivery of health
Engelhardt (resepect for persons, best care, especially when patients are comatose,
interest) to derive respect for persons, incompetent (whether due to age- i.e.,
beneficence and justice. Later, children, or to mental ability) or, for
nonmaleficence was separated theoretically example, imprisoned. And this is an issue in
from beneficence, giving the four principles the clinical research setting, especially as it
of today. relates to the provision of informed consent,
with its need for competence, disclosure,
This paper will look briefly at each of the comprehension and voluntariness.
principles and will then examine a selection
of current thinking and literature on these Beneficence
foundational principles of bioethics.
The common morality requires that we
Review of the Four Principles contribute to others’ welfare, perhaps as an
embodiment of the Golden Rule.
Autonomy Beauchamp and Childress suggest that there
are two principles of beneficence, positive
In examining each of the four principles, it beneficence and utility. The principle of
is interesting to note that while the 5th positive beneficence asks that moral agents
edition of Principle of Biomedical Ethics provide benefit, while the principle of utility
opens with a discussion of autonomy, the requires that moral agents weight benefits
authors take pains to state that “…our order and deficits to produce the best result. This
of presentation does not imply that this seems to beg the issue of a risk benefit
principle has priority over all other analysis, with nonmaleficence representing
principles. A misguided criticism of our the deficit/risk side of the equation and
account is that the principle of respect for beneficence representing the benefit/asset
autonomy overrides all other moral side of the equation. What cannot be so
considerations. This we firmly deny.”1,p.57 easily answered is how much benefit a moral

Journal of Chiropractic Humanities 2007 © NUHS 35 Four Principles of Biomedical Ethics - Lawrence
agent should provide, how to weigh that Justice addresses the questions of
benefit against risk, and then how to act distribution of scarce healthcare resources,
accordingly. In the sense of the four respect for people’s rights and respect for
principles as a method of ethics, the moral morally acceptable laws. Justice represents
agent is charged with determining the one of the thorniest issues that a country can
“good” in a specific scenario or situation, face, and in the United States is a source of
and then weighing that good against the risk ongoing concern and political rancor. At its
of specific actions. base, the fundamental question is, is there a
universal right to healthcare? If there is not,
The practice of beneficence is challenged by how are we to provide care for those who
the respect for autonomy. It is not possible for whatever reason cannot afford it; if there
to act without the permission of a free moral is, to what level is such care to be offered,
agent without that agent’s consent. It is for and how will it be funded? How can we
this reason that Engelhardt privileges the ensure fairness is the process? These are not
principle of permission. And determining question with obvious answers, and they
good is a personal decision, and the good lead to various ways of answering the
that a patient may determine can often differ question, from the distributive (those who
from that of his or her physician or need more get more, for example) to the
caregiver. Beneficence therefore must non-distributive (each public health center
overlap in part with autonomy; patients wish will get 1000 doses of a vaccine and will
to be provided various levels of information, provide them to whomever shows up first).
and may wish to select a particular direction
for their care because in their view that is
the greatest good. Because this may differ DISCUSSION
from the physician’s perspective, a tension
is created. Current Commentary

Nonmaleficence While principlism is, in my opinion, the


driving force in bioethics today, it is by no
In healthcare, it is not uncommon to see the means without challenges or critics. As
words primum non nocere, first do no harm. noted, Engelhardt is one chief critic2; he
While hardly original, it represents in just feels that one problem with principlism is
four words the ethical principle of that no one of the four principles has priority
nonmaleficence; we should not harm others. over any of the others, whereas he feels that
It is the negative side of beneficence, though the principle of permission forms the basis
some, such as David Thomasma5 see the two of today’s secular content-free ethics of
as more like two sides of the same coin. This agreement. But the bioethics literature has
also represents the risk side of a risk-benefit other papers both supporting and taking
analysis. In clinical research, this is issue with principlism. Here is an overview
addressed in the disclosure of risks of that literature.
associated with being a participant in a
research project. But again, the question as Gillon6 is credited with first introducing
to what to disclose- every possible risk that readers of the British Medical Journal to the
could potentially occur, or just the more four principles. One of the comments that
likely- is not clearly delineated. Gillon notes in his 1994 overview7 is that
Justice they are not designed to provide a method

Journal of Chiropractic Humanities 2007 © NUHS 36 Four Principles of Biomedical Ethics - Lawrence
for choosing, but rather provide a set of In the feldschrift issue of the Journal of
moral commitments, common language and Medical Ethics that many of the articles
a common set of moral issues. It is cited here come from, AV Campbell
necessary to view these in the context of contrasts principlism with virtue ethics9. He
scope in order to properly utilize the describes how virtue ethics asks the
principles. By scope, he means scope of question, “how should one live?” by
application, or who to what or whom we focusing on the character of the moral agent.
owe these moral obligations. For example, Beauchamp and Childress to address the
how much beneficence is owed to a given positive aspects of virtue ethics in their text1,
person? How much help are we to offer? He but also offer critiques of it, with a caveat
notes that we have a special relation with out that virtue cannot be, in their estimation, a
patients, in the sense that we have an prior measure of morality. The example
obligation to help our patients. At the same Campbell offers as a criticism of virtue
time, he notes problems with questions ethics is to suppose that Eichmann went
about who falls within the principle of about exterminating entire populations of
respect for autonomy and what is the scope Jews with a sincere desire, but Campbell
of a “right to life.” Finally, he makes the also states that to think that nothing more
observation that a four principles approach than character matters is simplistic and
to ethics does not offer a method for dealing wrong. To him, virtue ethics and principlism
with conflicts between the principles. But are partners, not opponents; they
quite obviously Gillon supports a complement one another. I find this a
principlistic approach. compelling argument, for I feel that
principlism is a set of tools, and like most
John Harris8 is on the other side of this tools have to used where appropriate; they
debate. He favors what he calls can be used by all approaches to ethics:
“unprincipled ethics,” feeling that the four Kantianism, utilitarianism, and yes, virtue
principles are neither the beginning nor end ethics.
of ethical reflection. He claims that the use
of the four principles leads to a sterile McCarthy offers a discussion that asks
bioethics, and uniformity of thought in the whether we have to choose between
ethics community. The principles are neither principlism or narrative ethics10. The schism
sufficient nor always a useful way of he discusses is between the use of principles
approaching ethics. Instead, he feels that and the use of communication, and
principles become nothing more than a McCarthy refuses to advantage one
checklist, and he offers two scenarios which approach over the other. McCarthy provides
he feels show up the shortcomings of this a fine overview of principlism, describing
approach, one addressing commerce in each of the four principles in detail and
organ transplantation, and a second modeling how Beauchamp and Childress
addressing genetic manipulation producing develop moral theory from it, using
germline transmissible genetic enhancement. reflective equilibrium, specification,
I will not provide the details of his reciprocal weighing, testing, revision and
arguments due to space, but he provides a judgment. He then contrasts this to
compelling discussion demonstrating how narrativism, whereby the foundational
principlism may not be an effective means concept is the uniqueness of the moral
of addressing these concerns. situation, the life story of the persons
involved and the need to create and maintain

Journal of Chiropractic Humanities 2007 © NUHS 37 Four Principles of Biomedical Ethics - Lawrence
dialogue. McCarthy notes the unique Macklin14 examines the same cases offered
strengths and weaknesses of each approach, by Gillon, and while supporting the use of
and suggests that each uses a different set of the four principles, she also offers several
skills, those of principlism requiring us to cautions about how they are or may be used.
examine norms while those of narrativism First, she simplifies the case regarding the
requiring a far greater reliance on intuition Jehovah’s Witness by commenting on how
and literary/critical skills. While different, the principles might be used: respect for
they are not antithetical and can work persons (autonomy) mandates respecting the
together to better illuminate ethics patient’s desires even if they appear to
challenges. unfavorable, while nonmalificence suggests
that honoring the request to not act would
Returning to Gillon, he offers a set of create a harm, and beneficence would
scenarios to demonstrate how the principles suggest that benefits are not being
are used for analysis11. Gillon is himself a maximized. Without being ordered, which
leading advocate for this approach, though principle takes precedence? How can harm
he notes that challenges to principlism be assessed, when considering the sincere
comes from sources as varied as feminist beliefs of a person who espouses that faith
ethics, narrative ethics, virtue ethics and and for whom the transfusion might lead to
other forms of ethics. In this paper, he negative metaphysical implications?
provides four scenarios for others to discuss. Macklin uses the principles to argue both
sides of this dilemma and offers compelling
Beauchamp himself weighs in12. His paper arguments both supporting and denying the
is a summary of his influential textbook1, use of the transfusion. Macklin finds that
but he emphasizes here the idea of context is often the single factor leading to a
considered judgments, which he equates to decision and that the inability to know
Rawls’ concept of reflective equilibrium13, accurate predictions of good or bad
as well as the concept of specification, a consequences will always be a challenge
process he uses to reduce indeterminateness when using this approach.
of general norms to strengthen them as
action guides. All of this leads to coherent Dawson and Garrard15 challenge two
ethics, or the reduction of inconsistency. contentions made by Gillon. One is that
Beauchamp then uses the illustrative cases respect for autonomy has a special position
of a Jehovah’s Witness refusing a blood within the hierarchy of the principals (which
transfusion for himself, or for his child. By were seen as co-equal historically), and the
using the principles, he is able to other is cultural variation is a significant
demonstrate why one could allow the refusal factor in how we manufacture moral
in the first case, but not in the second; in judgments. In fact, the idea that autonomy
fact, he strongly argues that in the second has some sort of precedence over other
case it is required to overrule the parent, not principles is very much in line with the
just permitted. Finally, he applies the writing of Engelhardt2. But Gillon feels that
principals to the question of allowing kidney autonomy is morally precious and that the
sales, and finds that it is not always possible other principles require us to respect
to argue that sale of a kidney is never autonomy. This does not convince Dawson
allowable. This is based on a close reading and Garrard, who feel that no principle can
of the principals, applied to a thorny come before any other. They deconstruct the
question. argument in favor of privileging autonomy,

Journal of Chiropractic Humanities 2007 © NUHS 38 Four Principles of Biomedical Ethics - Lawrence
noting that if it promotes other principles it action guides. They are in conflict with one
is actually subservient to them. They also another, and seem to lack, in an ironic use of
argue that to say that respect for autonomy is the term against its authors, coherence. They
above the other principles leads to a number provide their own unified moral theory, as
of possible interpretations of what that developed in their text.
means. The four principles are prima facie
in nature; that they are reduces the potential Gillon himself offers his thoughts after
for moral absolutism. reading through the attacks, comments and
papers that make up the feldschrift issue of
The idea that cultural variation is important the Journal of Medical Ethics21. I will not
is also offensive to Dawson and Garrard. delineate his comments here, but he offers
This suggests a relativism at play that can commentary on each paper and its
lead to different judgments in different arguments, in essence getting the last word.
cultures. Dawson and Garrard argue instead He finds that no one has been able to
for what they term “contextualism” that dislodge his view of principlism, and he
would then limit the potential problems that comes away feeling that it can withstand
arise with relativism; it preserves the even withering criticism. He argues that the
importance of the four principles in ethics use of the principles mitigates the potential
decision-making. They decry the potential for both moral relativism and moral
problem that is created by what they view as imperialism. And he refuses to back down
Gillon advancing a form of moral on the primacy of respect for autonomy,
imperialism. They favor a moral objectivism even in the face of Beauchamp disagreeing
instead. with him. To Gillon, principlism is not just
morally relevant in health care, but is the
Others have criticized principlism as well. foundation for a global bioethics.
Holm16 suggests that principlism underplays
the importance of both beneficence and
justice, and that the methodology used in CONCLUSION
principlism is inadequate. Lustig17 feels that
there is a divide between theory and Perhaps there is no greater signifier of the
practice, that it fails to offer a systematic primacy of principlism in modern bioethical
account for the four principles and that it is debate than the level of attacks and
agnostic in approach. Beauchamp himself challenges it undergoes and withstands. Its
writes about what he terms “alleged importance for research ethics is undeniable,
competitors” of principlism: impartial rule and its use on the clinical setting drives
theory, casuistry and virtue ethics, and much of modern ethics debates. However, it
argues that these are consistent with is not known how much the use of the four
principlism and not adversarial to its principles drives the ethical decisions that
methods18. Finally, Gert and Clouser offer a need to be made in the chiropractic research
compelling argument against principlism, as setting, nor how conversant members of
they indicate in their seminal paper of various institutional review or ethics boards
199019. This critique later led to their text20, are with regard to them. This suggests that
which also argues against principlism while this area itself may be a fertile one for study.
advancing its own approach to ethics. They
view principlism as failing to function as That there are other approaches to these
claimed, lacking theory and failing to act as debates signals that the field is vital and

Journal of Chiropractic Humanities 2007 © NUHS 39 Four Principles of Biomedical Ethics - Lawrence
alive, but much of this debate grows out of part series in Br Med J from 1985;290:1117
understanding the implications of the to 1986;292:543-545.
principles in action. And in a postmodern 7. Gillon R. Medical ethics: four principles
society, that other, perhaps radically plus attention to scope. Br Med J
different, approaches to ethics exist should 1994;309:184. Available from:
hardly be surprising. Taken together, this is www.bmj.com/cgi/content/full/309/6948/18
an indication that modern bioethics is more 4.
than a series of arguments about irresolvable 8. Harris J. In praise of unprincipled ethics. J
issues such as abortion. Principlism provides Med Ethics 2003;29:303-306.
a working set of tools that are used every 9. Campbell AV. The virtues and vices of
day in modern health care. the four principles. J Med Ethics
2003;29:292-296.
This paper provides an overview of, and 10. McCarthy J Principlism or narrative
commentary about, the four principles ethics: must we choose between them. Med
developed by Beauchamp and Childress and Humanit 2003;29:65-71.
which remains the driving force in modern 11. Gillon R. Four scenarios. J Med Ethics
bioethics. Given its privileged position, 2003;29:267-268.
exposing the chiropractic profession to the 12. Beauchamp TL. Methods and principles
concepts the principles entail is be a worthy in biomedical ethics. J Med Ethics
endeavor, all the more useful because of the 2003;29:269-274.
profession’s growing research and clinical 13. Rawls J. A theory of justice. Cambridge:
enterprises. Harvard University Press; 1971.
14. Macklin R. Applying the four principles.
REFERENCES J Med Ethics 2003;29:275-280.
15. Dawson A, Garrard E. In defence of
1. Beauchamp TL, Childress JF. Principles moral imperialism: four equal and universal
of biomedical ethics, 5th ed. New York City, prima facie principles. J Med Ethics
NY: Oxford University Press; 2001. 2006;32:200-204.
2. Engelhardt HT. The foundations of 16. Holm S. Not just autonomy- the
bioethics, 2nd edition. New York City, NY: principles of American biomedical ethics. J
Oxford University Press; 1996. Med Ethics 1995;21:323-324.
3. Johnson AR. On the origins and future of 17. Lustig BA. The method of
the Belmont Report. In: Childress JF, Meslin “principlism”: a critique of the critique. J
EM, Shapiro HT, editors. Belmont revisited: Med Philos 1992;17:487-510.
ethical principles for research with human 18. Beauchamp TL. Principlism and its
subjects. Washington, DC: Georgetown alleged competitors. Kennedy Inst Ethics J
University Press; 2005. 1995;5:181-198.
4. Feinberg J. Harm to self. In: The moral 19. Clouser KD, Gert B. A critique of
limits of criminal law. New York, NY: principlism. J Med Philos 1990;15:219-236.
Oxford University Press; 1986. 20. Gert B, Culver CM, Clouser KD.
5. Thomasma DC. A philosophy of a Bioethics: a systematic approach. New York
clinically-based medical ethics. J Med City, NY: Oxford University Press; 2006.
Ethics 1980;6:190-196. 21. Gillon R. Ethics needs principles- four
6. Gillon R. Philosophical medical ethics. can encompass the rest- and respect for
Chichester; Wiley, 1986- derived from a 26- autonomy should be “first among equals.” J
Med Ethics 2003;29:307-312.

Journal of Chiropractic Humanities 2007 © NUHS 40 Four Principles of Biomedical Ethics - Lawrence

S-ar putea să vă placă și