Sunteți pe pagina 1din 9

Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 48 (2014) 12e20

Contents lists available at ScienceDirect

Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and


Biomedical Sciences
journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/shpsc

Vital forces and organization: Philosophy of nature and biology in Karl


Friedrich Kielmeyer
Andrea Gambarotto
IHPST, 13, Rue du four, 75006 Paris, France

a r t i c l e i n f o a b s t r a c t

Article history: The historical literature on German life science at the end of the 18th century has tried to rehabilitate
Received 4 April 2013 eighteenth century vitalism by stressing its difference from Naturphilosophie. Focusing on the work of
Received in revised form Karl Friedrich Kielmeyer this paper argues that these positions are based on a historiographical bias and
17 July 2014
that the clear-cut boundary between German vitalism and Naturphilosophie is historically unattested. On
Available online
the contrary, they both belong to the process of conceptual genealogy that contributed to the project of a
general biology. The latter emerged as the science concerned with the laws that regulate the organization
Keywords:
of living nature as a whole. The focus on organization was, at least partially, the result of the debate
Romantic life sciences
Philosophy of nature
surrounding the notion of “vital force”, which originated in the mid-eighteenth century and caused a
Vital forces shift from a regulative to a constitutive understanding of teleology.
Karl Friedrich Kielmeyer Ó 2014 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling
Gottfried Reinhold Treviranus

When citing this paper, please use the full journal title Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences

In the course of the last thirty years a considerable body of Göttingen by a well-connected group of biologists after receiving its
scholarship has examined the life sciences that arose in Germany first formulation in Kant’s Critique of the Power of Judgment in 1790.
at the end of the eighteenth century. This literature has shown In the second part of this work, Kant sees teleology as a necessary
that previous dismissals of this tradition, assumed to be infected tool to understand fundamental features of living beings such as
with a pathological imagination, were unwarranted. Yet the in- functions and development. He also considers it as a mere heuristic
terpretations of the period have not always been consistent with principle, not as a constitutive character of organized bodies. Lenoir
each other, and have often been characterized by vagueness. claims that Blumenbach was the first naturalist who accepted the
Generally speaking, the scholarly debate has focused on the his- Kantian understanding of teleological principles and organized it as
torical and conceptual relationship between three elements: (1) a structured research program. This program was first developed by
Kant’s philosophy of biology, (2) the biological vitalism developed his most distinguished students Karl Friedrich Kielmeyer, Alex-
at the Göttingen medical school by Blumenbach and his students ander von Humboldt and Gottfried Reinhold Treviranus. This group
Kielmeyer, Link, Treviranus, and Reil, and (3) the Naturphilosophie of naturalists is thereby addressed as “Göttingen School.” The
of Schelling, Oken and Carus. distinctive approach practiced at Göttingen derived from ideas
In his pioneering studies Timothy Lenoir (1978, 1980, 1981, fashioned principally by Blumenbach during the 1780s and 1790s.
1982) argues that, although the life sciences developed in Ger- He synthesized some of the best elements of Enlightenment
many in the late eighteenth century have been dismissed as an era thought on biology, particularly Buffon, Linnaeus and Haller, in
dominated by empty speculation, they were in fact the result of terms of a view of biological organization found in the writings of
a coherent research program. This program was developed in Kant (Lenoir, 1981, 115). The disregard of this “Kantian” tradition in
life sciences has, for Lenoir, both theoretical and historical grounds.
The main issue is the assumption that only reductionist models are
E-mail address: andrea.gambarotto@gmail.com. capable of generating a quantitative account of natural phenomena.

http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsc.2014.07.007
1369-8486/Ó 2014 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
A. Gambarotto / Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 48 (2014) 12e20 13

Nevertheless, the idea that biological organization is not reducible 1. Theories of vital forces before Kielmeyer: from Haller and
to the laws of physics and chemistry is fully compatible with the Wolff to the Göttingen School
fidelity to quantitative rigor as a touchstone of scientific explana-
tion. According to Lenoir, the “vital-materialism” of the Göttingen It is a striking fact that the great majority of scholarly works
School accepted this challenge and developed a “teleo-mechanical” dedicated to the vital-materialism of the Göttingen School dealt
research program based on the Kantian distinction between with the issue using the vocabulary of Lakatos. The idea of a Kante
constitutive and regulative understandings of teleology. On the Blumenach “teleo-mechanical” program for biology, formulated for
other hand, ascribing constitutive character to teleology, i.e. the first time by Lenoir, is still endorsed in recent studies (Bach,
considering it as a real feature of living bodies, the Natur- 2001; Dupont, 2007; Schmitt, 2006). This notion, however, is
philosophen exceeded the boundaries of science in the direction of inadequate for understanding the transformations that led to the
empty speculation. From the historical point of view, the main birth of biology at the beginning of the nineteenth century. The idea
reason for disregarding the Göttingen tradition is the assumption that the Critique of the Power of Judgment provides a research pro-
that it was just another example of speculative philosophy of na- gram for biology can in fact be criticized not only by emphasizing
ture. Lenoir believes this assumption is proven wrong by textual the divergence of Kant and Blumenbach, but also by showing that
evidence, since both Kielmeyer and Treviranus openly criticize Kant’s attention to biological issues was not the result (at least not
Naturphilosophie. Thirty years later, Hans Peter Reill (2005) unifies primarily) of scientific concerns, but of strictly transcendental
the vital-materialism of the Göttingen School with the Montpellier questions (Huneman, 2012; Zuckert, 2007). On the other hand,
tradition of Bordeu, Barthez and Ménuret under the general label of however, it is equally true that Kant dealt with biological matters in
“Enlightenment vitalism.” Once again, the pivotal point of the at least three different respects: (1) the relationship connecting the
argument is the distinction of this tradition from Romantic Natur- notion of Naturzweck to modern epigenesis, since the process of
philosophie. Both accounts share a common argumentative pattern. embryogenesis seems to presuppose its result (the adult organism)
Their fundamental aim is to rehabilitate eighteenth century and be directed towards its realization (Huneman, 2007; Zammito,
vitalism by showing that its research program can be considered in 2007); (2) the problem of functions, which cannot be explained
“naturalized” terms. Their most important concern is then to mark without referring to final causes (the structure of a bird, for
the difference of this program from Naturphilosophie, which is example, is apparently grounded in the purpose of allowing flight:
considered the metaphysical and anti-naturalist program par Illetterati, 2008); and (3) the difference between Naturbeschreibung
excellence. In what follows, I argue that these positions are based on and Naturgeschichte, i.e. the discussion of the epistemological status
a historiographical bias, using the work of Karl Friedrich Kielmeyer of natural history as descriptive cataloguing or causal explanation
as a basis for my argument. of varieties (Fischer, 2007; Sloan, 1979, 2006).
Scholars have already argued that the alleged agreement This discussion is not the result of a research program but of a
between Kant and Blumenbach was based on a substantial conceptual shift taking place in the last decades of the eighteenth
misunderstanding of the respective conception of teleology: century. It has been pointed out (Cheung, 2006) that during the
Blumenbach ignores the Kantian distinction between constitutive eighteenth century the word “organism” generally refers to a spe-
and regulative principles and conceives of the Bildungstrieb as a cific form of order that could apply to different kinds of entities
goal-directed drive proper to all organized beings (Richards, such as plants and animals, but also artifacts. At the end of the
2000). For this reason the Lenoir thesis can no longer serve as eighteenth century, the term became a generic name for individual
point of departure for the reconstruction of the German life sci- living entities, by around 1830 it became a recurrent technical term
ences of this period (Zammito, 2012). Resting upon these studies I in the emerging biological disciplines. Theories and models of
will develop my argument by showing that the clear-cut boundary living beings developed until the late eighteenth century must
between the vital-materialism advocated by Lenoir and Natur- therefore be defined as pre-biological. With regard to this frame-
philosophie is historically unattested. I will thereby position work, even Kant makes no exception: although the critique of
myself in accordance with Richards (2002), but use a different teleological judgment has in different ways been regarded as an
argumentative strategy. I will argue that Naturphilosophie is part endeavor towards the scientific foundation of biology (Löw, 1980;
of the same process of conceptual genealogy that contributed to Marcucci, 1972; Philonenko, 1982; Zumbach, 1984), Kant’s posi-
the emergence of a general biology as a unified science. The latter tion on this issue is actually much more cautious (Ginsborg, 2001,
became possible only after the determination of its proper object 2006; Goy & Watkins, 2014; Guyer, 2005; Illetterati, 2010;
had reached completion. The object in question is “organization” McLaughlin, 1989, 1990; Zammito, 1992). According to Kant,
as a specific property of living nature. Biology emerged as the biology may indeed never be regarded as a proper science, as the
science that deals with the laws regulating organization, both of consideration of living beings implies reference to teleological
single natural bodies and of living nature as a whole. I will try to principles, and the use of these principles has only regulative
show that the focus on the concept of organization was at least character. On the other hand, from the late eighteenth century, the
partially the result of the debate on the notion of “vital force” term “biology” began to appear in the works of several naturalists,
originated in mid-eighteenth century Germany. This debate led to the most important of which is the monumental Biologie, oder
a functional interpretation of the scala naturae according to which Philosophie der lebenden Natur für Naturforscher und Ärzte (1802e
higher levels of organization display a greater number of vital 1822) by Gottfried Reinhold Treviranus. What happened between
functions than lower ones. I will develop my argument as follows. 1790, the year of publication of the third Critique, and 1802, when
I will first provide a sketch of the different theories of vital forces Treviranus used the term “biology” as the title of a scientific work
formulated in Germany before Kielmeyer, with a particular concerned with living nature as a whole? I wish to argue that the
attention to Haller, Wolff and Blumenbach. I will then take into answer lies in the shift involving the modern semantics of orga-
detailed account the lecture on organic forces held by Kielmeyer nization. The birth of biology as a field is better understood in
in 1793 to verify the meaning of the claim of it being the first genealogical terms, considering the way through which “organi-
systematic program of a general biology. Finally, I will show how zation” became a specific object of natural science. In what follows I
the framework put forward by Kielmeyer was coherently devel- will argue that this process is intertwined with the conceptual
oped by Schelling and Treviranus. history of the notion of “vital force.”
14 A. Gambarotto / Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 48 (2014) 12e20

The undisputed father of the notion of vital force is Albrecht von famous debate between them (Roe, 1981). The second edition of the
Haller. He joined the Göttingen faculty in 1737 and from 1747 work, Theorie von der Generation (1764), is not merely a German
directed the Göttingische Anzeigen der gelehrten Sachen, a Journal translation and restatement of the theory, but it also entails a
founded in 1739 which hosted important scientific debates in detailed attack on the preformationist views of Haller and Bonnet.
embryology and physiology. Eighteenth century physiology pays It was followed by a major response in Haller’s Elementa physi-
tribute to Newton’s natural philosophy. It assumes the notion of ologiae corporis humani (1766). The pivotal concept of the work is
“irreducible properties” of matter whose laws of expression had to the notion of “essential force” (vis essentialis). According to Wolff,
be formulated without speculating on the cause of their origin generation cannot be conceived without the existence of a peculiar
(Wolfe, 2014). This concept is combined with the notion of fiber, force inherent to epigenetic development. Plants and animals arise
used since the end of the seventeenth century by Francis Glisson for from raw material, an amorphous and undifferentiated substance.
his study on the contraction of muscles. Especially in his 1672 work Within it, vesicles (vesicuale) and vessels (vasae) are formed as
De natura substantiae energetica, Glisson was the first to bind the spherical cavities filled with liquid. Vesicles then become organs
notion of fiber to the specific property of irritability. Living fiber is that appear one after the other. According to this model, the
flexible, extensible, resistant, elastic and irritable, i.e. it has a radical streaming of liquid and its tendency to coagulate were sufficient to
force activated by external or internal stimuli, and causes the explain the formation of plants and animals without reference to
change of shape and all remaining vital phenomena. For Glisson, preexistent structures. The tendency of vegetable and animal em-
the irritable fiber provides a general overview of a character of the bryos to coagulate is always caused by the vis essentialis. Each part
living body, not a concept defining a specific property. As Boer- secretes the other after its own formation in a gradual process of
haave’s student, in the general context of a mechanistic physio- self-organization. As each part begins to solidify, it becomes orga-
logical framework, Haller gave specific attention to fibers. The first nized and acquires vessels and vesicles produced by the movement
appearance of irritability can be found in a note on Haller’s own of fluids into the new parts. In higher animals, the first structure to
edition of Boerhaave’s Praeselectiones academica, where he remarks solidify is the spinal chord, from which all other organs are sub-
that the heart keeps beating after it has been extracted from the sequently produced. These processes are caused by the essential
animal’s body. It is however in the dissertation De partibus corporis force, which Wolff deems possible to postulate on the basis of
humani sensilibus et irritabilibus (1752) that he further develops the observational evidence: “the essential force along with the ability
notion. Haller claims to have proven by animal experiments that of nutrient fluid to solidify constitutes the sufficient principle of all
only the muscular fiber possesses the ability of contraction, which vegetation [i.e., development] both in plants and in animals” (Wolff,
he defines as “irritability”, which was responsible for movement. 1759, x 242).
From this property he clearly distinguishes “sensibility,” which is French vitalism developed only marginally with respect to the
responsible for sensual impressions and inherent only to nerves problem of epigenesis and more directly on Haller’s physiological
and parts furnished with them. He thereby challenges the tradi- model. The works of Bordeu on glands, for example, led him to
tional mechanical (mainly Boerhaavian) model on three main attempt a direct characterization of functional factors. Based on the
points. First, he postulates a force inherent in the muscular fiber idea of the sensibility of parts, he developed a model of organiza-
and independent of the nerves and the soul. Second, he concep- tion grounded on the integration of elementary organs. The inte-
tually and physically separates the two properties of movement gration of complex structures is the emergent effect of elementary
and sense perception. Third, he establishes a strict correlation be- processes that can be reduced to phenomena of tonicity and reac-
tween structure and function not on the level of elementary par- tivity. Such a notion of the organic machine was criticized by Bar-
ticles but of compounding structures, i.e. muscular and nervous thez, who instead tried to establish that the phenomenon of vital
fibers (Monti, 1990). The explicit connection made between struc- mobility, like those of sensibility and of “sympathies,” translates the
ture and function poses a question concerning the purposiveness of regulative activity of a vital principle heterogeneous from structural
the structure. Haller never doubted that heart, muscles, intestines and mechanical conditions (Duchesneau, 1982, 361e430). In Ger-
etc. had the structure needed to perform their function. Even the many, on the other hand, the groundbreaking relevance of Haller’s
deformed organs of the so-called “monsters” were arranged in such physiology was measured up to Wolff’s compelling arguments. The
a way as to most easily fulfill their duty. This teleological postula- idea of a structuring order operating in the epigenetic process
tion underlays Haller’s physiological arguments and allows produced a vitalist modification of the Hallerian model in which the
the correlation of structure and function. Haller establishes the idea of self-organization played a seminal role.
correlation of muscle-irritability and nerve-sensibility on what he Johan Friedrich Blumenbach (1752e1840) studied in Göttingen
considers a sufficient experimental basis. However, as a prefor- and graduated in 1775. He was appointed extraordinary professor
mationist, the teleological arguments, for Haller, are based on the of medicine and inspector of the museum of natural history in
assumption that objects are formed in accord with intelligent Göttingen in 1776 and ordinary professor in 1778. Like Haller he
design. It was not nature itself, but God who arranged structures, was in the habit of illustrating his theory by a careful comparison of
laws and functions. As shown by his embryological positions, Haller the animal functions of man with those of other animals. Rejecting
envisages nature as a machine that runs according to prescribed Haller’s preformationism while simultaneously proposing a teleo-
laws of mechanics. For this reason, Haller’s physiology does not logical agent as sufficient reason for the resulting order, Blu-
break with Boerhaavian mechanism, but is rather a full acknowl- menbach’s physiology operates as a significant variation on the
edgment and elaboration of non-reductionist elements in the late Hallerian model. In his Institutiones physiologicae (1787), Blu-
conception of his teacher (Steinke, 2005, 94e96). The integration of menbach uses the notions of “force” and “drive” to indicate five
this physiological theory on vital properties into a framework of fundamental properties of living matter: (1) formative drive (nisus
self-organization was a consequence of modern epigenesis. formativus), which is responsible for developmental organization
Georges Canguilhem has argued that research concerned with and remains active in the organized body throughout its life; (2)
the origin of organic models in biology would have to begin with contractility (vis cellularis), which is responsible for the contraction
the detailed consideration of Caspar Friedrich Wolff’s doctoral of mucosa; (3) irritability (vis muscolaris), which is responsible for
dissertation Theoria Generationis (1759) (Canguilhem, 1962, 13). A the contraction of muscles; (4) vitae propriae, which is responsible
copy of the dissertation was sent to Haller, triggering his review in for the contraction of specific organs such as the iris or the fallopian
the Göttingische Anzeigen von gelehrten Sachen, which started the tube; and (5) sensibility (vis nervea), which allows perceptive
A. Gambarotto / Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 48 (2014) 12e20 15

functions (Blumenbach, 1828, 27e33). The peculiarity of this species. Kielmeyer’s lecture Über die Verhältnisse der organischen
schema is the presence of the formative drive (nisus, Trieb) as Kräfte untereinander in der Reihe der verschiedenen Organisationen,
somehow opposed to the other forces (vis, Kraft). While in fact die Gesetze und Folgen dieser Verhältnisse (1793) is the first and most
Blumenbach associates the notion of force to a blind agent, he important example of this program, which has been properly
considers the nisus as a goal-directed drive responsible for the defined as “physiological systematics” (Schmitt, 2006).
specific form of the single organism. In the famous paper Über den
Bildungstrieb (1791) he argues that in the unformed matter of an 2. Vital forces and organization: Kielmeyers’s lecture as a
organized body is active “a peculiar lifelong drive” which “pushes it program for a general biology
towards its determined shape.” This drive is “clearly different from
all the other vital forces of living bodies (contractility, irritability, Karl Friedrich Kielmeyer (1765e1844) began his studies at the
sensibility etc.) and from all the universal forces of bodies in gen- Karlsschule in Stuttgart and furthered his education at the Univer-
eral.” It is “the first important force for every generation, nutrition sity of Göttingen between 1786 and 1788 under Blumenbach’s su-
and reproduction, and that can be called formative drive (Bil- pervision. He returned afterward to Stuttgart where in 1792 he was
dungstrieb, nisus formativus) in order to distinguish it from other appointed professor of chemistry and zoology. He published little in
vital forces” (Blumenbach, 1791, 32e33). Here Blumenbach refers to his lifetime, but on February 11th 1793 he delivered a famous
“a perspicacious physiologist, Caspar Wolff,” who “assumed plenary lecture in honor of the sixty-fifth birthday of Duke Carl
another force for the growth of animal and plants, that he calls vis Eugen of Württemberg. In this lecture Kielmeyer attempted to
essentialis. If one knows it only by hearsay, he could confuse it with demonstrate, on the basis of inductive evidence, that peculiar
my nisus formativus.” According to Blumenbach, however, the dif- teleological laws regulate the distribution of vital functions
ference is clear as soon as one reads the definition of the vis throughout the animal kingdom. Concerned with a general theory
essentialis given in the Theoria generationis. For Wolff the vis of animal organization, Kielmeyer’s lecture has been regarded as
essentialis is merely the force by mean of which the nutritive ma- the first Systemprogramm of biology (Bach, 2001; Kanz, 1994).
terial is driven through the plant or the animal. This is for Blu- In his lectures on comparative zoology, held in Stuttgart be-
menbach only one aspect of the formative drive. The essential force tween 1790 and 1793, Kielmeyer defines this program as Physik der
can be observed among less formed outgrows (like tree strains) Tierreichs (physics of the animal kingdom). This discipline had to
where no definite formative drive is to be found. On the other hand, account for: (a) the number of organs in the machine of the animal
the essential force can be very weak in poorly nourished organic kingdom, the number of animal forms, and the laws according to
bodies, whose formative drive is unscathed (Blumenbach, 1791, which they are divided into different groups Additionally, the
39e41). An explicit discussion between Wolff and Blumenbach discipline must consider the causes, consequences or purposes of
took place in 1789 in a publication titled Zwo Abhandlungen über die these classification (Zwecke); (b) the relative position of the organs
Nutritionskraft. The volume includes a long paper, Von der eigen- in the machine of the animal kingdom, the division of the animal
tümlichen und wesentlichen Kraft der vegetabilischen sowohl als auch kingdom into groups upon the earth (geography) according to
der animalischen Substanz. This treatise was written as a response to different characters and laws, causes and effects of the differences
and published along with two essays on similar topics by Blu- according to different groups; (c) the interrelated formation of or-
menbach and Carl Friedrich Born. Both being selected for first-place gans in the animal kingdom, the gradation of animals and affinities
honors in a competition held by the St. Petersburg Academy of in their formation generally as well as according to groups, and the
Sciences for the best essay on the nature of the “nutritive force.” In laws, causes, and effects of this gradation; (d) changes in the animal
this sense, Blumenbach’s vitalist physiology represents, as it were, kingdom and its groups, and the developmental history of the animal
the point of intersection between Haller’s physiological model and kingdom in relation to the epochs of the earth and those probable
Wolff’s theory of generation. He multiplies the vital properties of for our solar system, which are symbolized by the parabola; (e)
the former calling them “forces” and includes the vis essentialis of changes which the animal kingdom and its groups undergo
the latter under the name of “formative drive.” The latter displays a repeatedly throughout all epochs, and the life of the machine of the
teleological character that was extraneous to Wolff. The Bildung- animal kingdom or its physiology, which is symbolized by the circle
strieb does not only represent the vital principle of organic self- (Kielmeyer, 1938, 28e29).
construction, but also the sufficient reason of the resulting vital This program never resulted in an extensive work, but the Rede
forces that exercise their action in the different organs. From this held in 1793 constitutes an incisive outline. Like Blumenbach,
point of view, the Bildungstrieb supplies an explanation for the Kielmeyer considers natural purposiveness as a proper feature of
different functions present in the living body. living bodies, which he explicitly refers to as “organizations”: “let
In conclusion, Haller’s “animated anatomy” opened a new field us grant that nature had no intention in establishing this artful
of investigation concerned with the vital properties of fibers. He juxtaposition of appearances in time, that effects and their conse-
thereby adopted a conception of organic functions that relies on the quences were to form no goals that she had wished to achieve,”
specific properties of elementary structures. Blumenbach modifies nonetheless “we still must confess that the chain of effects and
this framework on the basis of Wolffian epigenesis, elaborating an causes in most cases seems like a chain of means and ends to us and
organic model characterized by a multiplication of those proper- that we would find it advantageous for our reason to assume such a
ties. Like Haller, Blumenbach understood the vital forces as cor- chain” (Kielmeyer, 1793, 6). As stressed by Richards, Kielmeyer’s
relatives of specific physiological properties, but their reciprocal remarks are here grammatically cast as counterfactual sub-
relation was understood as forming a functionally integrated junctives. They grant that nature might not have intrinsic purposes
whole. The main result of the notion of Bildungstrieb is the and that the search for higher goals might appear to be a mere
conceptualization of an agent of organic formation modeled on fantasy. These concessions, however, display a direct reference to a
Wolff’s vis essentialis. In Blumenbach’s physiological formulation Kantian argument. In the third Critique, Kant maintains that any
this was a model for the distribution of the different vital forces in inductions focused on organic processes would lead to poetic
the individual living body. This model was employed by Kielmeyer phantasizing (dichterisch zu schwärmen), as one conjures up tele-
to account for the distribution of vital functions in the animal ological principles supposedly governing those processes. Kiel-
kingdom. This gave rise to a peculiar line of inquiry in animal meyer’s point is rather that such inductions nonetheless convince
taxonomy based on the different vital forces displayed by various us, and properly so, that nature is teleologically structured
16 A. Gambarotto / Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 48 (2014) 12e20

(Richards, 2002, 242). Organic forces must therefore be regarded as feet of some spiders, for example, have been observed moving for
teleological principles which make organisms different from more than seven days after being removed from the body. On the
nonliving matter. On these premises, the questions Kielmeyer other hand, the majority of animals displaying such enduring irri-
wished to address were: Which forces gathered in most in- tability tend to be slower in at least some of their movements. The
dividuals? What are the reciprocal relationships between these movements of most amphibians are weak and their hearts beat
forces in different kinds of organizations? And according to which more slowly than those in warm-blooded animals. Finally, Kiel-
laws are these relationships modified in the series of different or- meyer points out that most animals with long-lasting irritability
ganizations? On the basis of Blumenbach’s schema, Kielmeyer are precisely those in which the multiplicity of sensations has been
distinguishes five forces: (1) sensibility, or the ability of the nerves greatly limited. The opposite is the case for warm-blooded animals,
to retain representation; (2) irritability, or the ability of muscles and whose irritability is utterly temporary, but whose muscles are far
other organs to respond to stimulation through contraction; (3) more articulated. Based on these observations, Kielmeyer formu-
reproductive force, or the ability of organization to restore injured lates a second law: “irritability, estimated according to the
parts of a creature or to produce a new individual of like kind; (4) permanence of its manifestations, increases as much as speed,
secretive force, or the ability to deliver different fluids to the right frequency and variety of these same manifestations, and the variety
places; and (5) propulsive force, or the ability to move fluids through of sensations decreases” (Kielmeyer, 1793, 23). The lack of duration
vessels. The original Hallerian forces, sensibility and irritability, is thereby compensated for by frequency, variety, speed and better
remain unaltered, while the formative drive is considered as a force sensibility.
among the others (not as principle of organization) corresponding The reproductive force, claims Kielmeyer, is the most universal
to reproductive functions. The vis cellularis and the vitae propriae and distributed force among organizations, and could be defined as
are replaced by secretive and propulsive force. This difference is the force that distinguishes them from other products of nature.
irrelevant since it involves the least important forces of both Since it is the most universal among organizations, a greater variety
schemas. The latter are, in fact, not even taken into account in of manifestation is to be expected. However, for Kielmeyer, this
Kielmeyer’s lecture, while several examples are provided with re- amazing variety fits under a few simple laws. The number of
gard to the others. First, Kielmeyer deemed necessary the estab- offspring produced at any one time by warm-blooded quadrupeds
lishment of the criterion according to which the magnitude of is between one and fifteen. This number increases among birds, and
various forces had to be measured and compared. Frequency of more so among amphibians and fishes. Insects, worms and plants
effects at equal times, plurality and magnitude of the resistance to generate with greater frequency than all the previous classes. This
other forces, or the permanence of the effect under equal condi- pattern suggests a general decrease of reproductive faculties from
tions were considered particularly suitable for the task. complex mammals to simpler organizations. Higher organizations
Sensibility is the first organic force he takes into account. generate a small amount of larger individuals in a longer time than
Empirical evidence, argues Kielmeyer, shows that the faculty to lower ones. A third law is also formulated: “the reproductive force,
receive different sensations decreases across the series of organi- the number of new individuals that will be created in a given place,
zations from higher mammals to lower classes (Kielmeyer, 1793, increases as much as the magnitude of what is to be produced; or
12e13). Among quadrupeds, birds, snakes and fishes, all sense or- more generally, the dimension of individual product, as it appears
gans still display high perfection; however, among insects, the after birth, decreases” (Kielmeyer, 1793, 28). Animals with lower
auditory and olfactory organs are largely gone. Among worms, the fertility are also those of larger size and are more extensively
brain and most of the nervous system found in other animals is not developed at birth. They are also those for which generation takes
present, and a single organ collects all sensory stimuli. In plants, more time. To form an elephant, for example, nature strains for two
this receptivity to impressions is present only in very obscure years, while it only takes a few weeks to generate a rat. Kielmeyer
traces. It is also evident, however, that when a sense organ is lost, thus formulates a more specific and universal version of the law:
which effectively decreases the multiplicity of sensation, the the more the reproductive force is manifested in a certain place by
remaining senses are finer and more elaborate. Insects and worms, the number of new individuals, the smaller the size of the body of
mostly deprived of eyes and ears, have a significantly more devel- such individuals; the simpler is the constitution of their bodies, the
oped sense of touch than monkeys and humans. The malfunc- lower is the time it takes to form them in the body of the parents
tioning eyes of moles seem to be compensated for by the (Kielmeyer, 1793, 30).
development of finer paws and noses. Other animals’ ocular These are, for Kielmeyer, the laws that regulate the distribution
insensitivity similarly results in the sharpening of auditory and of the vital forces in the animal kingdom, which he generalizes as
olfactory organs. From these observations, Kielmeyer draws a law: follows: “the faculty of sensation is gradually replaced in the series
“the multiplicity of possible sensations decreases in the series of of organizations from irritability and reproductive force and finally
organizations as much as the ease and finesse of remaining decreases the irritability of the latter [organizations]; the more the
sensation increases” (Kielmeyer, 1793, 19). The lack of multiple first increases the less is the other. Furthermore, there is little
kinds of sensations among lower animals is thus balanced by the accord between sensitivity and reproductive force; the greater one
sophistication of those remaining. of these forces is at the time of initial development, the more the
After his discussion of sensibility, Kielmeyer provides empirical other is neglected” (Kielmeyer, 1793, 35). In general, then, the fac-
observations on irritability. Nature has placed major differences not ulties of sensation, widely developed in higher animals, gradually
only in relation to the multiplicity of its manifestations, but also to decrease in lower classes and are endowed with great irritability.
the duration and frequency of their effects under the same condi- Equally, in lower classes (insects, worms), irritability is gradually
tions. Among warm-blooded quadrupeds and birds, all traces of replaced with reproductive force. The simplicity of these laws
irritability are extinguished as a consequence of the separation of becomes clearer after the realization that “the forces divided
the body from the sensory apparatus or the division of individual among the various organizations are also those under which the
limbs from the trunk. By contrast, the manifestations of this force division of forces took place among the different individuals of the
are almost indestructible in cold-blooded animals: frogs continue same species, even in the same individual at different phases of
hopping after decapitation, and turtles continue moving for days development” (Kielmeyer, 1793, 36). At the beginning of their
after experiencing fatal heart trauma and/or amputation of the development, humans and birds are both similar to plants. They are
head. Similar phenomena are observed among fish and insects: the mainly endowed with reproductive force, only in the following
A. Gambarotto / Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 48 (2014) 12e20 17

developmental phases does their irritability increase. Thereafter, which I refer the reader to the lecture of prof. Kielmeyer on this
senses hatch sequentially, according to the order in which they subject that already appeared in 1793, a lecture from which in
appeared in the series of organizations. The faculty of irritability the years to come a new epoch of natural history is to be ex-
thereby replaced by the faculty of representation, or at least in its pected” (Schelling, 2000, 252e253).
most immediate material organ. These far-reaching conclusions
have been interpreted as the first formulation of the principle of
The concrete realization of this program is found in the Erster
recapitulation, which will have extraordinary implications for the
Entwurf eines System der Naturphilosophie (1799), where different
theory of species evolution (Coleman, 1973, 1977; Richards, 1992).
animal classes are conceived of as the result of different relations of
This will be indeed one of the most appealing and long-lived doc-
the various vital forces. They differ from each other not only in their
trines of Naturphilosophie and transcendental morphology. The
material composition, but in the relation and proposition of their
core of this principle stresses the fact that many animals, as they
constitutive forces among themselves. According to Schelling, a
develop embryologically, temporarily manifest structures which
species is the expression of a certain proportion of primary func-
closely resemble those exhibited by the adult forms of species
tions. The continuity of organic functions throughout the animal
lower down in the scale of animal organization. The detailed
kingdom forms a universal organism. Schelling establishes a
explication of the law was carried out by Johan Friedrich Meckel
comparative physiology of organic functions, which endeavors to
(1781e1833) in Germany and by Étienne Serres (1786e1868) in
establish the various degrees and proportions of essential forces
France. It has often been referred to as the MeckeleSerres Law of
belonging to different organisms. In fact, every organism displays a
parallelism, in order to distinguish it from the later biogenetic law
specific proportion of reproductive force, irritability and sensibility.
formulated by Ernst Haeckel (1835e1919). In my view, however,
It is primarily defined not by its external form, but by the particular
this is neither the most important aspect nor the actual contribu-
proportion of forces active within it. Its form and organs will follow
tion of the lecture. Its meaning can be properly understood only
from the disposition of these forces, each one prominent in a
within the genealogical process connecting the various theories of
different class. Plants, for example, have a preponderance of
vital forces in the second half of the eighteenth century. Blu-
reproductive force while displaying no sensibility. Mammals have a
menbach’s contribution was the unification of Wolff’s vis essentialis
preponderance of sensibility but can generate few offspring and
with Haller’s physiological notions of sensibility and irritability,
they do not display regenerative features which are frequent in
which created a model of animal economy characterized by mul-
amphibians. Each organism is itself nothing else than “the collec-
tiple vital forces. The latter were responsible for different functions
tive expression for a multiplicity of actions (Aktionen), which
in the living body conceived as an organized whole. Kielmeyer
mutually limit themselves to a determinate sphere.” This conflict of
made use of a similar model to explain the distribution of vital
actions will express itself in certain functions. The variety of the
forces, not however in the individual body, but rather in the entire
animal kingdom results from the variation in proportion of these
living nature. Animal organization is thereby understood as the
functions. The latter have inverse relationships to one another, such
result of the organization of the “great machine of the organic
that as the one increases the other necessarily decreases. Functions
world.” In this sense, Kielmeyer’s Rede addresses the problem of a
must be reciprocally opposed to maintain balance, “which in itself
general biology, a unified scientific field concerned with the laws
already corresponds with the concept of an organism.” In a single
that regulate the organization of living nature as a whole through
organism any one of these functions could be dominant while the
its internal relations.
rest are present in a lower degree. On account of this opposition, it
is impossible for those forces to unify in the same part. The or-
3. Philosophy of nature and biology after Kielmeyer:
ganism in which they are unified must be divided into many single
Schelling and Treviranus
individual parts performing different functions. Through their
collective actions, these parts must produce the single organism:
The pivotal role of Kielmeyer’s Rede for the elaboration of the
“they would relate simultaneously to the whole organism as cause
conceptual framework of Schelling’s Naturphilosophie has been
and effect of its activity. That which so relates itself to the organism
already addressed by scholars (Bach, 2001; Schmitt, 2006, 2007).
(as a whole) is called an organ.” Functions must relate to different
The first work with biological relevance among Schelling’s writings
organs, such that “the more the multiplicity of the functions in-
is Von der Weltseele (1798), whose subtitle is “A hypothesis of higher
creases in the organic domain of nature, the more complexly the
physics for the explanation of the universal organism.” This venture
system of the organs develops” (Schelling, 2001, 114e115). This
is a development of the physiological framework put forward by
model conceives “the continuity of organic functions as principle of
Kielmeyer, with a peculiar emphasis on the functional lexicon. The
organization” (Schelling, 2001, 116, emphasis added). These pas-
animal kingdom is thereby understood as a balanced system of vital
sages are almost quotes from Kielmeyer’s Rede.
functions corresponding to different animal classes:
This Schellinghian interpretation of Kielmeyer is adopted by
“Since it is undeniable that in living beings takes place a series of Gottfried Reinhold Treviranus (1766e1837), who also studied with
functions (Stufenfolge der Funktionen), as nature opposed irri- Blumenbach in Göttingen, where he got his doctorate degree in
tability to the animal process, and sensibility to irritability, and 1796. In the first volume of his Biologie, oder Philosophie der lebenden
so arranged an antagonism of forces that keep each other Natuur für Naturforscher und Ärzte (1802e1822), Treviranus con-
reciprocally into balance, as while one increases, the other de- ceives of nature as a “universal organism” where no change can
creases and vice versa, so one will be led to the thought that all occur to a part without influencing the whole. He thereby criticizes
the functions are only branches of the same force, and that for Schelling for the assumption of a “world soul” as explanatory ground
example a natural principle, that we must assume as the cause of for the ongoing activity of the universe (Treviranus, 1802, 33). This
life, emerges in them only as in its own phenomena, just as without fact may lead to endorse Lenoir’s position. This critique, however,
doubt one and the same universally spread principle manifests must be read in context. Not many pages before criticizing Schelling,
itself in light, electricity etc. Since great naturalists reached the Treviranus addresses in fact Alexander von Humboldtdhis senior at
same result, it is possible to boldly trust this idea. In particular, it Göttingen and also Blumebach’s studentdwhose definition of the
is confirmed through the consideration of the progressing vital force he considers “even more useless” than that provided by
development of organic forces in the series of organizations, about Stahl (Treviranus, 1802, 19). Shortly after he criticizes Kant for his
18 A. Gambarotto / Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 48 (2014) 12e20

mechanistic conception of matter (Treviranus, 1802, 27, 39) and from external stimuli to be the origin of life. Such principle was the
explicitly agrees with Schelling that the reduction of fundamental world soul (Weltseele) of the platonists, Cudworth’s plastic nature,
forces to “attraction” and “repulsion” makes it impossible to explain or Blumenbach’s Bildungstrieb. Chemical principles can explain the
the “specific qualities and forms” of living nature (Treviranus, 1802, elements of which living bodies are composed. One can also inquire
54). The fact that Treviranus criticizes Schelling’s assumption of a “all the traces of electricity, magnetism and all further physical
world soul while accepting his idea of nature as a universal organism forces in the living body and pursue them as far as possible. The
proves that he considered him as much a reliable discussant as all result of this investigations will always be that those agents in the
other major figures of late eighteenth-century science. animal and vegetable organism are as much active as outside of it,”
Other passages of the Biologie provide further evidence for this but that “the actual secret of living nature will not be disclosed.” The
claim. In the fourth volume Treviranus maintains that life is “the nourishment of living bodies is in fact regulated by specific laws of
product of the interaction between excitable substances and the the formative drive that cannot be reduced to the laws of physics or
external exciting powers.” It is vain to look for an explanation of life chemistry (Treviranus, 1814, 631). The realm of living organisms is
if we do not assume that its emergence “is grounded on a principle different from those of mechanism and chemical affinities and re-
to which must be ascribe a certain degree of independence from quires a reference to teleological principles.
external influences, of self-determination to effectiveness, an There are two main tenets behind these passages. The first is
analogous of spontaneity” (Treviranus, 1814, 626). This principle is that all vital forces (sensibility, irritability, reproductive force) are
relevant with respect to the procreation of species, which was hard branches of the same fundamental force. This fundamental force is
to explain for most biological systems. The unexplainable aspect the excitability of a living organism in relation to the external
lies in the fact that this phenomenon displays teleological features environment. The second is that this relation is characterized by a
which appear irreducible to a mechanistic framework. Plants that certain degree of spontaneity which is peculiar to living beings. The
vegetate under unfavorable conditions rush in producing flowers latter must be understood as a higher level of organization with
and fruits before they pass away, so that from their seed germinates regard to mechanism and chemical affinity and can be explained
again a healthy progeny. Vegetation behaves as if it was the product only in reference to the principle of purposiveness. Both of these
of a spiritual principle: “precisely this similarity between the action tenets are drawn from Schelling’s Naturphilosophie.
of a spiritual being and the effects of the vital principle points to Lenoir considers Treviranus to be the most paradigmatic reali-
some kind of spontaneity of the latter.” Monsters are another class zation of the Göttingen program. With the Biologie the “transcen-
of phenomena in which this effect of life is expressed. The internal dental biology” of the Göttingen School had concluded its
parts of these bodies are “purposefully organized only as much as formative period. According to Lenoir, Treviranus succeeded in
the degree of external deformity allows, in all of them is expressed pulling together various aspects of the program that had been
a tendency of the formative drive (Bildungstrieb) to produce a under intense discussion beginning in 1750 with Haller’s trans-
possibly complete organism also under unfavorable conditions” lation of Buffon’s Histoire naturelle. Treviranus synthesizes these
(Treviranus, 1814, 627). These phenomena involve both the onto- conceptual elements into what he describes as a dynamic theory of
genesis of single organisms and “the formative levels (Bildungs- organic nature, which he attempts to ground in an encyclopedic
stufen) climbed by living nature as a whole.” The kind, as the overview of biological research from mid-eighteenth century on-
individual, has its periods of formation, bloom and death, “the ward. Lenoir does not disregard the relationship between this
whole as the single is in a state of eternal transformation” conceptual framework and Naturphilosophie. Through careful
(Treviranus, 1814, 628). Treviranus maintains that these trans- reading of Schelling’s early philosophy of nature in conjunction
formations cannot be reduced to a mere modification of the effect with the critical edition of his correspondence he deems it possible
exerted by cosmical influences and must rather have their ground to show that while in Leipzig, in the period during which he
in the laws that regulate life: “the vital force (Lebenskraft) of every devoted himself almost exclusively to acquiring background in
individual, inasmuch it expresses itself as formative force (Bil- natural science, Schelling concentrated on the works of the Göt-
dungskraft) is the outflow of the common fundamental force tingen School, particularly Lichtenberg, Blumenbach and Kiel-
(Grundkraft) that, as the light broken with a prism, splits itself into meyer. Through direct personal contact with Pfaff and Eschenmaier,
countless rays and produces the plurality of kinds and individuals Schelling gained also an in depth knowledge of Kielmeyer’s Physik
of the kingdom of living organisms” (Treviranus, 1814, 628). der Tierreichs. In addition to these personal debts Lenoir identifies
The idea that all vital forces are branches of the same funda- other intellectual ties between transcendental Naturphilosophie
mental force and that this force is a general excitability of an or- and speculative theories of nature. The concepts of Einheit, Stu-
ganism in relation to the external environment is first formulated in fenfolge, Polarität, Metamorphose, Urtyp and Analogie have been
Schelling’s Erster Entwurf. Here excitability is considered as the described as distinguishing elements of this approach to nature.
general principle from which all other forces could be deduced. The notion of ideal types was central to the Göttingen thought on
Formative drive, irritability and sensibility were conceived of as comparative anatomy. Similarly, in the work of Kielmeyer the dy-
further determinations of this fundamental force. In the Biologie namic interaction of vital forces bears strong similarity to Schel-
Treviranus maintains that the vital principle (Lebesprinzip) of every ling’s notion of polarity, as well as the use made of that notion in
organism depends from a communal fundamental force (Grungk- the work of Nees von Essenbeck and Oken. Goethe’s notion of
raft). For this reason “every living being takes part to the modifi- metamorphosis is closely parallel to the modification of an original
cation of the original source of life and thus living nature displays ground plan developed by the Göttingen biologists (Lenoir, 1981,
phenomena whose cause lies way higher than the effect of me- 192e193). Surprisingly enough, after stressing the proximity be-
chanical or chemical powers” (Treviranus, 1814, 629). Teleology is tween vital-materialism and Naturphilosophie Lenoir maintains
envisaged by Treviranus as the result of a higher level of organiza- that beside the strong similarities in key concepts of these ap-
tion than mechanism and chemical affinity. Accordingly, the proaches, there are still major differences in both their interpre-
formative principle (Bildungsprincip) of living bodies is ascribed a tation and significance. Most importantly, vital-materialism
certain degree of independence from external influences. Trevir- worked hard at remaining consistent with Kant’s philosophy of
anus maintains that this peculiar independence and spontaneity organic nature, while Naturphilosophie worked towards its over-
had been previously defined in different ways. In ancient times coming. This distinction is historically unattested and unsupported
perspicacious thinkers assumed a purposeful principle independent by textual evidence.
A. Gambarotto / Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 48 (2014) 12e20 19

4. Conclusions Society studies in philosophy: 8. Understanding purpose. Kant and the philosophy
of biology (pp. 37e50). Rochester: University of Rochester Press.
Fischer, M. (2007). Kant’s explanatory natural history: Generation and classification
Lenoir has argued that Kielmeyer’s project of a Physik der Tier- of organisms in Kant’s natural philosophy. In P. Huneman (Ed.), North American
reichs is developed in accordance with the guidelines of the Kante Kant Society studies in philosophy: 8. Understanding purpose. Kant and the phi-
Blumenbach vital-materialist program and in opposition to Natur- losophy of biology (pp. 101e122). Rochester: University of Rochester Press.
Ginsborg, H. (2001). Kant on understanding organisms as natural purposes. In
philosophie. A letter Kielmeyer wrote to Cuvier (Kielmeyer, 1837) E. Watkins (Ed.), Kant and the sciences (pp. 231e258). Oxford: Oxford University
seems to endorse this claim. Cuvier had been Kielmeyer’s student Press.
in Stuttgart and kept epistolary contacts with him throughout his Ginsborg, H. (2006). Kant’s biological teleology and its philosophical significance. In
G. Bird (Ed.), The Blackwell companion to Kant (pp. 455e469). Oxford: Blackwell
Parisian carrier. In 1807 he wrote to his former teacher asking of his Publishing.
opinion on the recent development of German philosophy of na- Goy, I., & Watkins, E. (Eds.). (2014). Kant’s theory of biology. Berlin, New York: De
ture. Kielmeyer’s answer is long and detailed. He criticizes Natur- Gruyter.
Guyer, P. (2005). Purpose in nature: What is living, and what is dead in Kant’s
philosophie, argues against the endeavor of “deducing the teleology? In P. Guyer (Ed.), Kant’s system of nature and freedom (pp. 343e372)
multiplicity of nature from our own I” and positions himself in Oxford: Oxford University Press.
proximity to Kant’s Metaphysische Anfangsgründe. He also says, Huneman, P. (2007). Reflexive judgment and Wolffian embriology: Kant’s shift
between the first and the third critique. In P. Huneman (Ed.), North American
however, that “through the recent philosophical systems it has Kant Society studies in philosophy: 8. Understanding purpose. Kant and the phi-
become more usual to consider nature in its entirety as a living losophy of biology (pp. 75e100). Rochester: University of Rochester Press.
organism in all its aspects, and to conceive of single organization as Huneman, P. (2012). Métaphysique et biologie. Kant et la constitution du concept
d’organisme. Paris: Kimé.
individualized exponents of the great nature.” More than twenty
Illetterati, L. (2008). Being for. Purposes and functions in artifacts and living beings.
years later, in the course of a lecture held at the Muséum in 1832, In L. Illetterati, & F. Michelini (Eds.), Purposiveness: Teleology between nature and
Cuvier expresses his own position on the matter, defining Kiel- mind (pp. 135e161). Frankfurt: Ontos.
meyer as “the father of Naturphilosophie who did not want to Illetterati, L. (2010). Biologia. In S. Besoli, C. La Rocca, & Martinelli (a cura di) (Eds.),
L’universo kantiano. Filosofia, scienze, sapere (pp. 53e96). Macerata: Quodlibet.
recognize his daughter” (Bach, 1994). This statement provides a Kielmeyer, K. F. (1938). Natur und Kraft. Gesammelte Schriften (von F.-H. Holler unter
balanced understanding of the issue at hand: Naturphilosophie Mitwirkung von J. Schuster, nach den Handschriften zum erstenmal veröffen-
draws indeed some metaphysical conclusions that are unaccept- tlicht). Berlin: Keiper
Lenoir, T. (1978). Generational factors in the origin of Romantische Natur-
able for the empirical scientist, and in this sense Kielmeyer had philosophie. Journal of the History of Biology, 11(1), 57e108.
right reasons to refuse its assumptions; on the other hand, how- Lenoir, T. (1980). Kant Blumenbach and the vital materialism in German biology.
ever, Schelling’s philosophy of nature develops the framework laid Isis, 70, 77e108.
Lenoir, T. (1981). The Göttingen School and the development of transcendental
down in Kielmeyer’s Rede and formulates conceptual models later Naturphilosophie in the Romantic Era. Studies in the History of Biology, 5, 111e205.
employed in Treviranus’ Biologie. Lenoir, T. (1982). The strategy of life: Teleology and mechanics in nineteenth-century
I agree with Zammito that the vital-materialism as it was German biology. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Löw, R. (1980). Philosophie des Lebendigen. Der Begriff des Organischen bei Kant. Sein
developed at Göttingen is not quite the Kantian “transcendental Grund und seine Aktualität. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
philosophy of nature” that Lenoir wants it to have been. On the Marcucci, S. (1972). Aspetti epistemologici della finalità in Kant. Firenze: Le Monnier.
contrary, we find the Göttingen School far closer to the Natur- McLaughlin, P. (1989). Kants Kritik der teleologischen Urteilskraft. Bonn: Bouvier.
McLaughlin, P. (1990). Kant’s critique of teleology in biological explanation: Antinomy
philosophen than Lenoir would like. Instead of viewing the close-
and teleology. New York: Mellem Lewinston.
ness of the Göttingen School to Naturphilosophie as contamination, Monti, M. T. (1990). Congettura ed Esperienza nella Fisiologia di Haller: La Riforma
we might view it as historical evidence that something essential to dell’Anatomia Animata e il Sistema della Generazione. Firenze: Olschki.
the character of biology as a special science was at stake (Zammito, Philonenko, A. (1982). Kant et la philosophie biologique. In L’Heritage de Kant.
Melanges philosophiques offerts au P. Marcel Regnier (pp. 63e79). Paris:
2012, 130). I hope to have shown that what was at stake was the Beauchesne.
determination of “organization” as the specific property of living Reill, H. P. (2005). Vitalizing nature in the enlightenment. Berkeley: California Uni-
nature and that this process implied a shift from a regulative to a versity Press.
Richards, R. J. (1992). The meaning of evolution. The morphological construction and
constitutive understanding of teleology. Biology emerged as the ideological reconstruction of Darwin’s theory. Chicago: University of Chicago
general science dealing with the teleological laws that regulate the Press.
organization of living nature as a whole. In this scenario, Kant’s Richards, R. J. (2000). Kant and Blumenbach on the Bildungstrieb: A historical
misunderstanding. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical
views on teleology constituted more of an hindrance than an aid. Sciences, 31(1), 11e32.
On the other hand, if the Göttingen vitalism cannot be excluded Richards, R. J. (2002). The romantic conception of life. Science and philosophy in the
from this process, neither can Naturphilosophie. Age of Goethe. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Roe, S. A. (1981). Matter, life, generation. Eighteenth-century embryology and the
Haller-Wolff debate. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
References Schelling, F. W. J. (2000). Von der Weltseele. Eine Hypothese der höhern Physik zur
Erklärung des allgemeinen Organismus (Von J. Jantzen unter mitwirkung von T.
Bach, T. (1994). “Kielmeyer als »Vater der Naturphilosophie« ? Anmerkungen zu Kisser). Stuttgart: Frommann-Holzboog
seiner Rezeption in deutschen Idealismus”. In K. T. Kanz (Ed.), Philosophie des Schelling, F. W. J. (2001). Erster Entwurf eines Systems der Naturphilosophie (von W.G.
Organischen in der Goethezeit: Studien zu Werk und Wirkung des Naturforschers Jacobs und P. Ziche). Stuttgart: Frommann-Holzboog
Carl Friedrich Kielmeyer (1765e1844) (pp. 232e251). Stuttgart: Steiner. Schmitt, S. (2006). Les forces vitales et leur distribution dans la nature. Un essai de
Bach, T. (2001). Biologie und Philosophie bei C.F. Kielmeyer und F.W.J. Schelling. “systématique physiologique” (Texte de C. F. Kielmeyer (1765e1844), H. F. Link
Stuttgart, Bad Cannstatt: Frommann-holzboog. (1767e1851) et L. Oken (1779e1851) rassemblés, introduits et annotés par S.
Blumenbach, J. F. (1787). Institutiones physiologicae. Göttingen: Dietrich. Schmitt). Turnhout: Brepols
Canguilhem, G. (1962). Du développement à l’évolution au XIXe siècle. Paris: Puf. Schmitt, S. (2007). Succession of functions and classification in post-Kantian
Cheung, T. (2006). From the organism of a body to the body of an organism: Naturphilosophie around 1800. In P. Huneman (Ed.), North American Kant So-
Occurrence and meaning of the word ‘organism’ from the seventeenth to ciety studies in philosophy: 8. Understanding purpose. Kant and the philosophy of
the eighteenth centuries. The British Journal for the History of Science, 39(3), biology (pp. 123e136). Rochester: University of Rochester Press.
319e339. Sloan, P. (1979). Buffon, German biology and the historical interpretation of
Coleman, W. (1973). Limits of the recapitulation theory. Carl Friedrich Kielmeyer’s biological species. The British Journal for the History of Science, 12(2), 109e
critique of the presumed parallelism of earth history, ontogeny, and the present 153.
order of organisms. Isis, 63(3), 341e350. Sloan, P. (2006). Kant on the history of nature: The ambiguous heritage of the
Coleman, W. (1977). Biology in the nineteenth century. Problems of form, function, and critical philosophy for natural history. Studies in the History and Philosophy of
transformation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 37(4), 627e648.
Duchesneau, F. (1982). La physiologie des Lumières. Empirisme, modèles et théories. La Steinke, H. (2005). Irritating experiments: Haller’s concept and the European contro-
Hague, Boston, London: Nijhoff. versy on irritability and sensibility, 1750e90. Amsterdam, New York: Rudopi.
Dupont, J. C. (2007). Pre-Kantian revival of epigenesis: Caspar Friedrich Wolff’s De Treviranus, G. R. (1802). Biologie oder Philosophie der lebenden Natur für Naturforcher
Formatione Intestinorum (1768e69). In P. Huneman (Ed.), North American Kant und Ärzte, Band I. Göttingen: Röwer.
20 A. Gambarotto / Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 48 (2014) 12e20

Treviranus, G. R. (1814). Biologie, oder Philosophie der lebenden Natur für Natur- Understanding purpose. Kant and the philosophy of biology (pp. 51e74).
forcher und Ärzte, Band IV. Göttingen: Röwer. Rochester: University of Rochester Press.
Wolfe, C. T. (2014). On Newtonian analogies in eighteenth-century life science: Zammito, J. (2012). The Lonoir thesis revisited: Blumenbach and Kant. Studies in
Vitalism and provisionally inexplicable explicative devices. In Newton and History and Philosophy of Science, Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of
empiricism (pp. 223e261). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 43(1), 120e132.
Wolff, C. F. (1759). Theoria generationis. Halle: Hendel. Zuckert, R. (2007). Kant on beauty and biology. An interpretation of the critique of
Zammito, J. (1992). The genesis of Kant’s critique of judgment. Chicago: University of judgement. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Chicago Press. Zumbach, C. (1984). The transcendent science. Kant’s conception of biological meth-
Zammito, J. (2007). Kant’s persistent ambivalence toward epigenesis 1764e90. In odology. The Hague: Nijhoff.
P. Huneman (Ed.), North American Kant Society studies in philosophy: 8.

S-ar putea să vă placă și