Sunteți pe pagina 1din 257

TÜRKİYE CUMHURİYETİ

ANKARA ÜNİVERSİTESİ
SOSYAL BİLİMLER ENSTİTÜSÜ
BATI DİLLERİ VE EDEBİYATLARI
(İNGİLİZ DİLİ VE EDEBİYATI)
ANABİLİM DALI

RECONFIGURATION OF HOWARD BARKER’S THEATRE OF CATASTROPHE AS

HISTORIOGRAPHIC METADRAMA: NO END OF BLAME, THE POWER OF THE

DOG, PITY IN HISTORY, SCENES FROM AN EXECUTION AND BRUTOPIA

Doktora Tezi

Yiğit SÜMBÜL

Ankara, 2018
ii

TÜRKİYE CUMHURİYETİ
ANKARA ÜNİVERSİTESİ
SOSYAL BİLİMLER ENSTİTÜSÜ
BATI DİLLERİ VE EDEBİYATLARI
(İNGİLİZ DİLİ VE EDEBİYATI)
ANABİLİM DALI

RECONFIGURATION OF HOWARD BARKER’S THEATRE OF CATASTROPHE AS

HISTORIOGRAPHIC METADRAMA: NO END OF BLAME, THE POWER OF THE

DOG, PITY IN HISTORY, SCENES FROM AN EXECUTION AND BRUTOPIA

Doktora Tezi

Yiğit SÜMBÜL

Tez Danışmanı
Prof. Dr. Nazan TUTAŞ

Ankara, 2018
iii

TÜRKİYE CUMHURİYETİ
ANKARA ÜNİVERSİTESİ
SOSYAL BİLİMLER ENSTİTÜSÜ
BATI DİLLERİ VE EDEBİYATLARI
(İNGİLİZ DİLİ VE EDEBİYATI)
ANABİLİM DALI

RECONFIGURATION OF HOWARD BARKER’S THEATRE OF CATASTROPHE AS

HISTORIOGRAPHIC METADRAMA: NO END OF BLAME, THE POWER OF THE

DOG, PITY IN HISTORY, SCENES FROM AN EXECUTION AND BRUTOPIA

PhD Thesis

Yiğit SÜMBÜL

Supervisor: Prof. Dr. Nazan TUTAŞ

Ankara, 2018
vi

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

This thesis has been written in a relatively short period of time; yet it is a product of years of

reading and research, and of my indefinable fascination with the late-20th century British

political drama.

First of all, I would like to express my deepest gratitude to my supervisor, Prof. Dr. Nazan

TUTAŞ for her invaluable support and guidance throughout this project; and also to my

committee members Assoc. Prof. Dr. Şebnem KAYA and Assoc. Prof. Dr. Sıla ŞENLEN

GÜVENÇ for having faith in me all the time. I also feel indebted to all academic staff of the

Department of English Language and Literature at Ankara University for their welcoming

smiles whenever I appear at their doors. In addition, I will forever be thankful to my former

professors at the Department of English Language and Literature at Hacettepe University,

from whom I received priceless education during my undergraduate years as well as to Prof.

Dr. Behzad Ghaderi SOHİ and Assoc. Prof. Dr. Hasan BAKTIR from the Department of

English Language and Literature at Erciyes University for their endless encouragement. I

wish to extend my gratitude to all academic staff of the Department of English Language and

Literature at Gazi University for their kindness and patience in my troublesome times.

Finally, I would like to express my deep gratitude to TUBİTAK (The Scientific and

Technological Research Council of Turkey) for the financial support they gave me during

my graduate education and for the infinite support and contribution they make to the

scientific, artistic and cultural development of Turkey every year by granting scholarships

for young researchers from all around the world.

Yiğit SÜMBÜL

ANKARA 2018
vii

TABLE OF CONTENTS

INTRODUCTION………………………………………………………………………….1

CHAPTER 1- The Evolution of a Genre: Historiographic Metadrama………………..14

1.1. The Theory of Historiography in the Modern Times: From Hegel to White14

1.2. A Brief History of Metadramatic Theatre in the Modern Times…………...47

1.3. From Historiographic Metafiction to Historiographic Metadrama……….77

CHAPTER 2- The Tenets of Howard Barker’s Theatre of Catastrophe……………….91

2.1. Tragedy, Death and the Catastrophic Effect………………………………..98

2.2. Language, Obscurity and the Question of Anti-Catharsis………...………109

2.3. Political, Moral and Aesthetic Functionlessness…………………………...116

CHAPTER 3- Rereading Howard Barker’s Plays as Historiographic Metadrama….130

3.1. No End of Blame and the ‘Terrible’ Power of Art………………………..133

3.2. The Power of the Dog and the Question of ‘Appropriate’ Art……………..153

3.3. Pity in History and Art as ‘Vulgar Ostentation’……………………………173

3.4. Scenes from an Execution and ‘What the Circumstances Require’ for Art188

3.5. Brutopia and Art in the Face of Censorship………………………………..203

CONCLUSION…………………………………………………………………….…….219

BIBLIOGRAPHY……………………………………………………………………….232

ABSTRACT……………………………………………………………………………...247

ÖZET……………………………………………………………………………………..249
1

INTRODUCTION

Howard Barker’s talent as a dramatist, essayist and stage designer has demonstrated

itself in huge volumes of plays, books of theory of theatre and performance as well as a

substantial number of domestic and international performances of his plays let alone a theatre

ensemble dedicated to the staging of his drama. Rabey reminds the reader that Barker has

been described as ‘England’s greatest living dramatist’ in The Times and as ‘the Shakespeare

of our age’ by Sarah Kane with respect to the playwright’s prolificacy in writing, authenticity

of style and mastery of the English language in its most poetic form (2009:3). Barker’s drama

stands somewhere between the mainstream political theatre of the late 20th century and the

expressionistic experimental drama of the turn of the century, which manifests itself in his

interest in the historical subject matter, themes of death and desire for power and an intense

theatrical self-reflexivity. In this respect, his plays have been interpreted in their relations and

potential responses to the mainstream political drama of the Brechtian vein -represented by

dramatists like Caryl Churchill, David Hare and Howard Brenton- as well as to the

experimental drama of playwrights like Sarah Kane.

Barker’s work has drawn intense critical attention for the last few decades in terms

of his unconventional approach to the role and functions of drama in the social, political and

moral contexts. Many researchers have positioned Barker’s “Theatre of Catastrophe” up

against the long tradition of Aristotelian catharsis and Brechtian epic theatre, which attribute

various functions to the dramatic work and its representation on the stage. However, such

discussions are inevitably contingent upon a blind acknowledgment of Barker’s drama as a

decisively and perfectly functionless kind, as proposed in the playwright’s theoretical

treatises on drama and performance. The studies conducted on Barker’s theatre so far have

focused on its thematic richness with an insistence on the subject of death, violence and
2

sexual desire as well as its technical aspects like the use of poetic language, asides and its

attitude towards the audience. Among these studies are Charles Lamb’s Howard Barker’s

Theatre of Seduction (1997) and David Ian Rabey’s Howard Barker: Ecstasy and Death

(2009), both of which examine Barker’s career as a dramatist with respect to his alleged

aloofness from politics and moralism.

However, this study focuses on the relationships between the contemporary

postmodern theories of history and literature and Howard Barker’s dramatic works and his

theoretical works on the art of theatre from a different point of view. It examines to what

extent Howard Barker’s plays are suitable for categorization as ‘historiographic metadrama’

and how much these plays contribute to the development of the genre. Such a reading is

expected to reveal the playwright’s views of history and art in general along with his use of

those historical and metadramatic references as a means to address contemporary political,

moral, ethical and aesthetic issues. To that end, this study also discusses how such a reading

of Barker’s plays is potentially subversive of his theatrics of “Theatre of Catastrophe”

proposed in his theory books on theatre and performance.

Such an objective begins with an attempt to come up with a new definition of the

contemporary dramatic genre, historiographic metadrama, with respect to the treatment of

historical data and process of artistic creation in Howard Barker’s selected plays. In addition,

it requires a re-reading of the plays concerned within the framework of historiographic

metadrama in an effort to reveal the playwright’s political, moral and artistic stance through

intertextual elements in the plays and, thus, challenge his arguments constituting his “Theatre

of Catastrophe”. This dissertation analyses Barker’s plays No End of Blame, The Power of

the Dog, Pity in History, Scenes from an Execution, and Brutopia in the light of post-modern

theories of historiography and literature to display their thematic common threads like
3

distortion of documented historical data, the struggle of the artist against the authority,

responsibilities of the artist towards society and functions of art in a chaotic, ugly world. To

that end, it compares the arguments deduced from the analyses of the plays with Barker’s

principles for his “Theatre of Catastrophe” to reveal the contradictions between what the

playwright proposes and what he produces.

As mentioned above, a new perspective is required to the analysis of Howard

Barker’s, one of the leading figures of contemporary British drama, work in order to reveal

the playwright’s contributions to the development of a new genre, historiographic

metadrama. Using Linda Hutcheon’s proverbial theory “historiographic metafiction”, a

potently self-reflexive genre with a challenge to validity of historical knowledge, and its

applications to drama, this study offers a new aspect to ‘historiographic metadrama’ and

discusses Barker’s famous works in terms of their use and problematization of historical data

and their self-reflexive commentary on issues like artistic innovation, freedom of expression,

censorship, the artist’s struggle against the authority and the ethics of art. It also relates this

discussion to Barker’s self-crafted genre ‘the Theatre of Catastrophe” as detailed in his

dramatic manifesto, Arguments for a Theatre, with particular emphasis on his views

regarding functions of art, responsibilities of the artist and art’s relation to politics, morality

and history. Consequently, it is assumed that the playwright’s tenacious use of documented

history as the time and setting for his plays and his metatheatrical references to the nature of

art stem from his will to address contemporary political, moral, ethical and aesthetic issues,

and, thus, seem to contradict what he proposes in his theorization of “the Theatre of

Catastrophe” about functionlessness of art and irresponsibility of the artist.

The discussions here derive mainly from the concepts of metadrama and

historiography with respect to Howard Barker’s plays within the context of historiographic
4

metadrama. The term metatheatre is used in accordance with Lionel Abel’s 1963 formulation

of this new genre with particular emphasis on self-reflexivity, self-referentiality, artificiality

and illusoriness of dramatic works. In addition, Richard Hornby’s definition of metadrama

as the kind of drama in which “the subject of the play turns out to be, in some sense, drama

itself” (1986:31) is also utilized along with the ‘varieties’ of metadrama listed in his Drama,

Metadrama and Perception (1986) as the play-within-the-play, the ceremony within the play,

roleplaying within role, literary and real life reference and self-reference. This dissertation

also refers, in the discussion of Barker’s claim to history-writing, to the seminal postmodern

works on history-writing like Hayden White’s Metahistory: The Historical Imagination in

Nineteenth-Century Europe (1973) in which he defines a historical work as “a verbal

structure in the form of a narrative prose discourse that purports to be a model, or icon, of

past structures and processes in the interest of explaining what they were by representing

them” (2).

Bringing together the two concepts defined above, the present study discusses

Howard Barker’s selected plays as historiographic and metadramatic texts which inevitably

deal with historical events in a subversive way and comment on the nature of drama or, in

general, art itself. In the re-readings of Barker’s plays as historiographic metadrama, it also

refers to Alexander Feldman’s definition of ‘historiographic metatheatre’ as “those works,

and parts of works, in which self-reflexive engagements with the traditions and forms of

dramatic art illuminate historical themes and aid in the representation of historical events”

(2013:2-3). Finally, the outcomes of the above-mentioned analyses are juxtaposed with

Howard Barker’s fundamental principles in his formulation of the “Theatre of Catastrophe”,

particularly the ones related to functions and responsibilities of art, to reveal the playwright’s

self-contradiction.
5

The first chapter of this dissertation gives a brief account of the historical

development of historiography which is born with the premises of an objective, scientific

discipline and, then, transformed into a subjective means of narrativizing the past. The

beginning of studies in historiography is attributed to the German philosopher Hegel who

discusses the concept of history under three sub-headings: original history, reflective history

and philosophical history. In his discussion, Hegel emphasizes the role of the historian in the

representation of historical events which ultimately determines the level of objectivity of the

given historical account. From Hegel onwards, the arguments related to history possess

similar motivations, treating history either as a science or as an art. Lord Acton, in the 19th

century, draws attention to the political implications of historical accounts and the qualities

that distinguish historiography from historical literature. Acton believes that history has the

power to aggrandize or stigmatize nations and, in this respect, ideological intervention in the

writing of history is inevitably necessary for the good of the majority.

With an eye to Hayden White’s discussion of the evolution of historiography in a

chronological order, the first chapter also includes a review of the ideas put forward by the

philosophers of the German tradition like Droysen, the Anglo-American philosophers of

history like Walsh and Gardiner, the French Annalistes like Foucault and Le Goff, Marxist

critics like Jameson and the hermeneutic philosophers like Ricoeur and Gadamer. Basically

referring to Droysen’s Historik (1868), it also discusses how he sees history as a

representation of the past, not the past itself, serving the dominant ideology and morality.

Droysen relates historical knowledge and representation ultimately to the interpretative

mechanisms of a given era, ideological group and individual historian motivated by his

immediate needs. Foucault, on the other hand, refers to the accumulation of historical

knowledge as a process of linguistic encoding and decoding in an attempt to interpret and


6

make sense of a past on which present-time knowledge is quite limited. The representative

of Marxist historiography, Jameson emphasizes the necessity of a narrative structure in an

accurate representation of historical events with respect to the cause and effect relationship;

and he attributes great powers to that narrativity in the dialectical process of cultural

development. The difference between the French Annalistes and the Anglo-American

philosophers of history in terms of their approaches to the element of story-telling in

historical representation is also discussed with particular references to the representative texts

of the two schools of thought. Ricoeur, on the other hand, along with other hermeneutic

philosophers, discusses historiography as an act of narrativizing the past through which

historical accuracy and understanding can be achieved without a necessity to explain the past.

He argues that, without a plot, historical accounts are deficient and it is the narrative structure

which gives a historical temporality the shape of a logical account with an emphasis on

reasons and consequences.

In the last few decades, the discussions over historical narratives have focused on the

possibility of achieving the status of a science for historiography when stories as its basic

source material and its ideological and mythical nature are taken into consideration. For

contemporary French historians, the Annalistes for instance, it has always been crucial to

eliminate storytelling from historical representation if historiography is meant to be a science.

For major Anglo-American philosophers of history like Walsh and Gardiner, however,

storytelling is not only an inseparable organic component of historiography, but the most

appropriate way in representing the past, as well. What distinguishes historiography from

fiction, in this sense, is the former’s subject matter being what is real and lived whereas the

latter’s being what is imagined and liveable. Separating storytelling from historiography, for

these Anglo-American philosophers, is an unnecessary measure, as the past itself was


7

comprised of individual stories to be transformed into historical accounts thanks to the

historian’s storytelling capabilities. However, in the postmodern way of thinking, there is no

clear-cut distinction between a historical account and a fictional work that claims to be

dealing with lived events in the past, based on the textuality of history and the historicality

of texts. As White argues, “history as a discipline is in bad shape today because it has lost

sight of its origins in the literary imagination” (1978:99). This complication calls for a close

analysis of the narrative structures of the texts, fictional or non-fictional, with respect to the

three basic types of narrative discourse being mythic, historical and fictional to which Paul

Ricoeur turned his attention in the 70s.

In the second part of the first chapter of this study, a brief history of metadramatic

theatre is given from Lionel Abel’s coinage of the term ‘metatheatre’, through Richard

Hornby’s elaboration on the qualities and varieties of ‘metadrama’, to the contemporary

contributors like Calderwood, Egan and Homan. Abel, in his definition and discussion,

focuses on the issues of play-within-the-play and self-dramatization of the characters in the

long tradition of western drama from Shakespeare to Brecht. With an emphasis on the

technical aspects of dramatic works he deals with, Abel names the genre “metatheatre”,

whereas, in other studies on this newly emergent self-reflexive tradition in drama, the term

metadrama was also used interchangeably with Abel’s metatheatre, as in Richard Hornby’s

monumental Drama, Metadrama, and Perception (1986). Despite the dominant

interchangeable use of the two terms, there has lately been a tendency to categorize technical

self-reflexive elements of a dramatic work related to staging, acting or performance, such as

a play within the play or role-playing within the role, as metatheatrical while the textual self-

reflexivity and intertextual elements in a dramatic work related basically to content or reading

are categorized as metadramatic.


8

Abel attributes the beginnings of metatheatre to the 16th and 17th centuries when the

idea that all the world is a stage and humans are just actors playing the parts cast for them is

popular. Referring specifically to Shakespeare’s Hamlet and The Tempest, Marlowe’s Doctor

Faustus, Moliere’s Tartuffe and Calderon’s The Great Stage of the World, Abel discusses

how the characters in the plays, who have already been dramatized by the playwright’s

imagination, dramatize themselves and the other characters with a playwright’s

consciousness. Similarly, in the following centuries, plays like Ibsen’s Peer Gynt, Genet’s

The Balcony and Beckett’s Waiting for Godot among many others, give voice to characters

who are already dramatized by their personal histories, fates and the people around them.

After Abel’s introduction to this new genre, Richard Hornby sets the basic principles of what

he calls ‘metadrama’ with particular emphasis on both technical and textual aspects of

dramatic works. Hornby specifies the six elements that constitute metadramaticality in a play

as the play within the play, the ceremony within the play, role playing within the role, literary

and real life reference, self-reference and disruption of perception (1986:32). He refers to

famous plays like Shakespeare’s Hamlet and Kyd’s The Spanish Tragedy for the play within

the play, to Shakespeare’s The Merchant of Venice and Macbeth for the ceremony within the

play, to Shakespeare’s Othello and Jonson’s Volpone for role playing within the role, to

Shakespeare’s famous history plays and Stoppard’s Rosencrantz and Guildenstern Are Dead

for literary and real-life reference, to Shakespeare’s Henry IV for self-reference and finally

to Shakespeare’s As You Like It and Ibsen’s The Master Builder for perception.

The third part of the first chapter deals with the birth of a new genre, historiographic

metadrama, out of the merging of the postmodern conception of historiography and the

potentials of metadrama. In the formulation of a genre to be named ‘historiographic

metadrama’, all discussions inevitably derive from Linda Hutcheon’s seminal essay on
9

postmodern fiction- particularly its self-reflexive, intertextual and historiographic nature-

titled “Historiographic Metafiction: Parody and Intertextuality of History”. The defining

elements of Hutcheon’s ‘historiographic metafiction’ including self-reflexivity,

intertextuality, parody and a claim to historical knowledge become an inspiration for Richard

Knowles, the Canadian scholar of drama who coined the term “historiographic metadrama”

in 1987. In his extended research on contemporary Canadian playwrights like Salutin,

Reaney and Pallock, Knowles defines and exemplifies historiographic metadrama with

respect to these playwrights’ subversion of history with their own subjective accounts and

use of metadramatic elements like ceremony within the play and literary and real-life

reference. He also observes that historiographic metadrama has taken root in the whole

western drama, not only in Canadian drama, and it has become the defining genre of the

postmodern dramatic literature. Very much like Knowles, Alexander Feldman also attempts

at a definition of this genre which he names “historiographic metatheatre” and puts the

emphasis on the theatricality of history and the historicality of theatre as reflected in

contemporary plays.

The second chapter of this study attempts to determine Howard Barker’s place in a

long tradition of British political drama based primarily on Brechtian epic theatre in terms of

both form and content. Starting his literary career in the 1970s, Barker gradually lays the

foundations of his genre “Theatre of Catastrophe” which culminates in the establishment of

“The Wrestling School”, a theatre company devoted to the staging of Barker’s plays, in 1988.

Barker sets the principles of his self-crafted genre in two seminal books on the art of theatre

titled Arguments for a Theatre (1993) and Death, the One and the Art of Theatre (2005) in

which he elaborates on issues ranging from functions of art, the places of death and tragedy

in contemporary drama, language and obscurity to acting and staging of his plays. In these
10

books, Barker also makes a list of elements that distinguish his theatre from what he calls the

humanist theatre or the theatre of conscience dominating the stage from Brecht onwards. His

“Theatre of Catastrophe” basically refuses to possess any function whatsoever, including an

interest in giving political, moral or aesthetic messages to an audience whose responses to

the play must not be a collective, but an individually distinctive one. Barker also draws

attention to the supremacy of the tragic form and the element of death in dramatic works, as

death means a moral and political nakedness, the ultimate ambiguity and mystery, and the

means of the final judgment, all of which Barker embraces with his drama. His “Theatre of

Catastrophe” also designates a much more poetic language, obscurity in meaning and an

avoidance of purgation of feelings on behalf of the audience in Aristotelian terms.

The first part of the second chapter deals with a catastrophic effect which lies in the

centre of Barker’s “Theatre of Catastrophe”, a feeling of dignity felt even on the verge of

death, a feeling that makes the theatrical experience worthwhile for the audience. Barker

contends that the best form to convey this catastrophic effect to the audience is the tragic

form in which the audience learns the value of suffering and extracts the spirit of resistance.

The second part of the second chapter mentions how Barker’s catastrophic theatre opposes

the idea of clarity of meaning and the authoritarian view of art as ‘saying’. Instead, his theatre

aims to offer a very different kind of artistic experience by confusing the audience to the end

that it realizes the absence of generalizing, all-encompassing meanings. He criticizes the

popular political theatre of the previous decades for reducing the audience to an ‘intellectual

servility’ in which it craves for a message, as if knowledge was public property, and pushes

the experience of art into the background. Barker’s “Theatre of Catastrophe”, on the contrary,

strongly distances the audience from the feelings of empathy and self-assertion, and never

satisfies the audience with a restoration of any kind. It does not burden the audience with any
11

kind of truth, but privileges it with the knowledge that truth never exists. The third part of

the second chapter, on the other hand, discusses Barker’s deliberate liberation of his drama

from contextual meaning mechanisms including ideology, politics and public morality. He

sees “Theatre of Catastrophe” as a cure for this sickness intensified by the mechanical and

ideological theatre of his time which selfishly keeps the right of moral speculation to itself.

He claims that his theatre never makes circles about the audience’s perception, never assumes

any kind of ideological responsibility, never strives to elucidate or to amuse, never promises

to remain within the crippling framework of the facts and never fusses about the truth. His

“Theatre of Catastrophe” does not create the illusion that the audience is watching something

of its own, something it itself has already experienced in a certain part of its history.

The third chapter of this study discusses five selected plays from Howard Barker’s

most prolific years, all written and published during the 80s, with special emphasis on the

playwright’s use of documented historical events for his plots, famous historical personages

for characters and specific historical dates and settings for backgrounds along with artists for

his protagonists and works of art for the central motifs in order to express his ideas about the

accuracy of historical knowledge, freedom of expression, censorship, artistic innovation, the

artist’s struggle against the authority and the ethics of art. In the first part of the chapter, the

playwright’s 1981 play No End of Blame is discussed within the reaches of historiographic

metadrama by referring primarily to the protagonist’s, a Hungarian cartoonist named Bela,

struggles to liberate his art from the attempted governmental interventions spearheaded by

actual historical figures like Lenin and Churchill in a long period from the First World War

to the end of the Second World War. In the second part, Barker’s other 1981 play The Power

of the Dog is subjected to a similar scrutiny with a discussion of the protagonist’s, a Polish

photographer named Ilona, hardships when she is hired to photograph Stalin’s face in a post-
12

Second World War setting. In the third part of the chapter, Barker’s 1984 play Pity in History

is discussed with special references to the protagonist’s, a sculptor named Gaukroger,

questioning of honesty in art while subjecting himself to the wishes of the Cromwellian

government and the Puritan Church during the English Civil War. The fourth part, on the

other hand, is concerned with the playwright’s other 1984 play Scenes from an Execution in

which the protagonist, a free-spirited female painter named Galactia, defends her freedom of

expression against the pressure of the government on her depictions of the famous Battle of

Lepanto between the fleets of the Holy League and the Ottoman Empire. Finally, the fifth

part of the chapter discusses Barker’s 1989 play Brutopia with a focus on the issue of political

censorship by the King Henry VIII himself who sentences Thomas More to death due to his

‘overambitious thoughts’ and refuses to publish the book written by Cecilia, More’s daughter

and an ambitious female author, without ideological ‘proofreading’.

Finally, this study juxtaposes the outcomes of the discussions of Barker’s plays as

“Theatre of Catastrophe” and historiographic metadrama to display whether the playwright’s

work has been a continuation of a long-term political and moral drama- although the

playwright decisively considers his theatre separate from the cathartic Aristotelian moralism

and political Brechtian aesthetics- or not. The selected plays - No End of Blame, The Power

of the Dog, Pity in History, Scenes from an Execution and Brutopia – differ from the rest of

Barker’s plays in that they are all concerned with the same struggle of an artist against a

totalitarian authority in a time of catastrophe. All written in the 80s, these plays draw the

picture of a political, moral and artistic environment which strongly resembles the

atmosphere in contemporary England in terms of political, moral and aesthetic discussions.

Although Barker also wrote historical plays around the same time like The Castle (1985),

which uses a medieval setting during the time of the Crusades, and The Europeans (1990),
13

which depicts the catastrophic environment in the 17th century Vienna after the invasion by

the Ottoman Empire, such plays don’t seem to be making an attempt on disrupting historical

data or making political and moral criticism of any kind -at least overtly-, or using an artist

as the protagonist. Along similar lines, Hurts Given and Received, one of Barker’s latest

plays published in 2010, reflects the psychology and troubles of a poet-protagonist whereas

the play is not concerned with history or historical representation at all. Barker’s Blok/Eko

(2011) similarly depicts a poet-protagonist’s last stand in the name artistic perfection before

he sacrifices his body, not his soul; however, this play also does not concern itself with the

issues of historical representation and political as well as moral criticism. In this respect, the

selected plays prove rather coherent for a simultaneous analysis in terms of subject matter,

style and time of publication. This study offers a new dimension to the newly-emergent genre

‘historiographic metadrama’ through these plays and opens up new windows to the

playwright’s “Theatre of Catastrophe” with a challenge to it from within. In all these respects,

Barker’s “Theatre of Catastrophe” proves to be an inherently functional kind of drama with

the playwright’s problematization of historical knowledge and veiled comments on the nature

and ethics of art in the face of his political, moral and aesthetic concerns.
14

CHAPTER 1

THE EVOLUTION OF A GENRE: HISTORIOGRAPHIC METADRAMA

1.1. The Theory of Historiography in the Modern Times: From Hegel to White

The study of history and historiography in the modern sense can be traced back to the

late 19th century, to Hegel’s seminal lectures on the philosophy of history. Hegel begins his

discussion of the study of history by listing three methods of treating the historical subject

matter: original history, reflective history and philosophical history. The first method refers

to the classical understanding of history writing, of famous historians like Herodotus and

Thucydides, whose treatment of the past does not go beyond recording the deeds, dates,

names of people and events to which the historians themselves were eye-witnesses. In this

method, the historian’s job is limited to reflecting what happens before his eyes to the paper

by excluding his emotions from the representation, which is the basic different between him

and the poet. Hegel also acknowledges the fact that it is impossible for a historian to ‘see’

everything and historians also treat the events which are capable of ‘being seen’ to serve

faithfully the conceptive faculties of humanity, by which regard he must exclude such

imaginary and improbable events heard in legends, ballads and myths. However, this has a

crippling effect on the scope of the historian’s work, as such data require the historian’s

participation in a certain event at a certain place and time, very much like a painter painting

a scene with no touch of imagination. The duty of the classical historians or annalists is

transferred to the monks in the middle ages whose deliberate isolation from the general public

crippled their vision and their records could not go beyond naïve chronicles with a very

limited scope. However, in the modern times, the roles of the historians have gone under

drastic change and historical records have gained a narrative structure with vivid descriptions
15

and to-the-point details: “In richness of matter and fullness of detail as regards strategic

appliances, and attendant circumstances, they [have become] even more instructive” (17).

The second method, Hegel argues, extends the scope of historical representation from

the actual time and place in which the historical events took place to an undefined, unlimited

future; and the historian manipulates his subject matter to achieve a universal image of the

past by his own spirit and from his own point of view. However, the individuality of the

historian’s tone often disrupts the authenticity of the historical events when the historical

personages are given voices from the ‘future’ mouths. For Hegel, a historian who endeavours

to achieve universality must attempt to capture the past events as they really happened. Such

a representation must “foreshorten its pictures by abstractions; and this includes not merely

the omission of events and deeds, but whatever is involved in the fact that Thought is, after

all, the most trenchant epitomist” (19). Besides its claims to universality, reflective history

also strives to be pragmatic or didactic in the sense that it creates a present out of the

documented past based on the moral lessons derived from the experiences of previous

generations. Forming historical relations between the past and the present, such a pragmatic

approach proposes idealistic doctrines of behaviour and conduct in particular cases, which

must be supplemented with the reanimation of that historical spirit to better the present

circumstances. Reflective history can also take the form of criticism which investigates not

the history, but the history of history, that is the validity of other historical narratives to reveal

the level of subjectivity and the true intentions of the historian if there are any. One last face

of reflective history is that it reflects history’s own fragmentary nature by focusing on

particular subject matters like the history of art, history of medicine or history of law from a

general point of view. This approach is helpful in the constitution, though superficially, and
16

development of fields of research and sets the tenets of each field as an inward guide to the

following generations.

Philosophical history, the third method in Hegel’s classification, is defined as

“nothing but the thoughtful consideration of it” (22) in the simplest sense of the term. Even

though he admits that, in the study of history, thought looks inferior to the facts, Hegel sees

an inevitable connection between the subject matter of history and philosophy in their

treatment of what happens and how it relates to the following periods of time. As history

records the rational development of humanity, philosophy catches up with it in reason’s

domain, which is contemplated as the essence of the universe in his philosophy even if it

presents nothing more than the ideal, the intentional and the speculative. Hegel, here,

acknowledges that philosophers have always been accused of forcing the ‘a priori’ into the

history of mankind, and he professes that speculation is a central ambiguity in history writing.

For him, “[e]ven the ordinary, the ‘impartial’ historiographer, who believes and professes

that he maintains a simply receptive attitude; surrendering himself only to the data supplied

him — is by no means passive as regards the exercise of his thinking powers” (24). The

historian brings his contexts into the text and, if history is to be regarded as a science, he

gives way to the free play of reason and speculative reflection. Hegel views history as the

result of the doings of active reasoning and the investigation of that history is an act to search

the ‘Spirit’ that triggers the reason’s actions: “Universal History […] is the exhibition of

Spirit in the process of working out the knowledge of that which it is potentially” (31). In

that respect, true historical process is a self-revelation of the rational ‘Spirit’ which

constitutes the overall nature of the subjective and the objective cumulatively leading

humanity through historical stages to an infinite consciousness.


17

Lord Acton, in his famous lectures on the study of modern history published

posthumously in 1906, draws attention to the inevitable relationship between history-writing

and politics, and he grants the latter with the power to save history from the domain of ‘mere

literature’: “[T]he knowledge of the past, the record of truths revealed by experience, is

eminently practical, as an instrument of action, and a power that goes to the making of the

future” (3). He attaches great importance to historiography in that it contributes to the

advancement of both science and government by always keeping the tradition in view as a

role model. However, he admits that history must be concerned with accuracy whose origins

cannot be sought in the darkness of the Middle Ages, but in the Renaissance when the

perception of the world, notions of economy, law and government and even the trends in

education gained momentum towards an ‘untried experience’ stimulated by an ‘unknown

influence’. With an eye to that sharp disengagement from the past, Acton views 16th century

as the beginning of modern history: “It was then that History as we understand it began to be

understood, and the illustrious dynasty of scholars arose to whom we still look both for

method and material” (11). Beginning with the Renaissance, historians leave the ‘twilight of

fiction’, promises of invention and trusting false witnesses, and they begin to see

historiography as a duty to detect verifiable truth rather than the forgery of a past: “Taking

little for granted they have sought to know the ground they stand on, and the road they travel,

and the reason why. Over them, therefore, the historian has obtained an increasing

ascendancy” (12). Naming a few forerunners of history-writing like Leopold von Ranke,

Henry Hallam and S. R. Gardiner, Acton speaks optimistically of the future of history-writing

with his contemporaries’ disbelief in weak assumptions and generalizing narratives along

with their dependence on subjective conjectures: “We are still at the beginning of the

documentary age, which will tend to make history independent of historians, to develop
18

learning at the expense of writing, and to accomplish a revolution in other sciences as well”

(19). Acton believes that a neat study of history and careful archiving have the capacity to

uplift nations, very much like the study of the ancient texts uplifted European civilization

during the Renaissance. He accepts that history is a narrative that is created by and creates

national heritage based on the shared experiences of all the citizens by their collective efforts:

“To men in general I would justify the stress I am laying on modern history, […] by the

argument that it is a narrative told of ourselves, the record of a life which is our own, of

efforts not yet abandoned to repose, of problems that still entangle the feet and vex the hearts

of men” (19). Acton is also assured that the study of history is always rewarding to improve

one’s character by providing him with the ability of ‘historical thinking’, devoid of illusions

and biases, at least in private and public relations.

On a national basis, then on a universal one, Acton touches upon the relationship

between religion and the birth of modern history. After the Restoration of the Stuart dynasty

to the throne, the triumph of reason over belief and historical thinking over dogma takes place

in England giving superiority to freedom and human rights as learned from the cycle of

history. The cycle of events in question has taught humanity the lesson that the true religious

motive is not to seek perfection by the example of Christ, but to improve the world by that

example: “[T]he wisdom of divine rule appears not in the perfection but in the improvement

of the world; and that achieved liberty is the one ethical result that rests on the converging

and combined conditions of advancing civilisation. Then you will understand […] that

History is the true demonstration of Religion” (31-32). As humanity is indebted to the Dutch

Revolution for freedom of belief, to the English nation for constitutional state rule, to the

American nation for federation republicanism, to the French Revolution for equality,
19

fraternity and freedom, modern man’s share is to study these historical turning points to make

the world a better place.

Acton points to the second half of the 19th century as the time when historiography

and studies of history reached a kind of climax with the opening of papal archives to more

researchers and the rise of documentary studies. Although these sources have long been

available to the individual members of privileged circles, the true historians and researchers

of history have lately understood that “the main thing to learn is not the art of accumulating

material, but the sublimer art of investigating it, of discerning truth from falsehood, and

certainty from doubt. It is by solidity of criticism more than by the plenitude of erudition,

that the study of history strengthens, and straightens, and extends the mind” (40). This

investigation of the historical material brings about the questions regarding the reliability of

the sources, as historians have so far done nothing more than interpreting some other texts,

which are interpretations themselves. Along with these, history-writing is always questioned

with the level of the historian’s impartiality in terms of his political, religious and moral

stance as juxtaposed with his target material. To overcome such potential charges, Acton

argues that “history, to be above evasion or dispute, must stand on documents, not on

opinions […] Ideas which, in religion and in politics, are truths, in history are forces. They

must be respected; they must not be affirmed. [B]y a timely and discreet indifference […]

history might be lifted above contention, and made an accepted tribunal, and the same for

all” (45-46). Acton’s conviction stems obviously from a naïve belief that true sincerity is

possible in narrating historical events, as he looks convinced that an unshakable devotion to

‘evident morality’ in history-writing has the power to piece opposite poles together. He sees

it as the historian’s moral duty to refrain from any kind of judgment and to investigate the

past with neutrality and dubiousness in the face of political, religious and moral imperatives.
20

History, for Acton, is also an inevitably cumulative entity that relies on the principle

of causation in the form of a never-ending chain of events. It is liable to the “law of

continuous growth which has transformed history from a chronicle of casual occurrences into

the likeness of something organic” (56). In such a long, ceaseless tradition of recording the

truthful past, the modern historian is expected to take their forefathers as role models in talent

and knowledge, but not to remain limited within their horizons. The historians of the modern

era, compared to the old ones, have the capacity and chance to stay “more rigidly impersonal,

disinterested and just […] and to learn from undisguised and genuine records to look with

remorse upon the past, and to the future with assured hope of better things” (74). Acton

concludes that, by keeping this idea in mind, history keeps nations standing with strong ties

of religion and state power.

Hayden White, in his seminal study on the contemporary historical studies titled The

Content of the Form: Narrative Discourse and Historical Representation, discusses the place

of narrativity in historical representation and traces the journey of historical theory from

Droysen’s Historik through Foucault and Jameson’s ideas to Ricoeur’s philosophy of history.

In this respect, following White’s chronological classification will give a comprehensive

understanding of the contemporary theory of history and historiography with special

attention to the development of historical thought and changing the perception of the same

concepts.

White begins his discussion of history as a form of narration with the inevitable

human impulse to ‘narrate’ what really happened and to assimilate experience into more

fashionable facets in such a disruptive way that reality is transformed step-by-step into

unauthentic versions. In his understanding, such an urge leads narrator only to the extremes

where meaning is always refused. He names some historians or, to be more precise,
21

historiographers like Tocqueville, Huizinga and Braudel who choose not to use the forms

that are generally associated with storytelling in their treatment of historical data. Such an

approach helps White distinguish between the two basic historical discourses: one that

narrates without using the traditional ‘triangular’ structure of a story and one that narrativizes

using literary techniques of plot construction; “between a discourse that openly adopts a

perspective that looks out on the world and reports it and a discourse that feigns to make the

world speak itself and speak itself as a story” (2). White questions historiography’s stance

in-between these two approaches to reporting of the real and asks whether it is possible for

the ‘history-tellers’ to refrain themselves from the attractiveness of the imaginary over the

actual. He rightfully assumes that, whether narrated or narrativized, real events are doomed

to pass through the filter of ‘representation’ pretending to be the reality itself.

White mentions three nonnarrative forms of historical representation – annals,

chronicles and history proper – the first two of which do not satisfy the expectations from a

set of historical events to have a structure, interconnection, logical sequence, cause and effect

relation and overall meaning, where narration treads the borders. The annals, among these

two forms, are always incomplete in their listing of the historical events, as they are never

interested in hows or whys, but in whats and whens, though inaccurately. In any case, these

representative records disguise themselves under the veil of the ‘real’ rather than the

‘imaginary’, even though they lack the stimulation to attribute social, political or moral

importance to the events they catalogue. The participation of narrativity stems from an urge

to moralize the historical events within the political, social and moral system in an inevitably

authoritative way. The chronicle, on the other hand, is known to be a superior form of

historical representation in comparison with the annals, in the former’s classification of its

subject under coherent titles and detailing of the events chronicled. However, modern
22

scholarship denies the chronicle the claim to official history due to its failure to provide these

chain of events with a proper closure, connection or an all-encompassing meaning even if it

provides the reader with specific subject matter, location, and point of view. The narrative

structure of each article in the chronicle brings the form close to modern-time historical

narratives, but it, at the same time, decreases its objectivity in line with the ‘point of view’

included. And it is also crucial to note that, by the time the chronicle began to be used as a

form of historical representation, history-writing had already become an institutional

endeavour, mainly hovering around the church, and it inescapably represented the authorial

understanding of the past rather than the past as it really was. Speaking of an authorial

influence on history-writing, White mentions a multi-layered structure including the patrons,

the sources of inspiration and the historian himself as parties that impose shapes to the

shapeless past. The history proper, in that respect, differs from the other two in its

acknowledgment of the necessity to give historical data a coherent, desirable discourse

without missing out the fact that every narrative is open to argument and refutation in its

claim to originality: “In order to qualify as historical, an event must be susceptible to at least

two narrations of its occurrence. Unless at least two versions of the same set of events can be

imagined, there is no reason for the historian to take upon himself the authority of giving the

true account of what really happened” (20). By offering closure and meaning to the past

events, the history claims that it gives the ideal shape to reality among many other options.

The version of reality that can give the most desirable shape to it achieves recognition by the

majority.

The fact that historical narratives bring about the desire for a meaningful conclusion

can closely be related to the moral guardianship of the authority figures in the history of

mankind. Once the narrative gets involved in the recording of historical events, some
23

invisible force fills in the gaps, offers moral solutions to some social or political ills and

centralizes some ideological outlook while marginalizing the others. By doing so, historical

narratives survive within those moral and ideological outlooks as well as helping them

survive, too. The moral message drawn from the set of historical events also strengthens the

sense of closure in the way a didactic literary work leaves the reader satisfied and more

comfortable. Furthermore, such moral preoccupations give the historical narrative a

‘realistic’ consciousness, as it leaves no room for the imaginary gap-fillings of the addressee

of that historical narration and it also satisfies the desire to find consistency, relationality,

completeness and stability in the representation of real events.

White, then, moves on to the examination of the concept of ‘narrative’ in the

representation of historical events which lays claim, in itself, to the domain of sciences. He

openly questions the validity of narrative structures in the scientific field and describes the

narrative mode of representation as “an index of a failure at once methodological and

theoretical […], one that investigates its data in the interest of telling a story about them

[which] appears methodologically deficient” (26). Although the extent to which narrative is

used in the representation of historical data depends on the focus point of the historiographer

being the event itself or the analysis of its circumstances, the issue of narrativity, by

definition, is inevitably bound to the intrusions of imagination. In this respect, the distinction

between the documented history and fiction lies in their subject matter rather than their mode

of representation. The more faithfully a narrative describes a historical event, the more easily

it can be taken as a true historical account: “The story told in a narrative is a mimesis of the

story lived in some region of historical reality, and insofar as it is an accurate imitation, it is

to be considered a truthful account thereof” (27). However, the dissertative tendencies of the

historian must also be taken into account in order to distinguish the amount of facts from
24

comments or historical accuracy from interpretation. To emphasize the necessity for such a

distinction, White quotes Hegel in the latter’s search for a ‘pragmatic’ interest that stimulates

the historian’s desire to narrate and preserve certain historical happenings. As Hegel relates

that pragmatic motivation to politics, it is justifiable that professional historiography has

always had an ideological side to it, as it basically served as a means of representation and,

thus, maintenance of the political identity of nations.

The discussions over the nature and functions of narrative structures in historiography

can be categorized under four approaches that dominated the theory of history in the second

half of the 20th century. First among these comes the Anglo-American philosophers of

narrative including Walsh, Gardiner, Dray and few others who stressed the inseparable ties

between narratives and reality which make it a suitable mode for historical representations.

The second group includes such French historians as Braudel, Furet and Le Goff among

others who endeavoured to disconfirm narrative’s claims to historical truth in an attempt to

exclude history from the domain of science. The third approach to the theory of history is

initiated by some other French philosophers of literature including Foucault, Derrida,

Barthes, Todorov and Genette who questioned the nature of narrative as a linguistic referent

of history. And finally comes philosophers like Gadamer and Ricoeur who focused on the

hermeneutical nature of narratives as time-bound accounts (31).

Among these four theoretical positions, White pays special attention to the second,

which he names shortly as the French ‘Annales, in their critical approach to representative

potentials of narratives in history-writing. For these theorists, documented history in the

narrative form has always been closer to literature than science in terms of its fictive

representation of mainly political turning points and the content of historiography must be

limited to more objective processes like economics and demography rather than politics.
25

They believe that “narrative is inherently ‘dramatizing’ or ‘novelizing’ of its subject matter,

as if dramatic events either did not exist in history or, if they did exist, were by virtue of their

dramatic nature not a fit object of historical study” (33). However, White draws attention to

the fact that narrativizing is possible without dramatizing, and dramatizing is possible

without theatricalizing; thus, the Annales’ discontent with the potentials of narrative sounds

conclusory. The philosophers of the following generation obviously do a better job in terms

of revealing narrative’s partiality and susceptibility to ideological interventions. Among

these structuralist and post-structuralist thinkers, Claude Levi-Strauss treats narrative

historiography as pure ‘myth-making’ which is incorrectly taken for granted as what really

happened in the past: “The specific chronological scale used for this ordering procedure is

always culture-specific and adventitious, a purely heuristic device the validity of which

depends upon the specific aims and interests of the specific discipline in which it is used”

(34). In this respect, the number of historical narratives is dependent on the number of the

interested parties, which shakes their safe ground as representatives of human history.

Similarly, Roland Barthes’ seminal essay “The Discourse of History” (1967) also

questions the seeming difference between the discourses used in historiography and fiction,

by pointing out the ideological nature of any narrative account and referring to historical

narratives as ‘constructs’ rather than ‘discoveries’ put on paper: “[H]istorical discourse is in

its essence a form of ideological elaboration, or to put it more precisely, an imaginary

elaboration […], a speech act […] through which the utterer of the discourse (a purely

linguistic entity) ‘fills out’ the place of the subject of the utterance (a psychological or

ideological entity)” (Barthes, 1986:138). White explains Barthes’ distrust of historical

discourse with respect to its subjective nature by which it is used to make definitions of

communities in a narcissistic way and to make meanings rather than discover realities.
26

The discussions about narrative historiography in the last century have all been based

on the efforts to put it under the category of ‘science’ or, contrarily, to reveal the ideological

subjectivity that stimulates the writing of the historical account. The first vein of argument

treats historical narratives as a means of communication between different periods of time

by which a message is transmitted from the past through the present time to an infinite future

and interpreted from the present point of view. The central incentive in this process of

interpretation is human logic which, at the same time, is the active force behind the validation

and coherence of that interpretation, by consigning the representation to the domain of

causality. In this respect, there is a reciprocal relationship between two historical events in

their narrative representations, as the former explains the existence of the other whereas the

latter illuminates the importance of the former. Besides the necessity for a causal coherence,

believability of a historical narrative is also linked to the correspondence of the story to the

facts in the most faithful way possible. The historical account must be so accurate that it

should still invoke the same causality, coherence and correspondence in the minds of the

readers even when the narrative structure is extracted from it: “[T]he narrative code adds

nothing in the way of information or knowledge that could not be conveyed by some other

system of discursive encodation” (41). In short, the theorists who emphasize the

communicative function of historical narratives pay more attention to the content of the

narrative rather than its form and connotations of fictitiousness, which stands only for

embellishment.

The first line of argument, however, bears in itself a huge controversy in terms of its

openness to innumerable possible interpretations regarding the cause and effect relationship

between two events in the same historical line or that the sense of logical coherence easily

differs from one point of view to the other. As the interpretation concerns not a single event
27

in history, but a chain of events that affect each other, the complexity of the account reaches

unimaginable levels along with the number of differently-interpretable encoded messages:

“Every narrative code consists […] of a complex set of codes the interweaving of which by

the author – for the production of a story infinitely rich in suggestion and variety of effect

[…] – attests to his talents as an artist, as master rather than servant of the codes available for

his use” (42). As an opposition to this communicative model, the other line of argument deals

with the narrative not as just a tool for conveying information from the referent to the

recipient, but as an active participant in the meaning-making process. In other words, the

narrative structure is not just a structure that gives just the shape to the objective

representation, but an intrinsic element of the story which ‘contaminates’ the content in some

ideological direction. This is the basic difference between a chronicle and historical narrative,

not in terms of a difference in their content, but in terms of their treatment of the same

informational content. In other words, ‘narrativization’ is different from ‘chronicalization’ in

that the former “impos[es] a discursive form on the events that its own chronicle comprises

by means that are poetic in nature” (42), which gives prominence to the stylistic outfit of the

narrative discourse. Compared to the chronicle, historical narrative offers not only the event,

but also a comment on the event in an attentively-woven cultural context directed to an

intended population. However, this does not mean that historical narratives do not possess

any grain of truth; they obviously take a share from the actual past in the way works of fiction

are not totally independent from reality. To elaborate more on the relationship between

historical narratives and literature, White continues:

Historical discourse differentiates itself from literary discourse by virtue of its


subject matter (‘real’ than ‘imaginary’ events) rather than its form. […] The
historical narrative does not […] dispel false beliefs about the past, human
life, the nature of the community, and so on; what it does is test the capacity
of a culture’s fictions to endow real events with the kinds of meaning that
28

literature displays to consciousness through its fashioning of patterns of


‘imaginary’ events. (44-45)

This brings the discussion of historical narratives, in the structuralist and post-structuralist

sense, to the conclusion that historical narratives are still somehow within the domain of

reality even though they display ideological additions; this makes such accounts not literary,

but allegorical on the level of meaning suggestion.

The hermeneutic philosophers, on the other hand, emphasize the potentials of

translating one discursive formation to another in the making of historical meanings.

Gadamer and Ricoeur argue that interpreting one discursive account from another temporal

standpoint within the same tradition is sufficient to achieve historical accuracy. Their view

of history gives prominence to understanding the past rather than explaining it, by which they

dismiss history from the domain of sciences, very much like understanding a literary text

without the prior need to explain it. “In the process of attaining this understanding,

explanations of various sorts are called for, in much the same way that explanations of ‘what

happened’ in any story are called for on the way to the story’s full elaboration” (50). Ricoeur

forms an analogy between human actions in the past and written texts, and calls for an

understanding of the historical events as a whole by paying special attention to the causes,

circumstances and consequences in the same way a reader has to understand the connections

between individual sentences to grasp an overall meaning of the text itself. He sees plot as

an essential motive in historical representation, as it is the element that organizes the events

in a logical order which is what makes the composition meaningful; in other words, historical

narratives can make sense only when they present the historical event in a way to be easily

pictured by the reader. Ricoeur, in this way, places narrativity within the category of symbolic

configuration whose significance does not lie in its factuality or believability of content, but
29

in its character as an image to be interpreted and made sense of. “For Ricoeur, then, narrative

is more than a mode of explanation, more than a code, and much more than a vehicle for

conveying information. […] It is a means of symbolizing events without which their

historicality cannot be indicated” (53). So, the historical knowledge lies in the decoding of

the symbolic meaning attributed to the linguistic representation of the historical event; in

other words, the accuracy of the historical representation is ultimately connected with the

success of the narrative structure in coherently encoding the symbolic meaning within the

language.

It is crucial to understand what White means by “the politics of historical

interpretation” in order to grasp how historical narratives are created and why they are chosen

among many other potential interpretative strategies. For White, a disinterested interpretation

is never possible when the interpreter’s political and moral tendencies are taken into

consideration; yet, it is always possible for the interpreter to ‘dissolve’ these political and

moral impulses into a strategy of interpretation through which he comes up with a new

discipline; hence, discipline and sublimation. History as a field of study is one of the few

disciplines among all social and practical sciences that do not claim the authority to ‘explain’

the causes and consequences of their subject matter, but comply with just ‘understanding’ it.

However, in the modern times, there has always been a tendency to make a discipline out of

historical studies by using or abusing the frailty of history’s narrative and interpretative

nature into certain political directions. White attributes the beginning of such tendencies to

the early 19th century in which history was used as a political and social tool to consolidate

the power of the newly-rising bourgeoisie. With an aim to reconstruct the nation-state on new

social and political bases, the bourgeois authorities encourage their historians to interpret and

re-interpret historical sources to come up with an ‘official’ history with a claim to the highest
30

standard of realism. White refers to Hannah Arendt’s seminal essay “The Concept of

History” to explain that, after the French Revolution, politics began to contaminate historical

accounts more in favour of the totalitarian governments against the rising individualism and

statements of human rights: “The politicalization of historical thinking was a virtual

precondition of its own professionalization, the basis of its promotion to the status of a

discipline worthy of being taught in the universities, and a prerequisite of whatever

‘constructive’ social function historical knowledge was thought to serve” (62). The discipline

of history is the product of a ‘utopian’ outlook upon which the authority bases the past in

accordance with the ideal present it aims to build, setting the morals, values and rules on its

inferences from the lived past.

The conception of history as a discipline leaves the floor open for a never-ending

battle between historians and history philosophers in their different approaches to the same

subject matter, a clash between disciplined and undisciplined thinking, in search of an

ideological explanation to the past and an attempt to expose it, respectively. Before the 19th

century, which marks the beginning of historical studies as a scientific discipline, the study

of history had more of an eclectic nature, an interdisciplinary essence, as it was handled as a

supplementary field in the study of politics, philosophy, arts and science. The past, in the 18th

century understanding of history for instance, was seen as a model from which moral lessons,

traditional ties and cautionary drives were extracted by means of a chronological ordering

and classification, as can be seen in the annals tradition. Such conception of history served

two purposes, one being the teaching and expansion of Christian ideals, and the other being

the development of the western civilization, which led to the Enlightenment, by the lessons

taken from the tradition. White, here, evokes Kant’s examination of historical knowledge in

which he came up with three potential outcomes of the historical process; the first being a
31

constant development of humanity in any possible way, the second being a constant

retrogression of human kind in any possible way, and the last one being humanity making no

headway at all. He, then, comes to the conclusion that, in the three possible ways, the

politicalization of historical knowledge is inevitable and the turning of studies of history into

a discipline ultimately establishes it as the “arbitrator of the realism of contending political

programs, each attended by its own philosophy of history” (65).

From Aristotle on, liberating history from political rhetoric has always been an

attempt to emphasize the necessary distinction between the real and the imaginary, between

the verifiable data and fictitious creation. Such a distinction cripples the potentials of

imagination in historical thinking and dooms historical knowledge to the listing of provable

facts and short descriptive captions. With the initiation of the romantic aesthetics, the concept

of imagination was basically associated with sentimentality, personal taste and sensitiveness

to external stimuli; the same principle entailed historical representation to be proper, within

the framework of what is considered ‘beautiful’, along with having a proper object:

The imagination […] operates on a different level of the historian’s


consciousness. It is present above all in the effort, peculiar to the modern
conceptualization of the historian’s task, to enter sympathetically into the
minds or consciousness of human agents long dead, to empathize with the
intentions and motivations of actors impelled by beliefs and values that may
differ totally from anything the historian might himself honour in his own life,
and to understand, even when he cannot condone, the most bizarre social and
cultural practices. This is often described as putting oneself in the place of past
agents, seeing things from their point of view, and so forth, all of which leads
to a notion of objectivity that is quite different from anything that might be
meant by that term in the physical sciences (67).
In this respect, modern theory of history emphasizes history not as an imaginary account, but

as an imaginative one written by historians whose capabilities are not limited to the recording

of minute details, but sufficient to make them think in the way the agents of the past thought

from the latter’s perspective. However, imagination must not be forced into the domain of
32

fabrication and the imaginative historian must stick to verifiable, interpretable sources in his

relation of the texts to the contexts.

In the fourth chapter of his The Content of the Form, White refers to the German line

of historical studies that flourished especially after the Second World War as a means to deal

with the nation’s turbulent immediate past. As White argues, this German vein of historical

discourse excavated the glorious idealistic past of the nation to extract some lessons to use

that glory this time without verging on extremisms like Nazism. Along with Treitschke and

Sybel, Droysen is one of the pioneers of the German tradition of historiography which he

keeps subjectively related to politics, and his historical writings have been accused of having

deep moralistic and ideological undertones. “He is now generally regarded as the founder of

a discourse that, while both theoretical and systematic, is consistent with the ideals of the

humanistic tradition incarnated for many Germans in the figure of Goethe” (84). Droysen’s

seminal three-volume work Historik deals with a long range of time from Alexander the

Great through the Hellenistic period to the contemporary Prussian monarchy which he views

as the successor of the former two. Droysen believes that history writing is motivated by an

urge to put theory into practice in a sceptically speculative way to achieve realist bourgeois

morals. White describes this as an “in house discourse, product of a discussion within the

dominant class on how to give its own historically determinate existence the odour of

ideality” (86). In this respect, Droysen seems fully aware of the political and social powers

of ‘his’ historical discourse by which he reappropriates the moral judgments of the dominant

group, the estates of Schleswig and Holstein in the Prussian case, as ‘the’ law by which all

citizens must wholeheartedly abide. Such an approach turns historiography into a means of

representation of what happened in the past rather than the thing itself, a category of values

rather than an objective account of the lived past.


33

Droysen’s open acknowledgment of the moralistic and ideological nature of historical

accounts incapacitates the whole tradition of historical criticism which challenges originality

of historical writings by their subjective tendencies. In this respect, his conception of

historiography offers less “a theory of historical composition than a kind of phenomenology

of historical reading [and] he instructs historians in how to produce different readings of

history so as to engender different kinds of moral perspectives in their readers” (88), which

is why his work is often classified under the title ‘historical hermeneutics’ rather than

constrained categories that view history as a science. This view begins historical accounts

with the determination of the norms by which the historical event will be represented along

with the objectives to be pursued. Droysen regards the past as a domain which is distant to

the present in its ‘pastness’, but also somehow related to it with respect to the cause and effect

principle. He leaves an open door to the free play of human imagination in interpreting the

historical past, as he believes that the past is comprehensible as long as it is imaginable from

the present point of view, and realistic as long as it creates a sense of ‘real’ in the mind of the

reader. “[I]n his discussion of the problem of representation, Droysen makes clear that he

regards the content of the historian’s discourse, not as the facts or events that comprise his

manifest referent, but as his understanding of these facts and the moral implications he draws

from their contemplation” (90).

Droysen, in a way, equates the content of historical discourse with the objective of it,

listing four potential categories by which the discourse acquires a character: investigative,

narrative, didactic and discussive. Even though the subject of different historical discourses

may be the same, the motivation of the historiographer in writing about that particular

historical event changes the discourse’s character. Among these four kinds, Droysen gives

priority to discussive form of historical discourse, as he believes it is the one which achieves
34

the highest level of relevance between the time in which the account was written and the time

in which it is being read. Droysen’s ‘presentist’ tendencies are displayed more clearly in his

conception of the nature of historical knowledge which he connects directly to its traceability

in the present time: “This gives the ‘form’ of a specifically historical existence, which is

nothing other than the sense of the historicity of the present engendered by the intuition that

we are at once continuous with our past and distinctly different from it” (92). Offering an

understanding to the remains of a particular historical event in the present time calls for the

interference of ‘interpretation’ as the only means to make sense of the past, inevitably from

a particular ethical, ideological and intellectual point of view.

Droysen lists four operative motivations in the interpretation of historical data being

“(1) the individual’s immediate practical aims and needs, (2) the material conditions of his

time and place, (3) the character type and elements of personal will of the individual, and (4)

the moral principles of the culture to which the individual belongs” (92). Some, or all, of

these categories inform the historian’s understanding and interpretation of the historical

matter in question and these categories define four basic types of interpretation of historical

events; pragmatic, conditional, psychological and ethical (93). With reference to these types

of interpretation, Droysen challenges the claim of the realist vein of historians to absolute

truth, and reduces those representations to the category of ‘plausible’ rather than ‘realistic’,

the category Aristotle attributed to poetry. He contrasts the job of a historian with that of a

landscape painter in that the latter’s object of representation lies before his eyes whereas the

former’s is both present, in the form of inherited images to be assimilated into human

understanding, and absent to him. Droysen lists four stages of historical representation

through which the historical past is brought to ‘light’ and made sense of in the present time:

investigation, narration, didacticism and discussion. First of all, the historical object of
35

inquiry is located by the historian in a chain of documented past events, then this object is

patterned into a narrative structure by which it represents the historical action in a plausible

cause and effect framework, and then the narrative is interpreted to extract a moral for

instruction of the present readership, and finally the moral extracted is discussed within

contemporary social, political and moral contexts. Droysen also relates these four stages of

historical representation to the earlier four modes of historical interpretation, the stages in the

former category being applicable to any mode of interpretation in the latter. The ultimate aim

of the historian, Droysen concludes, is not to fabricate an objective, impartial account of the

historical event, but to put forward a ‘proper’, inevitably partial version of it to the

understanding of an intended readership: “Since man has his historical existence in his

membership in a number of fragmentary circles of ‘commonality’ […] –natural, ideal, and

practical – his perspective on reality is necessarily ‘parteilich’” (95).

In Droysen’s view, historical representation is more or less a secular version of

theology in that both investigate questions concerning the whole humanity and try to reach a

universal moral framework for the benefit of it. In the same respect, the number of historical

realities being multiple can be related to the number of moral ideals extracted from the same

religion being multiple. Droysen, here, puts the emphasis on the concept of freedom of belief

and choice by which every single individual interprets the same historical event from

different points of view and reach different moral lessons:

The historically real is never given by naked ‘experience’; it is always already


worked up and fashioned by a specific organization of experience, the praxis
of the society from within which the picture of reality is conceptualized. This
is why, no doubt, he placed such emphasis on the possibility of conceiving
alternative but equally valid images of historical reality and sought to classify
them and to rank them by type. Such images would be as various as the kinds
of socially organized experience permitted by the praxis of any given age (98).
36

Such a subjectivity, however, never appears to bother Droysen in the way that it discomforts

philosophers like Marx and Nietzsche who always challenge history’s claim to historical

truth as a grand narrative. Droysen views this subjective, fictitious nature of historical

representation as a necessary element by which the bourgeois standpoint he has long adopted

gains its strength and its values are justified. In this respect, Droysen’s conception of history

is “nothing but a sublimation, a raising to consciousness, of the practice of society itself […]

given a specific content that can be identified with the social praxis of the historian’s own

lived present” (96-97). White approaches Droysen’s conceptualization with the

understanding that history has always been inquired in its potential relations to the social,

political, economic, moral, religious, pedagogical realities of the time of the inquiry. From

this point of view, it is quite understandable that Droysen viewed history and historical

representation as a means to validate, to advertise and to promote the bourgeois ideology and

morality in the 19th century when these were promising a new social and economic order

feeding on the premises of French Revolution and Romanticism. Although Droysen’ outlook

disconfirms history’s claims to the level of objective sciences, it must still be regarded as, in

White words, a “cultural superstructure of an age, as an activity that is more determined by

than determinative of social praxis” (101). Through its own historical representation, each

social praxis contributes to the formation of a ‘reality’ which can also be traced in the rise of

‘realism’ in literature in the 19th century, especially in the naturalistic novel tradition in which

each story poses its own claim to writing a history.

Foucault’s arguments about discourse in its obscurity and extravagance characterize

his whole philosophical system which depends on his refusal of an origin and centre for the

Western thought, culture and civilization. In his close inquiry of the genealogy of these, he

traces the turning points in the history of science, philosophy and arts to come up with a
37

chronicle or an archaeological structure of ‘knowledge’ or to prove the nonexistence of it.

The histories that Foucault offers us are always fragmented, disconnected stories that provide

no logical cause and effect relationship or a coherence with a set of gaps inbetween, as the

discourse always stems from an individual, subjective desire to know and to achieve power.

However subjective, the individual’s discourse is always informed by the ‘external restraints’

that determine the right, reasonable, proper and central on the one hand, and wrong,

unreasonable, improper and marginal, on the other, in a social structure. Foucault aims to

frustrate the attempts to centralize discourse under the domination of a subject or a means of

representation by what he calls the conventionalist theories of discourse. By doing so, he

strives to liberate the discourse for its natural free play in order to make the individual ‘will

to truth’ dominant. Therefore, Foucault argues that, since language was located at the centre

of all representative activities, there has been a critical ‘mutation’ in the development of the

Western thought in that each discursive representation has obscured reality. In other words,

“reality inevitably took on the aspects of the linguistic mode in which it was presented to

consciousness” (123). In this respect, the whole historical knowledge appears to be the

product of a linguistic system that derives its motivation from the discourse of power in its

endless conflict with the discourse of desire. Foucault also realizes that the line of historical

knowledge is a fragmented structure, full of gaps inbetween the distinctive movements of an

epoch, as history only sees wherever the knowledge looks, displaying no origin or

connection.

In his Order of Things, Foucault deems history the oldest of human sciences, going

all the way back to the beginning of human culture and memory. History has always been in

the background of other human sciences, informing them in the form of ‘traditions’ and

enabling them to be passed down across centuries. History had been following a straight
38

chronological line until the 19th century, Foucault argues, when there occurred a revolution

in the way human beings had the knowledge of things, and a discovery that every single

individual being had its own independent history from the master historical narratives. At

that time, “the historicity discovered within man was extended to the objects he had made,

the language he spoke, and – even further still – to life” (402). From then on, human beings

subjected themselves to the histories of others in order to verify their existences. Human

beings acquired the knowledge that they contributed to the continuance of a historical line of

thoughts, actions and habits and, at the same time, attributed an identity to their own existence

by the same line; they defined and were defined by it. Foucault claims that 19th century marks

the beginning of historical studies as an independent discipline, as history-writing abandoned

simple chronicling of events and began to pay attention to the historical progress as a whole

with respect to the developments, turning points, cause and effect relationships and

generalizing laws in due process.

In The Archaeology of Knowledge, Foucault elaborates on the changing nature of

historical studies, saying: “history has altered its position in relation to the document: it has

taken as its primary task, not the interpretation of the document, nor the attempt to decide

whether it is telling the truth or what is its expressive value, but to work on it from within

and to develop it” (6). In other words, Foucault emphasizes the fact that history has

transformed from an attempt to transmit documents across generations into a discipline that

writes, rewrites, explains, defines and assigns new meanings to the past in order to make it

more understandable for the present human consciousness. History has the power to change

memories into texts and texts into monuments by revealing the silent or silenced voices or

‘inert traces’ underneath what is being shown to the present consciousness. Foucault lists

three types of historical analysis separated from each other in their approach to the
39

constitutive elements of a field of study. In the first category, the history of a given discipline

is treated as a clinical case in which the historian makes definitions of discovered historical

items, forms connections between them, arrives at a cause and effect relationship and finally

forms generalizations useful for the formation of that discipline. Second category of historical

analysis approaches the historical data in a similar scientific way, not to understand and digest

them into the formation of the discipline, but to reveal the secret metaphorical meanings lying

beneath the surface indications in order to understand why and how a certain concept comes

to meet the necessities in that particular discipline. In the third way of historical analysis, on

the other hand, scientificity is set aside in the name of displaying the linguistic and discursive

structures that attribute meanings to the historical knowledge used in the formation of that

discipline (189-190).

White claims that Marxists have a different view of history, regarding it not as a

means to know what happened in the past, but as a source to determine the social, political

and economic laws operative in the formation of social structures in the past, and thus,

influential on present ones. And contrary to the general view, Marxism has not only been a

critical social philosophy, but a constructive and therapeutic outlook which found a voice in

the visionary, sometimes utopian, discourse of the artists of the early 20th century. These

Marxist artists have made use of history as a catalogue of attempts at human liberation on

various levels, mostly unsuccessful, and offered alternative paths to redeem those

victimizations. Works of art, in this respect, come forward as the proofs that humans are

capable of constructing better social formations and political systems, or at least imagining

them. Fredric Jameson, the Marxist literary theorist best known for his The Political

Unconscious: Narrative as a Socially Symbolic Act (1981), invests narrative with the

authority to turn raw material or the content of art into a meaningful entity to realize the
40

abovementioned utopian visionary outlook. In Jameson’s understanding, adopting a Marxist

critical approach to literary texts is never enough; instead, true Marxist critics must develop

“something like an ultimate [Marxist] semantic precondition for the intelligibility of literary

and cultural texts” (60). The literary and cultural texts, in Jameson’s Marxist approach, are

to be pictured as a web of symbols related to political history, the social context in question

and the relevant history of social and economic systems. In other words, all texts have to be

read as the product of the political, socio-economic and moral conditions of the time they

were written in with special attention to the ideological messages embedded in symbols.

White asserts that literary and cultural texts are “rendered intelligible […] by their

systematic insertion into ‘history’ that is conceived to be not only sequenced but also layered

in such a way as to require different methods of analysis at the different levels on which it

achieves the integrity of what is normally thought of as the ‘style’ of a ‘period’” (146). A

Marxist critic, in this respect, is expected to pay special attention to the causality behind every

text’s expressive particularities comprised solely of the author’s or the age’s desire to be

situated in a particular historical sequence rather than a necessity to be situated in any other.

This opens the issue of historical representation, going back to Aristotle, to the charge of

imaginary intrusions of what could have happened in the form of what really happened. As

historical experiences cannot be experienced again under the same circumstances, at least not

in the same temporal conditions, historical knowledge gains a similar status to that of

rhetorical discussion or textualized imagination, which is never more than what literature sets

forth. Jameson, as a Marxist critic, deals with the realist texts’ ideological nature and claims

to historical truth and argues that the capacity to narrativize equals the capacity to locate a

particular event into the chain of history; and in texts whose narrative structure is either

fragmented or non-existent, it is not possible to find a patterned plot to be documented as


41

historical representation. In other words, narrativity becomes a necessity for literary and

cultural texts to achieve historical accuracy of whose promises a ‘future present’ will define

itself as a fulfilment: “Considered as a transition between a past and a future, every present

is at once a realization of projects performed by past human agents and a determination of a

field of possible projects to be realized by living human agents in their future” (149). Jameson

calls this process ‘narratological causation’ which can best be observed in artistic and cultural

movements like modernism or romanticism, as they are the cumulative and dialectical

representations of earlier experiences. For instance, romanticism can best be defined as a

combination of a nostalgic idealization of a remote past – basically the medieval times- and

the premises of the French Revolution among other motivations. This view liberates

historical accounts from the accusations of time- and place-boundedness, as, in Jameson’s

understanding, “historical epochs are not monolithically integrated social formations but, on

the contrary, complex overlays of different modes of production that serve as the bases of

different social groups and classes and, consequently of their world-views” (156).

In a direct Marxist outlook, Jameson also attributes great powers to narrativity,

because the historical epochs gain their status by uncovering the historical processes that lead

to their own formation in a narrative structure in this long chain of causations. He believes,

in White’s words, that “narrativity not only represents but justifies, by virtue of its

universality, a dream of how ideal community might be achieved. […] The dialectical

movement by which a unity of plot is imposed upon the superficial chaos of story elements,

narrative serves as a paradigm of the kind of social movement by which a unity of meaning

can be imposed upon the chaos of history” (157). As many Marxist literary critics do,

Jameson directs his attention to the realist texts, especially novels, of the 19th century as the

detailed narrativized versions of a lived history in the form of social and cultural documents
42

that reveal the consciousness, aspirations and fantasies of the bourgeois class. He attributes

considerable importance to the novel genre as a mode of historical representation, as it turns

out to be the ideal means to reveal the ideological implications beneath the surface human

actions and the very form of the representation, which is the narrative. He believes that the

realist novel paved the way for narrativity to be presumed as a means of historical account

keeping, and the modernist novel established it as a source of innumerable versions of

historical interpretation. And White contends that, in Jameson’s view, a personal history

gains validity as long as it is appropriated into a story which is only a small ring in a chain

of stories; thus, the matter is not representing the past in the most faithful way, but having

enough power, political in this sense, to be able to narrativize the personal past to the attention

of a bigger number of concerned parties and turning these narratives into master narratives.

In his monumental three-volume book titled Time and Narrative (1983,1984,1985),

Ricoeur attempts to come up with new definitions of narrativity and historical discourse as

understood in the modern times, and defines historical narrative as “a kind of allegory of

temporality, but an allegory of a special kind, namely, a true allegory […] assigned [with] a

specific task in the representation of a reality that presents itself to human consciousness […]

as an insoluble but ultimately ‘comprehensible’ mystery” (White, 171). In other words, the

mystery of temporality is made sense of as long as it finds a voice in the discourse of

narrativity and the historical events inherently possess a structure of narrativity, which natural

events do not, in the form of causes, effects, consequences, chronological order, human

agents and their actions leading to one another in a logical sequence. However, Ricoeur’s

conception of narrative history differs dramatically from a story reporting events that have

taken place in a specific past as they happened, of which any newspaper article or official

bill of indictment is also capable. He attributes an inherent ‘structure of temporality’ to the


43

historical discourse which provides it with an air of ‘historicality’ or ‘Geschichtlichkeit’ as

Heidegger puts it (Ricoeur, 1990:62). According to Ricoeur, what grants historical discourse

‘historicality’ is a greater structure of meaning rather than individual sentence meanings, a

greater structure of plot that changes the historical accounts from chronicles to narratives.

Emplotment invests the temporality of human experiences with meaning; but in doing so, it

does not stem from the historian’s imaginary and inventive capacities, but his skills in the

discovery of the already-invented meanings by the actual active participants of the concerned

past. That is, historiographic emplotment is a poetic act not in the sense that it writes stories

on its own account, but that it gives historical events the shape of a narrative without the help

of the historian’s associative faculties (Ricoeur, 1990:68-70). Ricoeur is also aware that

historians have a broader view of the historical events than the performers of them, thanks to

‘the advantages of hindsight’, as White calls it, including the knowledge of all reasons,

motivations, consequences and other forces taking part in the historical agents’ actions.

Ricoeur acknowledges historical discourse’s similarities with literary discourse in

terms of their narrative structure not as a disadvantage for the former on the way to a scientific

status, but as an advantage, because this means that historical discourse achieves that

symbolic linguistic nature, always associated with literary works, which liberates it from

technical and mathematical terminology. This technical and mathematical discourse refers to

the structure of the chronicle, in Ricoeur’s understanding, and it is both unnatural, as the

events are isolated from the contextual elements in such a representation, and selective in the

way that it leaves out some potentially significant details which might have otherwise helped

the reader have a better understanding of the historical event. Yet, Ricoeur does not totally

discard the chronicle out of the process of historical representation. He views the chronicle

as the first level of historical symbolization which, though plotless, gives the historical
44

account its ‘within-time-ness’ or, in other words, its historicality. By historicality, he means

not a simple sequence of events, but an experience of the historical past as a process through

which the knowledge of beginnings, successions and endings of events along with transitions,

transformations and evolvements (White, 1987:177). The part the modern historian must do,

here, is to narrativize these already-historicized accounts and strengthen the accounts’

believability to the human consciousness.

On the level of representation, Ricoeur describes narrative history as a combination

of the historian’s mimetic and diegetic skills going hand in hand to form a factual discourse

whose subject matter is solely the historical past. According to Ricoeur, “narrative discourse

does not simply reflect or passively register a world already made; it works up the material

given in perception and reflection, fashions it, and creates something new, in precisely the

same way that human agents by their actions fashion distinctive forms of historical life”

(White, 1987:178). In the way human agents of the past attempted to give symbolic meanings

to the world around themselves coming up with what we call ‘culture’ today, the historian

uses the symbolic discourse of the narrative to make sense of the same past in the form of an

allegorical temporality.

White argues that the focus of contemporary historical studies has moved away from

the ideas of such philosophers as Hegel, Marx and Dilthey towards new approaches initiated

by thinkers like Benjamin, Barthes, Gadamer, Ricoeur, Foucault and Derrida who

emphasized the treatment of the discourses of historical texts in relation to the discourse of

their contexts. The necessary linkage between the historical texts and contexts seems to

possess a difficulty in itself in deciding the boundaries of one from the other; yet, White sees

this issue as an advantage on behalf of the intellectual historian, as this will lead him/her to

a more dialogistic interpretation than a mere judgmental one. However, White abstains from
45

privileging the Structuralist or Post-Structuralist linguistic approaches to historical

representations, as the former bears the risks of ‘ahistoricity’ whereas the latter cannot set

measures to the imaginative fantasies of the historian (187). In any case, historians of an era

come face to face with the choice between just ‘explaining’ the historical past and

‘interpreting’ or ‘speculating’ on it, which eventually determine the representation’s level of

‘scientificality’ or ‘fictionality’. This calls for a discussion regarding to what extent the

historian is, if at all, responsible towards society or the level of moral and political

intervention in the historian’s representation of the past. As historians have always resorted

to some other branch of social sciences in their historical analysis, their representation can

be said to have always been motivated in one way or another as long as narrativity is involved

in the process. The historians of the 20th century are known basically with their tendency to

adopt a linguistic model in their investigation of historical texts especially after Saussurian

theories come into fashion, as they see their jobs in ‘translating’ the textual meanings encoded

in linguistic structures into the present meaning patterns.

White mentions four ways in forming a relation between the linguistic signs and the

world outside: Language as “(1) a manifestation of causal relationships governing the world

of things in which it arises, in the mode of an index; (2) a representation of that world, in the

mode of an icon (or mimesis); (3) a symbol of that world, in the mode of an analogue […];

(4) […] a sign system […], a code bearing no necessary, or ‘motivated’ relation to that which

it signifies” (189). The first of these approaches is represented by major Marxist and social

determinist intellectuals who understand language as a culmination of social and cultural

forces that has organic observable connections with them. The second outlook has been

adopted by historians and thinkers like Spitzer and Auerbach who view language not as

indicating, but as representing the world outside by means of linguistic rules of grammar and
46

syntax in the way a painting depicts a landscape. The third approach refers to the Hegelian

conception of language as the transformation of the world into symbols that are expected to

have a natural connection with the object in question in the eye of general humanity. In

opposition to these three views of language which presuppose a predetermined connection

between the linguistic sign and the world, the fourth outlook refers to the Saussurian idea

that denies any natural connection between the two, emphasizing the arbitrary nature of

linguistic signification. White claims that this fourth conception of linguistic representation

has not yet been comprehensively adopted by contemporary intellectual historians, which

eventually led to the free play of ideologies in historical interpretation. Using Althusser and

Jameson’s terminology, White problematizes the concept of ‘meaning’ which has always

been produced as a result of the juxtaposition between ideology and science; and thus, reveals

the subjection of historical representation to distortions related to the meaning-making

mechanisms. This issue leads historians to the inevitable choice between a purely linguistic

theory of interpretation, which requires a clinical and analytical approach to the text, and a

semiological effort to form referential connections between the text and other systems of

signs. This second attitude calls for certain scepticism towards the meaning structures

encoded within linguistic signs in terms of their possible privileging of one ideological

referent over another.

There lies a bigger problem under the fact that the sources the historians use in their

narrative histories are themselves ideologically shaped accounts of a given past, as “everyone

recognizes that the way one makes sense of history is important in determining what politics

one will credit as realistic, practicable, and socially responsible” (73). In this respect, the

semiological perspective in historical representation assumes an ideal reader, the target of

the ideological code-shifting, for the text in question whereas the linguistic outlook contents
47

itself with the shapes on the paper and their immediate meanings without the intervention of

any contextual interpretation. The former “seeks, first of all, to identify the hierarchy of codes

that is established in the process of the text’s elaboration, in which, one or more emerge as

seemingly self-evident, obvious, natural ways of making sense of the world” (202). This

process always involves what White calls ‘the dissolution of the ego’ into a mode of

representation and setting the boundaries of meaning to avoid certain readership while

inspiriting some other. As historical events are only accessible through their ‘artefacts’ which

are textual in essence, all historical texts display at first glance a direct referential structure

according to the one-to-one correspondence principle, each sign corresponding to one, and

only one, referent in the past in question. But what is called a historical inquiry must concern

itself with the metaphorical and rhetorical aspects of the linguistic system, the indirect

referentiality of linguistic signs, too.

1.2. A Brief History of Metadramatic Theatre in the Modern Times

What characterizes post-modernist drama, even post-modernist literature in general, is an

intense self-reflexivity and self-referentiality used as techniques to address contemporary

debates like the ethics, responsibilities and functions of artistic works along with an attempt

to problematize the process of artistic production beyond meaning-making. After the term

metafiction gained high popularity in the theorization of modernist and post-modernist

fiction, a similar tendency occurred in the description of some modernist and post-modernist

dramatic works, leading to Lionel Abel’s coinage of the term ‘metatheatre’ in his 1963 book

titled Metatheatre: A New View of Dramatic Form. In the preface to the book, Abel calls for

the necessity to designate a term for a new wave of dramatic works, having its roots within a
48

long tradition from Shakespeare to Brecht, even though he expresses his openness for a

change in the naming of the genre. He defines metatheatre as “a dramatic form for revealing

characters whose self-consciousness create their dramatic situation” (2003:6).

In his reassessment of Shakespeare’s Hamlet, Abel argues that the play has mistakenly

been labelled as a tragedy throughout centuries without particular attention to the

playwright’s potential artistic and philosophical intentions. He claims that Shakespeare is

trying to make a point in Hamlet’s delaying of action and philosophizing at the very moment

in which he is expected to take his revenge. Shakespeare, in this sense, changes the play’s

direction from a tragedy into a self-reflection in which all characters constantly dramatize

themselves and the others, culminating in the famous play within a play scene where Hamlet

reveals his uncle’s guilty conscience. As an example to this, Abel mentions the scenes in

which Gertrude urges Hamlet to change his mood for the better towards his uncle, now the

king, and the ghost tries to sow the seeds of revenge into Hamlet’s mind. In such scenes,

Abel argues, “the reaction of Hamlet is that of a man with a playwright’s consciousness who

has just been told to be an actor, and is now determined to make an actor of the very

playwright who had cast him for an undesired role” (47). From that perspective, Hamlet

appears to have found himself in a conspiracy for the throne and a web of domestic intrigues,

all of which attribute different roles to the prince. The same situation applies to other

characters as well, as Claudius plays the part of a mournful brother who has recently lost his

brother and king, Polonius plays the part of a wise counsellor to the new king along with

casting various roles for his son and daughter, Gertrude pretends to be a grieving loving wife

to the late king and imperatively dutiful queen to the new one, and even Rosencrantz and

Guildenstern are featured by Claudius as loyal friends to Hamlet in appearance, but spies in

reality. In this respect, Abel categorizes the characters in Shakespeare’s Hamlet as either
49

fundamentally dramatists or fundamentally actors, the first group including Hamlet, the

Ghost, Claudius and Polonius while the second group includes Gertrude, Ophelia, Laertes,

Rosencrantz and Guildenstern. However, above all these internal dramatists and actors, the

central dramatist of the play turns out to be ‘death’ which makes the existence of all

characters theatrical towards an inevitable end by revealing their masks. Death’s dramaturgy

leads the characters to a ‘staged’ duel at the end of which all the major characters die as

‘themselves’ for the first time in the play, that is, without their masks and with the realization

of their true faces.

Having attributed dramatizing qualities to the ‘dramatist’ characters in Hamlet, Abel goes

deeper in his categorization of this type and describes Claudius and the Ghost as writers of

melodrama within the frame play, evoking feelings of hatred, revenge and pity in both

Hamlet and the audience. Compared to these two, Polonius appears to be a minor writer

whose script is basically comprised of misconceived ideas about the future of the court and

a sentimental attempt to secure his daughter’s marriage to the prince. Hamlet himself, on the

other hand, seems trapped between his uncle’s and the Ghost’s melodrama and his

melancholic questionings taking him to the verge of tragedy (50-51). Hamlet proves to be a

superior dramatist to all the other characters in the play, as indicated in his masterful

suggestions, related to staging and performance, to the actors that are going to perform the

‘Murder of Gonzago’ in front of the courtly audience. Above all, Hamlet falls victim in the

plot of the biggest dramatist, death, within the frame play after he fails to realize the necessary

steps dictated by melodramatic and tragic tendencies. Yet, Abel believes that Hamlet is the

first character in the history of drama with a playwright’s consciousness, one who is totally

aware that he has been and he is being dramatized by many other forces both within and

outside the play, by both the other characters including death and Shakespeare himself.
50

Abel furthers his arguments by designating a special kind of play, generally having

comical tendencies, whose characters are aware – as well as making the audience aware –

that the whole play is the invention of the playwright’s imagination. He refuses to reduce

these plays to having a play-within-a-play scene which is just a device in such plays, though

not a must. The plays Abel tries to designate appear to have one central common element:

all of them are theatre pieces about life seen as already theatricalized,
[meaning] that the persons appearing on the stage in these plays are there not
simply because they were caught by the playwright in dramatic postures as a
camera might catch them, but because they themselves knew they were
dramatic before the playwright took note of them. What dramatized them
originally [was] myth, legend, past literature and they themselves (60).

These plays represent on the stage a life which is interesting as long as its theatricality is

assumed well by the dramatist with the addition of his thinking on that life and its active

participants on a new level of dramatization. As an example to this, Abel invokes Moliere’s

Tartuffe, whose hypocritical hero of the same name is aware of his theatricality among other

characters and, thus, dramatize the ones around him to the end that the play turns into a

criticism of what the playwright tries to criticize. In other words, Tartuffe negates Tartuffe

as soon as the audience relates the plot to the world outside the play, that is to the 17th century

France with the dominating moral, political and religious hypocrisy. In a similar way,

Tartuffe and Hamlet go beyond the dramatic situations drawn for them by the playwrights

thanks to their own dramatizing abilities very much like Marlowe’s Doctor Faustus who is

less a tragic victim in the Devil’s drama than a self-conscious, strong-willed dramatist who

subjugates the Devil to his (Faustus’) wishes. Abel explains this further with the assumption

that Hamlet, Tartuffe or Faustus, or even Falstaff from Shakespeare’s Henry IV, are superior

characters to what their inventors intended them to be, flowing over their dramatized

personages and completing their development by dramatizing themselves and the others

around them.
51

Besides Hamlet, Shakespeare’s The Tempest bears metatheatrical characteristics with

the protagonist Prospero being the ultimate dramatist who has an island for a stage, real

enemies for villains, Ariel for a choreographer, Caliban for a stagehand and other characters

for bit players (69). Prospero has also been examined by many scholars as a parallel to

Shakespeare’s own self as an artist, as the former’s retirement from magic is likely to stand

for the latter’s retirement from art. Prospero also refuses to be an actor in some other

character’s drama, which is perhaps why Shakespeare abandons writing having realized that

he has finally achieved what he has been trying to do through his art, a character larger than

even himself. In comparison to Shakespeare above plays, Calderon’s Life is a Dream is a

lesser metaplay, in Abel’s opinion, even though it contains a well-organized play-within-a-

play at its centre. Abel still praises Calderon’s ability in giving Basilio great dramatizing

skills by which he both saves his own life and restores his son back to himself. After being

told by a prophet that his newly-born son will terminate his life when he comes of age, King

Basilio imprisons his own son Sigismund for twenty one years. Unable to fight his conscience

and impatient to see the outcome of the prophecy, Basilio uses his playwriting skills and

stages a plot for his son to act freely after being convinced that all he has gone through so far

was just a dream. After Sigismund refuses to take his father’s life, King Basilio’s drama

succeeds in overcoming Calderon’s intentions for a tragedy; in other words, metatheatre

disempowers tragedy.

Abel turns his attention to the examination of some ‘modern’ plays which bear

significant resemblances to what he imagines to be ‘metaplays’ like Shakespeare’s Hamlet,

Calderon’s Life is a Dream or Moliere’s Tartuffe. He claims that metatheatricality to modern

dramatists is what tragedy was to the Greek masters of this art, and it finds one of the most

effective representations in Jean Genet’s The Balcony whose protagonist “casts, directs, and
52

co-ordinates performances in a house of infinite mirrors and theatres” (Rosen, 1992:516).

For Abel, what Genet’s play shares with those Elizabethan and Spanish plays of the same

time is a subtle self-consciousness on behalf of the playwrights and the protagonist. It is the

same self-consciousness which rules out great Shakespearean plays like Hamlet – Abel

excludes Macbeth from this perspective – from the categorizations as ‘tragedies’, as the

protagonists of such plays were more active writers of their own fates than passive

participants in some other writer’s story about them. Furthermore, the whole western literary

tradition is built upon a liberal and sceptical outlook, compared to the Greeks, which is why

certain self-consciousness overcomes those unshakeable Greek values and external forces.

The playwrights of the modern times, from the Renaissance on, are obviously aware that the

world is a stage and individual lives are plays written by self-conscious actor-dramatists, as

Jacques from Shakepeare’s As You Like It and Calderon in his The Great Stage of the World

indicate. In this respect, “illusion becomes inseparable from reality” (79) in modern plays.

Abel also adds that there is always a fantastic dimension to modern metaplays, as illusion

goes hand in hand with reality while dreams and acting stand for real life and real human

actions.

Turning back to Genet’s The Balcony, Abel describes Madame Irma’s brothel, the

setting of the play, a place where reality is replaced by illusions and real faces with masks

and pretensions. The three men coming to the brothel, for instance, dramatize themselves

from the very beginning as a bishop, a general and a judge, having worn appropriate costumes

for these roles and expecting due treatments from the prostitutes while a revolution is taking

place outside the brothel, which is the ultimate ‘real’ opposite of the illusoriness inside. Genet

makes his characters change their attire not offstage, but right in front of the audience to

display that there are at least two levels of reality in his play, dramatized first by himself,
53

then by the characters themselves. The revolutionaries plan to design a role play in order to

make the public sympathize with their causes by killing a prostitute from Madame Irma’s

brothel and advertising her as the martyr-saint of the revolution. Through such interactions

between what is inside and outside the brothel, The Balcony blurs the distinction between

what is real and what is illusion in the world of the play dramatized by characters who are

already dramatized by Genet himself. Abel concludes that the modern metaplay justifies the

claim that the whole world is just a stage on which roles are played and lives are just dreams

acted out by self-dramatizing characters (83).

In a similar approach, Abel describes Beckett’s drama as metatheatrical, even though

there is not a single play-within-a-play scene in any of the latter’s plays. With respect to

Waiting for Godot and Endgame in particular, he argues that Beckett’s characters are

dramatized not by the playwright through the lines written on the page or spoken on the stage,

but by their individual pasts that have happened to them. It is for the same reason that memory

and remembrance hold a very significant place in Beckett’s character formations, for instance

in Krapp’s revitalization of his self through the tapes from his youth or Estragon’s problems

with remembering even the immediate past. Abel relates Beckett’s insistence on the theme

of time and memory to his ‘nostalgia for eternity’ which finds a voice in his suggestion that

“the actual characters are themselves the scenes of an invisible action” (85). He also contends

that, due to the same preoccupation with human memory, Beckett’s plays are metatheatrical,

because characters build themselves upon the remains of their personal histories; in other

words, they dramatize themselves on the face of passing time. Time in Beckett’s plays stands

for the element of metaphysical wonder very much like death in Shakespeare’s ‘tragedies’.

When it comes to Brecht, Abel begins his examination by stating the two central

constituents of the former’s literary career, rejection of the individual and the exclusion of
54

moral experience through art. To communist literary theorists’ surprise, Brecht as a

communist playwright refuses to use realism in the writing and the Stanislavskian method in

the performance of his plays. Although the communists view art as a means of moral and

political propaganda of the values of the Party, Brecht regards the representation of the

individual on the stage as pointless and giving moral messages to the audience as comical.

As a result of these principles, tragedy as a dramatic form does not appeal to Brecht’s schema,

which culminates in his development of Piscator’s epic theatre as an opposition to what the

former calls the ‘Aristotelian’ theatre. Recalling his definition of metatheatre on the basis of

two principles, the world being a stage and life a dream, Abel claims that Brecht had no other

option than drawing upon these two in order to attribute a form to his plays, having already

rejected moralism and individualism. As Brecht emphasizes that an actor must not identify

himself with the character he is portraying, then the actors on the stage are well aware of the

notion that they dramatize themselves in the identity of another in a stage-like world, whether

or not Brecht did this on purpose. Similarly, as the audience is not obliged to any moral

deduction from the action on the stage, the play is more a representation than reality itself,

hence dream-like: “Certainly Brecht’s idea of recalling the spectator back from involvement

would be a contradictory one had Brecht been trying to write tragedy or realism; it is not

contradictory, considering that what he actually wrote was metatheatre” (106). Abel comes

to the conclusion, after his discussion of Brecht’s plays, that the German playwright’s theatre

is to be easily categorized as metatheatre with respect to his highlighting of the central role

of performance in human life and detachment of the actor and the audience from the realm

of reality, which is the core of his ‘alienation’ effect.

Referring to Henrik Ibsen’s Peer Gynt, Abel concludes his treatise on the formulation

of this new dramatic genre which he calls ‘metatheatre’. For him, Peer Gynt proves the
55

greatest playwright of the 19th century even though Ibsen had no intention to give a

metatheatrical essence to any of his plays, as he was extremely limited to the bringings of

European naturalism and Sophoclean tragic form. The expectations of the bourgeoisie and

the rise of realism throughout Europe taken into consideration, Ibsen’s literary agenda looks

reasonable and effective on the 19th century stage. However, his Peer Gynt, “a kind of milder,

more mediocre, and more bourgeois Faust” (108), does not share the passiveness of other

Ibsen characters, such as Hedda Gabler and Rosmer, under the whipping of an all-controlling,

scowling Fate. Ibsen’s contemporary Chekhov, on the other hand, does not sacrifice his

characters’ free will to predestination and gives them certain self-consciousness regarding

the consequences of their actions in a world of performances. “Thus Chekov could produce

a kind of metatheatre while remaining genuinely realistic. The characters he described were

already theatrical” (109). What distinguishes Ibsen’s drama from Chekov’s, in this sense, is

that the former’s ‘tragic’ outlook to life leaves no room for the flourishing of ideas, as his

characters, or even the playwright himself, are caught in the web of submission to external

forces. Such a way of looking at life and potentials of dramatic art, for Abel, is what

characterizes the most famous generation of American playwrights, as well, including

Eugene O’Neill, Tennessee Williams and Arthur Miller. Despite being a follower of Ibsen’s

footsteps, George B. Shaw, however, manages to liberate his theatre from the constraints of

tragedy and attributes an intellectual character to it which Ibsen’s theatre is lacking. For this

reason, Abel describes major plays of Shaw, including Don Juan in Hell, Pygmalion and

Saint Joan, not as comedies, but as metaplays (111). Abel sums up his discussion with

reference to the Italian playwright Pirandello, specifically to his metatheatrical play Six

Characters in Search of an Author, as the epistemologist of the new genre thanks to his

blurring of the distinction between reality and illusion, and to Brecht as the logician of it
56

thanks to introduction of self-conscious, alienating characters to the modern stage. Tragedy,

in this sense, turns out to be the opposite of what Abel defines as ‘metatheatre’, as the former

suggests a well-structured world of ultimate realities whereas the latter conceptualizes a

world of performances built on shaky grounds where the ultimate projector is human

imagination and consciousness. In other words, “[t]ragedy, from the point of view of

metatheatre, is our dream of the real. Metatheatre, from the point of view of tragedy, is as

real as are our dreams” (113). All these aspects taken into account, Abel wholeheartedly

welcomes metatheatre as the refined dramatic form of the post-modern era having deposed

tragedy from its cold, anti-intellectual throne.

Richard Hornby’s treatise on metaplays, titled Drama, Metadrama, and Perception

(1986), differs from Abel’s in its theoretical approach to the mentioned type whereas the

latter’s remains more analysis-based than definitional. Hornby aims to come up with a

definition and fundamental principles of the genre with greater emphasis on the textual

elements of the plays in question rather than the ones related to performance, which is

perhaps why he chooses to name the genre ‘metadrama’ instead of ‘metatheatre’. He begins

his discussion with the assumption that dramatic criticism has always been dominated by

realistic critical approaches even if the work being treated is not necessarily realistic at all,

thanks to derivations like ‘unrealistic’, ‘surrealistic’ or ‘revolting against realism’: “Whether

one likes realism or not, the defining trait for the theatre is always how ‘close to’ or ‘far from’

everyday life it seems” (13). In a rather post-structuralist attitude, Hornby questions such

binarism as crippling with regard to the nature of certain categories and claims that such an

outlook has been dead for the last few decades, including the realistic-antirealistic dichotomy

in the theory of drama. However, he calls for a distinction between realism as a form of drama

and realism as a category encompassing all drama, the latter of which leads to the above
57

problematic polarization of genres while the former finds its roots in the Aristotelian concept

of ‘mimesis’. Very much like other binary oppositions, realism and anti-realism in dramatic

theory validate and define each other’s essentialities, leading to a clearer understanding of,

for instance, Stanislavskian and Brechtian conceptions of writing, acting and staging of

dramatic works (16). Hornby also turns his attention to the ‘advising the actors’ scene in

Shakespeare’s Hamlet, though with different motivations than Abel. Even though he finds

Hamlet’s preaching to the actors rather Stanislavskian with expressions like ‘holding a mirror

to nature’ in the art of acting, Hornby doesn’t obviously believe that Shakespeare’s blank

verse lines prove realistic in Hamlet’s mouth. The problem, in this case, seems to stem from

a forced imposition of the contemporary understanding of ‘reality’ to the Elizabethan mind

as well as the evaluation of the ‘naturalness’ of the prince’s inflated poetic character with

respect to today’s standards. Hornby asserts that the role of mimesis in drama has been

subordinated by contemporary critical theories to the analysis of the ‘poetic’ aspects, stylistic

innovations and technical diversities of a work.

Hornby finds the obsession with realism in dramatic and performance studies very

disadvantageous on behalf of the actors, playwrights and even directors, as it narrows down

the artistic potentials to be put on stage by all these entities. To overcome this confinement,

the idea that drama is a reflection, rather than a representation, of real life must be abandoned.

What he proposes as an alternative to this view lies in the structuralist and poststructuralist

dramatic theory, mainly of Roland Barthes and Northrop Frye, whose ideas can be listed as

below:

1. A play does not reflect life; instead, it reflects itself.


2. At the same time, it relates to other plays as a system.
3. This system, in turn, intersects with other systems of literature, non-
literary performance, other art forms (both high and low), and culture
58

generally. Culture, as it centres on drama in this way, I shall refer to as the


‘drama/culture complex.’
4. It is through the drama/culture complex, rather than through individual
plays, that we interpret life (Hornby, 1986:17).

The first objective derives from the structuralist belief that language, or writing in this case,

is a self-sufficient entity, independent from any contextual referents, including the author,

once put on paper. Instead of reflecting an external world, the text itself ‘becomes’ a world.

Similarly, the second objective derives from the Saussurean structuralist idea that individual

linguistic utterances are inevitably bound to an invisible linguistic system which each speaker

of the concerned language must have acquired to make sense of those utterances; hence

parole and langue (Saussure, 1986:9-10). In this respect, a literary text makes sense to the

readers or the audiences as long as they have already had a sense of the linguistic system, the

literary tradition related to that text and the archetypal knowledge. Neither the author nor the

audience changes the direction of the text against a wall of reality, even if the text had a claim

to reality in the first place, but both parties bend the reality outside the text to make sense of

the one inside it. “A good production of a good play seems isolated and self-contained […]

Its self-contained quality derives from the intuitive sense of what a play is […] As it does for

the playwright, the play for the audience reflects primarily inward, and secondarily outward,

to the unstated but crucial conventions of the theatre” (19). Furthermore, a dramatic work

goes beyond its reaches as a work of art and relates itself to a whole literary and artistic

tradition, to codes of behaviour, conventions of eating and dressing and every single social

institution, not in an imitative but a representative way. And thanks to the cultural knowledge

treasured up from the first human interaction on, the audience and the author interpret ‘life’

represented on the stage.

Having recognized a dramatic work as an autotelic, self-contained entity with no

direct connection with what is outside the text, Hornby moves on to an examination of the
59

theatrical experience of the audience both as a product of the play’s independent internal

system and of the audience’s prior knowledge that a play is a play and it has to be experienced

in a certain way. As an example to this, he takes Falstaff from Shakespeare’s Henry IV whose

personality is enjoyed thanks to both his actions in that particular play and the audience’s

archetypal knowledge of the type character he represents. The same aspect applies to

Shakespeare’s unconscious resort to the archetypal cultural knowledge as he develops the

character as well as to the audience’s former experiences with the performances in their daily

lives, hence the drama/culture complex (21-22). For Hornby, the plays which draw attention

to these textual and cultural interconnectedness comprise a new kind of ‘original’ drama,

putting a critical distance between the audience and the performance on the stage, an

alienating or defamiliarizing effect to put it in Brecht’s or Shklovsky’s terminology. In other

words, success and originality of a dramatic work lie behind its ability to attribute new

meanings to what is traditional and well-known, not cutting loose from it, because the

worldview of the audience is ultimately and inevitably determined in relation to those

traditional, familiar values.

Hornby views Brecht’s epic theatre as the culmination of originality in dramatic art

in the modern times, as Brecht was somehow able to present accustomed situations

happening to accustomed characters whose actions lead to unaccustomed outcomes, almost

in a parodic way. Hornby believes that all ‘great’ art is a ‘serious’ and ‘complex’ parody of

some sort, and, “in parodying the received dramatic tradition, the serious playwright is

attacking and ultimately altering the means by which people think, behave and decide” (25).

Serious artists like Brecht do not strive to validate the established social, moral and political

order, but investigate it with the objective to change it for the better. Just as the 20th century

linguistic theories have changed the definition of language from a one-to-one written or
60

spoken version of reality to an operative, culture-based system with arbitrary, changeable

meaning structures, the dramatic theory of the past century has also altered expectations from

this art form. Drama, in the contemporary sense of the word, does not reflect life in a realistic

manner anymore, but operates on it with an attempt to change the drama/culture complex,

which is doomed to change anyway, in a favourable direction. Hornby also argues that there

would be no point in studying drama if it were just holding a mirror up to nature and reflecting

life as it really was. Instead, drama must achieve the opposite of this, breaking that mirror of

slavish imitation to have a say on what is being discussed, which is what Brecht did with his

epic theatre.

Hornby complains about the fact that there has been a huge lack in the study and

systematic theorization of metadramatic theatre apart from such analytical treatises on

Shakespeare’s drama as Calderwood’s Shakespearean Metadrama, Egan’s Drama within

Drama and Homan’s When the Theatre Turns to Itself. He also finds seminal books like

Abel’s Metatheatre and Schlueter’s Metafictional Characters in Modern Drama rather

narrow and limited in scope and unsatisfactory in treating the metadramatic genre in

philosophical terms as a whole. In this respect, Hornby sets out to define metadrama as a

genre and come up with a list of its characteristic elements. He defines the genre as “drama

about drama [which] occurs whenever the subject of a play turns out to be, in some sense,

drama itself” (31). To achieve this metadramatic effect, Hornby thinks, all drama inevitably

and unconsciously derives from the playwright’s perception of and vocabulary about his art

along with his connection with the external world. When this metadramatic effect is

consciously sustained by the playwright with the intention to alter the audience’s or readers’

perception of fiction and reality, the play in question must be categorized as ‘metadramatic’

and analysed in terms of the ‘varieties’ of metadrama listed by Hornby as:


61

1. The play within the play.


2. The ceremony within the play.
3. Role playing within the role.
4. Literary and real-life reference.
5. Self-reference (32).

Hornby also mentions a sixth element in the formation of the metadramatic effect, one that

targets the recipients’ perception of reality with an aim to dislocate it. However, he does not

lay it down as a condition that all metadramatic plays must include all these varieties at once,

and speaks of a ‘degree of intensity’ in a dramatic work’s metadramatic tendencies.

The first of these ‘varieties’, the play within the play, refers to a scene in a play in

which some or all characters discuss, rehearse or perform another play, often reflecting the

‘actual’ playwright’s ideas about the art of playwriting. Hornby divides the play within the

play technique into two as the ‘inset’ type and the ‘frame’ type, the former subordinating the

inner fictional play to the frame play like the ‘Mousetrap’ scene in Shakespeare’s Hamlet

and the latter treating the frame play as supplement to the fictional play’s plot like the ‘kind

of history’ induction in Shakespeare’s Taming of the Shrew (33). The degree of integration

of the inner play into the frame play may differ according to the playwright’s objectives in

using the play within the play technique, which, in turn, indicates the possibility to define the

play in question as ‘truly’ and ‘consciously’ metadramatic. For instance, Shakespeare’s plays

like Hamlet, The Taming of the Shrew and A Midsummer Night’s Dream form an essential

connection between the plots of the frame play and the inner play while Brecht’s epic plays,

like A Man’s a Man, make use of inner plays, dance shows or songs as a means of relieving

the tension, changing the mood or alienating the audience. Full integration is sustained by

the frame play’s characters’ acknowledgment of or awareness to the inner play, or vice versa,

as well as the presence of self-contained plot structures and full characterization for the

characters in both plays.


62

Hornby attributes the beginning of the conscious use of play within the play as a

metadramatic element to the English Renaissance, as classical and medieval western drama

makes use of such elements like choral intervention as a means of commentary on the central

plot or comic relief detached from it. The technique, however, is frequently used in English

drama of the late 16th and early 17th century, including Lyly’s Endymion (1588), Marston’s

The Dutch Courtesan (1603-5), Peele’s The Old Wives’ Tale (1595), Beaumont’s The Knight

of the Burning Pestle (1607-1610) and particularly Kyd’s The Spanish Tragedy (1584-9)

alongside Shakespeare’s abovementioned plays. However, play within the play falls from

favour in the following centuries, which Hornby relates to a change in the worldview from

mid-17th century on (39-40). Apart from a few occasional appearances, play within the play

vanishes from the stage in the neo-classical, romantic and ‘realist’ eras, which continues until

the turn of the 20th century when Chekhov’s The Sea Gull (1896) and Strindberg’s A Dream

Play (1902) were published. Both plays start a revolution against the one-layered, well-made

realism on stage and privilege obscurity, self-reflexivity and subjectivity.

The use of play within the play, then, evolved into a new kind with the Absurdist

drama of the mid-20th century which played with the audience’s perception of reality with its

strong dream-like quality. Along with such plays as Beckett’s Krapp’s Last Tape, Genet’s

The Blacks and Stoppard’s Travesties, Hornby attaches particular importance to Luigi

Pirandello’s metadramatic trilogy including Six Characters in Search of an Author, Each in

His Own Way, Tonight We Improvise, in which he annihilates, according to various critics,

the border between reality and illusion as well as commenting on the nature of dramatic art

through his characters. Yet, for Hornby, there is always a clear-cut distinction between

various layers of ‘plays’ within Pirandello’s plays, but the playwright constantly subordinates

one play’s believability to the other’s and he mingles one play’s characters and plot with the
63

other’s (43). However, Pirandello never gives priority to either the frame play or the inner

play in the development of his plots and the passage of characters from one to the other is

always an option. Hornby observes that the final representative of this play within the play

vein in the 20th century drama is the epic theatre of Vakhtangov, Piscator and Brecht along

with their minor successors. Using the Russian formalist Viktor Shklovsky’s terminology,

Hornby finds that the epic theatre uses its layered structure to ‘alienate’ (ostraneniye in

Russian) the audience from the illusion of reality into a critical attitude towards the

performance. Epic plays, to this end, generally use an inner play, which is particularly a

familiar play from the familiar history, and a narrator for the frame play who is/makes aware

that what is going on in the inner play is just a representation, not the reality itself. Hornby

concludes his chapter on play within the play with the observation that the frequency of the

use of the technique changes across centuries in close connection to the way the people of

those centuries perceive life (46-47). This explains why it was frequently used during the

Renaissance and the 20th century, as the people of the former had a perception of life as a

stage and humans as puppet-like ‘actors’ under the control of a greater power while the

people of the latter had no trust in any system of thought or institution whatsoever.

The second variety Hornby designates for metadrama is ‘the ceremony within the

play’ which appears in the form of performances both in serious plays like tragedies and less

serious plays like comedies. Among ceremonies carried out on the stage in the history of

drama are “feasts, balls, pageants, tournaments, games, rituals, trials, inquests, processions,

executions, funerals, coronations, initiations” (49) depending on the genre and themes of the

play. However, it must be noted that actions which have ritualistic or ceremonial tendencies

without a full formal structure as a ceremony do not count as metadramatic, because the

characters are performing no roles other than themselves in such cases. A full formal
64

ceremonial scene implicates characters’ acting out roles ascribed to themselves; for instance

as grooms and brides for wedding ceremonies at the end of traditional comedies or victims

and executioners commonly seen in traditional tragedies. However, ceremonies in real life

are not necessarily akin to dramatic performances, as they are less plot-based, more serious

and rigid in terms of rules, and the characters they contain are rather flat than round compared

to theatrical performances. Hornby observes that theatre is always associated with ceremony

not because of they are identical, but because “theatre is metaceremony [and] incorporates

ceremony in order to verify it, to examine it, or even to attack it” (55). And ceremony within

the play is metadramatic, as it represents the drama/culture complex through performance-

related means.

Hornby separates ceremony within the play into two in terms of the ceremony’s

completion or abortion for some reason, which can loosely be associated with the play’s

comic and tragic effect, relatively. The fulfilment of a ceremony within the play gives the

audience a feeling of closure, order and peace like the trial scene towards the end of

Shakespeare’s The Merchant of Venice giving relative satisfaction to the audience.

Contrarily, a ceremony within the play being interrupted for some reason leads to feelings of

restlessness, gloom and displeasure in the audience like the banquet in Shakespeare’s

Macbeth being aborted by the appearance of Banquo’s ghost to Macbeth. Hornby also

observes that tragedies having fulfilled ceremonies and comedies having unfulfilled ones

bring the plays to the verge of being characterized as ‘tragicomedies’. There are also two

types of unfulfilled ceremonies within the play, one being the already-mentioned abortion of

the ceremony for some reason and the other including the perversion of a ceremony to the

opposite of what is intended with it. The second type includes examples like weddings ending

with multiple murders, homecoming ceremonies turning into funeral rituals and celebrations
65

proving to be scenes of unmasking (57-58). These classifications mainly belong to the time

from the Greek and Roman classics to the end of Shakespearean era in which tragedy and

comedy had relatively clearer border lines.

From the 16th century onwards, the ceremonies are carried out offstage or absent in

some sense, but still bear the same significance in a more symbolic way. Hornby divides

these ceremonies into three main types: the offstage ceremony, the anti-ceremony and the

quasi-ceremony (58). The removal of these ceremonies from the stage has various reasons

depending on the era in which the plays were written. The offstage ceremonies are frequently

used in neoclassical drama, as festivity and sentimentality on the stage contradict neo-

classical literary ideals, which is why these events are just reported by some characters to the

others and the audience. Similarly, this type can also be seen in the naturalist drama of the

late 19th century, this time not with the intent of restraint, but with the motivation to show the

effects of incidents on the characters rather than the actions themselves. The second type, the

anti-ceremony, is a characteristic of Romantic drama in which traditional rituals and

observances are parodied to the end that they are transformed into the opposite of those rituals

and observances. The quasi-ceremony, on the other hand, pertains to contemporary drama,

especially to theatre of the absurd, in which ordinary events and actions are carried out in

such a way that they gain ritualistic qualities, possibly with an aim to reveal their spiritual

and symbolic emptiness (59-61).

Unlike the play within the play, the use of the ceremony within the play as a

metadramatic technique is not limited to a particular era or movement, but frequent in the

whole history of dramatic literature. Hornby relates this to the connection between

ceremonies and the issue of stability and change in the social life, and the evolutionary nature

of social systems gives way to ceremonies either for celebrating the new or lamenting the
66

old. However, since the turn of the 20th century, the concept of ceremony has begun to lose

its spiritual and symbolic meaning as a mode of expression, which found considerable

reflections in contemporary drama. The dramatists of the late 20th century has turned their

attention to the creation of personal ceremonies with an attempt to restore the order in their

own terms. This results in the neurotic inventions of a nostalgic mind which characterizes

the drama of the present time as a fiercely self-reflexive and metadramatic kind.

The third variety of metadrama indicated by Hornby is ‘role playing within the role’

on which Lionel Abel has also centred his discussions regarding metatheatre. Even though it

is a separate element in metadramatic plays, role playing within the role is inevitably

connected to the former two varieties, as they both depend on certain kinds of performance

of the characters who are already being performed by actors. However, Hornby puts the

emphasis in this chapter not on the role playing of characters in inner plays or ceremonies,

but on characters’ adoption of certain masks or faces in the development of the ‘actual’ play

in order to hide their true personalities. As examples to this, Hamlet’s feigned madness,

Iago’s feigned honesty, Volpone’s feigned sickness can be given to reveal the characters’

skills in hiding their true personalities behind invisible masks as strategies to unmask, mock

or avenge themselves against other characters (67-68). Such a multilayeredness gives the

metadramatic characters a huge depth in terms of characterization and becomes too

demanding for the audience to understand the true nature of the action on the stage.

Reflecting on contemporary psychoanalytical theories of ego and identity, Hornby

draws attention to the fact that characters’ role playing within the role has always had strong

ties with the psychological, sexual and physical development of individuals in a given period,

which is best observed and reflected by the playwrights of the time. In this respect, there

must be a particular reason behind, for instance, Shakespeare’s use of cross-dressing,


67

madness and physical deformity in his plays. Therefore, “role playing within the role sets up

a special acting situation that goes beyond the usual exploration of specific roles; it exposes

the very nature of role itself. The theatrical efficacy of role playing within the role is the

result of its reminding us that all human roles are relative, that identities are learned rather

than innate” (72). Having this in mind, the audience of theatre must be aware of the true

potentials of the characters on the stage who are actually made of the same essence as

themselves.

Like the other varieties, Hornby makes a division within role playing within the role

itself and designates three subcategories to the variety: voluntary, involuntary and allegorical

role playing within the role. As the name suggests voluntary role playing refers to a

character’s conscious pretention to be another person or to have a different personality. Feste

from Shakespeare’s Twelfth Night, for instance, disguises himself as a curate named Topas

in order to make fun of the imprisoned Malvolio while Richard from Shakespeare’s Richard

III pretends to be a devout Christian, despite not changing his attire, before the council that

is going to offer him the crown. Involuntary role playing within the role, on the other hand,

is a result of a character’s exposition to external factors which change his personality

temporarily or permanently, or of the character’s own distinctive emotional weaknesses

abused by the others around him, if not both. Hornby gives the example of Malvolio from

again Shakespeare’s Twelfth Night in which he is easily manipulated by other characters,

primarily Maria and Sir Toby, into thinking that he is the ideal partner for her mistress Olivia.

Even though his being manipulated is more his fault than anybody else’s, Malvolio is still

different than Feste and Richard, given in above examples to voluntary role players, in that

he is unconsciously driven towards such conclusions by the others around him and he

genuinely believes that he is actually fit for a marriage with Olivia. Lastly, the third type of
68

role playing within the role refers to the qualities given to a character by the playwright which

connotates another character from the history or literary tradition with the same qualities. As

the character is unaware of this allusion and his allegorically meaningful position, this type

of role playing does not count as a voluntary one; and it cannot be regarded as involuntary

role playing either, due to the lack of internal or external (within the play) interventions on

the character’s personality. Shakespeare’s As You Like It, for instance, deals with the struggle

between two brothers named Orlando and Oliver over supremacy, which makes the story a

direct allusion to the creation myth with the Orlando’s father figure’s name being Adam and

the setting being the Forest of Arden (74). In such cases when a character is aware of the

allusions he is making by the role he is playing or he is forced into that allegorical role by

other characters, allegorical role playing can be both voluntary and involuntary. Hornby

argues that role playing within the role becomes more interesting when there is a shift

between these types of role playing during the course of the play.

The use of role playing within the role can be traced back to the ancient Greek drama,

and it contributes to the development of many stock characters throughout centuries. Hornby

mentions two stereotypes from the ancient times, alazon and eiron, who are known to be

pretentious characters who see themselves better or worse than they actually are, as boastful

impostors or lowly nonstarters, respectively. It is also possible to find the first examples of

cross-dressing in the ancient Greek drama which resurrects more vividly in the Renaissance

drama. In medieval drama, role playing within the role is basically used to make biblical

allusions with the popularity of morality plays whose central literary element is allegory.

Role players are also seen in the Italian Commedia dell’arte in such stock characters as

Pantalone and Il Capitano who constantly pose as somebody other than themselves by using

their intellect to make profit or thanks to the fact that none of the locals know them,
69

respectively. Renaissance drama, on the other hand, is rather eclectic in the use of role

playing techniques of the characters and makes use of almost all the role playing stock

characters of the previous drama, culminating in plays like Webster’s The White Devil or

Shakespeare’s Hamlet, Othello and Richard III. The question of identity continues to occupy

the agenda of the stage in the following centuries, finding voice in the Restoration comedy

of manners with stereotypical characters like the Fop and the Country Bumpkin whose entire

popularity depends on their ability to sell themselves to the others around them in a fashion

beyond themselves. In the 19th and the 20th centuries, the role playing evolved into something

more than a technique, into a main theme of modern plays whose characters are depicted in

constant struggle to find a ‘proper’ identity for themselves by fulfilling any role possible

without knowing that the core of their personality is inevitably hollow. In the second half of

the 20th century, blurring the identities of characters has become a popular technique, as

people themselves have been shifting from pose to pose with existential questions after global

catastrophes. Besides such modern innovations, traditional modes of role playing have still

been kept especially in modern versions of old dramatic genres such as the comedy of

manners, to which Hornby gives the example of Jack in Wilde’s The Importance of Being

Earnest who leads a double life and pretends to be a decent man in the country and lives as

a libertine in the city (81). Another famous example of role playing within the role from

modern drama, this time an involuntary one, is Shaw’s Pygmalion in which Professor Higgins

imposes the manners and appearance of a lady on a poor flower girl, leading to her

transformation into something totally alien to her own self.

When the issue of acting and role playing is on the table, it is inevitable to incorporate

the Stanislavskian/Brechtian contradiction into the discussion. Modern theories of acting

based on the Stanislavskian method do not lean towards role playing within the role, as the
70

actors are expected to digest their personalities into that of the characters they are performing

without a tendency towards other poses. In contrast, the ideal Brechtian actor is expected to

put a distance between himself as an actor and his role as a character with an aim to alienate

both himself and the audience for a critical reception of the play. However, Hornby argues

that “in both cases, the actor’s ego boundary remains intact; one places the performance

entirely inside that boundary, the other, entirely outside, but the boundary (i.e., the actor’s

sense of everyday self) does not change” (84). In the Cartesian way of thinking, every single

individual is a role player in real life with at least two identities in private and in public; and

on the stage where the individual’s duty is to ‘act’, the multiple layers of potential role

playing become dazzling. As this Cartesian dualism of the self dominates the world of ideas,

role playing within the role becomes more and more popular in the world of drama and

evolves into an acknowledged technique rather than a mere character trait.

The fourth, and perhaps the most frequently used, variety of metadrama indicated by

Hornby is literary and real life reference within the play, which functions as a means of

alienation for the audience depending on the degree the audience is able to determine its

relation to other literary works or real life happenings. In such cases, the illusion created by

watching a play is broken for a moment and this leads the audience to reflecting and

elaborating on the allusion in a more critical way than simply digesting it as a part of the

performance. However, a metadramatic allusion to other literature and real life situations

must be distinguished from non-technical quotations, adaptations and borrowings. The same

question goes for the allusions which have acquired the status of cliché, and thus, do not need

a critical effort from the audience to make sense of. In addition to that, the references to well-

known mythological, religious and cultural sources are more parts of the linguistic system

itself than metadramatic allusions. However, when these non-technical borrowings and
71

allusions are made by means of a parody, the critical audience is expected to experience

certain degree of estrangement with a reflection on the use of that source material in its

original way at the back of their minds, which makes the allusion a metadramatic one (88-

90).

Like the other varieties, Hornby subdivides literary references into four types being

citation, allegory, parody and adaptation. He contends that these are all metadramatic,

perhaps with the exception of parody, in that they are “direct, conscious allusions to specific

works […] that are recent and popular” (90). By citation, he refers to the playwrights’ direct

references to or quotations from earlier literary works with the exact wording that appears in

the quoted text. The use of citation as a metadramatic technique dates all the way back to the

classical Greek drama, but such usage naturally loses its familiarity and alienating effect on

behalf of the audience as the quoted work falls out of favour in time. Another function of

literary reference is to draw attention to the work’s own fictionality or ‘dramaticality’,

because “when literary citation within the play moves towards literary criticism, it also moves

toward the play as self-reference” (92), as in Ben Jonson’s Poetaster, Shakespeare’s Hamlet

and Chekhov’s The Sea Gull. Such a metadramatic effect makes it easier for the audience to

form analogies between the literary reference made on the stage and the play they are

watching as a literary artefact.

In a similar way, allegory is used as a means to allude to previous works of literature

and other art in an attempt to comment on the nature of the play that contains the allegory.

Hornby gives Shaw’s Pygmalion as an example to metadramatic allegory by means of literary

reference, as it bears explicit traces of such tales as “Cinderella” and “The Ugly Duckling”

as well as of Ibsen’s The Doll’s House in a critical reading (93). Parody as a metadramatic

technique, on the other hand, may appear in the form of the former two types with the addition
72

that the subject matter is purposefully mocked by the playwright. Parody in its purest form

is to be easily found in the classical Greek comedy in which the comic effect is registered by

the ridicule of the works and even personalities of other playwrights, generally from among

the same generation. As a matter of fact, such parodies comprise a big part of neo-classical

drama as reflections of satire, the most popular genre in prose, on dramatic literature.

Parodies do not necessarily limit their scope to characters and actors, but they give voice to

playwrights’ concerns regarding criticism, a whole literary genre, certain styles and uses of

language. Last but not least, adaptations from earlier literature can be regarded as

metadramatic as long as the adaptation and the source work are not indistinguishable by the

audience so as to create estrangement on their behalf. Stoppard’s Rosencrantz and

Guildenstern Are Dead, for instance, engenders a powerful sense of alienation in the audience

at the back of whose mind is Shakespeare’s Hamlet as they proceed with the play (94).

Adaptations have become really popular at the second half of the 20th century and such plays

have created a sense of doubleness in the eye of the audience even though the playwrights

and the directors do their best to make the setting, characters and events relevant to the

contemporary contexts. As metadramatic adaptations require the prior knowledge of the

audience regarding the source texts, such plays have always been labelled as an intellectual

kind with a highly specific target audience.

The real life reference, equivalent to metadramatic literary reference, refers to a

playwright’s conscious and direct allusion to real personages, happenings and places which

necessitate the audience’s immediate recognition to achieve its metadramatic effect.

However, it must be noted that all real life references are not metadramatic, because an

allusion to unfamiliar people, events or places makes sense to the audience not as an

alienating technical element, but as an integral part of the play’s content. Very much like
73

literary reference, real life reference also loses its metadramatic effect in time in proportion

to the memorability and popularity of the referenced item. Hornby argues that the same

internal division of literary references into citation, allegory, parody and adaptation goes for

real life reference as well (95). When the words of a real person are quoted with the exact

wording he/she has used before, or when that real person is depicted as he/she really is in

real life, the metadramatic citation as real life reference is in full function. Aristophanes, for

instance, depicts his contemporary playwright Euripides as his central character in The Frogs

with an aim to ridicule the latter and his works. Shakespeare’s historical plays also depict

real historical personages as they have earlier been depicted in historical accounts popular

during his time. Howard Brenton, on the other hand, uses the Romantic poets Byron and

Shelley as his protagonists in his Bloody Poetry.

More common but less metadramatic at first glance, allegorical references to real

people, events or places abstain from depicting these elements as they really are, generally

thanks to a name change; but still they attribute recognizable traits from their real life features

to them. Caryl Churchill’s Marlene in her Top Girls, for example, obviously stands for

Margaret Thatcher in a microcosmic office atmosphere, though with a different name.

Playwrights seem to choose such allegorical references more often than citation in order to

make their plays more suggestive and demanding or simply not to face prosecution. Parodies

regarding real life people, events and places appear in the form of satire in dramatic works,

whose scope is really limited compared to the former two types of real life reference. A

parody of real life people or events is not metadramatic unless the element of satire in the

play is already a literary convention in the general framework. For instance, ridicule of a

character who is immigrating to the United States with the great American Dream at the back

of his mind becomes metadramatic only if the play turns this ridicule into a satire of a whole
74

literary tradition having used the American Dream as its central subject matter. In a similar

vein, adaptations from real life can never be metadramatic, as the mimetic nature of all drama

requires such transition from real life onto the stage where even an extraordinary element is

treated as real by the audience within the dramatic illusion created by the play. However, if

the emphasis is put on distinguishing the fictitious ‘real’ from the real ‘real’ in a play, as the

mimetic approach suggests, then the audience can be alienated into thinking critically of the

fictitious elements as a metadramatic technique (95-97).

Hornby contends that real life reference as a metadramatic technique has become

more popular in proportion to the advancements in technology, which culminated in Piscator

and Brecht’s epic theatre when slideshows, voice records, photographs and even videos were

introduced into plays to toy with the audience’s sense of illusion (97). Even if the play

performed on the stage creates an illusion of reality within itself and attributes new meanings

to people, objects and places, the audience watches the play with a preconditioning coming

from their real life experiences, which makes them understand that a chair used in a play is

both a prop in that performance and a chair in essence. The audience’s theatrical experience,

thus, is always informed by their real life existences, which is easily exploited by avant-garde

playwrights and directors to create a metadramatic effect. The possibility of this effect stems

from the art of theatre being a live, immediate, performance-based, on-the-spot experience

which makes it easier for the play to foreground the audience’s real life existence in the

background or make it stay where it is as long as it takes.

The last variety of metadrama listed by Hornby is self-reference which gives the

strongest metadramatic feeling to the audience as well as the characters, because the dramatic

work acknowledges its own dramatic nature and constantly reminds the audience of it. Very

much like in the opening scene of Shakespeare’s Henry IV, Part I, where Prince Hal addresses
75

the audience directly, in self-reference “the play stops. The audience is made to examine the

play as a play; an artificial construction with events that […] are not to be taken seriously”

(103). Self-reference is inevitably related to the other varieties of drama, though the former

differs from the others in its immediate and direct acknowledgment of its fictionality rather

than an indirect suggestion. However, a distinction has to be made between self-reference

and presentational techniques like aside, monologue and narration in which there is also a

direct acknowledgment of the audience by the actors on the stage. The latter category does

not break the dramatic illusion created by the play, but extends it to include the audience into

the fictional world with no particular acknowledgment of the play as a play. Prologues and

epilogues, on the other hand, are more metadramatic in essence compared to such

presentational techniques with an acknowledgment of the play as a play; yet they function

like a presentational frame which does not break either the action or the illusion that goes

with it (104-105).

It is crucial, at this point, to understand the nature of the illusion being broken by the

metadramatic self-reference not as a delusion, but as a virtual reality in which the audience

enjoys its vitality but remains internally connected to the actual world. Quoting Susan K.

Langer’s monumental book on aesthetics titled Feeling and Form (1953:77), Hornby

describes theatre’s dramatic effect as a passage into ‘a hypothetical state of existence’, one

of a temporary trance rather than a permanent madness (106). In Freudian terms, however,

the aesthetic experience is always a going back into the depths of the unconscious, a surfacing

up of certain psychosexual impulses inevitably limiting the aesthetic effect to an illogical

process of responding to an external stimulus. Hornby argues against such a Freudian

conception of aesthetic experience and emphasizes the crucial role of the active, intuitive and

intellectual participation of the audience. He says: “The dramatic illusion provides us with
76

an intuitively comprehensible imaginary presence rather than direct stimulation. The

dramatic experience is not like drinking a glass of beer or receiving a kick in the pants, but

is instead a form of knowing” (112, emphasis in the original). Even though the individual

members of the audience are directed towards an identification with the characters and

empathy with the events on the stage, it is not possible to speak of a complete displacement

of the self, but perhaps an expansion of it to contain more than one personality.

Despite the fact that self-reference is the most metadramatic one among other

varieties, it is not a popular one in the history of drama. Some rare examples are to be found

in such Shakespeare plays as Henry IV, Julius Caesar and Anthony and Cleopatra in which

the characters directly address the audience to express their expectations about the future

recognition of the play they are a part of. In the modern times, the use of self-reference is

also considerably rare compared to other metadramatic elements like play within the play.

Self-reference proves a very effective technique in epic drama, as it immediately breaks the

dramatic illusion and alienates the audience into a critical attitude towards the play. In this

respect, self-reference turns into a tool for moralistic purposes to teach something to the

audience rather than letting the theatrical experience turn into an escapist activity. In other

words, the serious playwright makes use of self-reference to “alter the drama/culture complex

rather than simply exploiting it without changing it” (117). When it is taken into

consideration that self-reference scenes in a play are generally the funniest ones, it becomes

easier to do two jobs with one metadramatic play, which is reminiscent of the ancient Roman

idea of literature, teaching and delighting at the same time.


77

1.3. From Historiographic Metafiction to Historiographic Metadrama

One of the milestones of postmodern literary theory is undeniably Linda Hutcheon’s

seminal treatise titled “Historiographic Metafiction: Parody and Intertextuality of History”

in which she lays the theoretical foundations of a newly-emerging genre that she names

‘historiographic metafiction’. Hutcheon begins her formulation of this genre with the

assumption that what characterizes postmodernist literature is an “intense self-reflexivity and

overtly parodic intertextuality” (3). In her A Poetics of Postmodernism: History, Theory,

Fiction, she observes that “self-reflexivity […] strengthens and points to the direct level of

historical engagement and reference of the text [which] define[s] the new postmodern

seriousness that acknowledges the limits and powers of reporting or writing the past, recent

or remote” (1988: 117). She also finds the equation of postmodernism with metafiction, “a

term given to fictional writing which self-consciously and systematically draws attention to

its status as an artefact in order to pose questions about the relationship between fiction and

reality" (Waugh, 1984:2), inadequate. Instead, she calls for the necessary addition of “an

equally self-conscious dimension of history” (3) to this metafictional essence. Each

postmodern text, for Hutcheon, is inevitably ‘historical’ in its formation of itself on the

grounds of the earlier texts consciously. However, what distinguishes a postmodern novel

taking its subject as history from a traditional historical novel is that the former makes room

for itself within history without posing as something other than fiction, thus displaying the

fictionality of the whole historical discourse: “Historiographic metafiction works to situate

itself within historical discourse without surrendering its autonomy as fiction” (4). Hutcheon

also emphasizes that history, viewed as the common property by historians and writers of

fiction, is inevitably to be traced in texts that have no more secure claim to reality than a

fictional work. In postmodern literature, however, “conventions of both fiction and


78

historiography are simultaneously used and abused, installed and subverted, asserted and

denied” (5). Historiographic metafiction sees history as a safe ground on which it rests its

foundations while shaking it from within at the same time. It situates itself within a historical

discourse which it sees “only in aesthetic terms” (5). On behalf of the postmodern text, to

parody the past means both to acknowledge its existence and, paradoxically, to falsify it.

Intertextuality liberates the textual meaning from the monopoly of author-reader

interaction and leaves the meaning-making to the text itself in its relations with the preceding

texts or the history of discourse, or the tradition. With references to other authors such as

Barthes and Eco, Hutcheon emphasizes that intertextuality is an integral part of textuality

and each text echoes other literary materials one way or another, consciously or

subconsciously, very much like those texts having already echoed their own predecessors.

With this idea in mind, though, a text can no longer claim originality, as it owes its sense-

making to the accumulated discursive knowledge. A postmodern text consciously and

proudly embraces its inevitable relationality with preceding texts to the end that it parodies

them and arouses awareness in the readers to the fictionality of documented history (6-7).

Historiographic metafiction, in this sense, shares the modern historiography’s outlook

regarding the essence of history as a narrative rather than an objective documentation, thus,

prone to additions, omissions, alterations and shadowings. Historiographic metafiction

problematizes history’s familiarization of the unfamiliar through revealing its own textual

formation; for, as a ‘filtered’ narrative, the fictional work echoes the production process of

historical accounts and their openness to interpretation: “The past really did exist, but we can

only ‘know’ that past today through its texts, and therein lies its connection to the literary”

(10). Hutcheon also refutes the accusations towards postmodernism of being ‘ahistorical’ and

professes that it is overtly and inevitably historical in its attempts to disarm that history from
79

its claims to the truth: “Historiographic metafiction [...] is overtly and resolutely historical-

though, admittedly, in an ironic and problematic way that acknowledges that history is not

the transparent record of any sure ‘truth’” (10).

In Hutcheon’s understanding, a text is never original in terms of content, but it can be

original in its approach to the already-existing content, in its treatment of the intertextual

data. Historiographic metafiction does not limit the potentialities of either history or fiction,

but expands their scope as well as adding to their value, “by locating the discourses of both

[...] within an ever-expanding intertextual network that mocks any notion of either single

origin or simple causality” (11). Hutcheon coins the term ‘interdiscursivity’ to denote the

multiplicity of textual voices in a given text, which, she believes, gives prominence to the

ex-centric, the marginal and the other in an otherwise one-dimensional perspective. This

approach frees fiction and history from the tyranny of the ‘dominator’ and gives voice to the

‘dominated’. In Historiographic Metafiction, thus, a historically marginalized, or perhaps

non-existent, character is used to subvert the clichés of the whole literary canon, such as the

heroism of the heroes or exaggerated reflections of historical events. Such elements force the

reader “to rethink and perhaps reinterpret history [... through] the dilemma of whether we

make history or history makes us” (17).

Hutcheon backs up her argument with a quotation from Doctorow who claims that there

is no clear-cut distinction between a work of art and of history. In Historiographic

Metafiction, the author arranges fictional meetings between historical figures and fictional

characters, though without privileging one over the other. The function of fictional characters

in those meetings is just to emphasize the narrative essence of historical data and that history

could have been written in different ways if the focus of the historian had been different:

“Narrativized history, like fiction, reshapes any material (in this case, the past) in the light of
80

present issues, and this interpretive process is precisely what this kind of historiographic

metafiction calls to our attention” (22). This issue perhaps adds a political dimension to

historiographic metafiction, as it makes use of history to comment on or have an

understanding of the present. This ‘double contextualizability’ of intertexts, as Schmidt puts

it, leads the readers “not only to double [their] vision, but to look beyond the centres to the

margins, the edges, the ex-centric” (25). After all such inferences, Hutcheon concludes that

historiographic metafiction is the ‘most didactic of postmodern forms’, as it brings together

history and literature which both “make and make sense of our world” (28).

The term historiographic metadrama was coined in 1987 by the Canadian literary scholar

Richard Knowles in his seminal article titled “Replaying History: Canadian Historiographic

Metadrama”. Building his arguments on another Canadian's, Linda Hutcheon's,

abovementioned epochal theory of historiographic metafiction, Knowles defines this new

genre, in an extended study published a decade later, as “the dramaturgies that concern

themselves with theatrical process (rather than product) as attempts at democratization; with

explorations of history and historiography as themselves self-reflexive probings into present

constructions and reconstructions of a unifixed and ever-changing past through which we

(continually) remake what we ‘are’” (1999:77-78). He begins his discussion with an

elaboration on the postmodern conception of history and historiography not as an unearthing

of facts of the past, but as creative writing. “Historiography, then, becomes the ongoing

process of remaking history, of ‘making it new’, as fiction and myth” (1987:228). In a similar

vein, literary scholars and the writers of fiction have lately concentrated on the instability of

textual meaning with an emphasis on the readers' capacities of rewriting the texts which

already have a metafictional ‘consciousness’.


81

Knowles draws attention to the increasing popularity of contemporary Canadian plays

which deal with historical topics from a present-time perspective in an attempt to rewrite

those ‘histories’ as well as commenting on their own dramatic conditions and meanings. He

argues that this metadramatic consciousness can be traced back to the 16th century, to

Shakespeare and his contemporaries, who made use of chronicles and other historical

documents as the basis of their plays. Similarly, in the 20th century, political dramatists

“since Brecht and Piscator have employed presentational, audience-centred forms of

documentary drama to deconstruct traditional 'authoritative' views of history and replace

them with self-consciously revisionist and populist re-presentations of history as

performance and process” (229). Contemporary Canadian playwrights have unsurprisingly

followed the footsteps of their European pioneers and directed their attention to political non-

illusionistic drama in a presentational style. Among these playwrights, three representatives

come to the fore with their exceptional political and historical consciousness along with a

self-reflexive style: Rick Salutin, James Reaney, and Sharon Pallock.

Salutin’s drama functions like an archaeologist's project which reveals the details of

Canada's cultural history from a nationalist's perspective. In his plays, he “subverts the very

concept of historical or dramatic 'authority'; and he avoids illusionistic naturalism [...] in

favour of a presentational metatheatricality that similarly subverts traditional Aristotelian

concepts of empathy and catharsis in drama” (230). In his 1837: The Farmers’ Revolt (1976),

for instance, he uses a documented historical event as his subject matter, the Mackenzie

Rebellion of 1837, by which he encourages the audience to relive the rebellion and rewrite

history from their own point of view. At the same time, he forms an obvious analogy between

the historical event and contemporary politics, especially the 1973 issues regarding cultural

and economic oppression in Canada. Salutin’s play also includes metadramatic elements with
82

the use of a storyteller within the play who narrates and, from time to time, acts out his story

to the other characters in the play. Similar metadramatic and historiographic elements are

also traceable in Salutin’s other play, Les Canadiens (1977), too.

James Reaney approaches the issues of history from a similar angle, seeing history as a

set of representations and drama as a means of reimagining that history with an attempt to

extract personal or collective myths. He openly views history as a stage on which the

powerful act out roles that they attributed to themselves. He attempts to 'explode' those false

historical myths and tries to 'correct' them in his own more realistic understanding. Knowles

gives Reaney’s Sticks and Stones (1975) as an example to historiographic metadrama with

respect to the playwright's parody of the historical Donnelly family's case and the

metadramatic medicine-show scene. As Knowles points out “Reaney’s interest in historical

subject matter, then, has to do with continuing the universal process of creation by

transforming history dramatically into pure story, extending that process by involving the

audience in it” (235). Very much like Salutin, Reaney invites his audience to piece up

fragments of the past to come up with a historical account as valid as the ‘official’ one widely

acknowledged. Such a “method suggests that the play's metatheatrical self-consciousness, in

which characters stand outside of the play to comment on their own roles, is designed to

contribute to the elevation of audience engagement above empathy with character and plot

to the level of imaginative engagement with the artist, and with the creative act of inventing

the past” (235-236). The play, thus, turns into a page on which history is re-written and made

new by the audience through the window the playwright has opened for them.

Knowles separates Sharon Pollock from the other two playwrights, not in her use of

metadramatic devices, but in terms of her use of historical settings and costumes for her

historical plays. Pollock’s drama from the very beginning of her career has always been
83

linked to exploration of the past on personal and social levels, and she views drama as a tool

to recognize the past to be able to design the future, for which she emphasizes the

performative nature of both history and drama itself in her major works. Her 1973 play

Walsh, for instance, deals with actual historical personages like Major Walsh and the Sitting

Bull, the former of which is depicted with a fluid identity, acting out roles as a government

officer and an ordinary individual. With this role playing within the role along with the

framing vignette at the beginning of the play, Pollock achieves to “present the play as a

demonstration” (237) and to shake the established belief in the minds of the audience

regarding the myth of the Indian and the Nationalist Canadian. Pollock’s Blood Relations

(1980) also employs similar metadramatic techniques like a frame story within which a

historical event is re-enacted and characters being forced upon roles to act out. The re-

enactment of Lizzie’s murder of her father and stepmother gives the audience and the other

characters a chance to revaluate the history from another perspective before condemning

Lizzie as an ill-hearted murderer.

As a conclusion to his article, Knowles observes that historiographic metadrama begins

to take root in Canadian dramatic literature as a self-contained tradition with quite a number

of representative playwrights not limited to the three mentioned. What characterizes the work

of these playwrights is an attempt to reveal the fictional nature of documented history by

means of a presentational, self-reflexive style which underlines the fact that history, very

much like the play being staged, is a scene for role-playing and representation. These

playwrights all make use of “the techniques of self-reflexive theatricality […] to deflect

cathartic engagement with character and plot, in order to produce a more active and ongoing

engagement associated with the imagination and the will, and to open their dramas outward

to the world as they lay open their documentary sources, for re-construction” (241). Very
84

much like its counterpart in fiction, historiographic metafiction, Knowles’ historiographic

metadrama obviously has a potential to become the defining genre of the whole contemporary

western drama, as it gives voice to both central postmodern reservations: historical accuracy

and soundness of textual meaning.

In line with Hutcheon’s and Knowles’ ideas above, Alexander Feldman comes up with

the term ‘historiographic metatheatre’, which he describes as historiographic metafiction’s

“self-conscious counterpart to dramatic art– theatre’s acknowledgement of its own artifice—

[…] [which] by exposing the theatricality within theatre, provoke[s] questions as to the

artifice, the spectacle, and the dramatic constructs of the world beyond” (2013:3). He calls

for a necessary distinction, though, between ‘historical’ and ‘historiographic’ and definition

of ‘metatheatrical’ on the basis of ‘theatricality’. With the use of the word ‘historiographic’,

he draws attention to, not only the historical events, but also the circumstances under which

those historical events are ‘narrated’ in a particular discourse, from a particular point of view

on a particular ideological basis. The term ‘metadrama’, on the other hand, refers to the

illusoriness of theatrical performances and their assumption of a representative voice which

is identical to real life. Feldman also draws attention to the self-reflexive nature of

‘historiographic metatheatre’, justifying his location of his formulation on the axis of

Hutcheon’s theory, as his idea, very much like hers, emphasizes the “seminal significance of

self-reflexivity in modern and contemporary history plays [which] share numerous features

with the novels under Hutcheon’s purview. [He] explore[s] interrogations of historical

understanding and historical representation, as she does, within art-works which may be

considered characteristic of late twentieth-century theatre” (5).

Feldman applies his theory to a number of British and German plays with an emphasis

on the use of play-within-the-play as the key, but not the only, factor in self-referentiality.
85

As Feldman also argues in his discussions of the plays, the primary contention of

‘historiographic metatheatre’ is becoming “a seminal mode of political and ideological

engagement in post-war European theatre. As well as staging history, these plays reflect upon

the pressing issues of their own periods. Dramas of the past they may be, but they thinly veil

their critiques of the present” (5). Feldman admits that his formulation has its roots in the

traditions of European historical drama along with the seminal theoretical texts of the

postmodernist vein including Hutcheon’s ‘historiographic metafiction’. To his

understanding, history and drama share an inevitable connection in terms of their essences

being representation, both creating a set of characters, attributing certain roles to them and

pretending that what they are telling or showing is real. This connection stems from the fact

that “it is one of the insights of postmodernist historiography […] that the fictionalising

process—the assignment of roles and the plotting of events— is crucial to the historian’s

practice” (7) the same way it is crucial to the dramatist’s. When the traditional idea of ‘the

world as a stage’ is taken into consideration, Feldman’s definition of history as ‘the theatre

of the world’ and of drama as ‘the theatre of the book’ makes perfect sense in revealing their

interconnectedness. Historiographic metatheatre, in this sense, brings these two interpretative

activities together to reveal the theatricality of history and the historicality of theatre.

Feldman also evokes Lionel Abel’s definition of metatheatre in a critical manner, as he

believes that the latter’s equation of metatheatre with a blurring of the distinctions between

reality and illusion is inadequate. Furthermore, Abel’s discussion revolves mistakenly around

the assumption that a play is metatheatrical as long as it deals with life ‘as already-

theatricalised’ being theatricalized once more on the stage. What Feldman proposes as an

opposition to this is an emphasis on the metatheatrical potentials of the play-within-the-play

scenes that acknowledge the performance on the stage as a performance and tries to reveal
86

the already-theatricalised nature of roles played by the actors with a strong self-referentiality

and self-consciousness. Such historiographic metatheatricality goes even beyond reflecting

on fictionality of history and drawing on the play’s own dramaticality, and it engages in a

“pursuit of political themes and ideological arguments” (16), which dominated the post-

Brechtian stage in the West. Feldman finds the basis for this domination not only in the

growing interest of professional historians in the fictional nature of historiography, but also

in the contemporary dramatists’ increasing political consciousness in an attempt to reveal the

histories of the oppressed to put it in Walter Benjamin’s terminology. These politically-

conscious playwrights of the second half of the century “began to explore alternative,

supressed versions of history, histories that could not be considered a linear flow of the past

into a progressive present, and to demythologize hegemonic representations of history as a

tawdry illusion” (Middleton and Woods, 2000:155). In doing so, they prove that history

writing is no different than interpreting the past from a present-time point of view and their

version of history is as valid as a professional historian’s, as both are subject to subjective

ascription.

Even though political awareness and dramatic self-consciousness bring these works

closer to the Brechtian epic theatre, historiographic metatheatre departs partially from the

Brechtian legacy in its inclusion of the audience to the illusion created on the stage. Actually,

the illusion becomes the central function of the metadramatic play, as it tries to put its version

of history over the one the audience has long been fooled with. Historiographic metatheatre

requires the performance of a naturalist play in a naturalist fashion, or whatever the

mentioned historical period calls for, rather than the epic style, to have a full command of

historical referentiality with a strong claim to historical accuracy in order only to prove that

it does not exist. In other words, it problematizes its own attempt to achieve historical
87

knowledge to display that such a thing is out of question. Very much like the professional

historical account, historiographic metatheatre “refer[s] to events that have taken place, in

one way or another, but the manner of their presentation subverts, or at least destabilises, the

referential capacity of [all] stagings. The ‘metatheatrical awareness’ […] renders all histories

suspect, contingent, provisional” (23). To that end, historiographic metatheatre draws

attention to the constructedness of its own plot, the affectedness of its characters and

illusoriness of its own action. Feldman ends his introduction to this new genre with a

quotation from Howard Barker, the pivotal subject of this study, who argues that “the theatre

is not a disseminator of truth but a provider of versions. Its statements are provisional”

(1993:45).

In a similar approach, Zapkin analyses two of Tom Stoppard’s plays, Travesties (1974)

and Arcadia (1993), in terms of their treatment of documented historical data and questioning

of the stability of textual meaning, the playwright being a representative of the ‘postmodern

scepticism’. Zapkin classifies these plays as historiographic metatheatre, the former being an

overt and the latter a covert example. Stoppard appears already to be the playwright showing

the highest interest in the issue of history, with plays set completely or partially in the past,

along with offering commentary on “epistemological issues [such as] reliability, the limits of

knowledge, and how humans experience the laws of the universe” (2016:308). Stoppard’s

plays display what Hayden White describes as ‘historical emplotment’, the activity of giving

interpretations a factual framework thanks to a formation of cause and effect relationships by

means of a plot. In other words, as Belsey puts it:

History is always in practice a reading of the past. We make a narrative out of


the available ‘documents,’ the written texts we interpret in order to produce a
knowledge of a world which is no longer present. And yet it is always from
the present that we produce this knowledge: from the present in the sense that
it is only from what is still extant, still available, that we make it; and from the
present in the sense that we make it out of an understanding formed by the
88

present. We bring what we know now to bear on what remains from the past
to produce an intelligible history (1985:1).

Stoppard seems fairly aware of this narrativity inherent in historical accounts by which any

individual can assume the right to write ‘a’ history. Using historical settings and personages

at the centre of his plays, he does not claim that his ‘version’ of history is correct, but proves

that, with deficient arguments based on subjective accounts, it is never possible to have direct

access to history (Mıyares, 2008:7). Zapkin is obviously of the same opinion as Mıyares

when he argues that “historiographic metatheatre such as Stoppard’s confronts both history

and science as epistemological discourses, exposing the limitations of narrative through a

historiographic reliance on error. Stoppard’s historiographic metatheatre accepts error not

just as inevitable but as part of the fabric of historiography” (312).

Stoppard’s Travesties arranges a fictional meeting among four famous historical

personages – Henry Carr, Vladimir Lenin, James Joyce and Tristan Tzara – in the Zurich of

1917, with no written historical document indicating that these characters all met each other.

The events in the play are narrated by the now-elderly Carr whose contradictory statements

draw attention to the unreliability of his account regarding the past which has already been

fictionalized by Stoppard himself. As Carr’s account is being acted out by actors on the

stage, some of them even twice in different ways, there is a discussion going on between

Joyce and Tzara over the potentials of art in conveying historical ‘facts’ accurately, which

problematizes historical knowledge by self-referentiality. Less obviously, Arcadia also offers

commentary on historical accuracy by means of metatheatrical references. The play is set

partially in the past and partially in the present in the same household and there are constant

passages between the two thanks to flashbacks, memories told and accounts re-enacted. Two

central characters from the present-time setting, writer Hannah Jarvis and professor Bernard

Nightingale, both investigate the history of the household and rewrite the history of it in due
89

process while the flashbacks prove them substantially wrong. In the play, “Stoppard stages

the past as a tool for critiquing contemporary historiographic discourses and epistemologies

[…] [and] goes beyond staging compromised histories and sets a trap for viewers and critics

to examine their own historiographic thought processes” (319). In doing so, however, he

never changes the décor or the props inbetween the two temporal phases, by which he

constantly reminds the audience that what they are watching is a fictitious performance very

much like the history the characters are trying to unearth.

With an eye to the ideas above, there is no doubt that historiographic metadrama has

been one of the most popular dramatic genres in the last few decades of western literary

tradition in line with the increasing postmodern scepticism towards generalizing narratives

like history. In English drama in particular, historiographic metadrama has found a place for

itself among the political playwrights – besides Stoppard – who have been categorized as

Brechtian by the literary scholarship, including David Edgar, Howard Brenton, David Hare

and Trevor Griffiths. In addition to these playwrights, Howard Barker stands out as a

practitioner of historiographic metadrama even though his drama is described by Barker

himself as one that abstains from any commentary and message whatsoever. In fact, a great

number of Barker’s plays take their subject matters from documented history, though in a

subversive way. Barker situates his plots right within the defining moments in history with

actual historical personages as his characters who are depicted as the opposites of what they

are in the history books. Along with such interest in historical knowledge, Barker’s drama

also stresses self-reflexivity, self-referentiality, artificiality and illusoriness of dramatic

works, particularly by the use of artists as his protagonists in the middle of their struggles

against authority, use of works of art at the centre of the events and discussions related to the

ethics and functions of art in the face of politics, morality and society. In this respect, Barker’s
90

drama bears strong potentials to be read and categorized as historiographic metadrama; but,

before that, it is necessary to comprehend Barker’s understanding of art as manifested in his

self-crafted genre, The Theatre of Catastrophe.


91

CHAPTER 2

THE TENETS OF HOWARD BARKER’S THEATRE OF CATASTROPHE

Howard Barker’s drama has always been juxtaposed with the generation of British

political playwrights including Howard Brenton, David Edgar, Edward Bond, John McGrath

and Caryl Churchill whose works dominated the stages in the last decades of the twentieth

century. These playwrights have been regarded as the torchbearers of the Brechtian tradition

of political epic theatre in Britain in terms of both content and technique. However, Howard

Barker’s self-crafted path as a playwright and the character of his drama definitely deserve

to be taken into account individually and independently. Even though Barker’s departure

from his contemporaries in terms of artistic character and motivation becomes clear in the

late 80s, his interest in political writing along with his admiration for the tragic form dates

back to the staging of his first plays at the Royal Court almost two decades earlier. Wilcher

attributes the beginning of Barker’s career “as a stage dramatist [to] the production of Cheek

in the Royal Court Theatre Upstairs in September 1970” (1993:176). Towards the end of the

decade, Barker has already found a place for himself among the famous generation of the

abovementioned playwrights due to his political orientation reflected in his early plays.

However, Barker’s plays remain unrecognized by the general public for a long time, as they

are not staged as widely as those of his contemporaries. Megson points out that Barker’s early

work “has [often] been received with marked circumspection if not outright hostility by

reviewers and, with occasional exceptions, has been rejected by major theatre establishments,

most notoriously the National Theatre” (2006:489). Despite occasional appearances on

mainstream stages, Barker keeps his plays off the market intentionally until the establishment

of his own theatre company named The Wrestling School in 1988. Until then and even after

that, Barker remains “essentially a fringe dramatist, and he is keenly sensitive to the fact”
92

(Rusinko, 1989:139) and this “uncompromisingly avant-garde stance has meant that some of

his plays have remained unperformed for years, and although the Royal Shakespeare

Company has mounted a number of productions, they have been confined to its studio

spaces” (Wilcher, 1993:176).

The Wrestling School was founded by a group of actors with the sole purpose of

staging Howard Barker’s plays in 1988 and, since then, the company has devoted its attention

to introducing the playwright’s highly distinctive style and techniques to an eximious group

of spectators who are in search of a distinctive theatrical experience. Since the opening

performance of Barker’s The Last Supper (1988), the company has staged around 40 of

Barker’s plays, “many of them [being] the English language premieres as well as workshops,

readings and public discussions to over 56,000 people in nine countries”

(http://www.thewrestlingschool.co.uk/tws.html). Thanks to the its stance inbetween

mainstream and fringe theatre, the company has also found the chance to work in

collaboration with other companies including the Royal Court and Joint Stock, as pointed out

by Lamb (2005:14). The Wrestling School, in time, has turned out to be an experimental

theatre company which “explores the dynamic between language and communication,

performer and audience, […] and works to develop new forms of expression for text-based

drama” (http://www.thewrestlingschool.co.uk/tws.html). The company takes its name from

the idea that each member of the audience as well as the actors performing a play must

‘wrestle’ with the innumerable possible meanings that the text suggests in order to come up

with an independently authentic, personal interpretation.

Barker’s already-distinctive dramatic style gains a theoretical foundation with the

publication of his monumental treatise on the art of theatre and performance, titled Arguments

for a Theatre, in 1993. In this work, he basically sets his ‘art of theatre’ or ‘the new theatre’
93

or ‘The Theatre of Catastrophe’ up against what he calls simply ‘theatre’ or ‘the humanist

theatre’ or ‘the old theatre’ referring to a whole tradition of Western dramatic theory from

Aristotle to Brecht. Barker views the old theatre as an act of marketing in which the actors

assume the role of a salesperson trying to promote his product to the taste of the audience

who is presented as a mere consuming entity. In such cases, the audience’s satisfaction

becomes “the necessary end of the performance” (67). However, the new theatre liberates

both parties from such an imposed exchange and expectations, and takes the experience of

theatre beyond purgation of any kind to the feeling of exclusiveness on behalf of the

audience: “To escape the pernicious memory of the market place, the new theatre will

dethrone its audience. […] It will not be encouraged to think itself a jury, obsessively

judgmental” (67). Barker then calls for a distinction between the ‘important plays’ and the

‘disappointing plays’. He believes that a play cannot achieve importance by remaining in the

framework of the existent ideology in which the good and the bad are predetermined. Instead

of satisfying the audience’s need to be rewarded with habitual outcomes, it must deliver a

wound which is “the aim of the new theatre and the intention of the actor” (68). As the wound

in the heart of the audience keeps bleeding, they will look for alternative ways to heal the

wound outside the framework of the dominant ideology.

Barker makes a list of assessments from which his “Theatre of Catastrophe” takes its

shape. The list includes the assumptions that “information is a universal commodity [,] that

knowledge is forbidden [,] that imagination has been maimed by collectivist culture [,] that

in this maiming the public itself has colluded [and] that this collusion is nevertheless detected

and is experienced as shame” (69). The below chart effectively summarizes Barker’s points

in his distinction between the ‘humanist’ theatre and his Theatre of Catastrophe:

The humanist theatre


We all really agree.
94

When we laugh we are together.


Art must be understood.
Wit greases the message.
The actor is a man/woman not unlike the author.
The production must be clear.
We celebrate our unity.
The critic is already on our side.
The message is important.
The audience is educated and goes home happy or fortified.
The catastrophic theatre
We only sometimes agree.
Laughter conceals fear.
Art is a problem of understanding.
There is no message.
The actor is different in kind.
The audience cannot grasp everything; nor did the author.
We quarrel to love.
The critic must suffer like everyone else.
The play is important.
The audience is divided and goes home disturbed or amazed. (71)

Barker sees his theatre as an honourably barbaric act in an environment where civilization

means political and social gibberish in the name of a moral unanimity. The theatre is, and

must be, protected by the invisible walls of this barbarism against a sea of moral and political

impositions and discussions while, inside those walls, the imagination continues its free play.

Barker concludes that when the audience experiences ‘the terrible ambitions of the human

spirit’ in silence and darkness beyond the constraints of ideology and education, it leaves the

premises between those walls not as ‘changed’, but ‘confused’ beings, which is the sole aim

of theatre (78).

The political theatre, for Barker, disregards complexity in its pursuit of exposure and

promotion, and assumes a ‘common morality’ in the background of the audience’s

perception. Such a theatre underestimates its audience’s meaning-making capacities and

serves it ready-made, ideologically-shaped meanings in the way a journalist or a

documentarian does in the public arena. Such an obsession with realism and accuracy

deprives theatre of its poetic potentials which should have been the sole motive determining
95

the way the author writes, the actor plays and the audience watches. As an anti-thesis to this

kind of theatre, he gives some examples from his own, from the productions of his plays such

as The Last Supper, The Possibilities, The Castle and The Bite of the Night. He claims that

these plays are indigestible, rather than incomprehensible, in their disruption of the moral

substructure they are expected to stand on. His catastrophic theatre is never afraid of the

audience’s potentials; instead, it challenges the audience to overcome the deliberate obscurity

on the stage and to prove that clarity murders imagination. Barker detests the theatre’s self-

assured authority on the audience which laughs or cries when the play motivates it to laugh

or cry. He bestows the medal of success to the theatre when it achieves to unleash the

individual members of the audience from the constraints of collectivity and meaning (79-82).

Barker’s understanding of theatre is a safe haven for the audience from the bombardment of

compelling comments “in an age of persistent meaning, of relentless indoctrination, not only

from the state, but from the artistic community, the commercial empires and the propagandist

forces of an information network” (82). In Barker’s catastrophic theatre, the audience enjoys

the ‘multitude of possibilities’ none of which assumes superiority over its receptive

capabilities or tries to change the audience’s moral or political standpoint.

Barker engages in a war against the crippling and narrowing reaction to his theatre in

terms of accessibility and obscurity; as he does not believe that obscurity stems from an

inability to communicate the message or that accessibility is solely related to such issues as

intellect, class and wealth. He, at the same time, regrets to admit that the value of a work of

art is determined in the present time by its understandability, digestibility, contemporaneity,

relevance and openness. However, what he still proposes is an obscure theatre whose “very

obscure transgressions occur which make it deeply unsympathetic to existing practice – the

first of these being irresponsibility” (88). Barker’s theatre of obscurity takes its leave from
96

the domains of the liberal-humanist theatre in its rejection to deal with the conscience or to

have a social purpose. In the chart below, Barker points out the battle his catastrophic theatre

wages against outdated perceptions of art, moral and political structures in society and

shallow critical methods of his time:

Table 1: The fortification of an imaginative work

Barker’s new theatre subordinates both author, who has been seen as an omniscient entity

since Brecht, and actor/director, who has taken ideological impositions as his duty so far, to
97

the audience, who are left insecure and confused to the end that their imagination is

‘stimulated’ and “the structures of morality are tested, even if only to be affirmed” (54).

However, it is noteworthy to emphasize that Barker never calls for a collective stimulation,

but for an individual assessment of moral values: “My own theatre has never aimed for

solidarity, but to address the soul where it feels its difference. It is intended to plunge beneath

the ground of common belief and to test the ground of first principles” (54). He compares his

understanding of tragedy with the Aristotelian understanding of it, which offered nothing

more than a generalizing public moral ‘correction’ generally stimulated by the death of a

morally idealized hero whose moral outlook reflects the playwright’s or the ruler’s. He lays

the burden of constructing morals onto the shoulders of the individual members of the

audience, reducing his role as an artist just to opening the gates of ‘knowledge’ and leaving

them on their own: “This knowledge, because it is forbidden by moral authoritarians of both

political wings, becomes the material of a new drama that regards men and women as free,

cognitive, and essentially autonomous, capable of witnessing pain without the compensation

of political structures” (50). He concludes that “the real end of drama in this period must be

not the reproduction of reality, critical or otherwise, […] but speculation – not what is […]

but what might be, what is imaginable” (38).

After such a brief introduction to the theoretical aspects of Barker’s drama, it is

crucial to make an in-depth analysis of the playwright’s books on the art of theatre and

performance to get a full understanding of his “Theatre of Catastrophe”. In this respect, the

following sub-sections deal with Barker’s insistence on the tragic form as the basis for

effective dramatic effect, his technical developments that distinguish his self-crafted genre

from the deep-rooted Aristotelian ethics in the history of drama and the prominent Brechtian
98

formula dominating the works of Barker’s contemporaries and the levels of deliberate

functionlessness in Barker’s drama.

2.1. Tragedy, Death and the Catastrophic Effect

The only point where Howard Barker agrees with Aristotle is perhaps his

acknowledgment of tragedy as the highest form of art, as it restores the privilege of

experiencing the pain of life to the individual. In an interview he gave to Nick Hobbes, Barker

argues that tragedy is “unsentimental, it takes us seriously as human beings, it is not

condescending. Paradoxically, by seeing pain we are made greater, it becomes a need. There

is nothing 'pessimistic' about this. […] Tragedy tells us what the world is - it doesn't explain

the world” (The Wrestling School, 2004). He sublimates the audience’s confrontation with

this pain as the ultimate reality of life and views this confrontation as a means to achieve self-

fulfilment in the face of imposed generic communal moral values. He abstains from

attributing a moral dimension to his tragedies, but describes them as catastrophic “because a

breakdown of order - social or personal - is always the starting point, and the protagonist

must invent himself out of the ruins of a life. Often this journey leads to a bitter solitude. But

so what? Theatre isn't a massage. We ask it to take us seriously. (The Wrestling School,

2004). Tragedy also liberates the individual member of the audience from banal collectivity

and separates one from the rest into questioning his subjective existence. In other words, “in

tragedy, the audience is disunited. It sits alone. It suffers alone. In the endless drizzle of false

collectivity, tragedy restores pain to the individual […] when society is officially philistine,

the complexity of tragedy becomes a source of resistance” (Barker, 1993:19).

For Barker, tragedy is the most appropriate art form for the 20th century in which

humanity suffered severely from authoritarian regimes, as tragedy aggrandizes even the
99

otherwise most trivial human experiences as well as liberating human speech from the

constraints of everyday habituality: “After the tragedy, you are not certain of who you are

[…] Tragedy liberates language from banality. It returns poetry to speech. Tragedy is not

about reconciliation. Consequently, it is the art form for our time. Tragedy resists the

trivialization of experience, which is the project of the authoritarian regime” (17-18). To save

the individual from banal collectivism, tragedy emphasizes the incalculable value of

subjective meaning-making capacities of humans, and Barker, in opposition to the

Aristotelian obsession with arousing pity and fear in tragedy to make the audience better,

attributes no function to tragedy other than shaking the audience out of its deadly routine:

“Tragedy does not stoop to hate life, for loving life and hating life are equally infantile, the

philosophical equivalent of a nursery rhyme. Tragedy has no opinion” (34). Barker portrays

death not as a means to arouse pity and fear, but as a reminder of the ultimate reality of human

life: “By making death the sacred object of our meditations the art of theatre at once dispenses

with the pitiful paraphernalia of representation that so disfigures the stage of the theatre, with

its shrill and infantile assurances we are in a real place” (53). In order to represent death on

stage in an appropriate way, Barker suggests that one has to abolish the idea that death is the

ultimate equalizer and the long-awaited retribution for the shortcomings of life: “To stage

death we must – let us admit it, and affirm it – abolish the critical regard – a regard so fissured

and cataracted as to have become in any case a condition of the blind” (54).

Barker contends that the greatest duty to realize the true nature of death falls primarily

to the tragic protagonist who must first deprive himself of his conscience, then experience

the atmosphere of death independently of the feelings of fear and empathy, and finally convey

the same experience to the audience in the most faithful way: “The artist who dares to be

tragic, the actor who is unafraid of tragedy, lives at the expense of his conscience, lives
100

outside conscience. He sins for the audience, living on the very fringes of morality” (77). On

behalf of the audience, on the other hand, who witnesses the fall of the tragic protagonist on

stage, there is no instruction intended by Barker’s conception of tragedy; on the contrary, the

audience is expected to be uneducated of his imposed limitations. In Barker’s own words,

“in the fall of the tragic protagonist we witness therefore the exhaustion of the conjuror . . .

in this spectacle we are privileged to know the supreme law of limitations but simultaneously

to be ecstatically uneducated by it” (93). The fall of the tragic hero in a classical tragedy is

an inevitable outcome of the hero’s fierce struggling against the forces beyond his strength;

and the hero sets a model for the audience in the face of the potential dangers rooted in their

fate. However, Barker’s understanding of tragedy acknowledges the tragic fall, which usually

manifests itself by means of death, not as a warning, but as an acceptance of life’s harsh

reality: “The failure of even the tragic character to overcome the gravitational pull of all

things, the impossibility of sustaining his conjuring of values, does not educate us against his

arts. Let us repeat: Tragedy is not a warning” (93).

Barker once more explains his theatre’s departure from the long tradition of realist

political drama that has dominated the 20th century stage under the influence of first Ibsen

and then Brecht. He claims that his tragedy evokes no sentiments in the audience regarding

any political, moral or social issues, and never seeks to amend or correct; on the contrary, it

sees immediate sentimental reaction on behalf of the audience as a sign of cheap emotional

abuse: “Tragedy shrinks from empathy, disdains sympathy and recoils from all the pseudo-

emotions of realism in the theatre, practices designed to generate the fatuous complacency

of identification or recognition. To announce, as the audience, ‘I identified with him’ – a

mark of failure” (86). Barker’s tragedy seeks to eliminate moral and political judgment from

the stage and the collective opinions offstage, as these kill the actual value of the theatrical
101

experience of the individual actor as well as the individual audience: “The public game of

the foyer is the coda to all dramatic art (the foyer being the rally of the party faithful). Here

opinion is official, but opinion is the enemy of tragedy . . . the foyer after the tragedy therefore

. . . a casualty station for the moralists” (94). In Barker’s ‘Theatre of Catastrophe’, tragedy

turns into a means to fight against the use of art as political and moral propaganda, because

it “eliminates conscience from the stage, and [serves] no political purpose” (96).

In his “Death, the One and the Art of Theatre”, Barker also pays particular attention

to the reasons why he has chosen the tragic form. He argues that the art of theatre must be

liberated from all forms of transitory, earthly idealism and must be organized around the

theme of death which is the dissolution of all ideals represented best in the tragic form:

All cultures are enslaved by idealism – they are defined by their servitude to
the ideal. Only tragedy locates the ideal in death, but because death is the first
enemy of political systems, tragedy is caricatured as negativity. The bravery
of tragedy – where not even sexual love is sufficient to abolish the fascination
of death – lies in its refutation of pleasure as an organizing principle of
existence. Who would deny that this contempt for pleasure is also an ecstasy?
(2005:3)
As the tragic art of theatre does not aim to tell, or to teach, or to preach, it is not plausible on

behalf of the audience to expect messages from a dramatic work whose motivation stems

only from a will to pay respect to the sole reality defining human existence. Barker elaborates

on this issue further saying: “To ask for truth in theatre is contradictory, a repudiation of its

essence. Consequently, death, a subject for which true statements are, a priori, inadmissible,

is the subject most perfectly suited to the form of theatre” (4). Barker acknowledges that the

hovering of death on a piece of work inspires negative feelings on the audience by which the

quality of a dramatic work is determined, as the art of theatre is realistic as long as it gives a

faithful representation of death and invokes an individually generated feeling in the audience

accordingly: “The art of theatre was fear-inspiring. The Humanists, who know of no use for

fear, nor can imagine the sublimity of fear, abolished it from the stage. We talk, however, of
102

theatre as crucially an art of death. We assert the dominance of fear in the life of the

characters. In this we are, paradoxically, realists” (7). He blames ‘humanist’ dramatists of

the late 20th century for banishing death from the stage or abusing it for emotional

exploitation whereas his ‘Theatre of Catastrophe’ restores death to its deserved place at the

centre of all great art. Barker suggests that “death is the preoccupation of great art even where

it is not the subject of it. When the utilitarians seized the theatre death simply stood in the

foyer, as patient as a chauffeur” (7).

Barker elaborates on the subject of death in drama with respect to the question of

catharsis on behalf of the audience, and argues that once death is on the table, the audience

is automatically alienated from other contextual feelings and passions like political views

and moral outlook: “To enter the space silently. To enter it thinking of death. To make death

the whole subject even when laughter discloses the ambiguity of our passions. To admit

death. To admit death . . . to know now what you knew but were denied consciousness of . .

. that all is predicated on death . . . is this political?” (7-8). Even though this fact has been

blatantly obvious to previous generations of political dramatists, they have turned a blind eye

to the grandeur of the subject of death in their works for the sake of not scaring the audience

and cheap ideological aspirations. However, Barker describes death as a natural human

apprehension which starts with the birth as a separation from nothingness, goes throughout

life which is a road to death and the final breath as an arrival to it. In Barker’s own words,

“we should all like to choose our deaths, both the moment and the manner. We should like

to control this as all the episodes of life. But death is not an episode of life, it is beyond life

and nothing that pertains to life pertains to death. It was the same with the birth agony. We

were coming into a place. With death we are going into a place. Or, if we are not going into

a place, certainly we are leaving one . . .” (9). To acknowledge such a natural human
103

apprehension in art brings about the highest form of realism which is liberated from any other

apprehension at the same time. Great art is tragic in the sense that it deals with death for

death’s own sake and obliges individual members of the audience to revaluate their value

judgments to see if they are genuinely theirs or they are imposed upon them by collectivist

social, moral and political projects:

Profound emotional experiences even where they fill the audience with
despair (perceived ‘negativity’) serve to increase resistance to social coercion
(the more so since all social coercion justifies itself on the pleasure principle).
The pessimistic work of art – who dares talk of death as pessimism? –
strengthens the observer by obliging him to include death in his categories of
thought. How do we sense the infinite value of death as the subject of artistic
undertakings? By reference to the hostility shown to it by authoritarians and
democrats alike, who identify it as inimical to their collectivist projects. This
alone endows it with charm, even – vitality . . . (13-14).
However pessimistic it may seem, Barker’s insistence on a confrontation with death in art

seems rather realistic in the face of the idealist political drama that has assumed the seat of

realism in dramatic art after Brecht. He contends that the ‘humanist’ dramatists among his

contemporaries have deliberately targeted tragedy and death, as their political projects

necessitated the sublimation of life in the most rationalistic and idealistic way possible.

Barker’s ‘Theatre of Catastrophe’ functions only to remind the audience of what he has been

distracted from by the political and moral agenda of the power-holders: “We go to the tragedy

to know what we already know, what we have known since birth, that our lives are dedicated

to death, a knowledge all other forms of social existence contrive to conceal from us, with

our connivance. Tragedy was attacked so long as death was attacked, a state of affairs so

preposterous it could not last, a state of affairs induced by a reckless, blind and alcoholic

rationalism. . .” (18).

Barker attributes great powers to tragedy both in terms of confronting the audience

with the ultimate reality of human existence and of offering them the purest form of beauty
104

in its most direct, courageous and sterile condition. “In the art of theatre beauty is

characterized by its brevity, its instability, its ill-health. Whereas death is the nightmare of

cheerless democracies, abolished from consciousness by the nauseating complicity of

medicine and leisure, death in the art of theatre is the condition of beauty and anxiety the

price of its revelation. Would you be seduced effortlessly?” (26). He views ‘humanist’ theatre

as a marketer of false hopes in line with so-called democratic projects and abolishes hope

from his own stage leaving his characters inbetween positive and negative attributes with an

open door for both miracles and catastrophes:

Tragedy is hope-less. Death is hope-less. Neither is bereft of hope, rather they


have dispensed with hope. They exist in a vortex, not of hopelessness (‘the
situation is hopeless’ always contains the plea for a miracle) but a vortex
without categories either of optimism or pessimism. Who would say tragedy
is pessimistic? Only a fool, for the tragic gesture demands the abolition of
pessimism at the outset, it identifies it as a redundancy, along with its opposite
(32).

As tragedy is inclined to frustrate all attempts at expectations on behalf of the audience, it

gives them a feeling of catastrophe unaccompanied by a feeling of waste, contrary to what

Bloom argues in his discussion of Hamlet. Barker observes that “tragedy is never about

waste, the source of the pain that surrounds the accident” (55); on the contrary, the tragic

hero(ine) is always aware that death is perhaps a better alternative to his/her life which has

already brought him/her to the verge of that catastrophe: “Pain is mesmerizing, let us admit

it. The tragic protagonist observes her own pain without asking to be saved. Saved for what?

For more of this life? But she has already repudiated this life . . . ! This is the secret

intelligence of the tragic experience, that the world is inadequate. Without this recognition,

how can she negotiate her own death?” (33).


105

Barker emphasizes the secret quality of death which is not within anybody’s

knowledge, as there hasn’t been anybody going there and coming back. In this respect, death

becomes the opposite of all functions, because it represents not knowledge, but a freedom

from knowledge; not an explanation, but inessentiality of explanation; not meaning, but an

escape from meaning. For him, “death communicates nothing. To describe it as mute is to

speak only part of its mystery. It is not to be found on the surface of the cadaver (however

one strains to make meaning from the cadaver, it yields nothing, it resists meaning, or if it

owns a vocabulary we do not know it)” (34). However, Barker’s understanding of tragedy is

completely incompatible with the blood tragedies in the Senecan sense, because the

catastrophic effect is never about the fear of the visible, but of the invisible, mysterious and

insolvable: “Death is not in the remains […] Tragedy, like death, is concerned with what is

not self-evident (the cadaver is not death, only the detritus of death. Death is the secret of

secrets, the origin of the idea of the secret, of which desire is the highest manifestation in

life” (34-35). In Barker’s ‘Theatre of Catastrophe”, the audience is not intended to achieve

the secret knowledge of death or what comes after it; on the contrary, the audience is

reminded of the fact that death is real and realistically unpredictable, strengthening that

catastrophic effect: “The art of theatre, which recognizes in tragedy the greatest gift of the

thinkers-of-death to the yet-to-be-dead, disposes of the self-evident with every gesture. In

other words, it deems all acts both possible and justified, thereby countering the humanist

slogan ‘we are all human’ with the terrible riposte ‘this is human also’” (35). The human

incapacity to know death for sure enhances tragedy’s catastrophic effect on the audience who

feels terror not at the potential pain accompanying death, but at its blindness to the only

reality surpassing human existence. Barker argues:

The greatest mystery of the universe is death. Unlike other mysteries, the
mystery of death is characterized by terror. Only tragedy makes death its
106

exclusive concern. It therefore enters willingly into terror, without presuming


to disarm it. More than ever tragedy is necessity, for we have passed through
the extinction of religion only to encounter the extinction of science. Admire
death for its disdain of these tranquillizing mythologies. Its obscurity is
impenetrable (48).
Tragedy also reminds the audience that death is for all and beyond human powers, and with

a faithful representation of death on the stage, the audience leaves the theatre with his

anxieties increased and tolerance tested. Tragedy plays with the audience’s ignorance when

it comes to the only reality in life and treats the audience like an innocent child who doesn’t

even know the difference between death and dying and is in constant pursuit of discovery

after discovery.

As for the tragic protagonist, Barker departs completely from the Aristotelian

understanding of tragedy as a culmination of human flaw and wrath of fate. He describes

such an understanding as the dimsightedness of sociological critics who evaluate the tragic

hero within the frame of a forced definition of ‘the perfect man’ (84). On the contrary,

Barker’s tragic protagonist is in full control of the action going on around himself and he is

aware of everything but the fact that he is being hunted down by death. Barker elaborates:

The tragic protagonist is not tired of life, nor thwarted, both conditions which
provide pretexts for evasion (and are the substance of the play of the theatre .
. .). On the contrary, he has an excess of existence to his credit, both of a
material and spiritual kind (authority, sexuality, imagination). It is true to say
of the tragic character that he lacks nothing – unlike in the political play, lack
is not the material of the drama, nor is it the source of his contempt. He might
alter everything to his will (becoming a ‘good’ king) but such considerations
are irrelevant to one who seeks, and is sought by, death (84).
In this respect, Barker’s tragic protagonists are never depicted as weak creatures in the face

of political, moral and social impositions, and they refuse any kind of authority trying to

cripple his spiritual capacities until death equalizes the table. Barker’s tragic heroes, or

heroines mostly, express their independence from social institutions with a moral, sexual and

political nakedness of which they are never ashamed. However, his tragic protagonists never
107

display superhuman qualities in their fight against institutional oppression, but they redefine

the limits of human capacities by stretching the borders of the familiar, stereotypical and

known (86).

The air of death pervades all of Barker’s plays accompanied by a catastrophic effect,

which manifests itself in a sense of futility and impression of waste regarding the fate of the

protagonist who ends up in a place where he never deserves to be. In Barker’s No End of

Blame, for instance, the image of the war is usually kept in the background with references

to the First and the Second World War. The protagonist of the play, Bela Veracek, journeys

through the war-torn Europe, from the Hungarian front and Moscow to London, and his

cartoons always take their subject matter from the greatest catastrophes taking place at the

time, like Hitler massacring huge numbers of people or soldiers being killed in the name of

a false sense of glory. As he himself is constantly being threatened with death by government

officials for the sharp edges of his art, Bela sways from one side to the other, ending up as a

mad man in an asylum at the end of the play after his failed suicide attempt. The play proves

quite tragic in the sense that nothing good comes to flourish whereas the bad keep

determining the way of the world. Similarly, in The Power of the Dog, Barker draws the

picture of the war-torn Europe after the Second World War with political figures like Stalin

and Churchill trying to snatch as much from the map as they can like ravenous vultures

hovering over dead bodies. The image of death stay at the background throughout the play,

with Ilona’s dead sister’s body coming and going, or Victor being shot towards the end of

the play, or Stalin’s obsession with his own death. In Ilona’s and Victor’s failed attempts to

reflect the war as it is in their photographs, not as the authority orders them to, Barker again

gives a sense of waste which is accompanied by McGroot’s defamiliarizing references to

other catastrophes around the world like a woman being raped by ten soldiers in Manchuria.
108

In Pity in History, the air of death and the catastrophic atmosphere are intensified

with the background of the Civil War, one of the bloodiest and darkest times in English

history, along with the constant screaming of Murgatroyd, the wounded army cook, whose

damnation of war echoes at the backstage throughout the play. The tragic impression of waste

is strengthened in the play with the fact that such a talented sculptor like Gaukroger has to

sell his artistic talent for a small amount of money in such a chaotic environment and that the

sculpture he has been working on since the beginning of the play is knocked down by some

vandalistic parliamentarian soldiers. In Scenes from an Execution, on the other hand, death

is at the centre of the whole plot with Galactia’s, the protagonist of the play who is a painter,

insistence on depicting the historical Battle of Lepanto as mere carnage in her painting

despite the fact that the officials’ commission asks for a celebration of the glory over the

Turks. Galactia points out the catastrophic side of the battle by emphasizing the mutilated

body of a veteran instead of depicting the commander of the Venetian armada leading a huge

victory. However, the same sense of futility and impression of waste are created again with

Galactia’s loss of her sanity along with her dominant character over the Duke and the

Cardinal. The play comes to a close in such a tragic way that the free-spirited Galactia leaves

her dignity aside in order not to be cast aside as a penniless and notorious painter. Finally, in

his Brutopia, Barker uses the execution of Sir Thomas More as the background story while

he explores the endeavour Cecilia, More’s youngest daughter, is making in order to be able

to get her book published by the king at the cost of losing her chastity as well as sanity. Even

after More’s death towards the end of the play, the catastrophic effect is sustained with King

Henry’s psychological instability and hot temper which culminates in Cecilia’s being

severely beaten and subjected to the king’s humiliations and insults. The same feeling of
109

waste is aroused when Cecilia cannot even find a proper means to distribute her published

book Brutopia and ends up falling into her greatest enemy’s clutches.

Barker’s ‘Theatre of Catastrophe’ is defined by such a preoccupation with death as a

central motive characterizing the whole action and pervading the general atmosphere along

with the protagonist’s spirit. To give death its due representation, Barker chooses the tragic

form with its graveness and loftiness compared to other forms of drama. He also prefers the

tragic form in order to sublimate death over all other human endeavours, which situates his

drama apart from the mainstream political theatre and theatre of violence popular among his

contemporaries. With the presence of death at the centre of his plays, Barker creates a

catastrophic effect first on his characters and then on the audience whom he aims to awaken

to the ultimate reality of human existence and shake out of their habitual political and moral

intoxication.

2.2. Language, Obscurity and the Question of Anti-Catharsis

Barker, in his Arguments for a Theatre, also gives a list of technical qualities that

conform with the tragic form he adopts as the representative form for his “Theatre of

Catastrophe” ranging from the language of his plays to the staging of them and further to the

level of the audience’s participation in the action and identification with the actors on the

stage. He sees a more poetic, rhythmical and lyrical language appropriate for the tragic form

he adopts in his plays and welcomes the obscurity of meaning and open-endedness coming

with it. He also attacks the Aristotelian concept of catharsis in drama, as he believes that such

solidarity among the members of the audience means nothing more than an orchestrated

mimicry.
110

For his “Theatre of Catastrophe”, Barker designates a special type of language,

bringing back the elaborated, rhetorical speech of the ancient Greek tragedies and liberating

the dramatic discourse from the banality of common speech. Barker’s designation connotes

“a new language whose rhythms and syntax are not those of common speech. It is a speech

as contrived as poetry, dislocated, sometimes lyrical, often coarse whose density and internal

contradictions both evoke and confuse” (1993:81). His attitude regarding the use of language

in drama verges on elitism, as he argues that his theatre departs drastically from naturalist

theatre in the latter’s target audience being the general public whereas the discourse of

“Theatre of Catastrophe” possesses an inflated diction with swift changes in tone and ruptures

in order. Barker elaborates on this issue as:

The characters speak not only in a fashioned way characteristic of me, but also
fully in a way that is impossible in naturalism. They have excess articulation,
no matter what their class or education. I aim deliberately at plethora, knowing
full well the public can’t keep up. The speeches are broken, themes dropped
and recovered again, strange, swift perceptions suddenly described, then
buried under a coarse banality. That’s their pattern of speaking. In terms of
their motivation, I’m unconstrained by Stanislavskian or Brechtian ideas of
truth. Since I have nothing to tell, I don’t need to adhere to laws of theatre that
are primarily to do with telling. And is the chaos in the minds of my characters
less authentic? Hardly, I think (177).

The deliberate complexity of the language of Barker’s catastrophic tragedies stems from the

playwright’s idea of truth as something not offered to the audience in a ready-made form, but

dug out by the individual members of the audience after much struggle with the meaning

mechanisms. However, this complexity is enhanced with the use of pauses and silences as

technical devices sometimes meaning more than the words uttered by the characters. Barker

explains this in his Death, the One and the Art of Theatre saying: “Silence is the consequence

of too-deep knowledge in some, of ignorance in others” (3). In other words, Barker gives as

great significance to silence as he gives to speech, and speech only matters as long as it

matches the grandeur of death that pervades the play. Barker’s “Theatre of Catastrophe” takes
111

heed of liberating the language of art from the banality of everyday speech and attributing

grander powers to it: “In the art of theatre we acknowledge a solitary obligation – to save

speech from itself” (3-4).

Barker defines drama as “not life described, but life imagined, it is possibility and not

reproduction” (30). His characters speak accordingly, having an imaginative, rather than a

descriptive, quality verging on poetry. Barker sacrifices clarity of language to lyricism and

the language his characters speak defies any kind of censorship, either institutional or social,

leading the protagonists to the margins of the society. Barker, in Arguments for a Theatre,

openly accepts that his language is meant to be obscure and ungraspable to lead the audience

to a productive confusion and questioning:

If the words are forbidden to the artist, the body reverts to the doctor, I would
suggest that the aim of the language censor is to return the body to the biology
class where eroticism is displaced and desire corrupted into a squalid
fetishism. […] I place the words in the mouths of certain characters […]
always with the deliberate intention of creating the unease in the audience
which is for me the condition of experiencing tragedy, an unease which is at
the opposite pole from the apathy an audience feels in a state of entertainment
(1993:30).

Barker sees obscurity of language and uncertainty of meaning as a necessity for the art of

theatre, as they are meant to create a disturbance in the habitual perceptions of the audience

in order to shake them out of their bystander apathy. This, in Barker’s opinion, is what

distinguishes the experience of tragedy from the experience of other forms of drama,

especially comedy, in which the audience is reduced to consumers of meaning in the manner

of crowds chanting banal tunes in unison.

When it comes to this question of collectivism in theatre, Barker comments on the

condition of English theatre in the present time as problematic, subordinating its great

potentialities for the sake of solidarity among the audience. For him, the audience of the

present time needs to experience pain instead of “contempt masquerading as comedy” (45),
112

dislocation instead of solidarity. His critique here is directed to a long tradition of theatre

whose central aim is to collect the individual members of the audience under one generalizing

moral message and enlighten them accordingly. Such an attitude is no different than a

marketing of values for Barker, and he, in his “Theatre of Catastrophe”, sacrifices collective

intelligibility to nonuniformity of meaning, saying: “The theatre suffers from a numbing

aesthetic of solidarity, elucidation, clarity, and so on, a sort of debased democracy that insists

on shared values and enlightenment. It is as if the culture was in dread of dissonance.

Personally, dissonance is where I feel at home” (2011:177-8). Barker refutes the inspirational

Aristotelian understanding of catharsis in theatre, and denies attributing such purgative

functions to the art of theatre as making the audience better or cleansing it by means of

feelings of fear and pity. The audience must never be meant to assume the personality of the

characters depicted on the stage, and for Barker, the art of theatre deserves more than an

experiential outlook: “The appetite for identification, which characterizes the theatre, has no

place in tragedy, where the death of the protagonist is perfection, i.e. never a cause for tears

. . . debased democracies make tears the lingua franca of collectivity (‘See how human I am’

says the weeping politician, ‘I’m just like you . . .’)” (Barker, 2005:90). However, Barker

never claims that the art of theatre must shake the audience out of its habitualness into a

critical attitude, like Brechtian political drama does. On the contrary, the art of theatre, in

Barker’s opinion, prohibits such premeditated reactions by the audience. Barker argues that

“the problem is not to make the audience critical (the collective sigh of orchestrated dismay

. . .) but hazardous . . .” (104). The art of theatre drives its audience to a questioning of a

personal kind and expects each member of the audience to come up with his own

understanding of the play rather than forcing packaged meanings into his mind.
113

The art of theatre uses a language of its own which denies the power to attribute

meanings to the words the characters are using in their speeches. Barker views this new kind

of language as a means to confuse the audience and send them to different directions in their

fluctuations in their search for a stable meaning. Barker elaborates on this issue saying: “The

art of theatre, in its impatience with the world, utters in its own languages. Moreover, it

understands these languages to be the means by which its public is cleansed of the detritus

of familiarity, domesticity and recognition” (7). Barker is quite serious about the lack of

meaning intended for his “Theatre of Catastrophe”, as he sees an inherent beauty in

oscillating between meanings and assumes that what matters is not the meaning of a dramatic

work, but the experience of tragedy: “Not understanding the point. The ecstasy of vanishing

meaning. Hiding in plethora. In the forest of concepts a pure stream” (14). Even though the

theatre expects a huge applause from the audience as a sign of their understanding and

agreement, the art of theatre cherishes the silence of the audience as a sign of success. For

Barker, the audience of “Theatre of Catastrophe” is never meant to understand, but to

experience the production on the stage after which silence means more than words. He states:

The theatre prefers the easy way because the audience prefers the easy way,
and the theatre defers to the audience; it is, in every sense, made from it. Of
those few who repudiate the easy way, fewer still can tolerate the silence of
the audience. They receive it as a wound. In the art of theatre not only do we
expect the audience to be silent, we demand it of them, we demand it as the
confirmation of our intentions. We concede there are many silences, but we
discriminate among the silences (17).
With the same motivation in mind, Barker proudly announces that his theatre never offers a

resolution to the actors and the audience, and his tragedies possess a deliberate open-

endedness which confuses the audience more into thinking and questioning. The audience is

always led into an unease, staying unsatisfied of answers from the beginning of the play till

the end. Barker puts it saying: “In the art of theatre we recoil from the idea of satisfaction,
114

either of the public or of ourselves. Satisfaction derives from resolution. Nothing in the art

of theatre tends towards resolution. We elevate anxiety over all things but beauty” (25). The

art of theatre is denied the satisfaction of the audience, because it does not have the

satisfaction for itself, either. Barker argues that the art of theatre renounces its potentials for

having knowledge and representing reality unlike the theatre: “The art of the theatre knows

nothing. It relegates knowing to the theatre, the place of commodities. In place of this

knowing, it affirms the integrity of fictions . . .” (46).

The language used in the plays concerned in this study, No End of Blame, The Power

of the Dog, Pity in History, Scenes from an Execution and Brutopia, never yields easy

meanings to the audience and celebrates obscurity as a means of saving dramatic experience

from populism. The language of the plays never tells directly, but suggests veiled political,

moral and aesthetic judgments on behalf of the playwright. For instance, the protagonists of

the plays never directly voice their political views to the face of the representatives of

authority, but suggest a perspective with the use of their arts. Bela uses his cartoons, Ilona

her photographs, Gaukroger his sculpture, Galactia her painting and Cecilia her book as a

reaction to the established, rotten system of political oppression only on a symbolic level and

they never resort to physical activism in order not to reduce their language to the banality of

the politicians’ speech. His characters reveal Barker’s leftist tendencies using language as

the ultimate means to come against political extremism, their distinctive intellectual language

substantially overwhelm that of the power holders. There are constant shifts of tone and

elaboration of speech from character to character throughout the plays. For example, in No

End of Blame, Bela outwits the committee of artists in Moscow while they are sunk into banal

formality with letter-perfect expressions. Similarly, in The Power of the Dog, Ilona’s

temperate speech is heavily contrasted with, for instance, Sorge’s military indelicacy of
115

speech. In Pity in History, on the other hand, the same observation can be made in the

differences between the ways Venables and Sergeant Boys speak. In a similar way, Galactia,

in Scenes from an Execution, outwits Cardinal Ostensible and Duke Urgentino with her

intellectualism beyond their capacities reflected in her brilliant argumentation. In Brutopia,

lastly, Barker makes quick shifts between Cecilia’s witty, sarcastic expressions and King

Henry’s bawdiness and incivility as reflected in his manners.

Barker explains the question of intellectual satisfaction on behalf of the audience in

theatre in his Death, the One and the Art of Theatre with an emphasis on the long-term

contributions of the art of theatre to the audience’s understanding whereas the theatre

complies with the audience’s immediate responses like applause and critical acclaim. The art

of theatre sacrifices such immediate responses from the audience to a deliberate

postponement of meaning and denial of resolution, as it attaches more importance to the

theatrical experience than to the theatrical meaning. Barker states that “the theatre gratifies

when it gives no more than is expected of it ... the art of theatre gratifies when it violates the

tolerance of its public (is this not a contradiction? But the effects of the work of art are

characterized by delay...)” (103). The same denial of meaning applies to the actors as well,

as they are not given a language that serves to mean, but to speak up. In a similar vein, the

actions of these actors on the stage do not necessarily have consequences and their actions

are not to be questioned by the audience with respect to a moral criterion. As long as the actor

is successful in serving his own desire and conveying the tragic beauty to the audience, he

stays faithful to his duties as an actor and instincts as a human. For Barker, “the art of theatre

replaces the question by the vortex of desire. We do not ask of a character ‘should he have

done that?’ He does what he does. We do not state ‘she is unforgivable’. She acts as she wills.

To bring the habits of questioning to the art of theatre is to be lost at the outset, rather as a
116

stranger to a locality, unable to speak the language, substitutes for his ignorance by shouting

. . .” (58). Barker sums up his argument regarding the art of theatre with the assumption

central to his “Theatre of Catastrophe” that true theatre exists only in the independence of

theatrical experience from the constraints of political, moral and even intellectual contexts.

2.3. Political, Moral and Aesthetic Functionlessness

Amanda Price, in her introduction to the second edition of Barker’s Arguments for a

Theatre, forms an analogy between the functionlessness of the playwright’s new style and

Roland Barthes’ seminal essay “The Death of the Author” in their deliberate liberation of the

text from the monopoly of the godly author “as the central organizing agent of truth” (4) and

proposition of a critical, distanced audience appointed with a role ‘outside’ the text. Thus,

the extermination of the author leaves the audience inbetween a huge number of ideological

suggestions and moral messages none of which has a claim to ‘the’ truth and, within that

multidimensionality, the audience is given a chance to do nothing else, but to experience the

theatre instead of its content. Barker creates this multidimensionality by not only his refusal

to attribute his characters ideological identities, but also by reflecting their ambiguous

personalities: “The only certainty Barker offers his spectator is that he will not purport to tell

the truth” (6). Barker’s plays demand a mutual struggle for meaning between the audience

and the actors on stage, which does not provide them with a meaning, but the struggle itself

which is what matters in the playwright’s terms.

Barker, in his distinction between the humanist theatre and his catastrophic theatre,

argues that the humanist theatre, which has been dominating the stage for the last few

decades, possesses a fatherly dutifulness to instruct, to make morally better and to cure social

sicknesses. He resembles such an effort to a utilitarian approach towards goodness and


117

happiness of the majority very much in the way that a shepherd drives the herd. He calls such

kind of theatre ‘the theatre of daylight, clarity and dubious truths’ whose most important

activity is to ‘research material’, “an activity closely related to the business of ‘dramatizing’

things” (73) to an inevitably didactic end. He condemns the humanist theatre’s misleading of

the audience to the assumption that whatever happens on stage is real, which actually does

nothing more than depriving theatre of its true potentials of unsettling and revolutionizing.

He addresses the humanist theatre as ‘The Theatre of Conscience’ which is “essentially a

mass declaration of loyalty to moral principles […] an activity that never sins” (74). In an

analogy between Schrödinger’s cat and Brechtian theatre, Barker critiques the latter’s

obsession with light and enlightenment whereas the former, in its acceptance of the potentials

of darkness, permits the river of innumerable possibilities to flow. He views darkness as a

triggering force for the audience’s imagination and light as a crippling effect that limits the

audience’s vision to what is seen. For him, a play should never be reduced to the stale ‘did

you know…’ attitude, but it should be dealing with ‘what ifs’ (75). Barker goes on by

accusing contemporary theatre of centring on questions of morality as strictly as possible and

of contributing to the rise of an audience of social conformists. Instead, “great art lives

outside the moral system, and its audience, consciously or unconsciously, demands it,

particularly in theatre whose very darkness is the condition of a secret pact, the pact of wilful

infringement, of the suspension of conscience, between actor and audience” (77).

In a deeper analysis of the ‘humanist’ or ‘liberal’ theatre of the present time, he

criticizes its insincere interest in giving messages to play with the audience’s conscience,

even though no one ever believes them even when they are applauding: “We are in a profound

contradiction when the audience claps what it no longer honestly believes” (45). He also

expresses his discontent with the liberal theatre’s reduction of the audience to the level of
118

passive consumers, always seeking ways to lead them to truths or meanings instead of, more

appropriately, providing versions: “A new theatre will not be ashamed of its complexity or

the absence of ideology. It will feel no obligations to lived life or to the journalistic impulse

to expose conditions. […] Consequently, what is achieved by [the new theatre] is achieved

individually and not collectively. There is no official interpretation. […] We need a theatre

of Anti-Parable, in which the moral is made by the audience, not by the actor” (46). He also

adds that his new theatre liberates the artist from his responsibilities to the public, to an

ideology or to himself, and he emphasizes the role of imagination as a superior means of

meaning-making than ideological reasoning: “The drama which I practice creates its own

world, it does not require validation from external sources, either of ideology or of spurious

realism, which is itself an ideology. It is compellingly imaginative and without responsibility

to historical or political convention” (29).

In his brilliant imaginary Socratic dialogue with the Jacobean dramatist Thomas

Middleton, whose famous tragedy Women Beware Women he rewrote, Barker defends his

theatre of catastrophe against the former’s accusations of ‘encouragement to bad morals’ and

distortion of his play’s essence. Middleton describes Barker as “an irresponsible optimist

[who] ha[s] deprived the audience of its right to moral satisfaction” (25), to which the latter

responds stating that “it is simply unrealistic to inflict slaughter on all the participants in the

interest of morality (25). In a comparison between the Jacobean England and the

contemporary political atmosphere, the deceased playwright complains about the crown and

the church as mechanisms of censorship in his era, which is why he had to keep away from

politics in his works in order not to end up in jail. He also blames Barker for removing the

‘moral spokesman’ from his play, but the latter argues that such conventional preaching does

no longer have a place in theatre. For Barker in the dialogue, the present time requires a
119

different form of drama in which the audience is not tantalized with false heroism, optimism

or poetic justice, but awakened to the dignity of human struggle and power of its creative

abilities: “Failure is unimportant, the attempt is all” (27).

Barker extends his arguments to what he calls the fundamental debate over the

function or, rather, functionlessness of art and claims he has never written a word for the

betterment of the public or for telling right from wrong: “The theatre I have chosen to

embrace is one which makes no compact with its audience as to entertainment, ideological

instruction, humanist celebration or changed perceptions” (89). He defends his theatre’s

suspension of any morality or ideology which he sacrifices to the artistic experience on behalf

of the audience. Barker draws attention to the contemporary dramatists’ self-deception that

the success of their work depends on their affirmation of the public morality. He admits that

there is certain safety in the satisfaction of the audience’s expectations, which secures the

artist’s popularity and the play’s rating at a high level; yet, such an approach enslaves the

artistic creativity within the cages of habitualness, repetition, servility and responsibility. For

Barker, the theatre in the 1960s and 1970s sacrificed its artistic innovative practice to the

political program of the period, reduced itself to a tool in the name of ‘contributing’ to an on-

going debate: “[They] are simply artistic arms of the national conscience – and the theatre of

the margins. […] What occurs is the routine massaging of collective values that passes for

‘communication’, communication being territorial familiarity, acts of recognition, the

stimulation of sympathy with the catalogue of known and revered victims” (92-93). In

opposition to this, Barker proposes his own understanding of theatre in which works of art

take their value not from the amount of entertainment they offer or the degree of change they

cause in the audience, but from the distortion they create in the core of those collective

wisdom, values and perceptions which reduce the individual artistic experience to common
120

servility. For him, “the governing principles of the contemporary theatre – still wholly

Stanislavskian and Brechtian in nature – are rigorously anti-speculative, obsessed with

intentions and objectives, and oppressive in their severe delimitations offstage action and

actors’ invention” (94). These principles, which specify any challenge to reality as heresy in

the face of the ‘flawless’ collective morality, have dominated the recent history of theatre

and, for Barker, debarred theatre from poetry. Barker’s catastrophic theatre, however, does

not expect the audience to be disciplined by forced meanings, but to speculate on the

possibility of those meanings to dislocate the familiar, the habitual and the collective.

Barker repeats his intentions to attribute the rights of interpretation to the audience,

which can only be achieved by abandoning two outmoded habits of contemporary theatre,

realism and clarity, both of which presuppose moral and intellectual weakness in the

audience. He acknowledges the fact that realism and clarity used to be necessary components

of theatre when there was certain moral and intellectual concurrence among the playwright,

the actors and the audience. Yet, in the present time when chaos prevails over all moral

deliberations, the function of a theatre should be “to return the responsibility for moral

argument to the audience itself […] [to ask] the audience to test the validity of the categories

it believes it lives by” (52). He acknowledges that the issue of ‘telling’ is no more the

playwrights’ job which has always been a means to undermine the audience’s capacity of

understanding and reasoning:

In a conscience-free theatre, there is, of course, no telling. It is the farthest


reach from the Brechtian demonstration. There is no ‘telling’ because the
writer had nothing to tell – his play was a journey to him as it is a journey to
the actor, the outcome of which was unknown at its beginning […] This is the
very act of honouring […] of an audience by refusing the simple satisfactions
of reiteration, affirmations, congratulation – the sort of theatre in which the
morality was fixed in advance, and the writing, and the narrative was a means
to an end (77-78).
121

However, interestingly and self-contradictiously, Barker calls for a covert, indirect political

involvement in theatre, not through stale didacticism, but through the use of complexity

against the present society’s coarse but equally deep-rooted moral values. He declares that

ambiguity itself is a powerful political weapon which does not impose a ready-made morality

upon the audience, but deliberately leads them into a moral conflict in themselves: “The play

which refuses the message, the lecture, the conscience-ridden expose, but which insists upon

the inventive and imaginative at every point, creates new tensions in a blandly entertainment-

led culture” (48). Although he admits that some of his own plays seem to possess direct

political identities, Barker never claims responsibility for circling about the audience’s

imagination and conscience, as he is not a ‘tailor’ of ideologies but an ‘exposer’ of them. He

openly blames the authorial voice of misdirecting the audience to political and moral

imperatives, rather than to themselves, a voice which, striving to illuminate the blind,

“prevents the proper focus of meaning in a work of art” (49). Barker, for instance, describes

Claw (1975), one of his earlier plays, as a “didactic play of politics demonstrating false

consciousness, […] whose didacticism is scattered in a surge of terror” (55-56). However, he

does not sacrifice the catastrophe’s grandeur to the potential message given by the play. He

shatters the audience’s expectations for a resolution and optimism for a restoration of the

order, and although the hero dies in the end, what matters is not his death, but the way he

dies at the end of the process of his struggle against the authority. He, in a way, subordinates

the political message to the language and the grandeur of the action. The hero’s death on the

stage is subordinated to his unquestioning acceptance of death without any resistance: “The

potential slogan is always suffocated by the complex beauty of language delivered of its

naturalistic bondage” (56). The terror the audience feels upon the action on the stage pushes

the didacticism to the background, as the audience is left unable in-between an exploded
122

optimism and the complex beauty of the language. Barker admits that the covert political

message veiled behind the context of terror and beauty in the scene has a stronger subversive

power than the direct didactic approach. The play deliberately fails to deliver a message and

obliges the audience to process the ending of the play in order to make up a message for

himself (57).

Barker also addresses his criticism to money-driven playwrights of his time whom he

describes as “the tin crusaders of the new populism, with a positively renaissance appetite

for personal gain on the one hand but a knocked-together ideology on the other” (34). The

new populism he mentions here refers to public acknowledgment as a result of the validation

of the dominant ideological and moral habituality, which necessitates the emergence of a new

genre, like his “Theatre of Catastrophe”, not to cure these sicknesses, but to raise an

awareness to them:

The deterioration of habitual moral and political assumptions was the sole
means by which a change in form became possible […] The tension between
the audience and the play became for me an aesthetic, the nature of experience.
This involved challenges to common morality, common socialism, even what
passes for common humanity […] The task of serious art is to describe not
wickedness but collision, not simply authority but submission […] A moral
theatre is not one which separates the sheep from the goats (the exploited, the
exploiter) but accuses the exploited also (22-24).

In Barker’s view, the playwright or simply the work of art possesses no responsibility towards

the dominant moral codes in a given society, as morality is not external, but internal to the

play, not validated, but created in the play by exposing the audience to “pain and the

illegitimate thought” (47). In other words, “the play is not a lecture and therefore owes no

duty of lucidity or total coherence” (55). Barker repeats the same objectives in an interview

that theatre, or at least his theatre, is a means to escape from practical and ideological

‘functions’, it is rather a glorification of the theatrical experience on behalf of the audience

and the actors who are the sole possessors of meaning and morality in their most individual
123

manners: “It is wilful suicide for theatre to permit itself to be annexed to functional ends […]

My obligation as director is to create metaphorical truth. For me theatre is about suggesting

things, not about telling everything” (2011:175-176). On behalf of the playwright, on the

other hand, theatre is not a means to serve in any possible meaning of the word, but a chance

to achieve beauty liberated from any forced background connotations: “It may sound […] as

if I believed in moral responsibility in artists, but I don’t, and it is anyway a false dichotomy.

The artist has no duty except to himself, by which I mean to say, to his instinct (not his

conscience…). If he obeys this injunction to speak his darkness, he will – inevitably – serve

a public, for theatre speaks what is not spoken elsewhere, it is its supreme beauty” (179).

A similar approach to political, moral and ideological involvement in theatre, or in

art in general, is present in Barker’s minor theoretical treatise titled Death, the One, and the

Art of Theatre (2005). He starts with a distinction between the theatre, which represents the

mainstream political drama popular among his contemporaries, and the art of theatre, which

refers to the ideal form of drama immune to political and moral interference – to which his

“Theatre of Catastrophe” has a claim. He calls for the necessity to come unstuck of the idea

that theatre buildings are built to cure socio-political sicknesses or to promote and sublimate

the ideological agendas of certain political parties: “Since theatre ceased to make death its

subject it surrendered its authority over the human soul. Since it allowed itself to be

incorporated into mundane projects of political indoctrination and social therapy it abdicated

its power. […] Whilst many have tried to make hospitals from theatres we keep our stage

infection-free” (2). He deems the art of theatre more intimate and honest with the audience,

as it never attempts to commercialize ready-made meanings and underestimates the

audience’s capacities:

The theatre resents the art of theatre, sensing its deeper intimacy with its
public. All the lavish endowment of superficial skills and décor, the critical
124

allegiance, the celebrity actors, the vulgar imprimatur of the patronage of the
state with its palaces of art and its marketing bureaucracy (would you require
to market a need?) cannot conceal the unhealthiness of the transaction. The
intimacy that characterizes the art of theatre derives from the very condition
the theatre is at such pains to eliminate – anxiety. In the theatre they talk of
‘the show’. Does this not tell us everything about their condescension? But
even they still possess sufficient modesty not to describe their efforts as
revelations . . . (40-41).

Barker voices his criticism of the political dramatists of his time, who follow the Brechtian

legacy in drama, for turning the theatre buildings into marketplaces and art-making into show

business. However, he traces the sources of this politicization of the dramatic art back to the

very beginning of dramatic criticism, to Aristotle who “forced politics onto the supremely

apolitical” (68) by means of catharsis. The modern-time representatives of the same outlook,

the so-called ‘humanist’ dramatists of the late 20th century, do it by means of trading human

conscience for a stale political message (96).

Barker persistently elaborates on the necessary distinction between theatre and the art

of theatre in terms of their moral, social and political preoccupations with an emphasis on the

functionlessness of the latter whereas the former is always dependent on a background. He

argues that “the art of theatre has many of the characteristics of religion. For example, it finds

so much theatre anathema. It excommunicates. Its methods are akin to prayer. What

distinguishes it from all religion is this, however: that it recoils from truth. It repudiates truth

as vulgarity” (2). In his comparison between the art of theatre and religion, Barker

emphasizes that the former has strict rules of conversion whereas it never assumes the role

of selling a false hope regarding an ‘other’ world. On the contrary, it attempts to awaken the

audience, as well as the actors and even the playwright himself, to the beauty of thinking for

the sake of thinking: “We repudiate all those who find theatre congenial. The art of theatre is

constructed on the premises that the creation of happiness is no part of its function. Nor does

it have a function” (4). In doing so, the art of theatre never deems itself responsible for
125

reproducing real life unlike the realist drama which dominated the late 19th and the early 20th

century. He clarifies this point saying: “So essential is theatre to the idea of life it cannot be

compromised by making itself the imitation of life. It cannot be humiliated by rituals of

reproduction. The theatre reproduces life. The art of theatre invents life. This act of invention

may be perceived as a critique of the poverty of existence. It is not social criticism” (6).

Barker seems to admit that Brechtian influence has dominated the European theatre

in the last decades of the 20th century and he views this as a blow inflicted on the aesthetic

potentials of the dramatic art on behalf of the audience, the actors and the playwright due to

its emphasis on outmoded, stale moralism: “The theatre – why did the moralists collect there?

Why had they always brought their gnawing missions to the stage, and why were they so

enraged when the art of theatre revealed its aesthetic incompatibility with morality? (It did

not stoop to repudiate what in any case was alien to it, a fundamental contradiction.)” (23).

In this respect, the sole function of the art of theatre, for Barker, may be to make its intended

addressees realize that they all are ignorant creatures in a world where light always means

deception and ignorance is bliss: “The art of theatre is a rehearsal for death but more, a

confession of ignorance, of the limits of knowledge. . .” (32). In a similar vein, the art of

theatre cherishes ‘not knowing’ or, rather, ‘not knowing for sure’ in a world where

knowledge means misapprehension, prejudgement and indoctrination. For the same reason,

the art of theatre never aspires to teaching, as teaching is just another name for brainwashing:

“The art of theatre aspires to a moral nakedness. It is the antithesis of education therefore,

which is clothing, which is a suffocation in ethical garments […] The art of theatre takes pain

as its subject, not to exploit it for political ends, as a lesson in moral obligations but as an end

in itself” (33). In an era in which nothing is actually for itself, Barker’s “Theatre of

Catastrophe” brings a huge challenge to the ongoing system by not offering any messages to
126

its audience whose interpretation –not collectively, but individually- matters above all.

Barker contends that, unlike the theatre, “the art of theatre exists for itself. How hard this is

to say, to mean, hard because the prejudices of contemporary morality abhor ‘things for

themselves’, demanding ‘meaning’ and ‘use’ in every man and every thing” (38). Although

the theatre authoritatively tells the audience what it needs to feel, the art of theatre draws

attention to the fact that the audience does not know what it feels or that it is not aware that

it possesses certain feelings.

The art of theatre falls within the realm of imagination, of which it seems to be really

proud, and takes the premises of realism as ultimate dishonesty towards the playwright

himself, the actors and the audience. Although the theatre has long taken the role of the realist

educator on itself, the art of theatre privileges itself with the loss or absence of realistic proofs

that pull the artistic endeavour into the domain of vulgar consumption. He states:

In the art of theatre something is always lost. In a world of relentless


aggregation, to lose might be a lightness, an intoxication. What is it that is
lost? The burden of your moral convictions. This is a loss that might be
experienced as a privilege . . . […] The art of theatre holds evidence in
contempt. Its propositions require no proof, nor are they susceptible to the
trivializing objections of empiricism. It consigns all questions of proof to the
realm of prejudice. […] The art of theatre does not occupy itself with the
amelioration of human existence. This alone distinguishes it from all other
theatre practice, whose goodwill is a vulgarity. All that may come to be
described as the satisfactions of the art of theatre are accidental, byproducts of
an ordeal (41-48).
However, Barker admits that the urge to teach is a natural human motivation which manifests

itself in the vilest form of preaching with the assumption that one’s moral and political

outlook is superior to the other. It is the playwright’s point of honour, in Barker’s view, to

suppress that base compulsion and transform his moral and political self into a neutral,

conscience-free voice whose sole determination lies in the achievement of the beauty of

theatrical experience. Barker argues that this is only possible through the tragic form with an

emphasis on death which is itself a symbol of darkness, obscurity, loss and unknowing:
127

The art of theatre is a darkness, because it speaks to a darkness. How does it


protect the wealth of its darkness from the enlighteners? How does it protect
its darkness from its own will to abolish this darkness – for, let us confess it –
there is no man alive who lacks the compulsion to teach? In the first instance
we scrupulously cleanse ourselves of all those moral, medical and political
neuroses pertaining to the improvement of mankind. We deny ourselves the
coercive pleasure of instructing the public. The annexation of theatre as a
platform for the conscience of the author we deem barbaric. Second, we
discard all obligation except the supreme obligation to intensify the hazard of
the performance, to the public and to ourselves alike. In this determination to
imagine beyond the perimeters of experience the art of theatre reveals its
absolute identity with the tragic form (49).
Barker, here, reminds his readers of the presence of death both as the ultimate form of reality

and the antithesis to all worldly endeavours including morality and politics. Thanks to its

interest in death, the art of theatre triggers the audience’s urge to discover what is yet

unknown to it and shakes it out of its habitual perception of the external realities. But the art

of theatre does not use the hypocritical techniques of preaching which belong to the theatre

of “second-order dramatists”, it does not “contaminate” the audience’s theatrical experiences

with the stain of “function” (57). As it never holds a claim to the representation of any reality

whatsoever, the art of theatre is also exempt from meaninglessness or coherence of any kind,

“repudiat[ing] the will to influence as a perversion shared by elements of the theatre as

diverse as socialist realism and the Broadway musical (how diverse are these on close

inspection?). Only in the abolition of the will to influence does the art of theatre begin to

recognize itself” (64). For the art of theatre to recognize its own potentials, it must first get

liberated from the quest for the truth and seeking a targeted audience for itself:

The abolition of function and influence determines the moral condition of the
production. In discarding the baggage of sordid ambitions that identifies the
theatre – the dispensing of ‘truth’, the ‘correction of attitudes’, the ‘giving’ of
pleasure – the art of theatre creates an immunity for itself. An immunity from
what? All transactions […] We cannot repeat it too often – the art of theatre
does not seek an audience, it acquires one . . .” (64-65).
128

Barker views an obsession with the truth and representing the reality as a perversity on behalf

of the social realist playwrights from Ibsen through Brecht to his contemporaries who

enslaved their pens to the political agendas of certain political and moral parties. He also

contends that, in the modern times, seeing is mistaken for belief, but what is shown to the

audience is nothing more than political and moral propaganda to which Barker intends his

plays to be an alternative. He believes that “in the art of theatre the more we exert ourselves

to abolish the real (the damage done to us by the recognizable) the nearer we approach the

known” (68). As what is shown to the audience to be the reality is a set of values, somebody

else’s values, in contemporary art, abolishing the real means abolishing the values, and thus,

the audience can be given a chance to stand against what Barker calls the moral police: “Since

[the art of theatre] was liberated from the obligations of realism it finds meanings both in its

form and in its content. The theatre by contrast can suggest no more than it is provided with,

it is miserably accident-proof” (91-92). The theatre, in Barker’s understanding, loves control

and fears autonomy very much like the authoritarian regimes in the history of mankind.

However, the art of theatre embraces autonomy as a central tenet of all artistic endeavours

towards a freedom from political and moral slavishness.

Barker summarizes his ideas about the functional nonalignment of his “Theatre of

Catastrophe” with a list of keywords that best defines the art of theatre, including “infinite,

functionless, intractable, nowhere, incalculable, illogical, arbitrary” (92) which are already

the attributes of death as the enemy of all ideological and moral preoccupations. He resembles

the theatre to an old woman on the verge of death, which is why it sticks to moral rules, and

concludes his views with an advice to the audience: “Like the old woman who shortens her

walk with every passing day the theatre is afraid to quit the moral perimeters of the domestic

. . . but this house stinks . . . ! You must get fresh air . . . !” (104). However, a reinterpretation
129

of Barker’s plays within the context of historiographic metadrama contradicts his designation

of his “Theatre of Catastrophe” as a politically, morally and aesthetically functionless kind.

His interest in historical subject matters and his use of artists as the protagonists of his play

come to have deeper meanings when these are examined in parallelism with the political,

moral and aesthetic environment in Barker’s time, and these turn out to be a means of veiled

criticism despite the playwright’s claims regarding his art as a non-didactic kind. In this

respect, the following chapter brings a new perspective to Barker’s selected plays written in

the 80s in order to reveal the political, moral and aesthetic consciousness beneath the surface

of Barker’s interest in history and arts for the subject matter of his plays.
130

CHAPTER 3

REREADING HOWARD BARKER’S PLAYS AS HISTORIOGRAPHIC

METADRAMA

Howard Barker’s career as a dramatist took a different direction in the 80s in line with

the playwright’s interest in history, the developments in England regarding the licensing of

art culminating in The Theatres Act in 1968 and the surreptitious censorship still going on

even after the preclusion of the Lord Chamberlain’s Office from taking such measures.

Rusinko observes that Barker’s interest in the study of history results in and stems from his

MA at Sussex University in history (1989:138). Most of Barker’s plays written during the

80s take their subject matter from history, documented or imaginary, with an aim to rewrite

history or reinterpret the historical events from an artist’s perspective. Barker himself

acknowledges that history has a significant role in his career as a playwright: “But history is

a vastly important factor in my plays. It broods over most of my work, it lurks in the back of

the characters’ minds, and is a persistent justification for action. The right-wing characters

invoke it continually and the left fret about its judgment” (in Trussler and Hay, 1981:30).

In another interview, Barker touches upon the relation between politics and history in

a different way explaining his choice of history to convey an indirect political message: “My

political sense derives from the past, and I view the present from the perspective of the past,

at least as I have constructed it, in imagination. […] I am acutely conscious of the collapse

of a political ethic in my own time, but my sense is always that we have been here before”

(39). Thus, it is seen that Barker differs from his contemporaries in the way he makes use of

the historical subject and setting in his plays. The past is a means for Barker to come up with

remedies for today’s shortcomings. This makes Barker a historical as well as a political

playwright even though he speaks otherwise in the formulation of his “Theatre of


131

Catastrophe”, as he turns a critical eye to the past without losing sight of the present in his

works. In his seminal Arguments for a Theatre, Barker confesses that he has a disbelief in

the premises of history as it is recorded in books written by ideologically-concerned

historians:

History is where I had begun, neither official history nor documentary history,
whose truth I deny but the history of emotion, looking for a politics of the
emotions, I discovered that the only things worth describing now are things
that do not happen, just as the only history plays worth writing concern
themselves with what did not occur. […] Writing now has to engage with what
is not seen (i.e. imagination) because real life is annexed, reproduced,
soporific (23).

To emphasize the differences between his theatre and the so called ‘humanist theatre’, which

he also calls ‘theatre of journalism’, Barker draws attention to art’s relationship with what is

out there, what is experienced by real people and what is known to have happened, in other

words with history: “An artist uses imagination to speculate about life as it is lived, and

proposes, consciously or unconsciously, life as it might be lived. The more daringly he

dreams, therefore, the more subversive he becomes” (36). From this comparison, he moves

on to his suggestion of the appropriateness of his “Theatre of Catastrophe” for the present

time, a new kind of theatre which, in order to be taken seriously, must abandon first comedy,

then factuality, and then an unquestioning trust in what is seen, and finally seeing itself

superior to its audience. Barker’s catastrophic tragedies, in this sense, set the rules for a new

kind of drama which “is not about life as it is lived at all, but about life as it might be lived,

about the thought which is not licensed, and about the abolished unconscious” (52).

Barker’s interest in the representation of history on stage is accompanied with a

concern with the artistic perspective in the historical representation. As a free-spirited artist

himself, Barker chooses his protagonists for his historical, or rather historiographic, plays

from among artists from whose perspective documented historical events are reinterpreted.
132

In the introduction to Barker’s Arguments for a Theatre, Price describes Barker’s theatrical

method as one that “determines to show not the author’s destination, but rather the process

of struggle which initiates artistic endeavour” (1993:6). In his major historiographic plays,

Barker pits the free-spirited artist against a superior, generally political, power and generates

a moment of crisis, which he calls the moment of beauty: “The moment of beauty is the

moment of collision between two wills, the will of the irrational protagonist (the non-

ideological) and the will of the irrational state (the officially ideological)” (Barker, 1993:59).

Barker glorifies this individual resistance against institutional or social oppression in many

of his plays and calls for again an individual, rather than a collective, deduction of morality

by the deliberate ‘removal of moral climate’ or ‘suspension of moral predictability’. His plays

do not “aspire to indicate ‘correct’ action, or ‘correct’ analysis” (59). Instead, they create

certain moral and political anxiety in which the audience, having been forced to be the judge

of what Barker calls the ‘wrong’ action or injustice on the stage, feels provoked to reconsider

his own moral and political outlook along with those of the characters. He explains the

reasons for his choice of characters from among artists saying: “I found in the study of the

artist himself […] the cause that was neither wholly self nor the rattling egotism of

entertainment. […] This was a sense of artistic responsibility both to order and to violation,

on the one hand to language and the literary culture […] and on the other, to the furtherest

reaches of speculation whether of desire or dissolution” (24). By the artist’s responsibility to

speculation driven by desire, Barker refers to the historical representation’s speculative

nature and its equal status to artistic endeavour in the representation of the lived past filtered

through imaginative faculties of an author.

With respect to these two points, Howard Barker’s historiographic plays which take

an artist or artists as their protagonists can be examined within the framework of the popular
133

dramatic genre which has earlier been discussed in this study. Barker, in the selected plays

to be analysed below, deals with documented history as a grand narrative whose claim to

accurate knowledge of the past is the product of an illusion or the imaginative faculties of a

‘narrator’. In doing so, he puts an artist at the centre of the historical events already known

to the readers and researchers of history and questions the validity of historical accounts by

writing an alternative account which, he claims, is as valid as any other historical writing on

the same topic. In addition to that, he uses these artists as a mouthpiece to form parallelisms

between the past and the present in order to voice his criticism of deep-rooted political, moral,

aesthetic and social shortcomings of his own time. With the struggle of his artist-protagonists

against various kinds of authoritative forces, Barker also expresses his views about such long-

debated issues as censorship of art, freedom of expression and the use of art as a means of

political propaganda. By referring to first documented historical events, then to other forms

of art and finally to themselves as works of art, Barker’s historiographic plays in question

display a metadramatic essence with an eye to Hornby’s list of varieties of metadrama. In

this respect, Barker’s famous plays written in the 80s- No End of Blame, The Power of the

Dog, Pity in History, Scenes from an Execution and Brutopia- are to be discussed as early

examples of the genre “historiographic metadrama” by taking into consideration the

historical texts dealing with the same period in history and the elements of metadrama

discussed before.

3.1. No End of Blame and the ‘Terrible’ Power of Art

Published in 1981 and staged every once in a while so far, Barker’s No End of Blame:

Scenes of Overcoming is one of the playwright’s historiographic plays which takes its subject

matter from the documented events of the European history and revolves around a free-
134

spirited artist who struggles against diverse forms of institutional oppression over the course

of a few decades. The play follows the footsteps of a Hungarian cartoonist named Bela

Veracek through some of the milestone stages of European history including the Hungarian

front of the First World War, the early years of the Soviet Union and the English-German

war in the Second World War. With Bela’s never-ending conflict with the power-holders on

the potential functions of his cartoons, Barker draws attention to contemporary issues

troubling the artists like political intervention in art, violation of freedom of thought and

speech and the question of responsibilities of an artist towards his society.

The play opens in a remote setting in the Carpathian Mountains at the end of the First

World War with two Hungarian soldier-artists, Grigor Gabor and Bela Veracek, a painter and

a cartoonist, working on a drawing titled ‘Soldiers Bathing’ and examining the saggy body

of a naked Romanian woman who serves them as a model at gunpoint. As Bela attempts to

rape the naked woman, Grigor interferes, causing the woman to escape, and Grigor begins to

draw now-naked Bela instead of the woman. Then, the two artists engage in a hot debate

concerning the question of morality and Bela accuses Grigor of being a ‘moral hero’ “in the

midst of all [the] sin and shame and human vileness, where [they] eat [their] breakfast off a

man’s divided trunk” (1990:77). Their discussion is interrupted with the entrance of a group

of Hungarian soldiers who, syllogising from Bela’s nakedness, accuse the two of

homosexuality and desertion, which are both serious crimes to be punished with death. The

moment the soldiers get ready to execute the artists, some Red Soldiers, or communists as

one of the soldiers puts it, flood in and save the two from the execution, giving Bela a chance

to shoot the officer who has intended to execute him a few minutes before. Bela takes the

officer offstage, one gunshot is heard and he comes back in to tell the Red Soldiers that he

has shot the Hungarian officer. Upon hearing about the deed, Grigor refuses to stay friends
135

with Bela who explains his friend that he has let the man go, and the two depart to go home,

as the war is officially over.

The second scene moves the setting to the Bucharest of 1921 where Bela and Grigor

are working on a sketch of a female model named Stella at the institute of fine arts. As the

two are having trouble with the model girl who keeps moving and spoiling the moment, the

head of the institute, named Billwitz, appears in the room with a paper in his hand, a cartoon

titled ‘We Will Revive the Spirit of Hungary’ which he deems a humiliation to the grand

duties of art due to the grotesque images of ‘two soldiers beating a man to death’. Upon

learning that the cartoon has been drawn by Bela, Billwitz asks the others to leave and begins

preaching about the functions of art and the duties of an artist to represent truth as if it really

existed. He, then, informs Bela that he is to be expelled from the country for his provocative

drawings and behaviours which have long been attracting the attention of the police. Bela

responds to the man saying: “My art speaks, then! […] I stirred the police, therefore, I

touched the truth” (85). After Billwitz’s departure, Bela meets Grigor again to persuade him

to go together out of that dead place. Grigor hesitates first and expresses his contentment

with a little corner where he can paint and a diploma which Bela describes as a “shabby bit

of paper for performing dog” (86) emphasizing the governmental interference in art. The

scene ends with Bela, Grigor and Ilona, a fellow female art student who is apparently in love

with Bela, determining to go to Russia together.

Four years later, Bela appears in Moscow in front of a jury in the artists’ union where

the jurors praise his cartoons which also attracted Lenin’s attention. They inform him that

Lenin gives high prominence to art, implying that he views art as a means of political

propaganda. The jury of five artists, including a poet-sculptor, two critics, a painter and a

graphic artist, engage in a hot debate regarding the power of art and freedom of expression
136

or artistic vision from the bourgeois constraints, though not from political interference. All

seem to agree that art has “a terrible power […] of addressing hearts and minds, articulating

the unspoken will of peoples, […] a power which in the case of the very greatest artists, may

be beyond even the control of genius itself” (94). The central topic of the meeting turns out

to be a particular cartoon titled ‘The New Economic Plan’ drawn by Bela which depictures

a capitalist stealing from an old Bolshevik while Lenin stands behind a wall turning a blind

eye to it. The jurors question Bela for the cartoon’s “tendency to criticize the line that

Comrade Lenin is advancing” (96) and warn him that he has to keep his head down for the

sake of the Bolsheviks’ great undertaking, even if Lenin has some apparent mistakes. Bela

refuses to be restrained by any force, whether it be political or social, as he puts freedom of

expression above all. To this, the jurors respond with a stress on the social and political

dimension of art, for they believe an artist’s freedom is bound to his society’s freedom. When

Bela openly confesses that he disapproves of some of Lenin’s undertakings, all the members

of the jury protest that he has to keep a low profile and, if he has to criticize, he must do it

some other way “in the wider interests of the people” (97).

In the fourth scene taking place in 1934, the setting moves to a garden in the suburbs

of Moscow where Grigor, Ilona and Bela discuss Grigor’s plans to live in the woods to expose

himself ‘unhesitatingly’ to his human essence. Bela protests that their real fight against

worship and surrender of oneself necessitates their stay in the heart of the events while Grigor

and Ilona, who is now Bela’s wife with a child, leave to realize the former’s plan. After the

departure of his wife and best friend, Bela meets Ludmilla, who was one of the members of

his jury in the related scene and with whom he is now apparently in a relationship; and she

informs Bela that Stalin himself wants him to have a holiday, most probably to keep his nose

out of the government’s practices. In the following scene, Bela arrives in England and kisses
137

the ground with the belief that he has finally drawn a free breath. In the customs shed of

Dover, Bela is treated like a beggar by two officers until Sir Herbert Strubenzee, a knight

with whom he has probably earlier made acquaintance, takes him through the customs onto

the so-called free English soil while, around the corner, “a Hitlerine bat […] casts a shadow

over the European portion of the globe” (104). The first act ends with a violent set of sound

effects including the firing of a gun and Ilona’s desperate screams.

The second act begins with Bela among some Royal Air Force personnel right

towards the end of the Second World War as he shares his views about the function of art

and responsibilities of an artist with them. He makes a distinction between important art and

great art, the former being about the people in general, the latter about the artist himself. He

confesses that the cartoon, his profession, is the lowest form of art, though with a huge

significance in terms of people’s struggles, and he cares more about humanity than himself.

Although he openly appreciates the power of ‘great’ art, like a painting which is ‘plundered’

for its strong private meaning, he believes more in the power of ‘important’ art, like a cartoon

which has only one meaning celebrated by millions: “The cartoon changes the world. The

painting changes the artist. I long to change the world. I hate the world” (108). These

sentences reveal that Bela’s view of art as an independent domain from all ideological

contexts has dramatically changed in time after witnessing all those catastrophic events; and

the political oppression has had an adverse effect on his artistic voice by which he now

condemns any totalitarian idea. However, Bela’s discussion with the English pilots prove that

there is always a bigger personal dimension of art, because an artist cannot reconcile

contrasting ideas in his art and has to be selective about his topic, producing what speaks to

him most.
138

Then, Bela meets Stringer, his publisher and the editor of a paper, and the two discuss

one of Bela’s cartoons which depicts an English soldier tackling with Hitler while a

‘profiteer’, probably a reference to Winston Churchill himself, is trying to bowstring the

soldier behind his back. Stringer warns Bela that he has to be ‘small’, ‘error incarnate’ and

praise the king and the parliament in front of the upcoming board of auditors, otherwise the

government has the power to shut down the paper under the pretext of ‘the Defence of the

Realm Act’. When the officials arrive, they get to the point swiftly and inform Bela and

Stringer that ‘Winston’ does not approve of their latest work, to which Stringer responds

mildly while Bela keeps ironically praising the kingdom and the parliament. The officials

compare Stringer’s paper with Mirror which has been uncritically supporting Churchill’s

campaign and assure the editor that they have the power to shut all the papers down if they

want to. Upon being questioned about his political orientation, Bela argues that his politics

are to look for the truth and to shout it when found; and Stringer defends his freedom of

expression and publication in the name of democracy for which England seems to have been

fighting. After being covertly threatened by the officials with imprisonment and shutdown,

Stringer and Bela decide to rub the officials the right way only to secretly be a law onto

themselves.

The short third scene of the second act takes place in London in 1960, with Bela

approaching the now-deranged Grigor in a park where the latter works as a street sweeper.

When Bela asks his friend about what happened in the woods during the war, Grigor leaves

him unanswered. In the meantime, Bela’s employer Diver, manager of a daily paper,

interviews another cartoonist named Mik to replace Bela at the express request of Lord Slater

who thinks that a paper does not need a genius, but a sheep to be herded with his cheap sense

of humour. Diver also asks Mik if he has a ‘point of view’ and suggests the new cartoonist
139

to adopt Lord Slater’s, that is, being against the trade unions. After Mik’s departure, Bela

walks in and spars with his employer, comparing him to the colonized natives fooled with

‘liquor and cunt’ and to parasites living underneath the smooth perfect ceilings. He also

accuses Diver of being the source of a dirty stream washing the common people away with

a bunch of lies every single day. Diver notifies Bela about the board’s decision of firing him,

but also informs him that ‘The Corporation’ is willing to publish Bela’s works in a special

edition. Bela fiercely rejects the offer; as he is aware that the publication will reduce him to

‘great art’ like Goya’s paintings, but he wants to keep his art ‘important’. The following scene

presents Bela on the parapet of Tower Bridge with the intention of ending his life while a

Beckettian pair of the river police try to talk him into cherishing his life. Bela jumps and is

saved by the police officers. In the last scene of the play, Bela ends up in an asylum where

he meets his old friend Grigor being made fun of and a bet on, though the two cannot

recognize each other. The play ends with Bela advancing the audience to ask for a pencil

after Doctor Glasson reminds him of the little temple in the bottom of his brain in which there

is a little flame of truth to be worshipped.

As a background for his play, Barker chooses the chaotic atmosphere in Europe

between the two world wars in which everything, including specifically arts, is politicized in

the service of great world powers struggling to achieve domination over each other. Instead

of using imaginary settings and events, Barker places his character in the middle of what is

familiar and known to shatter the audience’s expectations from a historical play and to

disclaim historical accounts’ pretence that they are the one accurate source to bring the past

to the understanding of the present.

Barker opens a new chapter to the history that has been recorded in books and taught

to generations with a claim to accurate knowledge of the past. In doing so, he gives voice to
140

the potential silenced individuals of that time who are depicted as real as those well-known

historical figures such as Lenin, Churchill and Hitler, though they are purely imaginary. What

Barker emphasizes here is that great historical personages mentioned in history books are

products of imagination just like his own characters, as he blurs the distinction between fact

and fiction. He draws attention to the narrative nature of historical accounts and attributes

similar powers of historical representation to his own play.

Barker reveals his historical consciousness at the very beginning of the play in which

the setting and time are specified as the Carpathian Mountains, a mountain chain stretching

over a number of Eastern European countries today, and 1918 with a Hungarian soldier

present in the scene. To the attentive reader, this information is sufficient to infer that the

subject is somehow related to the First World War, which is justified by Bela’s statement:

“We have butchered two million Russians, a million Italians, half a million Poles, the same

number of Roumanians, some Greeks, some French, a few thousand English, a division of

Bulgarians by mistake” (76). With the coming of the Red Soldiers announcing the ending of

the war, Barker gives an instant from the past which no history book has ever mentioned

before; however, he is aware that his imaginary version of the First World War scene is as

valid as any other version written in other historical accounts.

In the third scene of the first act, Bela appears before a jury of comrades in the

Writers’ and Artists’ Union of Moscow for his caricature titled “The New Economic Plan”

depicting the Soviet leader Lenin in a negative way. At this point, Barker’s imaginary artist

interferes in the life of one of the greatest power-holders of the time and the image of Lenin

is depicted once again through the eyes of an insignificant historical subject whom, as a part

of Barker’s scheme, history has omitted. The image of the Soviet leader that Barker draws in

the play is one of a destructive cunning and ambition who is wholeheartedly trying to use
141

Bela’s art as a means of propaganda for his Communist Party. This image complies with the

Lenin depictions made in history and biography books. For instance, Read observes that,

after the Great War, “in addition to newspapers, all print media and eventually all means of

artistic expression, including film (in which Lenin was to show increasing interest), theatre

and music, were under the supervision of a censorship apparatus which began to formalize

itself from 1918 onwards” (2005:236). Correlatively, the Fourth Comrade among the jury

informs Bela that “Lenin holds cartoons in the highest regard” (91) and the First Comrade

adds that Lenin is disturbed of Bela’s “tendency to criticize the line that Comrade Lenin is

advancing. Which is – which is – unhelpful –” (96). The New Economic Plan that gives

Bela’s cartoon its subject matter is also a “fact” found in history books with the name The

New Economic Policy, in which all economic enterprises in a free market system are

controlled by the State for maximum State profit (Lenin, 1965:196). Barker’s imaginary hero

criticizes the shortcomings of this economic plan refusing to keep a low profile unlike the

actual artists of the time who chose to keep their heads down to stay within the borders drawn

by the censors and were eliminated from documented history. Towards the end of the first

act, Bela’s insistence on keeping his art politics-free causes him to lose his job and

citizenship, as the Fourth Comrade informs him: “[Lenin] wants you to have a holiday” (103).

Bela’s cartoons keep getting him into trouble and strengthen the historically conscious

background with, for instance, a depiction of a ‘Hitlerine’ bat spreading its wings over

Europe evoking the coming of the Second World War.

The second act of the play continues to refer to historical events like “Hitler [having]

been gassing kids since 1938” (109) or one of the British airmen in the Royal Air Force being

named Kenny after the American general George Churchill Kenney who fought during the

war as the commander in chief of the Allied Air Forces in the Pacific (Wolk, 1988:93). In
142

addition, Bela’s troubles with the authoritarian government continue in England where his

cartoons attract the attention of state offices. The cartoon titled “There always was a Second

Front” depicts a ‘profiteer’ strangling a British soldier from behind when the soldier is

fighting against Hitler, and the suggestion that the profiteer is the English prime minister

Winston Churchill causes Bela huge trouble with the government. Bela’s editor in the

newspaper, Stringer, reminds him of the government’s right to close any newspaper on the

basis of “The Defence of the Realm Act” which was an actual Act having passed the English

Parliament right after the beginning of the First World War and continued to be enforced

during the Second World War. The act depends basically on the suppression of any

contradictory view that has the potential to harm governmental policies during states of

emergency like the war, saying: “No person shall by word of mouth or in writing spread

reports likely to cause disaffection or alarm among any of His Majesty's forces or among the

civilian population” (London Gazette, 1914:6968). With reference to this act, Barker

potentially forms a parallelism between the past and the present, evoking the long-debated

problem of censorship of art in England, culminating in the abolishment of the Lord

Chamberlain’s Office’s functions on theatre in 1968.

Very much like in the scene about Lenin, three governmental officers come to warn

Stringer and Bela about their biting tongue interfering in the government’s business and they

do not abstain from using Winston Churchill’s name. Deeds, one of the officers, openly

threatens the two with shutting up the newspaper completely saying: “Look, don’t want to

lose the entire morning over this, so get to the point swiftly, shall we? Winston doesn’t like

this […] I can assure you first thing in the morning he was practically pissing blood […]

Winston is thoroughly cognisant about the press. But feels you have abused his trust” (112-

113). Bela, at this point, observes that the British public is deceived by the government about
143

their enemy, they think that they are fighting against Hitler, but it is actually their own

government who is dealing the biggest blow on their democracy: “They are under the cruel

misapprehension that it is Nazi bombers that are blowing their limbs off and killing children

in their beds! How has this wicked deception been permitted?” (115). Winston Churchill has

always been known to take a firm grip on the press and art for the sake of the British

government’s soundness, which could also be observed in his establishment of the Press

Bureau in 1914 and his documented statements like “I think you ought to realize the harm

that has been done… I never saw such panic-stricken stuff by any war correspondent before;

and this served up on the authority of The Times can be made, and has been made, a weapon

against us in every doubtful state” (in Haste, 1977:33). The historical background is

strengthened by Barker with the reference to the Special Powers Act of 1922, an act giving

the civil authority the right to “take all such steps and issue all such orders as may be

necessary for preserving the peace and maintaining order” (in Donohue, 1998:1091), which

was obviously abused by the government in matters of censorship. Barker draws attention to

this abuse in the dialogue between Deeds and Stringer in which the former gives a notice to

the newspaper on the basis of this act saying: “This is a mighty piece of paper, Bob. […] This

paper says troops with bayonets on all the doors and lock the printers out” (116). Barker, in

a way, points at a historical ‘truth’ which was known by many but kept quiet about even by

history books.

Towards the end of the play, Barker refers to two daily newspapers of the communist

parties of Russia and China at the time, Pravda and Peking People’s Daily in a dialogue

between Diver, Bela’s current editor, and Mik, the cartoonist to be hired in Bela’s place on

condition that he will keep a low profile unlike Bela. Diver informs Mik that “Lord Slater

has owned nearly every paper in the world at some time or the other, excluding Pravda and
144

Peking People’s Daily, and he has come to the conclusion, in his wisdom, that human beings

need to laugh” (122). Barker’s reference to the newspapers seems more than coincidental, as

the papers were widely accepted as the highly-ideological and sided voices of the

governments during world war and cold war years. Pravda, for instance, had such a world-

wide notoriety, along with the other Russian newspaper titled Izvestia, that there occurred a

saying like “there's no truth in Pravda and no news in Izvestia” (Overholser, 1987), ‘pravda’

meaning ‘truth’ and ‘izvestia’ meaning ‘news’ in Russian. Pravda also turns into a symbol

of partisan press in Pravda (1985), a satirical drama written collaboratively by Howard

Brenton and David Hare, exploring the use of media as a means of political propaganda.

Similarly, Peking People’s Daily is described as “the ideological leader responsible for

delivering updated values and directing ideologies to the public. The newspaper is also well

known as the spokesperson of the State Council. Views therein are believed to reflect the

voice of authorities” (Zhang, 2014:183). Barker forms a relation between these newspapers

and the dominant press of his own time, as all have turned into mouthpieces of the dominant

ideology of the time and freedom of expression is wholeheartedly sacrificed to winning the

favour of the powerful.

All references that Barker makes to historical events, personages and institutions are

easily reinforced with historical, biographical or other non-fictitious texts in a conscious

parallel reading. These references also draw advantage from the collective memory, rumours,

tales and urban legends along with his personal observations and readings regarding those

historical issues. What differentiates Barker’s version of history from historical texts about

the same subject is that he brings a new perspective to these historical issues with an aim to

disrupt their referentiality to truth, to ultimate reality of the past as it was actually experienced

by the past agents. In doing so, Barker also draws attention to the parallelisms between the
145

past and his own time to voice his criticism regarding political intervention in arts, press and

violation of freedom of speech and expression. Barker shakes the grounds of historical

representation as a grand narrative with a claim to historical knowledge and, for him, any

account related to the past, including his own play, has an equal right of historical speculation

with an equal degree of validity.

Barker’s use of historical sources and his references to historical personages, events,

and institutions do not only show the playwright’s historical consciousness, but they also

have a metadramatic contribution to the overall meaning and presentation of the play when

Richard Hornby’s aforementioned varieties of metadrama are taken into consideration.

Hornby, in his Drama, Metadrama and Perception, notes that “real-life reference includes

allusions to real persons, living or dead; real places; real objects; real events” (95). In this

respect, Barker’s references to Lenin, the Communist Party, The New Economic Plan, Hitler,

the Royal Air Force, Churchill, the Defence of the Realm Act, the Special Powers Act and

the newspapers Pravda and Peking People’s Daily among many others are all metadramatic

elements that give the play a deeper dimension of meaning and another layer of

representation. These elements do not only “mean”, but also “suggest”, saving the play from

the monotony of drama whose meaning is only consumed by the audience and attributing it

a metadramatic outlook whose meaning is discovered and reproduced by the audience at

every turn.

However, Hornby also adds that real-life references tend to lose their metadramatic

potentials in time, as the referenced event or person or object loses its popularity among

public along with their referentiality: “Mentioning Jerry Falwell would be more intrusive on

a play than mentioning Southern Baptists generally; a reference to the American invasion of

Granada, soon after the event, would be more intrusive than merely referring to American
146

imperialism generally […] A reference to the Reverend Falwell will obviously have no

special impact after most people have forgotten who he was” (95). In this respect, Barker’s

historical references possess a metadramatic effect as long as the referenced historical

personages, events or objects make sense to Barker’s audience watching the play at a given

time. To secure the metadramatic quality of his historical ‘real-life’ references, Barker

constantly forms connections between the historical referent and the contemporary persons,

events and objects, by which he both voices his criticism of his time and enriches the meaning

of his play. For instance, by referring to the political intervention in art and official censorship

in the Soviet Union during Lenin’s rule and Britain under Churchill’s governance, Barker

evokes the long-debated issues of censorship of art troubling dramatists of his time, violation

of freedom of expression leading to student riots and conservative administrative mentality

under Margaret Thatcher.

Along with these real-life references, Barker alludes to other works of literature, or

forms of literature, that have come before him and dominated a certain period of time

establishing a tradition of their own. The fact that the first part of the play takes place in

Eastern Europe at the end of the First World War and then in Russia under the Soviet rule is

not a coincidence. Lenin’s insistence on politicizing art is quite reminiscent of the agitprop

convention, using arts and popular media as a means of agitation and propaganda as the name

itself suggests. The fact that Bela is a cartoonist adds more believability to such an

assumption, as cartoons were one of the most powerful weapons that the Communist Party

used in order to play with the public conscience and change their perceptions. Bodek argues

that the agitprop tradition gave rise to the agitprop drama first in Russia and then in the

Western Europe culminating in the political drama of Bertolt Brecht (1998:7). There is no

doubt that Barker was aware of the Brechtian political tradition from which he decisively
147

separates his “Theatre of Catastrophe” because of the former’s overt politically and morally

functional essence. In Hornby’s formulation, “there are many ways in which a play can refer

to other literature. In each case, the degree of metadramatic estrangement generated is

proportional to the degree to which the audience recognizes the literary allusion as such”

(88). With an eye to this statement, Barker’s insistence on a political background for his play

looks more functional given that the decade in which No End of Blame was written, the 80s,

witnessed the peak of political drama modelled on Brechtian epic theatre. Even though

Barker rejects any classification regarding his plays on the basis of their political functions,

his remarks alluding to the political issues of his time, such as governmental censorship of

art, violation of freedom of expression and criticism of totalitarian regimes, ultimately

involves his drama in the long tradition of British political theatre. In this respect, such a

politicization of drama is quite familiar to the theatre-going public in Britain when the play

is first staged, which gives the audience a deeper sense of political dramatic tradition, thus

strengthening the play’s metadramatic effect.

Barker’s No End of Blame is strongly self-referential, which stems from the fact that

the protagonist of the play is a free-spirited, left-wing artist very much like Barker himself

and the play revolves around works of art, Bela’s cartoons, through which the playwright

investigates issues like ethics of art, responsibilities of an artist and the process of artistic

production. Hornby refers to self-reference as “always strongly metadramatic with [which]

the play directly calls attention to itself as a play, an imaginative fiction” (103). At the very

beginning of the play, when Bela and Grigor are confronted by the Hungarian soldiers, one

of the officers ask Bela to make up a poem before he is executed. At gunpoint, Bela produces

a quatrain with something of a half-rhyme to which the officer responds saying: “Breast and

bed are not full rhymes. If you had said – forgive me – the blood in scarlet dressed – you see?
148

[…] I like rhyme. Poetry without rhyme is laying bricks without cement” (80). Barker, here,

draws attention to the fact that everybody has an opinion about art and everybody feels free

to express their opinions in the manner of cheap criticism. This is probably one of the issues

that troubles Barker himself as an artist in the process artistic production and he voices his

intentions to keep his art opinion-free like Bela himself saying: “He went on about rhyme.

Fuck rhyme. I hate it. […] Balls to rhyme! Balls to the heroic, national style! His brains were

pitiful, the pus of dead imagination on the ground, all his rhyming couplets running in the

mud…” (82). After the war, Bela appears in the Hungarian Institute of Fine Arts in Budapest

where he engages into a debate with Billwitz, the director of the institute, on who an artist is

and what his duties are to the society. What Bela argues is reminiscent of what Barker has

been arguing since the beginning of his career and later expressed in his treatises about theatre

and performance. The dialogue between the two goes like:

BILLWITZ: […] Why are we artists? We are artists because we thrill to


beauty. We look for beauty everywhere. […] Artists are the guardians of
beauty, high priests in the temple Art. Who drew it? […] It is not art.
BELA: I feel it. So it is.
BILLWITZ: It is not true. It is not half as true as any life drawing you did for
me.
BELA: It’s more true.
BILLWITZ: It’s prejudice! […] You will never be a great painter if you do
not tell the truth!
BELA: I don’t want to be a painter. I hate oils, studios, manipulating colours
inches thick. Give me ink, which dries quick, speaks quick, hurts.
BILLWITZ: Heal us, Bela. If there was ever a people needed healing, it is us
[…] I have just come from the police.
BELA: My art speaks, then! […] Did any single picture of yours win you
such an accolade? A visit from the police! There is a diploma, there is a prize!
Now I know I am a genius, now I hang in the echoing gallery of human art! I
stirred the police, therefore, I touched the truth (84-85, emphasis in the
original).

Here, Barker uses Bela as a mouthpiece to voice his own belief about the functions, or rather

functionlessness, of art against Billwitz’s argument that an artist has a duty to represent truth

as if it really existed. Billwitz’s voice in this dialogue must be quite familiar to Barker, as he
149

struggles throughout his career against a generation of political playwrights who believe art

to be supposed to have a function in order to change people’s minds and make them better.

In this respect, the dialogue between Bela and Billwitz stands as a self-referential element in

which Bela’s painting stands for the play itself and Bela stands for the playwright.

In the scene in which Bela appears before a committee of artists in the Writers’ and

Artists’ Union of Moscow, a similar discussion comes up regarding the ethics of art and

responsibilities of an artist between Bela and the committee members. Bela defends the idea

that art must be liberated from all contextual impositions including politics, morality and

social utility whereas the committee members are persistent that art is to serve grander

purposes:

FOURTH COMRADE: Lenin holds cartoons in the highest regard.


FIRST COMRADE: […] we are trying, quite simply, trying – to evolve a
different sort of art here. All right? An art which is not bourgeois. […] Because
although we have no shoe laces for our boots and no lenses for our spectacles,
our art is free. By free I mean free of bourgeois constraints. By bourgeois
constraints I mean the tying of the creative act to the demands of the private
ego. Individualism, I mean, all right? […] we have exerted our communal will
to rescue artists from their bourgeois habit […] if I say no artist can be wrong
– in the most fundamental sense – because he is obeying an impulse from
somewhere within – […] No artist does wring knowingly. Or else he’s not an
artist. […]
SECOND COMRADE: I think there is only one principle that we ought to be
rigid about, and that is – do we, as artists, serve the people? That’s the only
one, I think. […]
BELA: […] to an artist, freedom of expression matters even more than
nationality. I say that as a patriotic person, a person who loves his country and
his people. Not as a licker of governments. […] to an artist freedom comes
above all things […]
SECOND COMRADE: Wait a minute […] We say an artist is only free if his
society is free. He cannot be free against the freedom of his society. […]
BELA: I disagree with Lenin. […]
FOURTH COMRADE: He is entitled to disagree with anyone he wants.
That’s freedom, isn’t it? But he must be able to restrain his criticism in the
wider interests of the people. That’s responsibility, isn’t it? […]
BELA: But I want to protest! (91-97).
150

Putting the committee member comrades, who are also artists, against Bela in this debate,

Barker once more voices his criticism of the use of art as a means of political propaganda;

but at the same time, he also criticizes the artists who become a part of this puppetry by

submitting their art to the interests of political parties. In another respect, Barker also draws

a strict line between his theatre and the political theatre of the dramatists among his

contemporaries in terms of free art. He puts freedom of expression and artistic vision above

all meanings art can suggest, and sacrifices the meaning to the act of protest, the service to

beauty, and the social responsibility to the responsibility towards the artistic endeavour itself.

Barker, through Bela’s mouth, announces that true nationalism is not a cheap patriotism

through political involvement, but a true conservancy of the right to speak regardless of the

subject of the speech. He denies to attribute any duty to art and any responsibility to the artist

other than staying true to pure artistic vision and the impulse coming from within.

At the beginning of the second act, Barker’s own voice is again heard in Bela’s speech

to the officers of the British Airforce as he makes a distinction between important art and

great art. Bela’s speech functions as his artistic manifesto and is reminiscent of Barker’s ideas

discussed before. After giving a brief account about his early life, Bela sets the criteria that

separate his art from the rest, which caused him to be banished first from Hungary and then

from the Soviet Union. He says:

BELA: […] I am a cartoonist. I believe the cartoon to be the lowest form of


art. I also believe it to be the most important form of art. I decided in my
twenty-fourth year I would rather be important than great. I decided this
because I have always preferred shouting to whispering and humanity more
than myself. The cartoon is a weapon in the struggle of peoples. It is a
liberating instrument. It is brief like life. It is not about me. It is about us.
Important art is about us. Great art is about me. I am not interested in me. I do
not like me. I am not sure if I like us either, but that is private and the cartoon
is not private. We share the cartoon as we cannot share the painting. We
plunder painting for the private meaning. The cartoon has only one meaning.
When the cartoon lies it shows at once. When the painting lies it can deceive
for centuries. The cartoon is celebrated in a million homes. The painting is
151

worshipped in a gallery. The cartoon changes the world. The painting changes
the artist. I long to change the world. I hate the world (107-108).

Bela’s distinction between the important art and great art is reminiscent of Barker’s

distinction between the art of theatre and the theatre. At first glance, Bela’s statements may

sound a little contradictory with what he has said before regarding the responsibilities of the

artist towards his people and the functions of art as an instrument of any kind. However, after

a second, more critical reading, it is revealed that Bela is being ironical about the adjectives

“important” and “great” in the sense that greatness is calculated on the basis of acceptance

by the dominant ideology rather than being true to truth itself. By important art, Bela

mentions a kind of art which is functional in the long term through the liberation of humanity

from any kind of ideological involvement, an art whose only mission is to awaken people to

seeing the reality with their own eyes rather than showing them the reality.

Barker believes that whether or not art is pre-motivated by external forces, it cannot

and must not be squelched by means of ideological or repressive state apparatuses, in

Althusser’s terminology. In an era when censorship of art is widely disputed and Lord

Chamberlain’s Office’s authority is questioned by the artists and the public – culminating in

the deprivation of its rights to censor – Barker chooses up his sides openly and, through his

characters, expresses his intentions to fight till the end of his career to liberate his art from

any kind of external intervention. In addition to his defence of his art from Lenin’s and

Churchill’s insinuations, Bela lets on about his apolitical stance when it comes to his art

saying: “My politics are to look for the truth, and when you find it, shout it. That’s my

politics” (114). This statement is a paraphrase of what Barker discusses in his theorization of

“Theatre of Catastrophe” in terms of keeping politics offstage and being true to truth only.

Similarly, towards the end of the play, Barker draws attention to the same issue in a critical

way in the dialogue between Diver and Mik. As a replacement for Bela, Mik is questioned
152

by Diver regarding his political tendencies before being given a job; and Diver asks him:

“Lord Slater is very keen for you to have a point of view. Do you have a point of view?”

(123). Overhearing the dialogue, Bela intervenes and accuses Diver and his newspaper of

“washing men away with lies, the great flood of dirtiness, hold your heads up in the swell!”

(125). This is exactly what Barker remonstrates in his major prose works on the dramatic art.

For him, once ‘point of view’ is involved, what is produced is not art, but advertisement. In

Barker’s view, art must speak for itself, which differentiates it from cheap propaganda.

Consequently, Barker’s No End of Blame gives a panorama of the great catastrophes

in the 20th century Europe through the spectacles of a free-thinking artist. What makes the

play historiographic is the playwright’s attempt at disrupting the mainstream historical

knowledge and offering an alternative history to his readers and the audience with an equal

claim to historical knowledge keeping the historical background the same with references to

the First World War, the Bolshevik Revolution, the Second World War, the atomic bomb

attacks along with the hypocrisy of those who ruled the world at those times. Barker’s version

of history displays how subjective and flexible historical representations are and how they

depend on who is holding the pen. The play is also metadramatic with respect to the real life

references it makes to actual historical personages like Lenin, Hitler and Churchill along with

historical events like the passing of specific acts from the British Parliament and the world

wars. The references to other literature like the agitprop and the political drama strengthen

the play’s metadramatic outlook along with the play’s references to itself through other works

of art. By placing an artist into the centre of the play, Barker finds a voice to express his ideas

about art in general and the issues like censorship of art and freedom of expression in

particular. In his protagonist’s struggle against authoritative governments to purify his art

from ideological impositions, Barker answers questions about the ethics of art and
153

responsibilities of the artist using the protagonist’s cartoons as representatives of his own

play. With all these points taken into consideration, Barker’s No End of Blame turns out to

have sufficient elements to qualify as an example of historiographic metadrama.

3.2. The Power of the Dog and the Question of ‘Appropriate’ Art

Written in 1981 and published in 1985, The Power of the Dog is one of Barker’s

famous historical plays that is concerned with the immediate years after the Second World

War, exploring issues like history and art’s place in it as suggested in the play’s subtitle

“Moments in History and Anti-History”. Barker notes that this play has waited for years to

be staged presumably until 1984 when it was first performed by the Joint Stock Theatre

Company (1993:34). The play offers two versions of the same historical events from the

points of view of first Stalin, the centre around which the events revolve, and then Ilona, the

photograph artist who observes those events from the margins with a more objective, critical

view. Weeks observes that the action of the play “unfolds near the end of the Second World

War, around 1944. There are two settings – the Kremlin and the battlefields of Poland – and

three major groups of characters: Red Army soldiers at the Polish front, Stalin and his

entourage at the Kremlin, and two Hungarian photographers, Victor and Ilona, who have

been photographing war atrocities” (2001:62). With the strong historical background and

references to art as a potential means of historical representation, the play possesses

historiographic and metadramatic elements on the way to a classification as historiographic

metadrama.

The first scene of the play, titled “A Great Man Hallucinates”, opens with a Scottish

comedian named McGroot practicing juggling for a feast to be held in the Kremlin by Stalin

himself, including Churchill among the guests. While McGroot tries unsuccessfully to make
154

Stalin laugh, the latter discusses, with his secretary Poskrebyshev and a fellow politician

named Molotov, how to put the guests up and expresses a certain uneasiness that has been

troubling him. As the company of Englishmen arrives, the two parties begin to exchange

inflated and insincere compliments while McGroot, “a hilariously de-familiarizing presence”

(Weeks, 2001:59) who functions like the Greek chorus commenting on the others’ speeches

and actions, shows what is beneath their masks. Communicating through an English and a

Soviet interpreter, the two leaders also exchange toasts and gifts over a discussion regarding

the definition of History. Stalin defines it as “the incredulous overwhelmed by the incredible”

which is harshly contradicted by McGroot’s definition of it as “a woman bein’ raped by ten

soldiers in a village in Manchuria”, differing from hysterectomy only in that “one’s done wi’

a scalpel and the other wi’ a bayonet” (4). In the meantime, the interpreters as well as the

other politicians in the company do their bests to hinder any possible controversy between

the two leaders by either omitting some words from the translation or diverting the topic with

an irrelevant toast. The topic of their discussion suddenly turns to sharing out the lands that

have been saved from the Nazis. Churchill wants Italy and Greece, Stalin has already spared

Bulgaria and Poland for himself and they agree to share Romania. At that moment, Stalin

seems to be distracted by a fit of paranoia, thinking that the waiters have been planning to

wipe him away, to remove his face from the walls and to cut him out of the films. When the

Englishmen depart, Stalin asks his men to find the little Polish photographer and to bring the

man to him, which ends the first scene.

The second scene, titled “The Banality of Yet Another Murder”, opens in the Polish

plain where a photographer named Victor takes a picture of his friend, Ilona, under a dead

woman hanging from a rope. Victor protests that Ilona is stealing from the dead bodies,

including the stockings of the hanging woman who turns out to be her own sister. The two
155

engage in a discussion concerning the nature of murder before a Russian officer named Arkov

interrupts, questioning whether they have the necessary certificates to photograph the

battlefield. The soldier asks Victor to take his photograph standing next to Ilona if they want

him to ignore the fact that they have no authorization to be there. At last, Ilona remembers to

ask the men about her sister’s burial, which is dealt with by a Russian officer named Sorge

who appears from nowhere and comments that they are living in a wonderful century. The

third scene, titled “The Soldiers Fictionalize Their History”, presents an art student Georgina

Matrimova among Soviet soldiers who appear in her realistic war movie and discuss with her

what additions or omissions have been and should be made. Sorge approaches the group and

shares his own views about the functions of ‘proper’ art saying: “The proper film asks, did

the soldiers die for something, or did they die for nothing? It is a revolutionary question. So

the proper war film is not actually about the battle, it is about the reasons for the battle” (13).

To this, Matrimova responds idealistically expressing her great wish to make a film some

day in the future that will touch upon every political and personal truth possible, contain the

whole reality and exclude partiality. In the meantime, Sorge is confronted by an

infantrywoman named Sonya Tremblayev due to the former’s indifference towards her after

an affair. On the other hand, Ilona enters in search of her sister’s body covered in a tarpaulin.

Unable to find the body, she gives Victor a short history of her ties with her sister, detailing

how she tried to educate herself through experience rather than books. Victor has a very

different plan to write his own history by going to America. As also indicated in the play’s

subtitle “Moments in History and Anti-History”, the play’s preoccupation with personal

histories mistaken for ‘the’ History is clearly reflected in individual characters’ efforts to

change things in the hope of making room for themselves in that line of events.
156

A similar example is seen in the following scene titled “The Limitless Absurdity of

Another’s Life” in which the paranoid Stalin discusses with Poskrebyshev his fear of an early

death which he wishes to postpone until the most appropriate moment. In the scene titled

“The Poet Can Be Trusted to Castrate Himself”, Sorge has been expecting Ilona for an

interview regarding her photographs; and in the meantime, he has a talk with Arkov over the

latter’s letters to his wife being censored by the former for putting more emphasis on death

than victory. Sorge tries to channel his junior’s ‘death interest’ to writing poems instead of

letters, as “the letter […] has too much authority, the poem not at all [and] later, the poem

will have the authority and the letter none at all, but by then it won’t matter” (20). With the

arrival of Ilona, the subject changes to the nature of her art, which is not concerned with the

picture, but with the frame for Sorge as an inevitable consequence of the human urge for

selection. He admits that Ilona’s photographs are not to be criticized technically, though he

has certain ‘reservations’ in terms of their content. He openly believes that art must take a

side, for “the idea of a neutral art is utterly redundant” (21). Outside, a group of Russian

soldiers are circled around the assumed dead body of a female SS officer, Gloria, who begins

to move to everybody’s shock and ends up making Arkov shoot himself in the groin as

indicated in the title of the scene.

The following scene titled “The Spontaneous Nature of Historical Decisions” begins

with Stalin preaching about the ‘appropriate’ art which reveals the governmental intervention

in freedom of speech and artistic creations and he resembles an artist’s head to a boiled egg

not to be sliced off, but to be tapped it with a spoon in order to give it a shape. He states:

“[Artists] think they live on their own, but they’re mistaken, they live among us, and they

have to learn they aren’t only birds on the lake. If they want to sing out of tune, by all means

let them do so, but to expect us to construct music halls and pay the wages of the orchestra!
157

No, sing in tune or shit in your own nest” (26). He also admits that, as the head of the

government, he is engaged into a terrible struggle with the ‘ruthless’ artists who would do

anything to get past the censor organs. Commenting on a symphony seemingly dedicated to

himself, Stalin even goes so far as to confess that he has tapped the composer’s egg to make

him a better artist and to save him from ‘the wrong street’. He also mentions Khachaturian,

an Armenian composer, whose music has an unquestionably moral content that instructed

him out of the three days of disasters during the war. For him, music is the ‘least susceptible’

form of art to ‘materialist orthodoxy’. The discussion is interrupted when Stalin beleaguers

Poskrebyshev about his potential homosexual tendencies, ending up with the latter attacking

his leader.

In the scene titled “The Indignation of a Mass Murderer”, Matrimova tells an arrested

tradesman named Buber about her new film-making project in which she plans to use three

screens to eliminate the subjective representation of reality as well as to liberate the audience

from its passive role. At that moment, Victor and Ilona enter to take the arrested man’s

photograph for the archives, yet discussing the former’s anxieties that they are going to be

killed by Sorge or turn into the puppets of the government rather than independent artists: “I

said to him, I am an innocent photographer. He said there is no such thing as an innocent

photographer, only photographers with varying degrees of guilt” (30). With the arrival of

Sorge himself, it becomes clear that the photographers have been totally reduced to a

government instrument, appointed to use their camera in the army’s service. The following

scene titled “She Did Not Die for Love, But for Its Impossibility” explains everything about

the fate of Ilona’s sister. It is revealed that Sorge has long been in love with the girl and

arrested Gloria for her murder. The moment Tremblayev enters accusing him of indulging in

personal affairs on duty, a shot is heard from outside, as one of the soldiers shoots Victor
158

who has been trying to escape with two crates of photographs. When Sorge informs Ilona

about Victor’s death, she takes it in her stride to the man’s surprise, and Sorge asks Ilona to

be his mistress. As the two make love, Tremblayev appears with a man at the door and arrests

Sorge for inappropriate behaviour on duty. Matrimova, on the other hand, expresses her

admiration for Ilona’s artistic vision before implying that she is to be executed soon.

Towards the end of the play, as the title of the last scene indicates, history encounters

its antithesis when Stalin picks Ilona out of three hundred and forty eight photographers to

photograph him as he is. Obsessed with the representation of his face after his death, Stalin

pressures Ilona to be serious about the work and states: “It is not a face I have here, it is a

history” (42). Knowing that even a great man like Stalin who is known for writing the history

is inevitably dependent on art to achieve immortality, Ilona contributes to ‘that’ history

through her art by immortalizing Stalin. The interdependence of the two, Stalin and Ilona,

for survival is rather ironic, because the play ends obscurely without telling if either of the

two let the other do so.

For The Power of the Dog, Barker sets a similar historical background to his earlier

play, No End of Blame, and once again chooses the Soviet Russia as the setting with a time

shift to the Stalin period, even though the same air of totalitarianism is kept. Barker, in an

unpublished interview given to Lamb in 1987, explains the reasons for his interest in the

Eastern European history and setting saying:

I think history is an invention of both left and right. Both are equally
false.....When I go to east European countries, I usually go to visit what they
call a museum of the working class. And so I did in Prague - an enormous
building in which no Czech ever sets foot; so I had it to myself. Having walked
past enormous statues of Lenin which dominated a red-carpeted staircase, I
then went into endless rooms of photographs, because the photograph is the
icon of the artistic sections of the communist authorities, - room after room
where people are being shot, hanged, executed, being killed in bat ties, or
cheering their cosmonauts. You realise that the party itself has commandeered
159

the masses by this means: the photograph itself celebrates the individual face
but, at the same time, by enclosing it in mass cabinets, the masses are
entrapped by the party which claims to speak for them. I find that illuminating
for the theatre in that history is always about the extension of the individual
and one or other political grouping annexes the idea of the individual for some
ideological function. The good history play tries to rescue the individual from
that annexation which is what I'm talking about in subtitling THE POWER
OF THE DOG as MOMENTS FROM HISTORY AND ANTI-HISTORY.
Anti-history is about people who try to resist that occupation (in Lamb,
1992:122).

In this quotation, Barker also reveals the reasons why he chooses to write on historical

subjects, as he believes history to be a narrative written by whoever has the power at the

moment and art is a means to save the individual from such a bag of lies. In another interview,

Barker contends that “the history play is a good thing, because ... it's a metaphor, it enables

you to escape some of the crushing documentary factuality about the world and indulge in a

little ... speculation, and you can do that in a historical period” (in Irvine, 2012). Barker seems

highly aware of the speculative nature of historical accounts and of the power his art gives

him in filling the gaps in those incomplete narratives.

Barker, this time, chooses the chaotic aftermath of the Second World War for the time

of his plot along with the ravished Polish plains and the carnivalesque Kremlin Palace for the

setting. Besides well-known historical figures that give history its direction like Stalin and

Churchill, Barker also gives voice to the silent actors of that historical drama and offers an

antithetical version of documented history through the spectacles of a number of marginal

characters like a comedian, a photographer and an art student. It is not a coincidence that

Barker picks his major characters from among artists, as he uses these characters as a

mouthpiece to voice his own criticism from an artist’s point of view about censorship,

freedom of expression and artistic ethics in the face of the totalitarian Soviet rule. One other

reason why Barker prefers the Soviet history for his subject matter is that, as a left-wing

dramatist, he is already interested in the socialist thinking with a disbelief in its promises as
160

practiced by Russian rulers. He confesses that “[he] always knew socialism was tragedy”

(1993:21) in a world where capitalism has already taken the law in its own hands. Thus,

Barker views pessimism and catastrophe as better tools, compared to optimism and

celebration in art, to shatter the audience’s habitual reactions to moral and political

impositions, and condemns political interference in art to use it as a means of propaganda,

which was always experienced in the history of art, particularly under the Soviet rule: “The

left's insistent cry for celebration and optimism in art - sinister in its populist echo of the right

- implies fixed continuity in the public, whereas morality needs to be tested and re-invented

by successive generations” (49). As he believes that socialism is not as promising in practice

as it is in theory, Barker attributes the socialist idealism to art along with the power to imagine

a better society: “We are living the extinction of official socialism. When the opposition loses

its politics, it must root in art […] Art is a problem. The man or woman who exposes himself

to art exposes himself to another problem […] The opposition in art has nothing but the

quality of its imagination” (17-18). In this respect, Barker uses his artistic vision to re-

imagine the practice of socialism during Stalin’s rule and display its shortcomings by

juxtaposing the ideas of the despot and the free-thinking artist.

Barker’s references to documented historical events and personages begin in the very

first scene in which Joseph Stalin, the despotic ruler of the Soviet Union from Lenin’s death

in 1924 until his own death in 1953, hosts a feast in the Kremlin for the British Prime Minister

Winston Churchill. The two leaders are known to have come together several times, the two

most well-known being the Tehran Conference in 1943 (Overy, 1996:245-246) and the Yalta

Conference in 1945 (Plokhy, 2009:34) with the presence of the American President Franklin

Roosevelt. However, Barker refers to another meeting, a private one between Stalin and

Churchill organized in August 1942 in Moscow for the special purpose of quelling the
161

German advancement and sharing the lands that the Germans will be leaving behind

(Richardson, 1991:136). In the company of Molotov, the Soviet Minister of Foreign Affairs

of the time, and Poskrebyshev, Stalin’s personal chancellery, the two leaders meet and Barker

parodies this meeting with his never-ending impulse to satirize, which blocks his attempts to

purify his theatre from ‘relevance’ as a means of social usefulness. He mentions this meeting,

in which Churchill and Stalin are seen sharing out the war-torn lands from the map, as an

example to that impulse: “So grotesque was the politics enacted at this moment in history

that I could neither view it objectively nor discover a tragic form for it. The inescapable

baseness of power broking on this scale commanded a satirical response, and it remains

perhaps the finest satirical scene I have attempted, arguably dwarfing the anti-historical

scenes that make up the bulk of the play” (1993:33). One other means by which Barker

parodies the meeting is the Scottish comedian Archie McGroot who functions as “the

spokesperson of Stalin’s political clownery” (Alied, 2014:163) along with the interpreters of

the two leaders who deliberately miss out some words from their interpretation either by their

incapacity or in order to prevent a catastrophe. In Barker’s understanding, his version of the

meeting holds an equal historical validity to the other accounts regarding the meeting, even

though those accounts have autobiographical qualities, as the historian has the chance to

make additions and omissions very much like the interpreters in the banquet.

By attributing a chorus-like function to the comedian McGroot, Barker offers a new

interpretation of history from the point of view of an artist, a marginal figure who was not

even given a place in the official historical records. In other words, through McGroot’s

mouth, Barker gives his audience the anti-history of the silenced. When the subject of the

feast turns to the best definition of history, McGroot counters Stalin’s idealistic definition

with his comparison of history to hysterectomy and refers to a woman being raped by ten
162

Soviet soldiers in Manchuria as the ‘real’ history. McGroot’s reference can be traced in the

pages of historical sources, as the Soviet Union is known to have invaded the Japanese state

Manchuria towards the end of the war, simply ravishing the land, the goods and the women

in the territory (Pakula, 2009:530). Through McGroot’s comments, Barker brings to light a

historical event outtalked by Russian historians and reveals how history functions like a

medical operation in which the hands holding the scalpel determine the future of the patient.

In the following scene titled “The Soldiers Fictionalize Their History”, Barker reveals

his historical consciousness again by openly emphasizing the fictional quality of history and

that history is a personal phenomenon defined and filled in by the individual’s point of view.

Matrimova’s WHOLEFILM project is her way of keeping record of her history while Ilona

wants to dig into the mystery of her sister’s death to make sense of her own. Stalin, on the

other hand, seems obsessed with how history will record his story and how he will be

remember by future generations, saying: “History will never forgive me for dying at this

point. […] There must be a proper moment, a moment when history will say, it was right that

Stalin ceased to exercise the dictatorship of the proletariat” (19). Stalin’s paranoid character

urges him to put away all the portraits and photographs of him taken before, as he believes

that those images cannot faithfully represent what he believes himself to be at the moment.

He orders his men to find the photographer who can do justice to his face for the sake of

future generations, and this photographer turns out to be Ilona whose view of history differs

completely from Stalin’s. In a dialogue with Sorge, the Russian secret agent, she defines

history as a mad dog which devours the weak and spares only those who are powerful enough

to stand against it:

When the mad dog comes for you


Don’t run, you’ll only stumble.
Instead, lie down and show your throat,
Some dogs don’t bite the humble… (23).
163

Even though Stalin views history as something to be captured, Ilona believes that history is

the one who captures, and only the lucky can survive its bites. Weeks observes that “the

History [Stalin] represents is rhetorically and self-consciously a totality in-the-making and

retains a ‘world-historical’ glow. Ilona is not an agent in these terms; hers is a history ‘from

below’, strategically directed at avoiding the mad dog of power as best as she can” (2001:68).

Stalin obviously believes that it is in his capacity to change the direction of history with an

intervention from above in a very godlike manner. In his discussion with Mme Donkin,

Zdhanov, Lashenko and Poskrebyshev on the nature and functions of art, Stalin mentions the

Soviet Armenian composer named Aram Khachaturian whom he influenced in the

composition of his notes and who influenced Stalin with his music in depressive times of the

war. Khachaturian is an actual historical personage who is known to have achieved

considerable reputation in the Soviet Union under Stalin’s regime (Huang, 1999:341).

Through Stalin’s voice, Barker draws a different image of the composer as one who lets the

authority ‘tap his head’ in order to give a direction to his art on the way to promoting the

Party’s policies. Similarly, the composer’s music also gives direction to Stalin’s thoughts by

which he gives the gravest decisions about the fate of his nation revealing, as the title of the

scene suggests, “The Spontaneous Nature of Historical Decisions” (25).

The play moves towards a climax when Ilona is summoned to the Kremlin to

immortalize Stalin’s face thanks to her skills in photography. Alied argues that, “returning to

the Kremlin, the final encounter in the play between Ilona and Stalin is an encounter between

history (Stalin’s story) and its antithesis (the foreigner’s story)” (2014:176). Barker brings

together a historical figure and an imaginary character in the last scene of his play, titled

“History Encounters its Antithesis”, by which he proposes that history is not a chronology of

listed truths, but a dialectical process whose meaning is always flexible depending on where
164

one is looking at it from. Even though the subject of the dialogue between Ilona and Stalin is

the representation of the latter’s face as it is in the photograph to be taken by the former, it is

quite telling regarding historical representation, as well:

STALIN: You are to photograph me as I am […] It is very difficult to


photograph Stalin as he is. Who is Stalin? One day he was in the film, and the
next they rubbed him off. […] It is fraught with risks.
ILONA: Is it? Isn’t it a face like any other?
[…]
STALIN: Does it not show a profound ignorance of art to think you could put
Stalin next to George VI? It is not a face I have here, it is a history.
ILONA: But at the same time you are very ordinary! […] I wouldn’t look at
you twice in the street (41-42).

Barker, in this dialogue, draws attention to the subjective nature of artistic and historical

representations. While Stalin sees his face as a symbol of power and magnificence evoking

fear in the beholder, Ilona is aware that he has an ordinary face which does not even evoke

attention in her. When this face is conveyed through generations by means of Ilona’s

photograph as a historical proof, the future beholders of it will possibly believe that Stalin

was a man of grandeur, even though Ilona, the eye-witness to that moment in history, knows

that he was a paranoid man with prostate interested more in the future of his face rather than

the future of his nation.

Such historical references to people and events along with minor mentions of other

famous historical figures like Trotsky, Lenin and George VI all contribute to Barker’s

attempts at writing an alternative history, or an antihistory in his own terms. In addition, such

references attribute a metadramatic essence to the play with an eye to Hornby’s identification

of real-life reference as a variety of metadrama. Barker obviously makes use of his personal

interest in history, especially the Soviet history, along with his extensive reading regarding

the Russian history before and after the two world wars. Even though the metadramatic

referentiality of these real life persons and events has lost its effectiveness in time, the image
165

of two sovereigns sharing out territories on maps in secret meetings does not sound

unimaginable during the cold war years including the year the play was written in. Barker

shows that nothing has actually changed since the two catastrophic wars of the 20th century

and the world continues turning according to the words coming through the lips of a few

powerful men. His choice of the Soviet history as a subject matter does not seem coincidental

and the Stalin-Churchill meeting is reminiscent of the meeting in the 1961 Vienna Summit

between John F. Kennedy, the President of the United States, and Nikita Khrushchev, the

leader of the Soviet Union (Dunbabin, 2014:258) and the 1973 Washington meeting between

Leonid Brezhnev, the Soviet leader following Khrushchev and Richard Nixon, the US

President of the time (Kissinger, 1999:274-275). The professed motivations of such meetings

have been announced to be the betterment of bilateral relations; however, the actual reasons

behind them have always been speculated about.

Barker obviously sees no difference between his own time and the period he deals

with in the play in terms of governmental attitude to art and freedom of expression. In

Arguments for a Theatre, he argues that the artist’s struggle has never changed from the years

of the great wars to the years of cold war, for which art must acquire a different, target-

oriented outlook in order to liberate itself from the discourse that unconsciously serves the

purposes of the authoritarian regime: “In an era of authoritarian government the best theatre

might learn a different function […] it might engage with conscience at the deepest level. To

achieve this it would learn to discard the subtle counter-authoritarianism that lurks behind all

satire, and cease its unacknowledged collaboration with the ruling order by not reproducing

its stereotypes” (48). Such a parallelism attributes a deeper metadramatic essence to Barker’s

play, as its references to real-life historical personages and events still preserve their
166

referentiality on behalf of the audience who can easily form the connections between what is

shown to them and what they themselves experience in real life.

The metadramatic character of the play stems particularly from Barker’s abundant

use of self-referential elements both through the character McGroot, who constantly alienates

the audience with his comments on the other characters’ dialogues and actions, and the

central motive in the play being the question of artistic representation as in the case of Ilona’s

photograph or Matrimova’s film. Barker, very much like in Bela’s case in No End of Blame,

uses the artists in the play including Ilona, Matrimova and Victor as a mouthpiece to voice

his ideas regarding the issues like ethics of art, the artist’s responsibility and the hardships an

artist comes across in the process of artistic production. For instance, in the scene titled “The

Soldiers Fictionalize Their History”, Sorge confronts Matrimova and the soldiers cast for the

war film with his ideas about what ‘proper’ art is. He talks like a censor or an art critic in his

argumentation that true art must have a reason, saying: “The proper war film asks, did the

soldiers die for something, or did they die for nothing? It is a revolutionary question. So the

proper war film is not actually about the battle, it is about the reasons for the battle” (13).

Sorge seems ready to attribute a political and moral function to art regardless of art’s duty to

itself, which is inconsistent with Barker’s understanding of art as a completely functionless

endeavour. In opposition to Sorge’s misconception of art’s powers, Barker gives voice to

Matrimova and explains his own ideas about the true nature of artistic vision through her

mouth. Matrimova says: “Sorge, one day I will make a film, and it will tell the entire truth.

It will contain every political truth and every personal truth. It will contain the whole of

reality. I will call it WHOLEFILM. I hate partiality, I hate bits!” (14). This statement, in a

way, justifies Barker’s motivation to keep his art free of political and moral discourses, and

now that a complete aloofness from the realities of life is not possible for an artist, Barker
167

observes that an unselective covering of all truths will be equally impartial for an artist in the

face of a political and moral bombardment of meanings.

Similarly, the scene titled “The Poet Can Be Trusted to Castrate Himself” is quite

self-referential, as it refers to the process of artistic production in the face of external forces

of censorship as well as the artist’s unconscious urge for self-censorship as indicated with

the word ‘castration’. At the beginning of the scene, Sorge is seen examining Ilona’s

photographic plates for a test of ‘appropriateness’ while Arkov confronts him with a similar

issue that has been troubling him. Arkov accuses Sorge of reading his letters to his wife and

censoring them even though he believes there is nothing inappropriate mentioned in them.

However, Sorge’s justification is quite telling about the functions of art and the

responsibilities of the artist as viewed from the perspective of the dominant ideology which

Barker himself is known to have suffered from. The dialogue between the two officers go

like:

ARKOV: You are not to censor my letters.


SORGE: There is too much death in them. Write more about victory and less
about death.
ARKOV: I am not interested in victory. […] I detest your facile reasoning.
SORGE: You detest reason altogether. […] Put your death interest in some
poems. This letter, you see, has too much authority, the poem none at all.
Later, the poem will have the authority and the letter none at all, but by then
it won’t matter (20).
Barker draws attention to the long-debated question of censorship of art in this dialogue, a

disturbance to the playwright himself along with a great number of his contemporaries, as

the dominant political parties have always attempted to change the direction of art for the

good of the cause. Barker forms a parallelism here between the Stalinist regime in the Soviet

Union and the Thatcher period in England in the 80s with an attempt to display the true face

of governmental intervention in arts. The fact that Sorge criticizes the abundance of the

images of death in Arkov’s letters also strengthens the scene’s self-referentiality when
168

Barker’s aforementioned preoccupation with death and catastrophe in his plays is taken into

consideration. Barker seems to be voicing his own disturbance at the benighted criticism

directed at his plays regarding the air of death and catastrophe pervading them. A similar

parallelism is formed by Barker between the conditions which led to the occurrence of a

literary tradition, the agit-prop, in the Soviet Russia and the conditions which led to the

flourishing of a propagandistic political drama in Britain. Such allusions to other literary

forms and works add to the play’s metadramatic essence and display that Barker lumps the

political drama of his time with any other kind of political concern in art no matter what the

motivation is.

In the same scene, Ilona engages in a similar discussion with Sorge regarding the

nature and functions of her photographs in the face of the so-called greater motivations of

the party. With the dialogue of the two, Barker digs more into the issue of censorship and the

lack of freedom of expression in art in relation with his own time. While Ilona is interrogating

Sorge for the whereabouts of her sister, Sorge keeps questioning her regarding the side her

art is taking in such a chaotic time. He defines the art of photography as one that comes

together with “the problem of selection” (21) drawing attention to the spontaneous and

selective nature of artistic representation. As the representative of the totalitarian ideological

voice, Sorge expresses the authority’s wish to turn art into propaganda saying: “I’ve looked

with great interest at the photographs. Technically, they can’t be criticized. […] It’s not in

the technical area I have reservations. It’s in the content. […] Because I feel sure you will

agree the idea of a neutral art is utterly redundant” (21). Sorge argues that art is naturally

functional, and an artist must pick a side in order not to perish from the mainstream public

recognition. This is an argument which Barker strongly antagonizes, as he believes that art

is not inherently functional and is pure as long as it liberates itself from all these ideological
169

and moral functions. The response Ilona gives to Sorge is one that Barker gives to the

mainstream political dramatists of his time who commercialize their art for the sake of

acknowledgment and gain: “My bad breath is legendary. I think your smell comes from your

soul, don’t you? You blame the bowel, but really the bowel is only –” (23). Very much like

Ilona’s, Barker’s ‘bad breath’ obviously disturbs some ‘sensitive’ noses, even though the

bodies they are attached to is rotten inwardly.

Towards the end of the play, Barker, this time, gives a voice to the ultimate despot at

whose will art is given a direction. In the scene titled “The Spontaneous nature of Historical

Decisions”, Stalin openly confesses that governmental intervention in art is a necessity and

a useful move for the betterment of human understanding of beauty. In his conversation with

Mme Donkin over a symphony written in praise of himself, Stalin likens an artist’s head to

a boiled egg which needs some tapping with a spoon in order to give it the desired shape and

a better taste. The dialogue goes like:

STALIN: The artist’s head is a boiled egg. You do not slice it off. You tap it
with a spoon […] I have yet to meet an artist who did not benefit from being
tapped. They think they live on their own, but they’re mistaken, they live
among us, and they have to learn they aren’t the only birds on the lake. If they
want to sing out of tune, by all means let them do so, but to expect us to
construct music halls and pay the wages of the orchestra! No, sing in tune or
shit in your own nest. (POSKREBYSHEV claps).
DONKIN: I think the section praising you is most – appropriate.
STALIN: Which section’s that?
DONKIN: The third movement.
STALIN: Is that in praise of me?
ZDHANOV: It says so in the notes.
STALIN: Of course it says so in the notes. It would do, wouldn’t it? I don’t
read notes. When I’m dead he’ll say it was a trick to get past the censors. No,
they are ruthless, artists, we have a terrible struggle with them. […] I’ve mixed
feelings about it […] He was up the wrong street there. […] But we tapped his
egg, and you see, he has got better!
MME DONKIN: He nearly committed suicide.
STALIN: Did he! Did he really? Never mind, he didn’t, he became a better
composer instead! If they cannot resolve the contradictions, they are better off
dead (25-26).
170

In an openly threatening tone, Stalin confesses that the governmental support to the artists is

given in accordance with their servitude to the greater causes of the party. He claims that

such an intervention is motivated by an urge of mutual benefit, as both the party finds a means

to propagandize its policies and the artist gets to benefit from governmental financial support,

to easily arrange a place for exhibiting his art as well as making his art more ‘appropriate’.

The composer Stalin talks about turns out to be the Armenian composer Aram Khachaturian,

a very-well known artist in the Soviet Union who was awarded several titles and prizes by

the Communist Party including the title of People's Artist of the USSR in 1954 and The Order

of the October Revolution in 1971 (Geodakyan, 1979:18-19). Through Khachaturian’s

music, Stalin expresses his conviction that art has and must have a moral content that changes

the perceptions of its target audience, even if it is music which is “the least susceptible to

materialist orthodoxy” (Barker, 1985:27). He attributes a moral function to art and confesses

that the composer’s music helped him restore his spirit in the most hopeless and troublesome

moments during the war: “There is no question music has a moral content, but how? How

was it Khachaturian restored me at the very moment I felt I had betrayed Lenin and the entire

people? I was mad with guilt, I saw their ghosts crowding round the room, and yet in three

days I was able to emerge and take control” (27). However, Barker immediately refutes this

idea of a morally functional art by giving voice to Matrimova again who gives a detailed

description of what she means by Wholefilm in a dialogue with Buber. She says: “Until now,

all film has been warped by the interpretation of the single eye. The representation of reality

has been incomplete. Wholefilm […] produc[es] an artistic experience which maximalizes

the audience’s grasp of reality and at the same time offers the prospect of genuine socialist

development” (29). With these words, Barker admits, once again, that artistic representation

is an ultimately subjective activity which reduces reality to just one interpretation and has the
171

power to blur the distinction between what is right and what is wrong. The solution to this,

however, is not artlessness, but an impartial approach to the reality as a whole with an

emphasis on the artistic experience which the reality leaves on the audience rather than the

reality itself. As Matrimova observes, this is the only way in which a work of art can be

useful without being functional.

Along with Ilona and Matrimova, Victor stands as another self-referential element in

the play with his endless struggle against the censoring mechanism of the authority in order

to keep his art free of political and moral impositions, which is reminiscent of Barker’s own

struggle against such mechanisms. Victor is constantly confronted by Sorge with regard to

the sides his photographs are taking or must take, and Victor informs Ilona that Sorge has

been threatening him to make him work for the cause of the party. Victor tells Ilona: “I said

to him, I am an innocent photographer. He said there is no such thing as an innocent

photographer, only photographers with varying degrees of guilt. What does that mean? It’s a

death sentence” (30). Once again, Sorge attributes political and moral functions to art and

reduces it to an instrument to give direction to men’s thoughts. He openly confesses that

things have completely changed after the war and everybody has a purpose in living rather

than mere survival. When Ilona expresses her wish to go away, Sorge says: “Go where? […]

You see, I don’t think people will be just going - any more. That is archaic. That is very pre-

war, like Cook’s tours of the Danube Principalities. Like beggars, and caviar. Just going. Just

coming. What does ‘can I go’ mean? It means ‘can I avoid’, doesn’t it? I think we should

say, rather, ‘Can I serve?’” (32). Victor cannot stand the pressure anymore and he pays the

price with his life trying to liberate his art from censorship by being shot trying to escape the

compound with his photograph crates in his hand. Ilona, on the other hand, chooses to stand
172

against that authoritative mechanism and faces Stalin to prove the inevitable dependence of

earthly things on art to achieve immortality.

Consequently, Barker’s The Power of the Dog gives a panorama of the aftermath of

the Second World War through the spectacles of three artists in the face of governmental

oppression and censorship directed not only at their art but also at their freedom of thought.

The play becomes appropriate for a classification as historiographic in the playwright’s

treatment of the mainstream historical knowledge with an aim to disrupt it and to propose an

alternative version of history with an equal degree of validity of historical representation

thanks to an unfamiliar portrayal of historical personages like Joseph Stalin, Winston

Churchill and other minor figures. Barker’s portrayal of Stalin, for instance, replaces the

familiar image of the fear-inspiring despot with the image of a feeble old man suffering from

paranoia and prostate or the image of Churchill as a reasonable and serious man with the

image of a greedy old man with limited mental capacities. With these equally valid

portrayals, Barker proves the subjective and flexible essence of historical representations

changing according to point of view. The play can also be classified as metadramatic with

the real life references to historical figures and events indicated above. Along with these real

life references, the play is also self-referential in that it uses artists as central characters and

works of art as central motifs around which all the play’s action revolves. In his protagonists’

struggle against the authority, Barker voices his ideas regarding issues like censorship,

freedom of expression and ethics of art, using Ilona’s photography and Matrimova’s film

project as parallels to his own drama. In all these respects, Barker’s The Power of the Dog

appropriately qualifies as an example of the subgenre historiographic metadrama.


173

3.3. Pity in History and Art as ‘Vulgar Ostentation’

First published in 1984, Barker’s Pity in History is one of the playwright’s

catastrophic plays that explores the limits of human suffering and the motivations behind

historical representations and artistic creations. Setting his play in the chaotic atmosphere in

England during the Civil War, Barker questions the issues like the true functions of art, the

role of the authority in the recording of history and the war as a means of injury on the

physical, emotional and intellectual levels. Barker forms parallelisms between the 17th

century and his own time in order to display that history always repeats itself even though

the agents keep replacing each other and that art must be kept free, at all costs, of any

involvement in material gain or political propaganda.

The play opens in a cathedral, during the English Civil War, where the

parliamentarian Sergeant Boys talks his privates back into discipline while a wounded cook

named Murgatroyd is doing the opposite with his loud cry of damnation of war. After the

soldiers’ departure, the chaplain of the cathedral, Croop, tries to assure the cook that he has

been suffering for a perfect reason, in the name of Christ and political justice. In the

meantime, a mason-sculptor named Gaukroger scolds his apprentice, Pool, for not putting

pickles inside his sandwich although the boy has a valid excuse that the grocer has been

arrested because of the war. In the following scene, Gaukroger walks into the cathedral where

Croop, Murgatroyd and Factor, an officer, have been having a discussion over the nature of

war and idolatry. The sculptor makes an offer to the two officers of building a granite

memorial, an obelisk or a pillar in the memory of the martyrs of the ongoing war, to which

the chaplain responds with an indifferent, ignorant rejection of art, lowering the sculptor’s

spirits and appetite to turn his art into cash. The politically propagandistic chaplain openly

reduces art to the level of ‘pagan ornament’ and ‘vulgar ostentation’ while Factor seems to
174

enjoy the artist’s sense of humour and empathize with the man’s grievances regarding art

being not appreciated in the present time.

In another part of the cathedral, Murgatroyd keeps on shouting out the bitter truths to

the face of soldiers, condemning the war, the Cromwellian regime and the House of

Commons while Factor strives to calm him down, ending up confining him to the crypt not

to upset the soldiers anymore. Croop, on the other hand, has been doing the marketing of war

to the soldiers, by spreading fear into their hearts and persuading them that it is Christ’s war

they are fighting when Venables, a Catholic royalist widow, walks in and threatens them with

the King’s and God’s wrath. In the meantime, Gaukroger works on a monument, which later

turns out to be for the widow’s late husband, in some part of the cathedral and preaches his

apprentice about the power of an artist in overcoming time and death through his art. He also

acknowledges the fact that political and religious intervention in art is inevitable at such a

catastrophic time and all the artists are doomed to be “herded [...] like mad sheep, offering

their services to the bishop” (75). Their dialogue is interrupted by Venables who shows up

to see how her husband’s monument is turning out to be. When Gaukroger asks the widow

for some advance to feed himself and the apprentice boy, the latter protests that it is

disappointing to see an artist ‘rattling for grasp and profit’ before giving him the money.

Venables, then, comes across the hopeless Murgatroyd, who cannot even understand if he is

dead and in hell or alive and blind, in the crypt which turns out to be the widow’s secret store

for valuable paintings.

Back in the sculptor’s corner, Factor examines the monument and questions the artist

about the honesty of his art, as he is carving honour for a dishonourable man, a charitable

face, graceful hands and a lovely wig for a lout who was actually a mean, tight-handed man

with lousy hair. Gaukroger coldly responds to the man saying that honesty is not part of his
175

commission and his art tells the truth that the dead man was rich enough to buy the artist’s

skill and vain enough to believe what is written in the epitaph. Soon enough, a group of

soldiers, including Pool who has earlier left his master to become a mercenary, shows up in

the gallery with the intention of breaking the sculpture into pieces with Factor’s provocation.

The sculptor does not even try to hinder the soldiers who are scolded by the chaplain for

mistaking property with idolatry.

Meanwhile in the crypt, Venables tries to keep Murgatroyd silent, threatening him

with a blade on his neck in order not to be detected by the soldiers. When the soldiers depart,

she kills the cook coldheartedly, as she believes him to be a traitor to the crown and the God.

She, then, goes up into the gallery only to find the sculptor drunk and thrashing about among

the broken pieces of his sculpture. She tries to fire him with passion to build the monument

again, deeming great art as their only way to demand a place within history, before he notices

the cook’s blood on her dress. She uses the artist’s help to dispose of the cook’s corpse and

leaves for Calais until the end of the war. After the widow’s departure, the sculptor discovers

that Pool has been hiding in one of the tombs, as he deserted from the army. The play ends

with the artist making up with his apprentice to find the language, style and the new manner

for the new situation as all the artists do when History is sticking round their teeth.

Barker reveals his historical consciousness from the very beginning of the play by

setting it in the middle of the Puritan Revolt, one of the bloodiest uprisings in English history

which manifested itself in terms of extensive bloodshed, religious and political oppression as

well as limitation of human rights in all fields of life including arts. The Civil War in England

broke out as “the result of incompetent kingship which allowed religious militants to settle

their disputes about the nature of the church, and therefore of different concepts of the moral

order (Morrill, et al. 1984:19). It resulted in the death of thousands including King Charles I,
176

who was executed with the charge of treason, and the alleviation of the domination of the

Church of England in religious affairs and the English monarchy in political ones. However,

the reasons for Barker’s interest in this period in English history lie behind the cultural and

intellectual restrictions in the period, including the closing down of theatres and the violation

of the freedom of expression under Cromwell’s rule. Kastan observes that the Parliament’s

desire to close all theatres during the Civil War was a politically correct move, as theatre has

always been “a contested arena of power and desire, never inherently either an agent of

subversion or an apparatus of royal authority […] it belonged neither to the King nor to his

critics […] [and] was claimed by both, for it was a significant site of voluble articulation, a

locus of the production of meanings and images that could neither be stabilized nor

controlled” (1999:209-210). Barker thinks of these restrictions in parallel with his own time

with respect to the underhanded censorship of artistic activities by political power-holders.

The action in the play takes place in a cathedral right outside the battlefield where a

squad of Roundheads bands back together to tend the wounded and rest for the night. This

scene turns into a meeting among the Soldiers being the voice of the politics, the Chaplain

being the voice of the church and the sculptor being the voice of arts. Through these

characters, Barker shows how interrelated these voices were in the history, politics and

religion being the sole mechanism that gives artistic productions their direction. In his

dialogue with his master sculptor Gaukroger, the apprentice Pool mentions Oliver

Cromwell’s name, strengthening the play’s historiographic essence by looking at the Civil

War from a different angle through the eyes of an imaginary historical figure: “She says

Cromwell’s men tear pictures with their teeth. Do they?” (68). This speculative statement

about a famous historical figure is quite well-placed, though still fictive, thinking that

Cromwell has always been notorious for his attitude towards artistic endeavours, which was
177

extensively disapproved by the majority of the public during the Interregnum. Tomalin

observes that the public obviously had “enough of fighting, they never approved the

execution of the king, they resented puritan suppression of Christmas and Mayday festivals,

dancing, the theatre and children’s games on Sunday” (2002:118). Using Pool as a

mouthpiece, Barker voices the disturbance of the general public in the past and of himself in

the present time with such governmental intervention in artistic and cultural activities.

Barker also draws attention to the massive bloodshed and savagery during the Civil

War with an emphasis on the suffering of the wounded army cook Murgatroyd and the

accounts about the battlefield given by the soldiers. In a dialogue between the officer Factor

and the chaplain Croop, Barker expresses the level of butchery during the war which is

somehow justified by the two officers on the pretext that everything is being done in the name

of God:

FACTOR: They went barmy today, killing the killed several times over…
CROOP: They were filled with the fury of God.
FACTOR: At lunchtime the only cadaver they’d seen was their granddad, by
tea-time they’d walked through an acre of brains…
CROOP: What are you saying?
FACTOR: The sergeants could hardly restrain them. Had them drilling and
shouting their names…
CROOP: Was not Samson furious, and in his fury pure? (69).

Interestingly, the incident mentioned by the two men is reminiscent of a documented

historical event, known as the Bartholomy incident that took place during the Civil War in

1646, in which the Parliamentarian soldiers took refuge in a church after a brutal fighting and

more than a thousand casualties. An anonymous parliamentary document of the same year,

titled “Englands Wolfe with Eagles Claws, The Cruel Impieties of Bloud-thirsty Royalists,

and Blasphamous Anti-Parliamentarians, under the Command of that Inhumane Prince

Rupert, Digby, and the Rest. Wherein the Barbarous Crueltie of our Civil Uncivil Warres is

Briefly Discovered”, mentions the incident in such a way that it resembles the soldiers’
178

situation in the play: “How could wee forget that bloody massacre of Byron in Cheshire, that

in coole blood murthered no less than 1500, that fled to a Church for shelter” (in Coster,

1999:95). Barker, in this respect, seems to have made use of historical documents with the

addition of imaginary characters and dialogues in an attempt to blur the distinction between

the fictitious and the real.

At this point in the play, Gaukroger approaches the two officers with the intention to

offer his artistic skills as a means of political and religious propaganda in return for a small

amount of money. His comments on the war going on outside the walls is quite realistic, as

he seems aware that History is being written by guns, cannons and swords in the outside

world rather than his worthless efforts in shaping stones: “We listened from the tower, I said

to Pool, I hope this will not be another skirmish, just cuts and grazes, then we heard the

cannonade and I knew, this was History coming over the hill” (69). In another dialogue,

Venables justifies Gaukroger’s hopeless statements about the art in the wartime by referring

to another famous historical figure, Anthony Van Dyck, the Flemish painter of the English

court during Charles I’s rule. She protests that the Puritan revolt affected artistic

developments negatively, saying: “There was an Italian here six months ago, but he fled. You

can’t blame him, the puritans think all Italians are popes…the war has ruined English art.

Look at Van Dyke” (77). The Flemish painter is known to be the most famous representative

of what is called ‘the Cavalier Art’ with his new-fashioned portraits of King Charles I, which

won him extensive reputation. For instance, Levey argues that, in Dyck’s paintings, “Charles

is given a totally natural look of instinctive sovereignty, in a deliberately informal setting

where he strolls so negligently that he seems at first glance nature's gentleman rather than

England's King” (1971:128). In a similar example, Venables also refers to Bernini, the Italian

sculptor of the Baroque style (Boucher, 1998:134-142) in the service of the papacy in the
179

17th century, in her attempts to determine the limits of Gaukroger’s artistic skills. Such

references to historical characters of the 17th century place Barker’s play upon more realistic

foundations serving the playwright’s purposes to give documented history and products of

his imagination side by side with an aim to equalize their powers of historical representation.

The list of references to historical personages goes on with Venables’ mention of a

Lady Digby whose china gets lost at sea due to a storm on the way to the continental Europe.

Barker here benefits from his reading of historical accounts and draws attention to the fact

that many Royalist Catholic aristocrats and the rich had to escape England after the victory

of Cromwell’s army, Calais and Antwerp being the most favoured destinations. Jane Digby

is one of those aristocrats who fled the country for political reasons, but made a bigger

reputation with her multiple scandalous marriages including one with an Arab sheikh right

before her death (Keenan, 2000:167). Venables herself plans something similar, to escape

from the country to Calais after the completion of her deceased husband’s monument put up

by Gaukroger. However, Gaukroger expresses his hopelessness and fear that history will

erase them anyway, mentioning only those who are powerful enough to be mentioned. In a

dialogue with his apprentice Pool, Gaukroger, emphasizing the message behind the play’s

title, says: “The plough will go through every palace and the bomb in every bedroom […]

No pity in History” (85). Venables contradicts his hopelessness and fear with her idealism

and enthusiasm regarding art’s power to outlive centuries, echoing Barker’s own view of it,

when she says: “When all the world is tilted, we need people who can keep their feet, who

say of all calamity, this is a setback, but I hold to my own truth, I will not waver. The storm

of history. When it has passed, clean up. Stone on stone. Brick on brick” (89). Venables

admits that history has the power to wipe away, to silence, to change the reality and to

promote one over the other; yet, it still lies in the imaginative faculties of an artist to fight
180

against such disruptive powers of history and immortalize historical moments. A similar idea

is voiced by Pool who tries to elevate his master’s excitement about his art in order to save

him from his hopelessness that history will erase him. The dialogue between the two goes as

follows:

GAUKROGER: Frilly cuffs and whispering Catholics, scented fingers made


for intrigues…the new hand will have blunt fingers, not made for running up
a woman’s knee…
POOL: We’ll get it.
GAUKROGER: Can’t teach you. (Pause.) Can’t eat this sandwich, either…
POOL: (aghast.) Can’t eat a sandwich?
GAUKROGER: Something’s sticking round my teeth…I think it’s History…
POOL: (scrambling out the tomb.) Geddup, Gaukroger! […] Find the
language. Find the style. New manner for new situation. When in doubt,
invent. Copy. Cheat. Get by.
GAUKROGER: He lectures me…
POOL: Calamity, all right, bowled over, flat on yer back, looks bad, admitted,
but not fatal, still got ‘ands, still got ‘eyes… (emphasis in the original, 91-92).

Barker, in these scenes, uses Venables and Pool as a mouthpiece to express his ideas about

the equal validity of fictional accounts to historical documents in historical representation

and to attribute greater powers to an artist’s imaginative skills than a historian’s observational

skills contaminated with ideology. The ending of the play is quite telling in this respect, as

the soldiers – including Pool – bring down Gaukroger’s monument in ruins and the sculptor

gets up to rebuild it to leave a trace in history thanks to his artistic skills.

Barker’s references to all these historical events and personages also contribute to the

play’s metadramatic outlook when they are thought in consideration with Hornby’s

designation of real life references as a variety of metadrama. Barker, this time, turns his

attention away from the Soviet history and chooses an important historical event as a

background to his play, one which is expected to catch the audience’s attention thinking that

the immediate target audience is British and has certain knowledge regarding the English

Civil War along with some intellectual capacity. The references to the historical figures like
181

Cromwell, Van Dyck, Bernini, Lady Digby and Caravaggio give the play a realistic essence

whereas all the characters in the play are completely imaginary, diminishing that realistic

effect for a bigger purpose. By these real life characters appearing side by side with their

imaginary companions, Barker writes an alternative historical account with an equal claim to

historical reality which doesn’t even go beyond speculation. Barker gives voice to historical

persons who are too insignificant to even appear in historical accounts and offers their

perspective of the famous historical events to emphasize the subjective nature of historical

representations.

Like all real life references, these allusions lose their metadramatic effectiveness in

time as long as they don’t suggest a parallelism with the time of the performance, because

the audience is required to understand that a real life reference is being made and it has a

deeper metadramatic meaning beneath the surface. Barker’s Pity in History sustains a strong

referential relation to the date when it was written considering the playwright’s choice of the

Cromwell period for the time of his play which parallels the 1980s environment in England

under Thatcher’s premiership in terms of issues like censorship of art and freedom of

expression. In his Arguments for a Theatre, Barker himself forms a connection between this

play and the general condition of theatre in his own time, relating an event that takes place

right after a performance of Pity in History in London. He says: “The reaction of an old

soldier, who appeared to have wandered in from the street, bedecked with medals which

clearly demonstrated his rights to his own history - his empirical authority, so to speak, to

debate the subject of war and injury – was profoundly hostile to the portrayal of a dying army

cook […] This old soldier’s bitterness underlined for me the poverty of the common

perception of theatre and its responsibilities that now dominates the realist discourse”

(1993:94). Barker, here, criticizes the contemporary understanding of theatre which comes
182

with an obsession with functional and responsible representation on stage as a moral example

to the audience watching the play. Barker fights against such moral and political impositions

on any kind of artistic endeavours and aims to liberate his art from the constraints of what

realism dictates. Very much like the official banning of artistic activities during the English

Civil War, the theatre during Barker’s most prolific years suffers from governmental

interventions as well as the mainstream political dramatists’ futile attempts to come up with

a recipe of proper drama.

This issue is ultimately related to the central subject of the play, the artists’ struggle

against the authority in a chaotic atmosphere, the authority being the church and the

government in the play’s particular case. It is possible that the central characters of the play,

the artist Gaukroger and the art patron Venables, are taken into account as the two sides of

this never-ending discussion between those who view art as a functional activity and those

who view it as independent of any functions. In this respect, the characters’ ideas related to

functions of art and responsibilities of the artist are self-referential in the sense that they stand

for what Barker argues regarding the same matters. At the end of the second scene of the

play, for instance, Pool refers to the attitude of the governmental officials towards works of

art, which is reminiscent of the intolerant attitude in Barker’s time towards the idea of

complete freedom in art. Relating Venables’ statement to his master Gaukroger, Pool says:

“She says Cromwell’s men tear pictures with their teeth” (68). The attitude of the

parliamentarian soldiers stems from a conservative kind of morality pertain to the puritans of

the time in which a strict authoritarian populism is promoted and what is outside of these

moral borders is blindly destroyed. Barker’s relation of this attitude with the attitude of the

government of his time towards art is quite well-placed thinking that what is called the

Thatcherite morality is always associated with a strict moral code reminiscent of the
183

Victorian era (Tracey and Herzog, 2016:63-76). In both attitudes, art is reduced to a

governmental instrument which promotes and advertises the mainstream, dominant ideology

and morality or simply vanishes.

A similar attitude is exemplified in the play when Croop, the chaplain of the church,

refers to the statue built by Gaukroger in the place as a means of committing sin whereas he

justifies the killing of Catholic soldiers with being filled with ‘the fury of God’. He describes

the works of art around him saying: “The worship of idols. The mocking of the Lord. […] it

is not a place of worship, it’s a wedding cake. Dead men’s tombs higher than the altar. Vanity

offends Him, pomp makes His wounds bleed” (68). With Croop’s comparison of art with

idols built against God, Barker underlines the false conception of appropriate art once more

and emphasizes the timelessness of the attempts at attributing a moral function to art. He

depicts Gaukroger not as an honourable artist in such a chaotic atmosphere, unlike Bela and

Ilona in the two previously-discussed plays, but as a profiteer who tries to sell his artistic

skills in exchange for a little pension, some cheese and pickles. In the dialogue between

Gaukroger and Croop, the former never stands up to the latter’s propagandistic attributions

to and labelling of art:

CROOP: Do you find something to mock in the army?


GAUKROGER: No, killing must be done or I lose half of my commissions.
(He turns to a nearby tomb.) Here’s a captain of marines got murdered on an
island. I did that twenty years back---I was never very good at skulls, not that
there’s a call for skulls now. Necrophilia’s got unfashionable, they all want
swag and trophies.
CROOP: This is God’s army, and we rinse out all sin…
GAUKROGER: Amen.
CROOP: We demolish all pagan ornament---
GAUKROGER: Well, it’s only mass production, half of it---
CROOP: You ponder the ostentation of the vulgar. Pack up your hammers and
grow potatoes (70).

Even though an ordinary religious officer reduces his art to the level of pagan ornamentation

and vulgar ostentation, Gaukroger does not protest knowing that being marginal means being
184

annihilated under a totalitarian regime. The religious official’s ideas are echoed by the

officers of the army, showing that all the apparatuses of the totalitarian government work

hand in hand with an aim to supress opposing views, as seen in Sponge’s words: “That’s

idolatry. Ain’t it? When we got in the big ‘ouse at Harborough […] I went up these stairs

[…] the room looked bigger than a field, an’ it was full of bits, like pictures, an’ this furniture,

an’ it was all there, like it was a church, an’ I wanted to smash it, an’ I smashed it ‘cos it was

idolatry […] I was full of the Lord” (74). Even though Gaukroger seems to be realistically

profit-oriented in this chaotic environment, he does not seem to be completely unaware of

the true power of his art, but he chooses to keep a low profile for political reasons and does

not stand up against such accusations against his art. Such an attitude on behalf of Gaukroger

is used by Barker probably as a means to voice his critique of his contemporaries who know

the power of their pen, but choose to use this power for political ends.

In the sixth scene of the play, Gaukroger teaches his apprentice Pool the greatness

and limitlessness of an artist’s imaginative faculties with the addition that these faculties

mean nothing if the artist does not have an idea about where to use them. He says: “You have

all the sculpture in the world stored in your fingertips if you watch. And if they do not crush

your fingers you can make it all again, like the books can be re-written and all the pictures

painted over again, unless they murder all the painters, which can’t be done because painters

are born every minute, unfortunately. I say unfortunately because there’s too much talent and

it’s got cheap” (75). Even though the sculptor possesses a certain amount of idealism in his

heart, the circumstances seem to be contradicting his ideals and forcing him to be realistic,

as he later tells Pool: “All the masons will be herded in one place like mad sheep, offering

their services to the bishop. Down will come the wages and you will have fifty starving

masons instead of one fed. Stick to where you are. This will pass and you’ll get an income if
185

you are patient” (75). In such troublesome circumstances, Gaukroger believes that going with

the flow is the best option for an artist in order not to starve to death, as institutional religious

intervention in artistic activities has been rampant during the Civil War. With the example of

Gaukroger, Barker expresses his ideas about the responsibilities of the artist, in a critical way,

not to himself or any other person or institutions, but to the art itself whatever the

circumstances require.

Towards the end of the play, Barker draws attention to the power of art in terms of

writing history and changing the course of events with the motivation the artist has at the

back of his mind. In the case of Gaukroger, the motivation is one that forces him to build his

representation on lies which turn out to have a valid claim to reality in direct proportion to

the amount of money he is paid by his patron, Venables. In his dialogue with the government

officer Factor, the sculptor defends himself that his commission provides him with an

alternative reality and he relies on the power of his art in representing it as he likes:

FACTOR: Why do you do this? Carve honour for courtiers? Run up splendour
for dishonest men?
GAUKROGER: The honest men have nothing to pay me with.
FACTOR: It’s a lie, this. Bigger than the altar for a lout who spent his life
sipping in clubs and tampering with prostitutes.
GAUKROGER: His blood went bad and blew his heart up three times big,
and his foot came off with his boot…
FACTOR: Show that, then.
GAUKROGER: It wasn’t part of my commission.
FACTOR: His expression is charitable, though he was mean…his hand is
graceful, though it was tight…his wig is lovely, though his hair was full of
lice…
GAUKROGER: It doesn’t look a bit like him, but it has got life…
FACTOR: A bad art, this…
GAUKROGER: Why? It tells the truth.
FACTOR: What truth?
GAUKROGER: That he was rich enough to buy my skill, and vain enough
to believe his epitaph. He could have bought Bernini, but Bernini wasn’t
passing, so he bought Gaukroger for fifteen quid (81-82).
186

Like Barker, Gaukroger is also quite aware that art has the capacity to distort the reality or

underline it depending on the motivation of the artist. Even though Barker seems to be

agreeing with Gaukroger on the latter’s belief that reality is what is represented rather than

what really happened, he does not seem to be reading the same page with the character when

it comes to the outcome of this belief. This does not stem from an obsession with realism in

art on behalf of Barker, but from his insistence on the fact that reality is ultimately subjective

on condition that it remains purely unmotivated by external moral and ideological

interventions. With this motivation in mind, Barker criticizes his contemporaries who enslave

their artistic vision to others’ realities and turn their art into a means for political propaganda.

To emphasize this idea, Barker uses Venables as a mouthpiece in her attempts to put some

spirit, idealism and hope into Gaukroger’s heart. After the soldiers break the sculpture into

pieces, Venables finds the already-drunk sculptor among the broken pieces of his work and

tries to talk him back into building. When questioned by the sculptor why he needs to get

back to work in an environment where true art is given no value, she says: “Why, he says.

We need great art, that’s why. […] We have to have art or we don’t know who we are. It’s

very simple. Do get up” (88). However, Gaukroger opens his eyes to the reality only when

his apprentice Pool teaches him one last lesson by telling him “Never” as an answer to his

hopeless statement that art is dead. The play ends in an optimistic way not for any of the

characters, but for the future of art, as the paintings that Venables has been hiding in the

basement of the church are saved from the soldiers and Pool makes Gaukroger realize that

“too much imitation leaves […] nothing for the real” (92).

Consequently, Barker’s Pity in History bears strong resemblances to the previous

plays discussed in the previous sub-sections in terms of theme and subject matter when its

interest in the documented historical events like the English Civil War and famous historical
187

figures like Cromwell is taken into consideration. The play possesses a historical as well as

a historiographic essence with Barker’s attempts to write an alternative version of the history

of the English Civil War from the perspectives of historically minor or completely imaginary

characters assembled into the flow of documented historical events. Barker’s version of the

English Civil War is obviously supplied with his readings and research on the event along

with additions of his imagination, and this authentic version of history possesses an equal

claim to historical truth as much as any other historical document, because historical

accounts, in Barker’s view, have the same narrative and imaginative nature as fictional

accounts. Along with such historiographic tendencies, Barker’s Pity in History also possesses

a strong metadramatic essence with its continuous references and allusions to real life events

and people as well as to itself as a fictional account. Barker uses the characters in the play as

a mouthpiece to voice his ideas regarding issues like functions of art, responsibilities of the

artist, ethics of artistic representation, governmental censorship of art and the artist’s struggle

against the totalitarian authority. With his protagonist’s misconceptions about the functions

of art, Barker forms a parallelism between the artist in his play and the contemporary

dramatists in order to reveal their false political and moral motivations behind their writing,

which comes as an insult to art for Barker. Gaukroger’s sculpture and Venables’ paintings

also represent Barker’s views about great art in the former’s failure to survive the chaos and

the latter’s survival through centuries due to the differences in the motivations behind their

existence. In all these respects, Barker’s Pity in History appropriately qualifies as an example

of the subgenre historiographic metadrama.


188

3.4. Scenes from an Execution and ‘What the Circumstances Require’ for Art

Originally produced as a radio play for BBC in 1984, Barker’s Scenes from an

Execution was first staged in 1990 in London and reappeared several times after that thanks

to the positive remarks by the critics and the public. Costa describes the play as “the most

famous and accessible play” (2012) ever produced by the playwright even though Barker

himself openly refuses to regard the play as one of his best. Very much like Barker’s other

famous plays written in the 80s, Scenes from an Execution also takes its subject matter from

a historical event which brings an artist and the authority face to face in a struggle for

domination over historical and artistic representation. In an interview, Barker admits that

“state power is figured in a number of [his] plays about 1980/85” (2011:176) and Scenes

from an Execution is no exception to this, as it “explores the struggle between state power

and the power of artistic imagination” (Gritzner, 2012:337) in a 16th century Venice setting.

The play opens at Galactia’s studio in Venice where she engages in a discussion with

another painter and her nude model as well as her lover, Carpeta, over the latter’s intentions

and constant postponement of leaving his wife for the former. From their discussion over

love, marriage and originality in art, it is deducible that Galactia has a much stronger

character and steadier personality compared to Carpeta who is accused by his lover of lack

of originality, as he has painted the same Christ image eight times due to, what he calls, “a

passion for perfection” (2013:10). In return, Carpeta accuses Galactia of being “a woman and

a sensualist” (10) who thrusts herself to get commissions from the State. After Carpeta’s

departure, the scene proceeds with a veteran named Prodo showing Galactia his war-torn,

mutilated and distorted body as a source of inspiration, as Galactia has been painting the

famous Battle of Lepanto under the state commission. In her conversation with Prodo,

Galactia insists that she is not to be referred to as a woman, but as an artist. She also makes
189

the definition of an artist as a ‘midwife’ whose duty is “to bring the truth to birth” (14), and

consequently, decides to paint the destruction brought about by war, instead of the glory

gained by her native land.

With the completion of the painting, the scene is moved to the Doge’s palace where

he examines the painting and protests that his brother, the admiral, is not given a proper and

adequate representation in the work. At this point, the Doge’s views of art as mere reflection

of facts, or “an investment” (18), and history as a means of propaganda clash with Galactia’s

who wants to give an experiential experience to her audience. The Doge believes that an artist

has a duty towards his nation as well as ‘certain priorities’. For him, “a great artist must first

of all be responsible, or all his brush strokes, and all his colouring, however brilliant, will not

fit him out of the second rank. […] Great art will always celebrate!” (18-19). After being

demanded a new painting by the Doge, Galactia begins to struggle with the new painting

while engaging in conflicts with her daughters, Supporta and Dementia, and Carpeta. In one

of their discussions, Carpeta reduces art to the feelings of the artist saying: “You are violent,

so you can paint violence. You are furious, so you can paint fury. And contempt, you can

paint that. […] But you aren’t great enough for pity” (23). He also emphasizes the idea that

art can be and should be used as a means of propaganda, so that the artist can benefit from

institutional support and patronage: “If you could paint pity, the Church would stand up for

you, and if you could paint glory, you would have the State. But you will please nobody”

(23).

In the fifth scene, Galactia begins to paint Prodo as a Turkish soldier while engaging

in a fiery discussion with her daughter Supporta on the power of art, relativity of perception,

artistic imagination and social responsibilities of an artist. Although Supporta seems to adore

her mother’s skills and powerful stance against the authority, she reminds her of her
190

responsibilities “not to the State, but to Venetian women” (26). The following scene depicts

how Galactia paints the Admiral, Suffici, with an emphasis on their differing views on reality

and ‘truth’. As an artist commissioned by the State to paint the historical and political truth,

Galactia protests that politics and truth cannot go hand in hand, as one defies the other. At

that moment, Urgentino walks in with a female art critic named Rivera with whom Galactia

discusses the source of art as either inspiration or study. Urgentino praises Galactia’s work

so far but reminds her of the fact that it is the gold and silver of the State on her brush.

The seventh scene takes place in a church where the funeral ceremony of a fellow

painter is carried out and Galactia seems to be bothering Carpeta who objects to be seen in

public with her. The two end up being thrown out of the church in public disgrace. The eighth

scene brings back together Galactia and Rivera in the barracks where the former is working

on the commissioned painting while the latter interrupts her to preach on the political

implications of her work, especially if she glosses over the doge’s wishes. The scene ends

with three drunk sailors rummaging the barracks and Galactia determining to paint one of

them as the central figure of the painting. In the following two scenes, the focus shifts onto

Carpeta who appears to have been summoned by Urgentino and Cardinal Ostensibile to the

court along with the fellow painter Sordo with whom he has a quick conversation on the

outdatedness of their non-secular art. In the courtroom, Urgentino informs Carpeta about his

anxiety regarding Galactia’s work; as, for him, art has the undeniable power to create and

change ‘opinions’ which are “the source of all authority” (44). The two officials begin to

question Carpeta about the nature of his relations with Galactia to which he gives vague

replies. Urgentino’s reflections on Galactia’s art reveal that he openly admires, envies and,

most strikingly, fears her artistic talents and impressive willpower. Urgentino and Ostensibile

appoint Carpeta to paint the ‘Battle of Lepanto’ after he cringingly betrays Galactia’s
191

morality and sanity to them and expresses his slavish submission to paint ‘what the

circumstances require’. After Carpeta leaves, the two officials decide to give Galactia an

appropriate response by convicting her of immoral behaviour to serve some time in prison.

In the eleventh scene, the setting is moved to the barracks again where Galactia is

ready to show Carpeta the finished ‘Battle of Lepanto’, the first sight of which leaves the

latter in tears, possibly due to the greatness of it which he himself will never achieve or due

to guilty conscience. The following scene depicts Galactia in a harsh quarrel with her

daughter Supporta who admires her mother’s work, but determines to abandon her for the

fear that the government officials will be outraged by the carnage depicted on her mother’s

canvas. Meanwhile in the palace, Urgentino shows the painting to his brother, the admiral

Suffici who becomes enraged upon seeing the grotesque figure that represents himself with

claws for hands and an ‘untrue’ face. Urgentino, on the other hand, believes that only a mental

disorder can make an artist digress so vilely from what her patrons demand.

In scene fourteen, Urgentino is seen scolding Galactia for what she has done with the

painting while Galactia proudly defends herself for being herself unlike all those artists

hanging on the walls. With the coming of a committee into the room, an unofficial trial begins

for Galactia and she engages in a hot quarrel with the officials regarding the differences

between war as a noble struggle for furtherance of political ends and war as mere slaughter.

While Galactia defends her artistic freedom of expression, the committee members focus on

what is ‘behind’ the painting and refuse to hang it somewhere on the streets due to its lack of

morality. They even go so far as to associate Galactia’s dyed, unclean garment and her not

wearing breast supports with her immorality and label her as “an enemy of the Republic”

(57) before confining her to a prison. In the prison where she is denied light, Galactia is
192

comforted a little by the voice of the man in the next cell while, in another scene, Urgentino

discusses her punishment with Carpeta.

On the other hand, the two men discuss ‘the lack of celebration’ in Carpeta’s painting

of ‘Battle of Lepanto’. Carpeta cannot take the doge’s endless interruptions anymore and

expresses his wish to see Galactia to which Urgentino responds with a threat to imprison him

if he leaves the painting unfinished. With the arrival of Rivera to the scene, Urgentino blames

her for inseminating him with a passion for arts and the two agree that Carpeta is nothing

more than a hack without imaginative powers. In the following scene, Carpeta pays the now-

bedlamite Galactia a visit in her cell where she asks him to impregnate her so that she could

‘plead her belly’ to avoid execution. However, to everybody’s surprise, she is released from

prison by a letter signed by an unnamed official. After Galactia’s release, her painting is

exhibited in public thanks to Rivera’s efforts and becomes rather successful and popular, also

embraced by fellow painters and government officials including Urgentino and Ostensibile.

The play draws to a close with Galactia among the admirers of her work and Urgentino

offering her a seat in his dinner table.

As a background for Scenes from an Execution, Barker uses one of the greatest naval

wars in human history, Battle of Lepanto (1571), in which the fleet of the Holy League

defeated the navy of the Ottoman Empire and dealt a blow in its dominance in the Western

Mediterranean. Braudel views the victory of the Holy League in the war as “the end of a

period of profound depression, the end of a genuine inferiority complex on the part of

Christendom and a no less real Turkish supremacy” (1973:1103). Even though the defeat of

the Ottoman navy is attributed to the League comprised of the forces of the Papacy, the

Habsburg Monarchy and the Venetian navy, the victory means more to the Venetian Republic

as a compensation for their loss of Cyprus to the Ottomans in the previous year. The victory
193

over the Turks is celebrated by the Venetians with huge rapture and pride; however, the treaty

signed between the sides in 1573 reveals that it was the Venetians who suffered the

consequences of the war by renouncing their rights on a number of strategically significant

keeps and accepting to pay heavy taxes to the Ottomans (Yıldırım, 2007:552-553). The

rapture among the Venetian ruling class and the public manifests itself in public celebrations

along with artistic activities as a reflection of the flourishing renaissance art. The

repercussions of the victory find an expression mostly in painting in a number of depictions

commissioned by the notables of the Venetian society, including Tintoretto's “Victory of

Lepanto”, Paolo Veronese’s “The Allegory of the Battle of Lepanto”, Andrea Vicentino’s

“The Battle of Lepanto”, Tommaso Dolabella’s “The Battle of Lepanto” and an anonymous

one titled “The Victors of the Naval Battle of Lepanto” (Gombrich, 1967:62-68).

Furthermore, Dawkins elaborates on these representations and mentions one in which the

Turks are represented in such a disturbing way that it stands as a reflection of the public

opinion about the enemy as barbarous and monster-like (1930:1-3). Among these various

paintings, the anonymous one titled “The Victors of the Naval Battle of Lepanto” is quite

significant in the determination of Barker’s sources for Galactia’s painting in the play, as it

depicts the three admirals of the fleet of the Holy League, Don Juan of Austria, Marc Antonio

Colonna of Rome and Sebastiano Venier of Venice, which is reminiscent of Galactia’s

controversial depiction of admiral Suffici in the play.

At the time of the Battle of Lepanto, the Republic of Venice was under the provision

of Doge Alvise I Mocenigo (Mosto, 1936:10), who served as the Doge of the city state from

1570 to 1577. In this respect, Barker can be thought to have based the character of Doge

Urgentino on Doge Alvise. However, no historical record suggests that the Doge had a

brother who served as the admiral of the Venetian naval forces. In this respect, Barker must
194

have formed an imaginary relation between the Doge of the time and the chief admiral by

disrupting the historical data. The data suggest that Sebastiano Venier was the admiral of the

Venetian fleet in the Battle of Lepanto and the next Doge of Venice after Doge Alvise’s death

by suicide in 1577 due to the huge reputation he gained in the war against the Turks (in Laven

and Damien, 2013:14). What saves the allusion from the possibility of a coincidence is that

Sebastiano Venier is known to be the subject of two famous Italian paintings, one by the

famous Tintoretto depicting the admiral in front of a sea-war background and one anonymous

painting titled “The Victors of Lepanto” depicting him alongside John of Austria and

Marcantonio Colonna before a similar background. These paintings give the reader a clue

about the admiral’s interest in the representation of his image, which is reminiscent of

Suffici’s obsession about his representation in Galactia’s painting.

These historical allusions contribute to the metadramatic outlook of the play with an

eye to Hornby’s designation of real-life references as a metadramatic variety. Barker’s use

of a very well-known historical event, Battle of Lepanto, for the background of his play

balances the play’s realistic and fictional qualities, and thus, blurs the distinction between the

speculative and the realistic in historical representation. Even though his characters are

basically imaginary with a touch of historical allusion to real personages, Barker reveals his

observations of the real-life Venice of the time through a number of images. For instance,

the struggle of Galactia against the male authorities first as a free-spirited woman and then

as a female artist is highly realistic when the place of women in the 16th century Venice is

taken into consideration. Rosenthal observes that, in the 16th century Venice, “women

possessed virtually no political power of their own, owing to an oligarchy dominated by men,

and the laws passed by men reveal not only a class bias but a special arrogance toward

women” (1992:15). The way that Galactia is confronted by her partner Carpeta in romantic
195

affairs, by her daughters in domestic issues, by the Doge in the political sphere, by the

Cardinal in religious matters and by the critic Rivera in artistic matters is quite telling about

the situation of a headstrong, marginal woman in a society dominated by not only men, but

also women who have adopted male perspectives. In a very idealistic manner, Galactia

refuses to comply with all the political, religious and social impositions and sustains an intact

character till the very end of the play in which she sacrifices her sanity. For Lamb, “[t]hrough

listening to the voices of the dead, Galactia feels obliged to reject the view of History which

the Venetian establishment wants her to paint; she sees that to lie about the past is to

perpetrate future slaughters” (1992:135). Similarly, Barker depicts the Doge and the Cardinal

as ideological public officers who abuse their institutional powers for personal interests as in

the Doge’s threatening of Galactia with imprisonment in order to make her celebrate the

naval victory rather than emphasizing the carnage or the Cardinal’s attribution of a holy

meaning to the war which is purely political. Rabey agrees that Barker’s Scenes from an

Execution is a play in which “the patron is the existential seeker, impatient with material

encumbrances, and the artists and their agents are resentful, superior, disrespectful and

ideologically reductive” (Rabey, 2009:201). This is a quite realistic approach on behalf of

Barker given that the Renaissance indicates a period as well as a movement in which artistic

creativity flourishes alongside institutional corruption.

Above all, Scenes from an Execution possesses a very strong metadramatic character

thanks to Barker’s allusions to the work of art itself, using Galactia’s painting to reflect on

his own drama and speaking through her mouth to express his ideas regarding the ethics of

art, responsibilities of the artist, censorship and freedom of expression. Very much like the

previous plays discussed, Barker places an artist at the centre of his play in her ruthless

struggle against all kinds of authority in a male-dominated society in order to defend her art
196

from political, religious and social impositions. The way Galactia defends the freedom of her

art from external constraints is quite reminiscent of Barker’s own defence of the functionless

character of his drama in the face of political and social involvement. At the very beginning

of the play, Galactia confronts Carpeta about the question of artistic originality and

renovation in opposition to an obsession with the artistic perfection: “Carpeta, you know

perfectly well you only stand to benefit from the loss of concentration you have suffered

through loving me. You have painted Christ among the flocks eight times now, you must

allow the public some relief-” (10). To this, Carpeta responds with an accusation that Galactia

is a mere sensualist and opportunist who plays with the public’s emotions to get a

governmental commission whereas he waits for the right time for perfection: “And I have

painted Christ among the flocks eight times not because I cannot think of anything else to

paint but because I have a passion for perfection, I long to be the finest Christ painter in Italy,

I have a longing for it, and that is something an opportunist like you could never understand”

(10). However, Galactia seems to refuse to attribute any duties to an artist, not even when

perfection and beauty are concerned. In a dialogue with Prodo, the veteran sitting for her

painting, Galactia says: “I tell you I would not, I do not trust beauty, it is an invention and a

lie. […] I will paint your violence for all the passing crowds who mock your daft appearance”

(15). In her analogy between an artist and a midwife, Galactia defines her job as not giving

birth to truth, but helping others bring truth to birth. This analogy is quite significant in that

it resembles Barker’s rejection of collectivism in art and suggestion of partiality in its place.

In other words, Barker does not attribute the pregnancy with the ultimate truth to the artist,

but imagines an artist who evokes the masses to come up with their own individual truths.

In the second scene of the play, Barker brings the politician and the artist face to face

and gives voice to his ideas of political intervention in art and official censorship mechanisms
197

of authoritarian regimes. In the dialogue between Doge Urgentino and Galactia, Barker first

draws attention to the differences between the politician’s views of art and the artist’s views

of it and displays that the Doge views art as mere reflection of facts and history as a means

of political propaganda, which clashes with Galactia’s understanding of these. Urgentino

says: “I know you are an artist and I am a politician, and we both have all sorts of little

mannerisms, turns of speech, beliefs and so on, which neither of us will be happy to renounce,

but for the sake of easy communication may I suggest we stop the little dance of personal

regard and concentrate on facts?” (17). For him, art is an investment for the realization of

certain political priorities and only celebration and praise make a work of art great in direct

proportion to how much it serves. However, Galactia believes that art must be true only to

itself and defy all functions whatsoever along with a balance of factuality and imagination:

“I believe in observation, but to observation you must lend imagination. The Doge says I am

to submit to him another drawing in which the Admiral is given greater prominence. Well, I

shall do. I shall show him not only prominent but RESPONSIBLE. And a face which is not

exulting but INDIFFERENT” (22). When she is confronted by Carpeta about the motivation

behind her paintings, she expresses her determination to defend her art against any kind of

intrusions:

CARPETA: No. You are violent, so you can paint violence. You are furious,
so you can paint fury. And contempt, you can paint that. Oh, yes, you can
paint contempt. But you aren’t great enough for pity.
GALACTIA: ‘Great enough’?
CARPETA: It’s hard luck on you, because if you could paint pity, the Church
would stand up for you, and if you could paint glory, you would have the State.
But you will please nobody.
GALACTIA: You know what I think? I think you are marvellous at honouring
yourself. Marvellous. But pity’s got nothing to do with greatness. It’s
surrender, the surrender of passion, or the passion of surrender. It is
capitulating to what is. Rather than pity the dead man I would say – there –
there is the man who did it, blame him, identify, locate responsibility. Or else
the world is just a pool, a great pool of dirty tears through which vile men in
198

boots run splashing. You paint pity very well, but you endure everything (23-
24).

The way Carpeta reminds Galactia of the necessity of feelings for artistic creativity is an

invitation for Galactia to open up her art for servitude either to the political or to the religious

institutions of the time in an attempt to achieve acceptance and stay unexceptional. There is

an obvious confrontation between the patrons’ demands and Galactia’s self-declared

autonomy and she is determined to overcome this problem with her belief in the

boundlessness of artistic imagination with no regard to however the patrons patronize her.

She seems well aware that the power of her art is limitless and human perception of events

is completely relative culminating in a multiplicity of realities: “So with one figure I

transformed the enemy from beast to victim, and made victory unclean. And I suspect, even

as I draw it, they will hate this…!” (25). When her daughter Supporta warns her about the

possibility that the Doge will attack her for her lack of morality and promiscuity if she insists

on conflicting with him, Galactia still refuses to comply with him by celebrating the battle in

her painting on pain of defamation. In this respect, Galactia is a perfect tragic heroine when

Barker’s description is taken into account. In his Death, the One and the Art of Theatre,

Barker argues that “the tragic actress persuades you of her moral nakedness […] Never

beyond the human, she describes the possibility within the human, repudiating the sordid

practices of reproduction of the known, the familiar, the stereotypical. In this she privileges

herself as desirable, consequently a challenge to the likeable . . .” (2005:86). With these

words, Barker draws the picture of an ideal artist as one that deliberately remains beyond the

borders, defies the constraints of commonness and enjoys challenging the imposed norms

and values dominating common life.

As discussed before, Barker draws a line between his “Theatre of Catastrophe” and

the political drama dominating the stages in the last decades of the 20th century. Barker
199

explains his aloofness from political involvement with his determination to keep his art free

of servitude to any ideology. In Scenes from an Execution, Galactia displays a similar

character when she defends her art against the officials’ attempt at making it a means for

political propaganda. In her discussion with Admiral Suffici, the Doge’s brother and subject

of Galactia’s painting, Galactia defines an artist’s job as an unshrinking pursuit of truth

uncontaminated and unsplit by political entities:

GALACTIA: I don’t know whether Venice is a good republic or a bad one, I


am not political –
SUFFICI: Me neither, what about my –
GALACTIA: The moment you go in for politics, you cavil, you split up the
truth – […] I go from my belly. Yes or no. And when I show meat sliced, it is
meat sliced, it is not a pretext for elegance. Meat sliced. […]
SUFFICI: I think you are, for an artist, rather coarse.
GALACTIA: Coarse for an artist? It’s an artist’s job to be coarse. Preserving
coarseness, that’s the problem (30).

What Suffici implies with coarseness in this dialogue is bullheadedness on behalf of Galactia

by which she turns a blind eye to the political reputation of the Republic of Venice; and by

elegance, Galactia means the decorum the artists of the time are expected to follow by the

political and religious officials. In addition to this, Barker gives voice to his concerns about

the criticism of art in his time based on the question of originality and the source of inspiration

through Rivera’s mouth when she says: “You cannot try to be original. Either you are or you

are not, surely? […] The critic is afraid of the artist and envies her power. She is ashamed of

what she secretly believes to be an inferior gift, that of exposition. So instead of serving the

artist, she humiliates her” (31-32). It seems more than a coincidence for Barker to create a

critic character and to express his ideas about criticism of art through her mouth, as he himself

as an artist has been severely confronted by the critics of his time. Brown contends that “it is

unarguably the case that there has been, for some years, a virtual consensus among the

leading theatre critics in London where hostility to Barker’s theatre is concerned” (2013:96).
200

For this reason, Barker uses Rivera as a self-critical art critic to express his feelings about

criticism of art in general.

Very much like the other authoritative characters like Stalin, Lenin and Churchill in

the previously-discussed plays, Doge Urgentino in Scenes from an Execution represents the

governmental attitude towards art in a time when the authority is in need of a means to

propagandize the party’s political agenda. As he is unable to change Galactia’s mind about

her representation of the carnage rather than the victory in the Battle of Lepanto, Urgentino

decides to commission Carpeta with the job of painting the victory, as the painter’s ‘egg’ is

easier to tap to give it the most favourable shape. The Doge is aware of the powers of art to

change the perspectives of the common man and he attributes a duty to art to sustain the

authority of the dominant party. In his dialogue with Carpeta he confesses that “art is opinion,

and opinion is the source of all authority” (44). Barker obviously forms an analogy here

between the Doge’s attitude and the attitude of the government of his time towards the power

of art which culminates in excessive use of official censorship in order to secure the

reputation of the ‘party’. Barker admits that governmental intervention in art has always been

a reality, but it falls on the shoulders of the individual artists that they have to keep their art

clean. In this respect, Galactia in the play stands for the real life playwright whereas Carpeta

turns out to be a symbol for the political dramatists of Barker’s time who make an instrument

of their art for the sake of political, moral and financial convenience. This is evident in the

play in the scene where Urgentino openly admires and, perhaps, envies Galactia’s artistic

talents and superior will power in comparison to Carpeta’s easy-going morality. Urgentino

says: “She is under no influence but her own will, she has by her perseverance – and possibly,

perversity – achieved a following, she has a school of sorts, and she is brilliant” (45). As

discussed before, Barker attributes no duty to the artist except the one to himself, and Galactia
201

is the ultimate example of this kind of artist with “her fierce determination to stay true to

herself” (Oberon Editors, 2013) as indicated on the back cover of the play. In opposition to

her, Carpeta is ready to open up his artistic skills for political servitude and do “what – the

circumstances – require” (46) for him to be a ‘well-accepted’ artist, even if not a great one.

Barker, in this respect, comments on the qualities that make art great in opposition to those

that make art important once more.

After a long struggle with Galactia’s ideals as an artist, Urgentino comes to the

conclusion that it must be a mental disorder that prevents Galactia “satisfying the aspirations

of her customer” (51), because he believes that political sidedness has always been a natural

quality of all artistic endeavours. After the completion of her painting, Galactia reminds the

governmental and religious officers that she is not concerned with the meaning behind the

painting, as the meaning of art is subjective and changeable from one viewer to another. “No.

I am not going to give you the satisfaction of proving me wrong. If the surface of the painting

is my territory, the back of it is yours. You are specialists in arguments. I hate arguments”

(57). These words are quite reminiscent of what Barker argues in an interview given to the

Guardian in which he says: “I have contempt for messages in the theatre. I’m not trying to

influence anyone” (in Lawson, 2017: n.pg). Very much like Galactia, Barker attributes no

arguments to his art and refuses to play with the conscience of his audience for the sake of

not betraying his art. He gives full authority to the audience in the meaning-making process

despite a set of external anticipations to draw his plays within the borders of the expected

morality. Galactia faces a similar compulsion from the Cardinal Ostensibile who warns her

about “the little matter of public morals” (57) drawing attention to her way of dressing and

unsupported breasts. Galactia responds to the Cardinal’s accusations of loose morality

protesting that her art will never serve anybody’s moral code: “You can’t let someone say –
202

on the back of the canvas – all your principle is actually dirt, and stench, and matted buttocks

floating in the sea. I shall have to be broken in some way” (58). The play draws to a

conclusion with Carpeta realizing that offering his artistic skills for political or moral

expediency is a very dishonourable act and rejecting the Doge’s and the Cardinal’s

commission in the place of Galactia. Rivera comments on this event saying: “It is an offence

against art to flatter minor artists with projects they are not equipped to handle –” (64).

Consequently, Barker’s Scenes from an Execution offers a great number of elements

which ensure its classification as historiographic metadrama thanks to its concern with a very

famous historical event, the Battle of Lepanto, even though all the characters in the play are

imaginary with obscure allusions to real historical personages. The play approaches the

historical event from a different angle, offering an artist’s point of view to the long-debated

political event and describing it as a mere butchery rather than a victory on behalf of the

Venetians or a loss on behalf of the Ottomans. In this respect, the play turns into a

historiographic representation, rather than a historical one, with the playwright’s attempts to

subvert historical data with his omissions, additions and interpretations. Barker’s version of

the Battle of Lepanto is obviously reinforced with his readings about the event along with his

research on the Venetian society of the time, and his authentic historical account stands as an

equally valid claim to historical reality as much as any other historical document written on

the same event. Besides such historiographic elements, Barker’s Scenes from an Execution

displays a deep metadramatic structure with its references and allusions to real historical

events as well as to itself as a historically-concerned fictional account. The characters in the

play voice Barker’s own ideas about such issues as responsibilities of the artist, functions of

art, governmental censorship of art and the artist’s struggle against the totalitarian authority.

Through such self-references, Barker comments on the nature of his own play, or dramatic
203

art in general, and makes a criticism of the contemporary dramatists’ political and moral

involvements, which contradicts Barker’ view of art as a functionless endeavour. Galactia’s

painting represents Barker’s drama, as both stand firm against all political and moral

impositions to remain true to art itself. In all these respects, Barker’s Scenes from an

Execution appropriately qualifies as an example of the subgenre historiographic metadrama.

3.5. Brutopia and Art in the Face of Censorship

Written in 1989, Barker’s Brutopia: Secret Life in Old Chelsea is a television play

first published as a part of the playwright’s collected plays in 1993. Very much like Barker’s

other historically-concerned plays, the play explores the struggle of an artist against the

authority, this time both familial and governmental, before a very familiar historical

background. The play revolves around the story of Sir Thomas More, the English statesman

and author known basically for his famous Utopia, and King Henry VIII known for his

establishment of the Anglican Church and scandalous love affairs leading to the former’s

execution. However, Barker’s account centres on More’s historically-unremarkable daughter

Cecilia in her attempts to write a counter-text to her father’s famous book and protect her

self-dependence as a free-spirited female writer against the king’s efforts to dominate her

both intellectually and sexually. Wilcher describes this play, along with many others, as a

reflection of Barker’s “preoccup[ation] with the conflict between individual impulse and

society’s internal and external mechanisms of control” (1993:177). This preoccupation turns

into a rewriting of a historical incidence from an artist’s point of view and a commentary on

political, religious and aesthetic issues.

Barker divides Brutopia into two acts titled “The Sickness” and “The Recovery”,

respectively. The first act opens with King Henry VIII observing the moon with his telescope
204

along with trying to draw Sir Thomas More, his councillor, into silly discussions with a dirty

language while Cecilia, More’s daughter, makes ironical outlines of her imaginary society

called Brutopia as it appears in her dystopian work of the same title. The discussion is

interrupted by a yell from a heretic named Bonchope who is kept in a garden gaol with his

mouth gagged, and King Henry hysterically makes fun of the prisoner before turning on to

More to ridicule his sexual abstinence due to his religious views. After the king’s departure,

More opens up his intentions in writing Utopia to his wife who, in return, foreshadows that

his daughter Cecilia has been on to something that will unsettle More’s composure. The third

scene brings together More and Cecilia for the first time in the play in which the latter does

not miss any chance to express her disaffection with her father while he is seen trying to find

a common ground with his daughter. In the following scene, Cecilia meets a servant woman

who discusses with her the nature of the civil war in Brutopia and how the guilty poor kill

the rich as well as each other.

In the meantime, More approaches his other daughter Meg with whom he is obviously

in better terms; but he makes a mess of their little game and idiotically bites the blood out of

his daughter’s hand, refusing to apologize afterwards due to his ego-centric personal

principles. More, then, appears in an intriguing discussion with a doctor who claims to be

‘the’ doctor from the former’s Utopia while Cecilia engages in a hot debate with Roper,

More’s biographer and Meg’s husband, concerning the essence of love and marriage which

she approaches with a great deal of cynicism. Cecilia’s critical stance continues when she

meets her mother and Bertrand, a young and rich merchant whom the mother introduces to

Cecilia as a suitor, in the garden during one of her contemplations on her imaginary state,

Brutopia.
205

On the other hand, Sir Thomas More becomes obsessed with the doctor and what he

has to tell about Utopia from which he claims to have come. The image of Utopia drawn by

the doctor is no different than Cecilia’s imaginary dystopian society; as contrary to what

More has imagined in the first place, bodies overflow the jails in Utopia while the rest of the

people are the jailors. More, then, meets King Henry, who appears to him in disguise in the

middle of the night and recites to him one of his latest love poems; as More does not respond

enthusiastically to his emotions and suffering, King Henry foreshadows to his men that

“More’s death is on him like a growth” (152). Scene twelve presents More in a debate, first

with his daughter Meg and then with a workman, on private property as the ultimate source

of all crimes. But eventually, More manages to bring the issue back to his genius and

superiority of knowledge. A similar dialogue passes between More and Daker, a scholar who

is commissioned by More himself to write a preface to Utopia, in which More leaves the man

with no other option, but to write a preface that ‘praises the work to the skies’ with ‘the

highest compliments’. Soon enough, More is again approached by King Henry, again in

disguise, who appears to have lost his temper after reading the former’s Utopia. The king

uncordially scolds More for not including the politics and ‘the parties’ into his imaginary

ideal society and comes straightly to the main point that he wishes to get divorced from his

wife and that More has to find the proper political and religious means to legitimize it. He,

then, forces his councillor to sign a bill that justifies his wishes; and when responded with

hesitation, the king threatens More with fall from favour and eventual death. After the king’s

departure, the irreparable More seeks consolation in his two daughters and finds Meg at his

elbow while Cecilia denies him that.

The second act, titled “The Recovery”, begins with the offstage cry of the frantic

More foreshadowing his death soon while Bertrand impregnates an unemotional Cecilia in
206

the garden. In her imaginary kingdom and among her fellow Brutopians that hide in the maze

in the garden, Cecilia gives the reader a summary of the contemporary, dystopian Britain, or

British utopia (Brutopia) in this case, in which anger is an “expression of deepest desire”

(164) and funerals are loved while murders are frequently indulged, including killing of

children. On the other hand, Alice and Meg despairingly follow More into a rustic prison cell

where he wishes to stay for the rest of his numbered days. In her visit to her father’s cell,

Cecilia pours out her heart and lovelessness to her father who responds to her with a similar

indifference. In the following scene, the servant dresses Cecilia all in black for the funeral

and Holbein, the painter, arrives to draw her portrait with an image of the utopian Doctor’s

head on her lap. At that moment, Cecilia notices a handwritten book down in the Doctor’s

pocket which turns out to be the Doctor’s own description of a just society, his version of

Utopia; and Cecilia concludes that “in every prison the victims of one system scratch plans

for the torture of the next – on walls, in blood” (170).

In the meantime, Alice and Bertrand discuss Cecilia’s indifference and instability

towards the latter before Alice notices the Common Man passing by in More’s massive otter

coat which she herself bought for her husband as a gift. Learning that More has given it away

willingly, Alice easily gives into Bertrand’s wooing. Having torn her portrait without a

second thought, Cecilia rushes out to the garden where she comes across King Henry and

asks him to use his authority to licence her book, Brutopia, without a prior enquiry by the

censor. She tries to seduce the king into signing the book for publication and giving her father

a quicker death; but the king retires after a long struggle with his libidinal urges. In the

following scenes, Bertrand is seen on his knees expressing his love for Cecilia while she,

soon after that, again presents her body to King Henry who has her beaten by the Louts. In

the meantime, More passes through an assembly of family members and servants lined up on
207

the terrace to bid him farewell with the exception of Cecilia, and he walks away, leaving a

whole household in grief and gloom. Cecilia, on the other hand, sits in a quiet place in the

garden with Bertrand who tends to her bruises and scars. At that moment, Alice appears in a

delirious mood and expresses her hatred for and envy of her daughter as well as resentment

for her indifference to her father. Then, the scenes are interrupted by a bookish statement

announcing the execution of Sir Thomas More on 6th July, 1535.

The sixteenth scene of the second act presents Cecilia and King Henry kissing and

embracing intimately in the garden, which is now in a neglected state. She constantly asks

the king about the promised publication of her book and gets delayed of a satisfactory answer,

as he openly views art as a means of fouling the common people. Cecilia protests that her

father’s Utopia now swamps every corner of the city, to which the king gives an answer that

summarizes the authority’s view of art: “Literature must make us love ourselves. That is its

function. And yours don’t” (182). He also compares More’s book with hers in that the former

draws a ‘luminous’ democracy that praises Man while Cecilia implies that it was Henry

himself who censored her father’s writing. When Henry finally withholds his consent from

publishing the book otherwise, Cecilia accepts to be his mistress. Next time, Cecilia appears

in the maze, ‘as if prepared for birth’, and Ann Boleyn pays her a visit to threaten her not to

aspire for stealing her place on the throne and in Henry’s bed. However, it is revealed from

their discussion that Boleyn has mistaken Cecilia for Meg who apparently was another

mistress of Henry’s. Before the queen leaves, Cecilia asks her for help regarding the

publication of her book if she wants the body of her husband just for herself. After giving

birth to a baby girl, Cecilia tells the Servant that she does not intend to keep the baby and

wants to give her to a ‘better parent’, The Common Man, in order to keep her away from the

‘convictions’ of the Utopian ideas hovering around.


208

In the following scene, Cecilia is informed by a printer that her Brutopia has been

published in 700 copies after the receipt of an anonymous payment. When her mother asks

for one copy of her book, Cecilia refuses to give her one, as she plans to deliver the books to

the readers arbitrarily by leaving them on a highway. She also refuses to sell the books in

bookshops, as she thinks those places are prisons for books. Suddenly, Bertrand shows up in

a fury to reprimand Cecilia about the fate of their baby and the latter learns about his affair

with her mother. As Cecilia tosses her books over the garden wall into the street, some nuns

approach her to take her to a convent/asylum before King Henry comes in to save the gagged

Cecilia from the nuns only to enjoy her helplessness himself. As Cecilia attempts to speak

up, Henry turns away and leaves her to the mercy of his two executioners.

As to the origins of the title of the play, “Brutopia” obviously refers to Thomas

More’s Utopia both in terms of form and content, Cecilia’s treatise being a political treatise

in the form of an anti-utopia. However, Brutopia is not a term coined by Barker for his play,

as it appears in a number of Walt Disney’s Donald Duck tales as a fictional land named out

of the combination of the words ‘brute’ and ‘utopia’ (Erickson, 1989:1). Moreover, Don

Rosa, the creator of the Donald Duck character along with many others, confesses in an

interview that he based Brutopia and the Brutopians on the USSR and the Russian citizens

of the time (DeRider, 2012:n.pg.). Whether Barker himself was aware of the earlier use of

the word or not, this association makes sense when Barker’s interest in the history of the

Soviet Russia, as exemplified in his previously-discussed plays No End of Blame and The

Power of the Dog, is taken into consideration. In addition to making a critique of the Soviet

Russia with the corruption going on in its final years, Barker also forms analogies between

this imaginary land and contemporary Britain, as the word also sounds like a derivation from

‘British Utopia’. In Lamb’s opinion, “Barker clearly views the utopian project as an attempt
209

to postulate the ideal society, a literature of the final solution to the problem of communal

life, which extends from Plato’s Republic and Augustine’s City of God to Marx and the

totalitarian tendencies of contemporary liberal-humanism against which his own aesthetic is

directed” (2005:160). The England depicted in the play under Henry’s rule is reminiscent of

the country in the present time under Thatcher’s rule in terms of the governmental oppression

and self-ordainedness prevailing, England as a land ruled by a ‘brute’, hence ‘brute-opia’.

Barker’s Brutopia displays a very strong historical consciousness with the

implementation of historical data in captions along with historiographic additions of the

playwright’s imagination. Barker builds the entire play on a much-debated set of historical

events concerning the English royalty right at the beginning of a new era. The play is set in

the London of the early 16th century right after the publication of Sir Thomas More’s Utopia

as indicated by the caption inserted by Barker: “Thomas More published Utopia in 1516. It

describes the perfect society. His daughter CECILIA composed Brutopia in secret. Only now

has the text been discovered” (1993:131). With the insertion of such bookish historical

information throughout the play, Barker reinforces the realistic historical background of the

play only to distort the inside story below each caption. Even though the story behind More’s

execution is to everybody’s knowledge, the details of this incident are still a mystery

unravelled only in fictional works that make up much of the known history. Barker

emphasizes this fictitious side of written history by making up dialogues between such

historical characters as King Henry VII, Thomas More and Cecilia More among many others,

giving voice to such originally minor historical characters like Cecilia over other bigger

figures.

In almost all historical representations, Sir Thomas More is depicted as a devout man

with a strong sense of humanism; however, the image Barker draws for him is one of pride
210

and ambition, as he is an ego-driven man devoted to his personal interests in the play. Barker

includes a character to the original historical story, the Doctor who claims to be coming from

Utopia described by More in his political satire. In More’s dialogue with the Doctor, the

former says: “I like the way you keep your hat on it lends you an authority you otherwise

might lack, and never meeting my eyes is calculated also, don’t forget you are dealing with

a genius” (140). Similarly, the image of Henry VIII as a “lustful, egotistical, harsh, and

insecure king” (Ives, 2006:28-36) in the history books is juxtaposed with Barker’s image of

the king as an instable, hot-tempered and unheroic man. In the play, the king is also depicted

as an intellectually inferior man when he is confronted with Cecilia who bargains her body

for the publication of her book. She calls the king “goodness-stricken” (176) in a world too

harsh to be realistic. Cecilia, on the other hand, appears in the play as an unconventionally

free-spirited woman with an artist’s superior imaginative capacities, which is uncommon of

a time and place like 16th century England.

The play follows a very neat chronological timeline very much in the manner of

chronicles popular in the time in which the play is set. However, what differentiates the play

from those historical accounts is that Barker narrativizes the events in such a manner that the

historical account adopts a more fictional outlook, serving the playwright’s purposes to

display the narrative, subjective nature of historical representation. The play covers a period

of time from the publication of Utopia through Henry VIII’s announcement of his wish to

divorce his wife to More’s execution and even more within the framework of a very neat

cause and effect relationship, drawing heavily on historical accounts (Marius, 1984:153,466).

In doing so, Barker forms a parallelism between that period in English history and his own

time to draw attention to the fact that history repeats itself even though the means change in

time. Weissengruber indicates that “Barker instead presents a dramatic arena for the
211

dissection of an important figure in British and European History, for the purposes of

indicating Utopia’s entanglement in the political network of its day, and utopianism’s status

in contemporary political reality” (1998:264). Even though More draws the picture of an

ideal nation in his political satire, Cecilia’s image of the anti-utopia has a stronger claim to

represent contemporary England with an authoritative government that manifests itself in

terms of the violation of freedom of speech and thought, censorship of art and intimidation

by the use of political power.

The historical background is a façade for Barker to voice his critique of the political

situation in England towards the end of the century. Through Cecilia’s asides in which she

comments on the present situation and gives information about Brutopia, Barker draws a very

realistic image of contemporary Britain like: “Brutopia is a republic, but with a monarch. The

population is literate, but there are no books. […] Complain away, complaint is the music of

Brutopia! […] Do you want everybody getting knowledge? What would you do with it?

Upset Brutopia!” (145). Barker, here, criticizes the false idea of civilization and culturedness

of the British people of his time who choose to remain silent against a ‘monarch’ who is a

law unto herself. In her dialogue with her suitor Bertrand, Cecilia seems to be enjoying the

freedom of expression in the fictional world she creates for herself in which the unsayable

becomes sayable. Her Brutopia turns into an instrument for her, and for Barker, to voice

her/his criticism of the corruption in the social and political institutions. As a prototype based

on England, Brutopia is described by Cecilia as a place ruled by “the worst swine”, in which

the citizens suffer appallingly, beauty is used as an instrument of torture, perfection is

eradicated by a committee of eradicators and only one person has a vote while the others

must applaud (146-147). She also comments on the common Brutopians, giving voice to

Barker’s thoughts about his own people, saying: “The Brutopians were never silent except
212

when sentimental. And how sentimental they could be! They held childbearing in such high

esteem, whilst frequently killing children! And funerals they loved, whilst indulging

murder!” (166).

All the references to documented historical events and famous historical personages

also contribute to the metadramatic character of the play with an eye to Hornby’s designation

of real-life reference as a metadramatic variety. In this respect, the use of characters like Sir

Thomas More, Cecilia More, Henry VIII and Anne Boleyn is a strongly metadramatic

element, especially when the familiarity of the audience to such historical figures is taken

into consideration. Seeing these historical figures represented on the stage clearly breaks the

dramatic illusion on behalf of the audience and functions as a means of alienation in the

Brechtian sense. Similarly, the use of historical events like the publication of More’s Utopia

being a political and literary breakthrough, King Henry VIII’s divorce from his wife being a

religious and political scandal and the execution of More being a long-debated symbol for

abuse of political power strengthens the metadramatic effect of the play, as the target

audience is expected to know the actual chronology of these events and, consequently, the

ending of the play, which breaks the dramatic illusion more and takes the dramatic experience

on behalf of the audience to an upper intellectual level.

The fact that Brutopia is built primarily on another literary work, Sir Thomas More’s

Utopia, adds more to the metadramatic essence of the play, considering Hornby’s designation

of literary reference as another metadramatic variety. The play opens with a direct reference

to the publication of More’s Utopia and the story takes its shape in the protagonist’s attempts

to write a counter-text to it and get it published. Barker takes this allusion one step further

with direct quotations from More’s political satire, in which the work is discussed and

defended by the author himself in opposition to the accusations by his own daughter and the
213

king. In his discussion with the Doctor who is actually from Utopia, More defends his ideal

society as follows:

THE DOCTOR: I’m from Utopia.


MORE (with a laugh): There are no doctors in Utopia!
THE DOCTOR: Why, is there no sickness?
MORE: How could there be, there is no disharmony.
THE DOCTOR: I promise you, my hands are full.
MORE: With what? Childbirth? And please look in my eyes it is discourteous
to stare at the ground, clear evidence to me you never set foot there, it is a
society of honest men, without rank, shame or hierarchy (140).

In the actual Utopia, More similarly describes his ideal society as one of harmony and

prosperity in which those people who are in themselves good and honest sustain a perfect

communal life (1997:48). In a similar instance, More discusses the nature and functions of

his book with the king, in which the latter questions the former regarding the political

orientation of the book. The dialogue between the two goes as follows:

MORE: You are frank today. Fortunately I am not without endorsement.


Today I had a letter from Erasmus of Rotterdam fulsomely applauding its
ambition and congratulating me on the maturity of my Latin style. He
welcomes me into the –
KING HENRY: Shh –
MORE: Hallowed circle of the discourses on faith and government, I –
KING HENRY: Shh! (MORE contains himself. Pause.) Where’s the politics?
MORE: I replaced it with goodwill. (HENRY looks at him.)
KING HENRY: Where’s the parties?
MORE: Parties? (He is patient.) There are no parties because there are no
contradictions. And no contradictions because there are no separate interests
– (160).

These words allude to the second chapter of More’s Utopia in which he makes a description

of the division of labour among Utopians and says: “There are no taverns, no alehouses, nor

stews among them, nor any other occasions of corrupting each other, of getting into corners,

or forming themselves into parties; all men live in full view” (42). Besides More’s Utopia,

Barker’s Brutopia also draws heavily on another literary text, Robert Bolt’s A Man for All

Seasons (1960), a play which draws the picture of a very honourable and devoted Thomas
214

More in the final days of his life. Rabey observes that, in Brutopia, Barker constantly evokes

Robert Bolt’s play, subverting the latter’s treatment of Thomas More’s noble struggle against

the king and turning his image of the ‘Christian Saint’ upside down (2009:53-54). Barker’s

evoking of Bolt’s play goes even so far as to including the same additional characters like

Roper and The Common Man along with the central characters like Sir Thomas More and

Henry VIII. Moreover, Barker alludes to Bolt’s play in the thirteenth scene of his play in

which More says to himself “It’s Spring, my season!” (155). Rabey adds that “Brutopia

demonstrates a philosophical brilliance and a memorable sense of surprisingly disclosing

dramatic space, and is a purposeful subversion of both Bolt’s A Man for All Seasons and the

aesthetically related conventions of the television historical costume drama against which it

was originally conceived to play (2009:57). To the audience who is already knowledgeable

about these other literary texts, the play breaks the dramatic illusion and alienates the

audience into a more critical reception and understanding.

Barker’s Brutopia is also strongly metadramatic in the way it treats its subject matter

as a means of self-commentary, self-criticism and self-awareness. Very much like in the

previously-discussed plays, Barker uses a work of art as the central motif in his play to voice

his thoughts regarding issues like functions of art, responsibilities of the artist and ethics of

artistic representation in the face of official censorship mechanisms. Barker’s protagonist is

again an artist, Cecilia, depicted in her very struggle against political and religious authority

along with the social and familial prejudices against her being a female writer. Rabey argues

that “Barker renders the first, strongly nihilistic, energy in the dramatic form of More’s less

favoured daughter, Cecilia, who expresses her alienation through her secret composition of

a counter-text to her father’s central work. She develops the vision of her imaginary

alternative” (2009:55). In her journey into her own imaginative potentials, Cecilia is
215

confronted first by her father Thomas More, who resents her attempts to disconfirm her

father’s ideals of a perfect society with the image of her own anti-utopia, and then by the

king who abuses his institutional powers of censorship in return for sexual pleasure. Cecilia’s

experiences as an artist echo Barker’s own struggle against the mechanisms of official

censorship and a generation of political playwrights who betray the essence of art for the sake

of causing a sensation.

In the thirteenth scene of the play, Barker displays how politics and personal interests

intervene in the way works of art appear, get published and advertised by rather arbitrary

means in a dialogue between More and Daker, a scholar who is writing a preface to the

former’s Utopia. More openly commands Daker to write positive remarks for the book:

“Only the fullest praise, only the highest compliment, for Utopia’s a book commanding

reverence and obsequy. Admit its greatness and stop shuddering for fear someone will call

you creep, be honourable and praise it to the skies, how else can great work make its mark

but by the unreserved devotion of its addicts?” (156). While the preface of Utopia is being

written according to the demands of the author, the king himself demands More to change

the content of the book with respect to the potential gainings of the crown. On the other hand,

when Cecilia completes her anti-utopia, the first thing she does is to take her book to the king

to get it published without prior reference to the censor:

CECILIA: License my book!


KING HENRY: Refer it to the censor.
CECILIA: But you’re the monarch.
KING HENRY: I don’t appoint officials so I may do their work for them.
CECILIA (smiling): No, stuff all that, just –
KING HENRY: Authority is a pyramid, whose apex rests on functions no
matter how obscure –
CECILIA: You just put H there, on the cover. (He declines to take it.)
KING HENRY: You are weak on constitution and what a mouth you have. It
burns. It quarrels with the air. What book is it? I love brilliant women.
CECILIA: Mine.
216

KING HENRY: Speak some. I love learning from a woman’s mouth. Men
detest intelligence in skirt but I swell on it (173).

Here, Barker shows how governmental censorship has always troubled artists in the history

very much like in Barker’s own time when debates regarding the abolishment of official

censorship are still hot. Both in history and the present time, artists have always been

dependent on the governmental opinion to determine if a work of art is morally and politically

appropriate to be published. Barker emphasizes the necessity of a complete freedom of art

from all political and moral concerns and attributions of a function to art on the basis of

usefulness and propaganda. In the play, King Henry refuses to publish Cecilia’s book on the

excuse that it ‘fouls’ mankind with its excessively gloomy ideas. He argues that “literature

must make us love ourselves. That is its function. And yours [Cecilia’s] don’t” (182). Cecilia

protests that her book is superior to her father’s in every possible aspect and it controverts

every argument her father proposes by putting reality up against idealism. The dialogue

between the two turns into a means for Barker to express his belief that art has no duty

whatsoever towards anything else including society, humanity or political parties, but only

to itself.

Towards the end of the play, Cecilia is forced into being the king’s mistress to get her

book published; however, the king refuses to license the book anyway and Cecilia decides to

resort to Anne Boleyn for the publication of her book in exchange for giving the king up to

his wife. In order to persuade Boleyn for the licensing of the book, Cecilia makes a speech

in which she compares her artistic creation to desire and gives the upper hand to the former.

However, she is aware that an artist is inevitably bound to the prior permission of the

powerholders for publication no matter how high-quality the essence of the work is. Cecilia

says: “I have this work, you see, which your husband calls inhuman. Get it licensed. You

know the bishops. Get them to pass it for the printer. Do it for me” (186). Barker here uses
217

Cecilia as a mouthpiece to express his critical view about the standards and criteria by which

the value of a work of art has been determined in the history of mankind and the unfair

enslavement of art to political and religious authority. Just as Cecilia’s work has to please the

king and the bishops to get a licence in the 16th century England, literary works have to please

one political party or the other to stay free of the censor in Barker’s time. It has been one of

the biggest motivations in Barker’s career to liberate his drama from ‘functions’ of any kind

and fight against the domination of political drama among his contemporaries. He shares

Cecilia’s concern that bookshops and printing houses are prisons for books, as these places

have been functioning like places for castration of the greatest ideas.

Consequently, Barker’s Brutopia proves a rather appropriate play to be classified as

historiographic metadrama with an eye to its subject matter taken directly from a well-known

and widely-discussed historical event, involving real historical characters with their faces

that don’t appear in historical accounts. The play offers the point of view of a female artist,

Sir Thomas More’s daughter Cecilia, who is named but remains silent in all historical

accounts. Barker portrays such famous historical figures like the king Henry VIII, Sir Thomas

More and Anne Boleyn through the spectacles of Cecilia and presents an image of 16th

century England which is not only scandalous, but also corrupt up one side and down the

other. In this respect, Barker’s play turns out more to be a historiographic representation than

a historical one with the playwright’s intentions to twist historical ‘reality’ with additions of

imaginary characters and fabricated speeches which appear side by side with bookish

historical quotations. Barker’s version of the story of Thomas More and Henry VIII acquires

an equally valid historical referentiality compared to any other historical document written

on the same subject. Along with such a historiographic nature, Barker’s Brutopia also

possesses a very well-structured metadramatic essence with real-life references to historical


218

events and personages like Thomas More and Henry VIII, literary references to More’s

Utopia and Bolt’s A Man for All Seasons and self-references by means of Cecilia’s struggle

against official censorship and impositions of functions on her book. Cecilia’s voice as a free-

spirited artist in the play echoes Barker’s own ideas regarding issues like functions of art,

responsibilities of the artist and governmental censorship of art. Through such self-

references, Barker offers his commentary on the nature of his own drama, or dramatic art in

general, and criticizes his contemporaries in their political involvement in art. Cecilia’s book

Brutopia stands for Barker’s play of the same name in that both works defy political and

moral involvement with an aim not to betray the nature of art. In all these respects, Barker’s

Brutopia appropriately qualifies as an example of the subgenre historiographic metadrama.


219

CONCLUSION

Howard Barker’s work has drawn critical attention from various points of view for

the last few decades, ranging from examinations of themes like violence, promiscuity and

death to his use of technical and stylistic elements like asides, poetic language and the

question of anti-catharsis in his plays. These studies have generally dwelt on or drawn from

Barker’s own formulation of his drama as “Theatre of Catastrophe” and have wholeheartedly

accepted his plays as representatives of this self-crafted genre of the playwright. Among such

studies on Barker’s drama, the most well-known are Charles Lamb’s Howard Barker’s

Theatre of Seduction in which he deals with the challenge the playwright’s plays pose to the

contemporary theories of performance and calls for a necessity to come up with new

techniques in the performance of Barker’s ‘irrational’ plays. Even though Lamb admits that

Barker’s early career, during the seventies, “developed initially along lines similar to a

number of other ‘political’ dramatists such as Brenton, Hare and Churchill” (1997:1), he

acknowledges the fact that, from the eighties on, Barker’s interest shifted “away from the

political to the personal, from the stereotype to the individual” (1997:2), which brought about

the need to abandon the cliché ways of acting and performance. David Ian Rabey’s Howard

Barker: Ecstasy and Death, on the other hand, concentrates on the air of death pervading

Barker’s plays with special emphasis on the themes like violence, pain and revenge especially

in his rewritings of earlier drama. He describes Barker not only as one of the greatest living

dramatists of England, but also as “a major philosophical theorist on the possibilities of

theatre, and on the theatricality of the human mind, body and soul in situations of extremity”

(2009:3). However, in his analysis of Barker’s major plays published and performed in the

course of three decades at the turn of the century, Rabey does not go beyond the assumption
220

that Barker’s work is adequately categorized by the playwright himself as ‘theatre of

catastrophe’ and must be evaluated within this framework only.

However, the present study differs extensively from the mentioned research on

Barker’s plays in that it has approached a selection of his plays, all written during the 80s,

with an aim to subvert the central principles of the playwright’s assumptions in his

formulation of “Theatre of Catastrophe” and read the plays in question in opposition to his

claims that his drama purposefully excludes any kind of functions and that it never seeks to

give messages of any kind. It also responds positively to the fashion of reading the plays of

contemporary playwrights within the framework of the recently-designated dramatic genre,

historiographic metadrama, with special emphasis on the playwrights’ interest in history as

a subject matter and metadramatic elements defining their works’ technical and stylistic

character. Among such studies, one of the most prominent ones is Richard Knowles’

“Replaying History: Canadian Historiographic Metadrama” in which he examines the

development of this genre in Canadian drama through selected works by Rick Salutin, James

Reaney and Sharon Pollock. Similarly, Philip Zapkin’s “Compromised Epistemologies: The

Ethics of Historiographic Metatheatre in Tom Stoppard’s Travesties and Arcadia” examines

the selected plays by Stoppard with the same motivation.

With this objection in mind and the same method in hand, this study has given a

detailed history of the philosophy and theory of historiography from its earliest practices in

the ancient times considered as a means of recording the truth to the contemporary

understanding of it as mere subjective narration of past events. The background for

historiography presented here simply follows its transformation from a scientific activity into

a fictional one, from Hegel to Hayden White, from a belief in its promises into a decisive

disbelief in its stories. The loss of faith in historical representations has found reflection in
221

the literature of the modern times too, and Barker’s drama is no exception to that. Barker

responds to the developments in the philosophy of history by means of an attempt to write

alternative historical accounts with an aim to subvert a long tradition of well-accepted

historical knowledge.

After setting the background for historiography, the discussion moves on to the birth

of the theory of metadrama and refers basically to the two seminal, defining books written

on the subject, namely Lionel Abel’s Metatheatre: A New View of Dramatic Form and

Richard Hornby’s Drama, Metadrama, and Perception. Both critics draw attention to similar

elements, or varieties in Hornby’s terminology, that make a dramatic work metadramatic or

metatheatrical, which eventually refers the play to itself, its own dramaticality and

theatricality. Hornby’s list of metadramatic varieties- including play-within-the-play,

ceremony-within-the-play, roleplaying-within-the-role, literary and real life reference and

self-reference- sets the rules for metadramaticality in plays and Barker’s selected plays have

proven considerably fruitful in the employment of such elements. Once such technical and

contextual elements appear against the background of a historical subject in a play,

historiographic metadrama takes shape in practice whose theory has been built upon Linda

Hutcheon’s formulation of historiographic metafiction. In the naming and discussion of this

new genre, Alexander Feldman’s book titled Dramas of the Past on the Twentieth Century

Stage: In History’s Wings comes to the fore along with Knowles’ previously-mentioned

article.

Barker’s self-crafted dramatic genre “Theatre of Catastrophe”, in his own

understanding, marks a breakage with the long tradition of cathartic tragedies, in Aristotle’s

terminology, and political drama, drawing mainly on the Brechtian vein. Even though

Barker’s earliest plays have a strong awareness of contemporary political agenda, his later
222

plays seem to divert strongly from this preoccupation into a deliberate aloofness from

political and moral issues, especially after the publication of his own dramatic theory in two

separate books and numerous articles and the establishment of his own theatre company

named ‘The Wrestling School’ at the end of the 80s. Barker draws a red line between his

drama and mainstream political drama, or the art of theatre and simply the theatre, or the

catastrophic theatre and the humanist theatre in that the former never indulges in playing

around with the audience’s ideological and moral values unlike the latter. Barker refers to

the political theatre dominant in 70s and 80 in England as theatre of marketing, which tailors

ready-made meanings for the audience’s consumption, whereas his catastrophic tragedies

force the audience into a ruthless struggle with the play and the actors for meaning which

they acquire individually rather than collectively. He views political and moral involvement

in arts as a betrayal to the essence of art and an insult to the audience’s capacity of generating

their own beliefs. Barker proudly claims that his theatre shows rather than tells, and pursues

no didactic purposes whatsoever.

Among other elements that define Barker’s ‘Theatre of Catastrophe’ are a

preoccupation with death and the feeling of catastrophe accompanying it which find the most

appropriate environment in the tragic form. In all of Barker’s catastrophic tragedies, the air

of death pervades the play by means of war, catastrophe or death threats in a chaotic

atmosphere. What Barker deems tragic here is not the Senecan understanding of tragedy with

bloodshed and mutilation dominating the stage, but a nobler form of it in which the characters

never compromise on their dignity even on the verge of death. He believes that the tragic

form restores beauty to death and returns poetic lyricism to the otherwise banal human

speech. He attributes no functions to the tragic form, as death functions only as a means of

finalizing all other contexts, and contends that the pain generated by tragedy is, and has to
223

be, felt individually by the individual members of the audience, as a confrontation with death

addresses subjective memories in each individual.

Barker also sets the rules for the use of language in his catastrophic tragedies and

aims to go back to the elaborate, rhetorical and poetic language of the classical Greek and

Roman tragedies to save it from everyday banality and aggrandize drama to the level of

poetry. He seems well aware that such a speech pattern will bring about certain obscurity of

meaning on behalf of the general theatre-going public and welcomes it wholeheartedly with

the belief that tragic experience matters more than understandability. Barker believes that

easy digestibility of meaning in arts leads to a uniformity of interpretation, which he describes

as ‘chanting banal tunes in unison’, and this reduces arts to the level of preaching. As opposed

to this, Barker professes that each member of the audience comes to experience the theatre

with their own personal backgrounds and must react individually to the play and, thus, come

up with their own moral or ideological interpretations. The audience must never identify

themselves with the actors on the stage very much in the way that the actors must not identify

themselves with the characters they are portraying in order to keep up with the critical

distance throughout the performance. Barker’s catastrophic tragedies never intend to arouse

feelings like pity and fear in the audience, or any other feelings for that matter, as these plays

are not written to correct or to change individuals in a better way, but to shake them out of

their habitual consumerism of meaning.

Even though Barker categorizes his plays as “Theatre of Catastrophe” which

manifests itself as a politically, morally and aesthetically functionless kind, approaching his

plays from a different, opposite angle also proves rather fruitful with an assumption that

ideology lurks behind every artistic endeavour, especially in Barker’s time when political

drama has been dominating the stages for decades. In his plays written during the 80s, Barker
224

touches upon similar issues from a similar point of view and his choice of political historical

subjects seems more than coincidental when his own political views regarding the Thatcher

rule in England are taken into consideration. In other words, Barker’s plays written in the 80s

turn into a masterful and veiled critique of the so-called Thacherite liberalism and

conservativism at the time and the ongoing official censorship activities despite the

abolishment of the Lord Chamberlain’s Office with the passing of the Theatres Act in 1968.

Thatcher’s premiership for a little more than a decade in England between 1979 and 1990

has been constantly referred to as a modern dictatorship because of her debatable actions and

decisions leading to an increasing number of unemployed citizens, her aggressive attitude

against labour and trade unions, imposition of heavy taxes and limitations of freedom of

expression and thought. Thatcher’s government has also been mentioned a number of times

in engagement with practicing censorship on media and literature in the name of the good of

the nation. Atlas, for instance, mentions Thatcher’s government taking initiatives “to menace

the independence of broadcasting; to threaten academic freedom in the universities and

schools; to tolerate abuses committed in the name of national security” (in Goldstein

2001:348). It is also a very well-known fact that the Thatcher government appealed to

censorship on British news media during the military campaign on the Falkland Islands in

1982, forcing the media “not to speculate, and not to divulge operations or readiness states”

(Cultice, 1990:41). The passing of the Public Order Act from the parliament in 1986, banning

dissident riots and meetings in the name of ‘public order’, and the Official Secrets Act in

1989, banning certain publications in the name of protecting confidential information, led to

the announcement of Charter 88, a left-wing magazine’s proclamation in which many

intellectuals complained about ‘the intensification of authoritarian rule’ under Thatcher’s

regime. With this bad reputation in mind, Thatcher’s rule in England has been viewed as a
225

continuation of the totalitarian regimes having dominated European nations in the first half

of the century.

In his five plays written during the 80s, No End of Blame, The Power of the Dog, Pity

in History, Scenes from an Execution and Brutopia, Barker deals with such issues as

censorship and violation of freedom of thought and expression as natural consequences of

totalitarian regimes and forms a parallelism between the cases of political oppression in

European history and the time in which he is writing the plays. In all five plays, Barker takes

his audience to a journey in the pages of history to the incidents of governmental oppression

of thought and speech in order to voice his own ideas regarding the political atmosphere in

contemporary England. Along with such political parallelisms, Barker also expresses his

views about ethics and functions of art and responsibilities of artists in the face of public

morality with his use of protagonists who are all artists depicted in the middle of their

struggles against authority figures. Using these characters as a mouthpiece, Barker finds a

chance to voice his aesthetic views and criticism regarding the literature produced in his time,

as well.

In his 1981 play No End of Blame, Barker chooses the two decades between the two

world wars for the time and such European countries as Russia and England for the setting

of his play. This choice does not seem to be a coincidence when the attempts at political

intervention in arts in the play are taking into account in parallel with the situation in Barker’s

time. The protagonist of the play, a cartoonist named Bela, is constantly troubled by the

authorities in terms of the ‘sides’ his art takes. First Lenin’s and then Churchill’s attempts to

politicize Bela’s cartoons are quite reminiscent of the politicization of British drama in the

course of four decades until Barker’s time. Similarly, such attempts to ban some of Bela’s

cartoons criticizing Lenin after the First World War and Churchill during the Second World
226

War also allude to the political intervention in arts and freedom of speech and thought during

the 80s in England. In this respect, it is possible to say that Barker models Bela on himself in

the latter’s strong stance against such attempts at making his art a means of political

propaganda. However, the parallelism between the political outlook in the play and the

political atmosphere in Barker’s time proves that Barker’s No End of Blame is not genuinely

aloof from political functions and that he uses his art as a means of political criticism of some

sort. Similarly, Barker’s portrayal of Bela as an artist responsible only to truth and artistic

beauty reflects the playwright’s aesthetic stance along with his beliefs regarding ethics of art

and duties of an artist. In all these respects, reading the play as historiographic metadrama

brings about a new interpretation that contradicts Barker’s formulation of “Theatre of

Catastrophe” as a functionless kind of dramatic genre.

Similarly, in his other 1981 play The Power of the Dog, Barker touches upon such

issues as the enterprises of a totalitarian regime and censorship of art, centring his play on

the character of Joseph Stalin in the Kremlin as the setting right after the Second World War.

He simply parodies the political agenda of the time through the eyes of, first, a clownish

comedian named McGroot and, secondly, a photographer named Ilona. In the opening scene

of the play in which Stalin and Churchill come together to share out the unclaimed lands after

the war, Barker reveals the collusive agreements signed behind the scenes under the pretext

of public interest. With regard to the parallelism between the Stalinist totalitarian regime in

Russia and the Thatcherite ‘regime’ in England, Barker gives a very sound political message

concerning the enterprises of the Conservative Party which are manifested in reducing any

counter-views to silence. Stalin’s confession that he censored artists to stop them from

‘singing out of tune’ and the army officer Sorge’s attempts to censor the letters of other

soldiers along with Ilona and Victor’s photographs stand for the governmental intervention
227

in arts in England after the war, which Barker draws attention to in a critical manner. Besides,

Ilona’s views about the responsibilities of the artist to her art along with the art student

Matrimova’s project of WHOLEFILM as an impartial kind reflect Barker’s own aesthetic

views and functions like an artistic manifesto on behalf of the playwright. In all these

respects, Barker can be said to have used his play to convey his messages in political and

aesthetic matters along with answering questions about artistic ethics and morality. Such an

interpretation of the play as historiographic metadrama runs afoul of Barker’s formulation of

“Theatre of Catastrophe” as a potentially functionless dramatic genre.

Written in 1984, Barker’s Pity in History explores similar political and aesthetic

subject matters to the two previously-discussed plays, taking the audience to a journey to one

of the bloodiest times in English history, The English Civil War, through which Barker

comments on the social and political chaos in the contemporary England. The mid-17th

century is a notorious period of instability in English history due to political and religious

dualities and Barker’s protagonist, a sculptor named Gaukroger, struggles against political

and religious officials over the motivations and nature of his artistic endeavours in the way

the playwright himself struggles against governmental censorship and political as well as

moral impositions on his art. However, Barker’s artist protagonist in this play needs some

reassurance from an art patron named Venables before he realizes the true power of his art,

as he seems ready to sell his artistic skills for a handsome amount of money at the beginning

of the play. The attempts of the parliamentarian officer Sergeant Boys and Chaplain Croop

to use Gaukroger’s art as a means of political propaganda are quite reminiscent of the

Thatcher government’s attempts to smother up any contradictory voices by abusing their

institutional power. Very much like the 17th century London, the contemporary London is

the symbol of political dichotomy and instability in which the institutional power is abused
228

by the self-ordained, so-called democratic, Conservative Party. Barker’s choice of the

Cromwellian period to allude to the Thatcherite government does not sound like a

coincidence when the conservative character and violent nature of the two parties are taken

into consideration. Along with the political commentary he offers in the play, Barker also

expresses his aesthetic views through the relationships between the sculptor and his

apprentice as well as between the sculptor and his patron. Barker, in a way, defends his drama

along with all artistic activities against such accusations as art being useless ornamentation

and vulgarism and pleads his distrust in historical representations in reflecting historical

realities. Such a political and aesthetic consciousness contradicts Barker’s formulation of

“Theatre of Catastrophe” as a completely functionless kind even though the play possesses

other catastrophic elements like its concern with death, poetic language and obscurity of

meaning.

Barker’s Scenes from an Execution, written in 1984, has been the most well-known

and most frequently-staged catastrophic tragedy of the playwright with its masterful

reinterpretation of a famous historical event, the Battle of Lepanto, and its strong-willed,

free-spirited female protagonist, a painter named Galactia. In terms of Barker’s approach to

the historical subject matter, the play does not differ much from the others discussed in this

study, as Barker aims to draw attention to the universality of political and moral limitations

imposed on artists throughout the history of mankind. Through Galactia’s struggle against

the political and religious authorities of the 16th century Venice regarding freedom of artistic

representation, Barker voices his criticism of the contemporary government’s violation of

freedom of expression and censorship of art and press. By favour of Galactia’s resistance to

such political and moral impositions, Barker alludes to his own struggle to keep his drama

aloof from the mainstream tradition of political theatre. In this way, he expresses his views
229

regarding responsibilities of an artist towards society or art itself and discusses the issues of

artistic ethics and morality. In addition, Barker also subverts the historical understanding of

Battle of Lepanto being a glorious victory over the Ottoman Empire, depicts the battle as

mere butchery like any other battle fought in the history. In doing so, he claims that

representations of such milestone historical events in history books are nothing more than

subjective narratives masquerading as historical reality. In all these respects, Barker’s Scenes

from an Execution does not meet the requirements of a categorization as a politically, morally

and aesthetically functionless play as formulated by the playwright within the framework of

“Theatre of Catastrophe”.

Finally, Barker’s 1989 play Brutopia: Secret Life in Old Chelsea is of a similar

character in terms of its interest in the validity of historical representation and its critical

approach to political oppression of any kind, which is the ultimate enemy of artistic creativity

and freedom of thought. Taking its subject matter again from English history, particularly

from the famous incident that happened between King Henry VIII and Sir Thomas More over

the former’s desire to get a divorce leading to the latter’s execution, the play turns into a

critique of the abuse of political power for the derivation of personal benefits under the

pretence of public prosperity. Giving voice to a historically marginalized character, Thomas

More’s youngest daughter Cecilia who is depicted as the strong-willed author of an anti-

utopia against her father’s famous political satire, Barker draws attention to the possibility of

writing alternative histories just with a little touch of imagination and disavows the validity

of historical accounts written always by the powerful. Besides, Barker forms a parallelism

between the 16th century England and his own time in terms of the violation of freedom of

speech and thought along with governmental censorship of art. He uses his protagonist

Cecilia as a mouthpiece to express his ideas concerning an artist’s responsibilities towards


230

his society, himself and art itself along with the ethical and aesthetic concerns behind every

artistic endeavour. Barker’s depictions of Henry VIII as a despotic ruler and Thomas More

as an obsessive politician and uncaring father are quite telling about what he bears in mind

about the politicians of his own time. In all these respects, Barker’s Brutopia turns out to be

a politically, morally and aesthetically concerned piece of writing, which makes it unfit for a

classification as functionless “Theatre of Catastrophe”.

Consequently, the criteria determined by Barker in his designation of his own

dramatic genre are observed to be fulfilled by his selected plays only to a certain extent. Even

though Barker’s “Theatre of Catastrophe” possesses unique characteristics compared to the

drama of his contemporaries, his plays bear strong resemblances to the work of those political

playwrights of the Brechtian tradition in terms of the motivation behind the action being

political criticism and moral obligation. His selected plays all written in the 80s have several

characteristics in common not only in terms of their subject matters, but their stylistic aspects

as well. No End of Blame, The Power of the Dog, Pity in History, Scenes from an Execution

and Brutopia are all concerned with well-known documented historical events, each

depicting moments of political unrest and catastrophe under the rule of totalitarian regimes.

By means of these historical references, Barker not only invalidates the referentiality of

historical representations, but also offers his criticism of the political enterprises of his own

time like censorship of art, violation of freedom of expression and government’s aggression

in both internal and external affairs, although these plays differ from the mainstream

Brechtian political drama in their use of elaborate poetic language, obscurity of meaning and

concern with dividing the audience rather than uniting them under one political and moral

code. In all these respects, Barker’s “Theatre of Catastrophe” must be incorporated into the
231

mainstream tradition of political drama even though his political and moral preoccupation is

more indirect, his criticism is more veiled and his main concern is an aesthetic one.
232

BIBLIOGRAPHY

PRIMARY SOURCES

Barker, Howard. Arguments for a Theatre. Manchester and New York: Manchester UP.,

1993. Print.

---. Brutopia. Collected Plays Vol.2.London: Calder & Boyers, 1993, pp. 127-195. Print.

---. Death, the One and the Art of Theatre. London and New York: Routledge, 2005. Print.

---.No End of Blame. Collected Plays. Volume 1. London and New York: John Calder and

Riverrun Press, 1990, pp. 73-132. Print.

---. Pity in History. Women Beware Women / Pity in History. London and New York: J.

Calder and Riverrun Press, 1989, pp.63-92. Print.

---. The Power of the Dog. London and New York: John Calder Ltd. and Riverrun Press,

1985. Print.

---. Scenes from an Execution. London: Oberon Books, 2013. Print.

SECONDARY SOURCES

Abel, Lionel. Metatheatre: A New View of Dramatic Form. New York: Hill and Wang, 1963.

Print.

---. Tragedy and Metatheatre: Essays on Dramatic Form. New York: Holmes & Meier, 2003.

Print.

Acton, John Emerich Edward Dalberg. Essays on Freedom and Power. Boston: The Beacon

Press, 1949. Print.


233

---. A Lecture on the Study of History. London: MacMillan and Co., 1911. Print.

Alied, Amani. A Desacralisation of Violence in Modern British Playwriting. Manchester:

Manchester UP., 2014. (Unpublished PhD Dissertation).

Ankersmit, Frank R. and Hans Kellner. (eds). A New Philosophy of History. Chicago:

University of Chicago Press, 1995. Print.

Anon. “Englands Wolfe with Eagles Claws, The Cruel Impieties of Bloud-thirsty Royalistst,

and Blasphamous Anti-Parliamentarians, under the Command of that Inhumane Prince

Rupert, Digby, and the Rest. Wherein the Barbarous Crueltie of our Civil Uncivil

Warres is Briefly Discovered”. London, 1646.

Ashley, David. History without a Subject: the Postmodern Condition. Oxford: Westview

Press, 1997. Print.

Bann, Stephen. The Inventions of History: Essays on the Representation of the Past.

Manchester and New York: Manchester University Press, 1990. Print.

Barker, Howard. “An education in Living Poetry, Vivid and Violent: Interview with Nina

Rapi”. Howard Barker Interviews 1980-2010: Conversations in Catastrophe. ed. Mark

Brown. Bristol and Chicago: Intellect Ltd. 2011, pp. 175- 180. Print.

---. “Interview with Howard Barker by Nick Hobbes: From the programme for Scenes from

an Execution”. Dundee Rep, April 2004. Retrieved 14.12.2016.

http://www.thewrestlingschool.co.uk/twspages/barker.html#BarkerInterview

---. “Interview with Simon Trussler and Malcolm Hay”. New Theatre Voices of the Seventies.

Eyre Methuen, 1981. Print.


234

---. “On naturalism and its pretensions”. Studies in Theatre and Performance, 27:3, 2007, pp.

289-293. Print.

Barthes, Roland. “The Discourse of History”. The Rustle of Language. Trans. Richard

Howard. New York: Hill and Wang, 1986. pp. 127-140. Print.

Belsey, Catherine. The Subject of Tragedy: Identity and Difference in Renaissance Drama.

London: Methuen, 1985. Print.

Berkhofer, Robert F. Beyond the Great Story: History as Text and Discourse. Massachusetts

and London: Belknap / Harvard University Press, 1995. Print.

Bevir, Mark, Jill Hargis and Sara Rushing. Histories of Postmodernism. London: Routledge,

2007. Print.

Bodek, Richard. Proletarian Performance in Weimar Berlin: Agitprop, Chorus, and Brecht.

Columbia: Camden House, 1998. Print.

Boireau, Nicole. Drama on Drama: Dimensions of Theatricality on the Contemporary

British Stage. Basingstoke: Macmillan, 1997. Print.

Boucher, Bruce. Italian Baroque Sculpture. London: Thames & Hudson (World of Art),

1998. pp. 134–42. Print.

Braudel, Fernand. The Mediterranean and the Mediterranean World in the Age of Philip II.

Vol. 2. New York: Harper & Row Books, 1973. Print.

Brown, Mark. “Barker, criticism and the philosophy of the ‘Art of Theatre’”. Howard

Barker's art of theatre: Essays on his plays, poetry and production work. Eds. David

Ian Rabey and Sarah Goldingay. Manchester: Manchester UP, 2013, pp. 94-104. Print.
235

Byatt, Antonia S. On Histories and Stories: Selected Essays. London: Vintage, 2001. Print.

Canary, Robert H. and Henry Kozicki. (eds). The Writing of History: Literary Form and

Historical Understanding. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1978. Print.

Carr, Edward H. What is History? London: Penguin, 1990. Print.

Collingwood, Robin George. The Idea of History. London: Oxford University Press, 1967.

Print.

Conkin, Paul and Roland Stromberg. Heritage and Challenge: The History and Theory of

History. Wheeling: Forum Press, 1989. Print.

Cooper, Barry. The End of History: An Essay on Modern Hegelianism. Toronto: University

of Toronto Press, 1984. Print.

Costa, Maddy. “Howard Barker: 'I don't care if you listen or not'”. The Guardian. 1 October

2012. Retrieved 9 April 2017 from

https://www.theguardian.com/stage/2012/oct/01/howard-barker-scenes-execution

Coster, Will. “Massacre and Codes of Conduct in the English Civil War”. The Massacre in

History. Eds. Mark Levene and Penny Roberts. New York: Berghahn Books, 1999.

Print.

Cox, Jeffrey N., Larry J. Reynolds. New Historical Literary Study. New Jersey: Princeton

University Press, 1993. Print.

Cultice, William W. “Thatcher Government Censorship of British Media in the Falkland

Islands Campaign: A Model For Future United States Military Employments?”.

Unpublished Research Report. Alabama: Air University Press, 1990. Retrieved 07 June

2017 from http://www.dtic.mil/dtic/tr/fulltext/u2/a234516.pdf


236

Currie, Mark. Metafiction. New York: Longman House, 1995. Print.

Curtin, Adrian. “Howard Barker’s theatre: wrestling with catastrophe.” Studies in Theatre

and Performance. 35:3, 2015, pp. 260-262. Print.

Dawkins, Richard MacGillivray. “A Picture of the Battle of Lepanto”. The Journal of

Hellenic Studies. Vol. 50. Part 1. 1930. pp. 1-3. Retrieved 07 May 2017 from

https://www.jstor.org/stable/pdf/626158.pdf

DeRider, Mathias. “An Interview With Don Rosa”. 19 July 2012. Accessed 26.05.2017. E-

source. https://reviewordie.wordpress.com/2012/07/19/an-interview-with-don-rosa/

De Saussure, Ferdinand. Course in general linguistics. Third Edition. Trans. R. Harris.

Chicago: Open Court Publishing Company, 1986. Print.

De Toledo, Camille. Coming of Age at the End of History. Brooklyn: Soft Skull Press, 2008.

Print.

Donohue, Laura K. “Regulating Northern Ireland: The Special Powers Acts, 1922-1972”.

The Historical Journal. Vol. 41, No. 4. 1998, pp. 1089-1120. Retrieved 06 June 2017

from

http://people.stfx.ca/x2010/x2010rcj/Regulating%20Northern%20Ireland%20The%20

Special%20Powers%20Acts,%201922-1972.pdf

Dunbabin, J.P.D. The Cold War: The Great Powers and Their Allies. London and New York:

Routledge, 2014. Print.

Erickson, Byron. Ed. Walt Disney's Uncle Scrooge: A Cold Bargain. (Gladstone Comic

Album Series, No. 24). California: Gladstone Pub Ltd. 1989. Print.
237

Ermarth, Elizabeth. “Sequel to History”. The Postmodern History Reader. Ed. Keith Jenkins.

London: Routledge, 1997, pp. 47-62. Print.

Feldman, Alexander. Dramas of the Past on the Twentieth Century Stage: In History’s

Wings. New York and London: Routledge, 2013. Print.

Fischer, Gerhard and Bernhard Greiner. The Play within the Play: The Performance of Meta-

theatre and Self-Reflection. Amsterdam and New York: Rodopi, 2007. Print.

Foucault, Michel. The Archaeology of Knowledge and the Discourse on Language. Trans. A.

M. Sheridan Smith. New York: Harper and Row, 1976. Print.

---. The Order of Things. London and New York: Routledge Classics, 2005. Ebook.

http://beautifuldata.metalab.harvard.edu/2014/pdfs/readings/Foucault_The-Order-of-

Things.pdf

Francis, Penny. “Interview with Howard Barker”. Contemporary Theatre Review. 9:4, 1999,

pp. 37-39. Print.

Geodakyan, Gevorg. “Խաչատրյան Արամ [Khachatryan Aram]”. Soviet Armenian

Encyclopedia. Volume 5 (in Armenian). Yerevan: Armenian Encyclopedia Publishing,

1979, pp. 18–20. Print.

Goldstein, Robert Justin. Ed. Political Censorship. Chicago and London: Fitzroy Dearborn

Publishers, 2001. Print.

Gombrich, Ernst Hans. “Celebrations in Venice of the Holy League and of the Victory of

Lepanto” Studies in Renaissance and Baroque Art presented to Anthony Blunt on His

Sixtieth Birthday. London: Phaidon, 1967. Print.


238

Gritzner, Karoline. “Poetry and intensification in Howard Barker's theatre of plethora”.

Studies in Theatre and Performance. 32:3, 2012, pp. 337-345. Retrieved 13 May 2017

from http://dx.doi.org/10.1386/stap.32.3.337_1

Groves, Peter Anthony. Sacred Tragedy: An Exploration into the Spiritual Dimension of

the Theatre of Howard Barker. Diss. Warwick: The University of Warwick Press,

2014. Unpublished PhD Dissertation.

http://wrap.warwick.ac.uk/72932/1/WRAP_THESIS_Groves_2014.pdf

Haste, Cate. Keep The Home Fires Burning. London: Penguin Books, 1977. Print.

Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. The Philosophy of History. Trans. J. Sibree. Kitchener:

Batoche Books, 2001. Print.

Holmes, Frederick. The Historical Imagination: Postmodernism and the Treatment of the

Past in Contemporary British Fiction. Victoria: English Literary Studies, 1997. Print.

Hornby, Richard. Drama, Metadrama, and Perception. London and Toronto: Associated

University Presses, 1986. Print.

Huang, Hao. (Ed). Music in the 20th Century. Vol 2. Michigan: M.E. Sharp, 1999. Print.

Hutcheon, Linda. “Historiographic Metafiction: Parody and Intertextuality of History” in

Patrick O'Donnel and Robert Con Davis, eds. lntertextuality and Contemporary

American Fiction. Baltimore and London: John Hopkins University Press, 1989, pp.

3-32. Print.

---. Narcissistic Narrative: The Metafictional Paradox. London and New York: Routledge,

1984. Print.

---. A Poetics of Postmodernism: History, Theory, Fiction. London: Routledge, 1988. Print.
239

Irvine, Lindesay. “Interview with Howard Barker”. Guardian. 6th December 2012. Retrieved

05 March 2017 from

https://www.theguardian.com/arts/audio/2006/dec/06/culture1426

Ives, Eric. “Will the Real Henry VIII Please Stand Up?”. History Today. 56 (2): 28–36, 2006.

Print.

Jameson, Fredric. The Political Unconscious: Narrative as a Socially Symbolic Act. London

and New York: Routledge Classics, 2002. Print.

Jenkins, Keith. Rethinking History. New York: Routledge, 1991. Print.

---. “Editor’s Introduction: For Postmodern Histories”. The Postmodern History Reader. Ed.

Keith Jenkins. London: Routledge, 1997, pp. 33-35.Print.

Kastan, David Scott. Shakespeare after Theory. New York: Routledge, 1999. Print.

Keenan, Brigid. Damascus: Hidden Treasures of the Old City. London: Thames & Hudson,

2000. Print.

Kellner, Hans. “Introduction: Describing Re-Descriptions”. A New Philosophy of History.

Eds. Frank Ankersmit and Hans Kellner. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995,

pp. 1-18. Print.

Kissinger, Henry. Years of Renewal. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1999. Print.

Knowles, Richard Paul. “Replaying History: Canadian Historiographic Metadrama.”

Dalhousie Review. 67.2/3. Spring/Fall, 1987, pp. 228–243. Print.

---. The Theatre of Form and the Production of Meaning. Toronto: ECW Press, 1999. Print.
240

Lamb, Charles. Howard Barker’s Theatre of Seduction. London and New York: Routledge,

1997. Print.

---. 1rrational Theatre: The Challenge Posed by the Plays of Howard Barker for

Contemporary Performance Theory and Practice. Warwick: University of Warwick

Press, 1992. Print.

---. The Theatre of Howard Barker. London and New York: Routledge, 2005. Print.

Langer, Susanne K. Feeling and Form. New York: Scribners, 1953. Print.

Laven, David and Elsa Damien. “Empire, city, nation: Venice’s imperial past and the

‘making of Italians’ unification to fascism”. Budapest: Central European University

Press, 2013. Retrieved 17 May 2017 from

http://eprints.nottingham.ac.uk/2160/1/Empire_City_NationinBerger%26Miller.pdf

Lawson, Mark. “Howard Barker: ‘I have contempt for messages in plays. I'm not trying to

influence anyone’”. The Guardian. 20 January 2017. Accessed 24.04.2017. E-

source. https://www.theguardian.com/stage/2017/jan/20/howard-barker-interview-

in-the-depths-of-dead-love#img-1

Lenin, Vladimir. Lenin’s Collected Works. 2nd English Edition. Moscow: Progress

Publishers, 1965. Print.

Levey, Michael. Painting at Court. London: Weidenfeld and Nicholson. 1971. Print.

London Gazette, The. “Supplement to the London Gazette, 1 September, 1914”. Retrieved.

28.02.2017. https://www.thegazette.co.uk/London/issue/28887/supplement/6968

Löwith, Karl. Essays in the Philosophy of History. Chicago: Northwestern University Press,

1966. Print.
241

Lyotard, Jean-François. “The Postmodern Condition.” The Postmodern History Reader. Ed.

Keith Jenkins. London: Routledge, 1997, pp. 36-38. Print.

Marius, Richard. Thomas More: A Biography. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 1984. Print.

Megson, Chris. “Howard Barker and the Theatre of Catastrophe.” A Companion to Modern

British and Irish Drama: 1880-2005. Ed. Mary Luckhurst. Oxford: Blackwell

Publishing, 2006, pp. 488-498. Print.

Mıyares, Ruben Valdes. “Introduction: ‘The Facts Being Fixed About the Policy’”. Culture

and Power: The Plots of History in Performance. Eds. Ruben Valdes Mıyares and Carla

Rodriguez Gonzalez. Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing, 2008.

Print.

Middleton, Peter and Tim Woods. Literatures of Memory: History, Time, and Space in

Postwar Writing. Manchester: Manchester UP., 2000. Print.

More, Thomas. Utopia. London: Dover Publications, 1997. Print.

Morrill, John, Brian Manning and David Underdown. “What Was the English Revolution?”.

History Today. 34. 1984, pp. 14-32. Retrieved 16 May 2017 from

http://www.blackwellpublishing.com/content/BPL_Images/Content_store/Sample_Ch

apter/0631208089Sample/Gaunt0631208089.pdf

Mosto, Andrea Da. I dogi di Venezia: con particolare riguardo alle loro tombe. Ed.

Ferdinando Ongania. Venice: Unknown Publisher, 1936. E-source.

http://bsa.ve.ismar.cnr.it/fedora/repository/ismarbsa:ve00255/PDF/ismarbsa_ve00255

.pdf

Munslow, Alan. Deconstructing History. Second Edition. London: Routledge, 2006. Print.
242

Onega, Susana. Telling Histories: Narrativizing History, Historicizing Literature.

Amsterdam-Atlanta: Rodopi, 1995. Print.

Oppermann, Serpil. Postmodern Tarih Kuramı: Tarih Yazımı, Yeni Tarihselcilik ve Roman.

(Postmodern Theory of History: Historiography, New Historicism and the Novel).

Ankara: Phoenix Yayınevi, 2006. Print.

Overholser, Geneva. “The Editorial Notebook; Dear Pravda”. New York Times. (May 12,

1987). Accessed 2 March 2017. E-source.

http://www.nytimes.com/1987/05/12/opinion/the-editorial-notebook-dear-

pravda.html?pagewanted=1

Overy, Richard. Why the Allies Won. New York: W.W. Norton & Company, 1996. Print.

Pakula, Hannah. The last empress: Madame Chiang Kai-Shek and the birth of modern China.

New York: Simon and Schuster, 2009. Print.

Plokhy, Serhii. “Remembering Yalta: The politics of international history”. The Harriman

Review. 17(1). 2009, pp. 34-47. Print.

Price, Amanda. The Theatre of Promiscuity: A Comparative Study of the Dramatic Writings

of Wole Soyinka and Howard Barker. Diss. Leeds: Leeds UP., 1995. Unpublished PhD

Dissertation. http://etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/313/1/uk_bl_ethos_251695.pdf

Rabey, David Ian. Howard Barker: Ecstasy and Death: An Expository Study of His Drama,

Theory and Direction, 1988-2008.New York: Palgrave and Macmillan, 2009. Print.

--- and Sarah Goldingay. Howard Barker’s Art of Theatre: Essays on his Plays, Poetry and

Production Work. Manchester: University of Manchester Press, 2013. Print.


243

Read, Christopher. Lenin: A Revolutionary Life. London and New York: Routledge, 2005.

Print.

Richardson, Charles. From Churchill’s Secret Circle to the BBC: Biography of Lieutenant

General Sir Ian Jacob. GBE: Brassey’s, 1991. Print.

Ricoeur, Paul. History and Truth. Trans. Charles A. Kelbley. Evanston: Northwestern

University Press, 1965. Print.

---. Memory, History, Forgetting. Trans. Kathleen Blamey and David Pellauer. Chicago:

University of Chicago Press, 2004. Print.

---. Time and Narrative. Vol.1. Trans. Kathleen McLaughlin and David Pellauer. Chicago:

University of Chicago Press, 1990. Print.

Rosen, Carol. “The Structure of Illusion in Genet's The Balcony.” Modern Drama. 35.4

(December), 1992, pp. 513–519. Print.

Rosenthal Margaret F. The Honest Courtesan: Veronica Franco, Citizen and Writer in

Sixteenth-Century Venice. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992. Print.

Rusinko, Susan. British Drama 1950 to the Present: A Critical History. Boston: Twayne

Publishers, 1989. Print.

Rüsen, Jörn. Studies in Metahistory. Pretoria: Human Sciences Research Council, 1993.

Print.

Saunders, G. “Howard Barker’s ‘monstrous assaults’: eroticism, death and the antique text”.

in: K. Gritzner (ed.) Eroticism and death in theatre and performance. Hertfordshire:

University of Hertfordshire Press, 2010, pp. 144-159. Print.


244

Smart, John. Twentieth Century British Drama. ed. Adrian Barlow. Cambridge: Cambridge

UP., 2001. Print.

Southgate, Beverley. History: What and Why? Ancient, Modern and Postmodern

Perspectives. London: Routledge, 1996. Print.

---. What is History for?. London: Routledge, 2005. Print.

---. Why Bother with History?. London: Longman, 2000, Print.

Tholfsen, Trygve R. “Postmodern Theory of History: A Critique”. Memoria y Civilización.

2, 1999, pp. 203-222. Print.

Tomalin, Claire. Samuel Pepys: The Unequalled Self. London: Viking, 2002. Print.

Tracey, Michael and Christian Herzog. “Thatcher, Thatcherism and British Broadcasting

Policy” Rundfunk und Geschichte. 40 (1-2). 2014, pp. 63–76. Print.

Waugh, Patricia. Metafiction: The Theory and Practice of Self-Conscious Fiction. London:

Routledge, 1984. Print.

Weeks, Stephen. “Stalin's Face: On History and its Deconstruction in Howard Barker's The

Power of the Dog”. Journal of Dramatic Theory and Criticism. Vol. 16. No. 1, Kansas

City: University of Kansas Press, 2001. pp. 59-80. Print.

Weissengruber, Reik Paul. Utopia and Politics in the Theatre of Howard Barker. Diss. The

University of Minnesota, Ann Arbor: UMI, 1998. Print.

White, Hayden. The Content of the Form: Narrative Discourse and Historical

Representation. Baltimore and London: Johns Hopkins UP., 1990. Print.


245

---. “The Historical Text as Literary Artefact”. Narrative Dynamics: Essays on Time, Plot,

Closure and Frames. Ed. Brian Richardson. Columbus: Ohio State UP, 2002, pp. 191-

210. Print.

---. Metahistory: The Historical Imagination in Nineteenth-Century Europe. Baltimore: The

John Hopkins University Press, 1973. Print.

---. Tropics of Discourse: Essays in Cultural Criticism. Baltimore and London: John Hopkins

University Press, 1978. Print.

Wilcher, Robert. “Honouring the Audience: the Theatre of Howard Barker.” British and Irish

Drama since 1960. Ed. James Acheson. London: St. Martin’s Press, 1993, pp. 176-189.

Print.

Witt, Mary Ann Frese. Metatheatre and Modernity: Baroque and Neobaroque. Plymouth:

Fairleigh Dickinson UP, 2013. Print.

Wolk, Herman S. “George C. Kenney: MacArthur's Premier Airman”. in Leary, William M.

We Shall Return! MacArthur's Commanders and the Defeat of Japan, 1942–1945.

Kentucky: Kentucky UP., 1988. pp. 88-114. Print.

Wood, Gordon S. The Purpose of the Past. New York: The Penguin Press, 2008. Print.

Wrestling School, The. http://www.thewrestlingschool.co.uk/ Ret. 19.10.2016.

Yıldırım, Onur. “The Battle of Lepanto and Its Impact on Ottoman History and

Historiography”. Mediterraneo in Armi. Ed. Rossella Cancila. Palermo: Associazione

Mediterranea, 2007. pp. 533-556. Retrieved 13 March 2017 from

http://www.storiamediterranea.it/public/md1_dir/b700.pdf
246

Zapkin, Philip. “Compromised Epistemologies: The Ethics of Historiographic Metatheatre

in Tom Stoppard’s Travesties and Arcadia”. Modern Drama. Toronto: University of

Toronto Press. Vol. 59, Number 3 (Fall), 2016. pp. 306-326. Print.

Zhang, Qing Fei. “Transgender Representation by the People’s Daily since 1949”. Sexuality

and Culture. 18. 2014, pp. 180-195. Retrieved 08 March 2017 from

https://www.researchgate.net/publication/257771237_Transgender_Representation_b

y_the_People's_Daily_Since_1949
247

RECONFIGURATION OF HOWARD BARKER’S THEATRE OF


CATASTROPHE AS HISTORIOGRAPHIC METADRAMA: NO END OF BLAME,
THE POWER OF THE DOG, PITY IN HISTORY, SCENES FROM AN EXECUTION
AND BRUTOPIA
ABSTRACT
Howard Barker’s theatre has always been dealt with as a characteristically distinctive

kind with respect to the playwright’s formulation of his self-crafted dramatic genre called

‘Theatre of Catastrophe’ whose main principles were listed in his two monumental books on

drama and performance, Arguments for a Theatre and Death, the One and the Art of Theatre.

In these treatises, Barker designates a new genre which differentiates itself from the

contemporary mainstream tradition of Brechtian political drama, dominating British stages

for decades, with its non-didactic, anti-cathartic outlook aiming to divert the audience into

individual responses rather than a collective moral improvement. Barker’s plays also stand

apart from the mainstream drama in their concern with the tragic experience rather than the

political and moral message with an elaborate, lyrical language and obscurity of meaning.

However, this study aims to bring a new perspective to the understanding of Barker’s drama,

with specific examples from his five major plays written in the 80s, No End of Blame, The

Power of the Dog, Pity in History, Scenes from an Execution and Brutopia, with an emphasis

on the use of historical subject matter and the choice of characters from among artists. The

plays in question are interpreted within the context of the contemporary dramatic genre,

‘historiographic metadrama’, with an aim to reveal Barker’s veiled political, moral and

aesthetic criticism and, thus, to refute his claims that his ‘Theatre of Catastrophe’ is a

politically, morally and aesthetically functionless and non-didactic kind of drama. Even

though the criteria determined by Barker in his designation of his own dramatic genre are

observed to be fulfilled by his selected plays and Barker’s “Theatre of Catastrophe” possesses

unique characteristics compared to the drama of his contemporaries to a certain extent, his
248

plays bear strong resemblances to the work of those political playwrights of the Brechtian

tradition in terms of the motivation behind the action being political criticism and moral

obligation. It is argued in this study that, by means of historical references, Barker not only

invalidates the referentiality of historical representations, but also offers his criticism of the

political enterprises of his own time like censorship of art, violation of freedom of expression

and government’s aggression in both internal and external affairs, although these plays differ

from the mainstream Brechtian political drama in their use of elaborate poetic language,

obscurity of meaning and concern with dividing the audience rather than uniting them under

one political and moral code. In all these respects, this study concludes that Howard Barker’s

drama has to be incorporated into the mainstream political theatre of his time despite its other

distinctive thematic and technical qualities, with his political and moral preoccupation being

more indirect, his criticism being more veiled and his main concern being an aesthetic one.

Key Words: Howard Barker, Theatre of Catastrophe, Historiographic Metadrama


249

HOWARD BARKER’IN FELAKET TİYATROSU’NUN TARİHYAZIMSAL


ÜSTTİYATRO OLARAK YENİDEN YAPILANDIRILMASI: NO END OF BLAME,
THE POWER OF THE DOG, PITY IN HISTORY, SCENES FROM AN EXECUTION
VE BRUTOPIA
ÖZET
Howard Barker tiyatrosu daima yazarın Arguments for a Theatre (Bir Tiyatro İçin

Argümanlar) ve Death, the One and the Art of Theatre (Ölüm, Bir ve Tiyatro Sanatı) başlıklı

iki büyük eserinde temel ilkelerini belirttiği, kendi yarattığı ve “Theatre of Catastrophe”

(Felaket Tiyatrosu) adı verilen özgün tiyatro türü bağlamında incelenmiştir. Bu eserlerde

Barker, sanatta eğiticiliğe karşı olması ve seyirciyi topluca bir ahlaki gelişmeye

yöneltmektense her bir izleyiciyi kendi bireysel tepkisini geliştirmeye yönelten katarsis

karşıtı yapısıyla uzun yıllar boyunca İngiliz sahnelerine hakim olan Brechtçi politik tiyatro

geleneğinden önemli ölçüde ayrılan yeni bir tür yaratmıştır. Barker’ın oyunları ayrıca politik

ve ahlaki bir mesaj vermeyi reddedişi, bunun yerine trajik deneyimi vurgulayışı ve bunu

yaparken de süslü, şiirsel bir dil kullanıyor oluşu ve anlam belirsizliği ile anaakım tiyatrodan

ayrı bir yerde durmaktadır.

Ancak, bu çalışma, yazarın 80’lerde yazmış olduğu, No End of Blame (Suçlamanın Sonu

Yok), The Power of The Dog (Köpeğin Kudreti), Pity in History (Tarihte Merhamet), Scenes

From An Executıon (Bir İnfazın Portresi) ve Brutopia (Brütopya) isimli beş önemli oyununa

göndermeler yaparak ve yazarın tarihsel konular kullanması ve karakterlerini sanatçılardan

seçmesi üzerinde özellikle durarak, Barker’ın oyunlarına yeni bir bakış açısı getirmeyi

amaçlamaktadır. Söz konusu oyunlar çağdaş bir tiyatro türü olan ‘tarihyazımsal üsttiyatro’

bağlamında, Barker’ın yaptığı üstü kapalı politik, ahlaki ve estetik eleştirileri ortaya

çıkarmak, bu sayede yazarın ‘Felaket Tiyatrosu’nun’ politik, ahlaki ve estetik açıdan işlevsiz

ve eğiticiliğe karşı bir tür olduğu iddialarını çürütmek amacıyla incelenmektedir. Barker’ın

incelenen oyunları kendi yarattığı tiyatro türün kriterlerini bir noktaya kadar karşılıyor ve
250

onun “Felaketler Tiyatrosu” dönemin diğer akımlarına kıyasla eşsiz özellikler taşıyor olsa

da, bu oyunlar dönemin Brehtçi politik tiyatro yazarlarında görülen politik eleştiri yapma ve

ahlaki sorumluluk gibi konular bakımından o akımlarla benzerlik göstermektedir. Bu

çalışmada Barker’ın tarihsel göndermeler yoluyla sadece tarihsel temsilleri geçerliliğini

çürütmekle kalmadığı, ayrıca tarihsel olaylarla kendi dönemi arasında paralellikler kurarak

sanatın sansürlenmesi, ifade ve düşünce özgürlüğünün ihlal edilmesi ve hükümetin iç ve dış

meselelerdeki agresif tutumu gibi dönemin politik gelişmelerine dair bir eleştiri sunduğu

iddia edilmektedir. Yine de bunlara rağmen, Barker’ın oyunlarının Brehtçi politik tiyatrodan

ayrıldığı şiirsel dil, bilinçli anlam belirsizliği ve seyircileri aynı ahlaki ve politik mesaj altında

toplamama isteği gibi konular da vurgulanmaktadır. Bütün bunlar göz önünde

bulundurulduğunda, bu çalışma Howard Barker’ın tiyatrosunun tüm diğer kendine has

tematik ve teknik özelliklerine rağmen, anaakım politik tiyatro içerisine dahil edilmesinin

gerekliliğini vurgulamaktadır. Bu bağlamda tek fark, Barker’ın politik ve ahlaki kaygılarının

daha dolaylı olması, eleştirilerinin daha örtülü yapılması ve temel amacının estetik bir amaç

olmasıdır.

Anahtar Kelimeler: Howard Barker, Felaket Tiyatrosu, Tarihyazımsal Üsttiyatro

S-ar putea să vă placă și