Sunteți pe pagina 1din 8

Voegelin and Dogmatism:

The Case of Natural Law


David A. Nordquest

C o N s m m c NATURAL LAW a conventional body of eternally valid norms from them.


topic rather than part of the philosophy Voegelin does not trace the details of this
of order, Eric Voegelin never wrote sys- alleged derailment, but he does discuss
tematically on the subject. However, his the general character of the Stoics’ “de-
studies on the right by nature and on the formation of symbols,” a process whose
nature of nature pose a radical challenge effects he thinks are still being felt.
to the project of natural law. This chal- Their chief error, as he sees it, was
lenge is clarified by several of his other “the abolition of Plato’s critical distinc-
writings, including the important, post- tion between the dialectical movement
humously published Nature of the Law.’ of thought in t h e Metaxy and t h e
These studies reveal the thoroughgoing mythopoetic symbolization of the divine
character of Voegelin’s search for an a m b i e n ~ e . ”In~ other words, they forgot
undoctrinaire, experiential account of that our partly immanent, partly tran-
personal and social order, and should scendent life involves experiences of the
be of interest to those seeking a more divine that can only be conveyed in allu-
supple natural right. sive speech, such as that used in myth.
Voegelin’s suspicions of natural law When we adopt the more direct speech
stem from his understanding of its ori- of objective propositions to refer to such
gins. As he sees it, the Stoics made a experiences, we may succeed in con-
dogma of natural law by mishandling vincing ourselves that we are dealing
symbols such as the “right by nature,” with things or objects. However, in the
which Aristotle, in particular, had devel- process, we will lose a sense of the living
oped to capture and to communicate his relationship with the divine which is the
experience of fitting participation in real- ultimate source of order. The ability of
ity. Failure to grasp the essential link allusive speech to preserve a fuller open-
between experience and symbol led the ness toward God causes Voegelin to call
Stoics to give the symbols a misplaced myth “an indispensable forming element
concreteness, to manipulate them as if ofthe social ~ r d e r .The ” ~ Stoics, unaware
they intended objects rather than exis- of the problem, treated symbols of our
tential experiences, and to try to derive a participation in a wider reality, such as
~
nous, or reason, “asif they were concepts
DAVID A. NORDQUEST is Adjunct Professor of referring to objects on which the phi-
Political Science and Liberal Studies at Cannon losopher has to advance proposition^."^
University. In Voegelin’s view, they materialized the

32 Winter 1999

LICENSED TO UNZ.ORG
ELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED
divine-human encounter and reduced it sons that, as the first to use the symbol,
to a tonos, or tension conceived of as “the he must have had an experiential basis
property of a material object called the for articulating it, while later users may
psyche.”6 That made our relation with have had the experience in an attenu-
the divine appear static, which allowed a ated form, or, perhaps, not at all. The
fixed natural law to seem plausible. problem is that once a symbol becomes
For a better alternative, Voegelin turns opaque to its experiential source, it tends
to what he thinks the Stoics corrupted, to be used mechanically, producing dog-
to Aristotle’s more existential symbol- mas and logicchopping. Leibnitz’s jest
ism of the “right by nature.” H e finds of aproof “in sixty propositions andstate-
such an inquiry necessary because “the ments” of who by nature should be cho-
revived debate about natural law unfor- sen King of the Poles may serve as a
tunately still suffers from the topical char- reductio ad absurdum of this style.’*
acter of its object, separated as it is from Just as ideas in general lack an inde-
the experience containing its meaning.”7 pendent ontological status, so, Voegelin
Voegelin returns to Aristotle rather thought, does law, including natural law.
than tracing the development of natural In a careful and subtle investigation, he
law ideas, because he denies that ideas shows that law can be understood only
or concepts are meaningful apart from as part of a process by which “a society
their connection to our experience. This brings itself into existence and preserves
view, that symbols and ideas are not itself in ordered e ~ i s t e n c e . ”Recourse
’~
entities in history, was the defining in- to essences, comprehensive aggrega-
sight of Voegelin’s career, the one that tions, and procedural correctness fails
led him to abandon the manuscript of a to make the law fully intelligible. We find
monumental multi-volume history of its character only when we see it as part
political ideas and to write Order and of society’s pursuit of order. That pur-
History instead.8 From this perspective, suit has its source in experiences of a
Voegelin sharply criticizes the philoso- tension in our lives between the larger
pher who has “deformed himself by order of being in which we participate
adopting the belief that the truth of exist- and our own empirical existence. The
ence is a set of propositions concerning “Ought in the ontological sense” is the
the right order of man and society, the term Voegelin uses in The Nature of the
propositions to be demonstrably true Lawtoindicate this tension-and he finds
and therefore acceptable to e ~ e r y b o d y . ” ~ law gaining its normativity from it.I4
This same perspective accounts not only Although natural law is a response to
for Voegelin’s suspicion of natural law, this ontological ought, Voegelin thinks
but also for his critical views of meta- its ideal aim is to resolve the tension for
physics and of propositional revelations good, so we may be spared the uncer-
such as the decalogue.I0On the positive tainties of the Aristotelian right by na-
side, it explains his affection for the con- ture, with its requirement for ever-new
crete philosophy of Plato and Aristotle decisions. Thinking a life open to the
and his high view of myth as avehicle for divine is the only authentic one, Voegelin
conveying experiences of order.” rejects not just this orthat formulationof
Guided by this theory of the primacy natural law, but the entire project of
of experience over symbol, Voegelin ex- capturing in a set of rules the require-
amines the relevant Aristotelian texts to ments for personal and social order.
determine what experience lay behind Voegelin would not, of course, deny
Aristotle’s creation of the symbol of the us all guidance in making our moral deci-
right by nature (physei dikaion). He rea- sions. Forthe purpose, hefindshistotle’s

Modern Age 33

LICENSED TO UNZ.ORG
ELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED
right by nature superior to natural law embodiment in the law of the polis, but
because it places a more proper empha- the attunement t o the divine which pro-
sis on openness and context. Concerning duces law, adapts it and, in a true sense,
context, Voegelin argues that Aristotle is the heart of the law.
conceived of the right by nature as a p Arguing against Voegelin’s method-
plying fully only in the setting of the ological interpretation are passages in
polis, because the“po1is is the manifesta- theRhetoricwhere Aristotle distinguishes
tion of right order.” Because the polis is particular law, which a community de-
an historical and not a universal form of fines for itself, from universal law, which
community, we cannot abstract a law of is based on a notion of right and wrong all
nature true always and everywhere from m e n s h a r e . He quotes Sophocles,
what is right within it : “Given the domi- Empedocles, and Alcidamus to illustrate
nance of the politikon there can be no universal law. Voegelin does not treat
natural law conceived as an eternal, im- this passage, but it appears t o show a
mutable, universally valid normativity right by nature less closely tied to the
confronting the changeable positive polis, more likely to confront the posi-
law.”15Only “resemblances” of the right tive law, and with a more definite and
by nature are possible in other commu- lasting content than his interpretation of
nities-and Voegelin argues that these the Ethics and Politics passages would
are understood by Aristotle “inthe modus suggest. Consider, for instance,Aristotle’s
deficiens.”16Thepoint of Voegelin’sanaly- claim that everyone apprehends this law
sis is that Aristotle wrote primarily of the or rule, “even when they have no mutual
polis, saw justice as more characteristic intercourse nor any compact,” and also
of it than of other associations, and con- the quotation from Empedocles making
ceived of this justice as existential and it “the law for living creatures all.”19
embodied, not as a set of rules that could Aristotle later says that such law per-
be applied in all settings. tains t o “acts such as gratitude t o a bene-
Voegelin argues, too, that Aristotle factor, return of generous treatment, and
does not see the right by nature “con- service t o friends in need,” as well as to
fronting the positive law,” because equity.20He refers to such subjects as
Aristotle viewed the embodied rule of cases of “exceptional goodness or bad-
law among free and equal citizens as ness.”21 However, “exceptional” here
identical with the right by nature, a view means not “infrequent,”but “in the high-
that is sometimes termed conservative est degree.”
or secondary natural law. The actualiza- Asimilar passage in the Ethics remarks
tion of the right by nature in the law of the that some actions and passions have
polis seemed routine to Aristotle since names implying an unconditional bad-
“thejustice of the polis is not positive law ness. Thus, in committing adultery, theft,
in the modern sense but rather essential and murder, “it is not possible ever to be
law,” that is, the part of law in which right.” “Nor does goodness or badness
questions of right order rather than of with regard t o such things depend on
convention are at stake.17Ernest Barker committing adultery with t h e right
clarifies this point in arguing that, for woman, at the right time, and in the right
Aristotle, “law is natural because it is way, but simply to do any of them is to go
moral.”18In Voegelin’s terms, law is the wrong.”22This passage, too, seems to
fruitof the legislators’ existential struggle assume universal moral standards.
toward the right by nature against arbi- James Rhodes makes a strong argu-
trary human willing. What is permanent ment that this apparent endorsement of
about the right by nature is not its present permanent rules is not what it seems,

34 Winter 1999

LICENSED TO UNZ.ORG
ELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED
because Aristotelian morality is a matter correct on fundamentals.Voege1inmakes
of finding the path between excess and astrong case that what lies at the heart of
defect.23In telling us never to consider the right by nature is the “divine es-
committing adultery or murder or theft, sence” which “results in a sensitiveness
Aristotle is not denying the need to search of the soul for injustice in the concrete
our souls before deciding whether to s i t ~ a t i o n . ”Because
~~ ethics is mainly a
have sexual relations, to kill, or to take matter of being “permeable” to the di-
fromanother. Each oftheseacts is proper vine in this way, the spouduios, or mor-
in the proper circumstances, which can- ally mature man, is the “measure” of
not be predetermined by rules. Adultery, things, in the sense that his now sensi-
murder, and theft, however, arenot kinds tive soul will more accurately weigh what
of acts, but counters for excesses in sexual is required by justice. The well-ordered
relations, killing,and taking. Clearly,there soul, and not general rules, provides the
can be no mean in what is already an spoudaios with the guidance he requires.
excess. It seems, Rhodes argues, that Other symbols elaborate this context.
Aristotle is really saying no more than Phronesis, or practical wisdom, which
this: “Thou shalt not kill, take, o r have Aristotle adapted from Plato, is “a knowl-
intercourse at wrong times, involving edge with the help of which man realizes
wrong objects or people, o r with wrong his eu Zen, the specifically human mode
purposes or methods.”24He argues that of permeability for the order of the cos-
there are not in Aristotle specific criteria mos.” It is the “adjustment of the existen-
for determining what the right and wrong tial tension to the ground.” It provides
persons, objects, purposes, and meth- episfeme,a “kind of knowledge,” though
ods are. That depends on the choice of not a knowledge “of principles and de-
the morally mature person, whose expe- rived propositions.”26Also identified with
rience of the divine will make his soul political science by Aristotle, it is a “sci-
more sensitive to what is right. ence of inferior precision,” but vital for its
Enlightening as this is, it is not wholly concrete search for Voegelin sees
convincing. Adultery, after all, is not de- the value of the phronesis symbol par-
fined simply in relation to a mean com- ticularly in its ability to convey a delib-
pared to which it is excessive. It also erative openness that avoids dogmatism.
delimits a class of persons whose social Voegelin’s interpretation is fully in
standing in regard to each other makes harmony with Aristotle’s fundamental
sexual relations always improper. insight that concrete actions possess a
Aristotle does not leave us free to deter- “higher degree of truth” than general
mine the “wrong persons” on a case-by- principles do. Voegelin gives consider-
case basis. Rather, he assumes that there able emphasis to this “almost forgotten
is something inherent in the relation- knowledge of the philosopher, that eth-
ships in question which makes adultery ics is not a matter of moral principles.”28
wrong. In addition, Aristotle’s very down- He does so, it seems clear, because we
to-earth discussion of the virtues sug- must act in a world populated by other
gests he believes the fittingness of hu- beings, not in a world of propositions.
man actions can be considered without Only these beings are affected by our
immediate reference to our relationship actions, so we must be concerned with
to God. Otherwise, one wonders why our effects on them and on ourselves,
references to the divine d o not pervade rather than with whether a description
the Ethics, as they dovoegelin’s analysis. of our projected action falls within a
Still, it seems to me that Voegelin and description contained in a rule. In any
Rhodes, who largely follows him, are case, the transcendence which charac-

Modem Age 35

LICENSED TO UNZ.ORG
ELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED
terizes the divine standard of right and search for such order. He thinks a good
the changing circumstances of our lives philosopher constructing a model first
make the mean a moving target. makes a search which “penetrates to the
There is, indeed, a need for an organi- essence of the Ought in the ontological
zation and rationalization of our moral sense.” From these insights, he then “tries
views. However,Voegelin finds Aristotle’s to sketch the types of conduct that would
project of a model polis a better vehicle be adequate optimally to translate the
for this purpose than “the later ideas truth about order,”which lives in his own
about natural law as the quintessence of soul, “into the practice of society.”
eternal, immutable rules.”29H e seems to Voegelin concludes that “the weight of
favor it for pedagogical reasons. Its em- the work lies, therefore, in the inquiry
bodied character makes its illustrative into the nature of true order.” The model
function clearer, and the fittingness of its poleis are “more than literary devices,
various features to each other teaches but have the character of secondary
that t h e right must b e viewed in elaborations.” They must “not be taken
context.With the model polis, Aristotle as rules with autonomous validity.”32The
shows us the right by nature as the ongo- long inquiry which precedes the model,
ing construction of both a community ten books of the Ethics and six of the
and of political science. Because both Politics, counts the most. Without it, the
the polis and its study are part of our meaning of the model would be obscure.
striving for right order, the very different The models are not “superfluous,”
mechanical, external accounts commonly though. They are an act of judgment on a
given of them are inadequate. society by the philosopher and are “ani-
The detail of Aristotle’s model does mated by the claim that the empirical
raise certain questions, though. Some order should conform more closely to
features are quite remote from any ten- types that will express adequately the
sion toward the divine-having common truth of order.”The models areconnected
dining tables in guard-houses, for ex- t o the empirical society in which the
ample.3oWhile Aristotle does not baldly philosopher writes as “the standards of
prescribe such tables to us, it is not just its n ~ r m a t i v i t y .In
” ~what
~ was apparently
prescriptive form which makes a pre- an earlier passage, Voegelin also refers
scription. Voegelin notes elsewhere that to Aristotle’s model as offering “paradig-
many statutes consist largely of descrip- matic rules.”34Putting the different for-
tions, which descriptions, however, have mulations together, we find that the model
obligatory import.31We may ask, then, polis provides no autonomous rules or
whether aspects of Aristotle’s model do rules with autonomous validity, but that
not function as rules. If they do, the supe- it includes paradigmatic rules and stan-
riorityvoegelin grants to the model polis dards of normativeness for a society.
over natural law as a body of eternal There may be a change of emphasis, but
norms would be lost. there is no real contradiction here. A
Fortunately, Voegelin treats the sta- particular model feature might very well
tus of the model polis at length in The fit in the context of the model, which
Nature of the Law. There he remarks on might itself correct a problem in an exist-
the seeming oddity of philosophers con- ing society. However, the feature could
structing model poleis in societies too be quite inconsistent with conditions in
far gone to permit the embodiment of another community. It would lack au-
right order, but h e takes Plato and tonomous validity. Regarding a paradig-
Aristotle at their word when they repre- matic rule, it is surely to be understood
sent their constructions as part of a as a model for drafting similar laws rather

36 Winter 1999

LICENSED TO UNZ.ORG
ELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED
than as a fixed rule of conduct. this experience, until the contrast be-
From Voegelin’s already quoted char- tween a transcendent God and an imma-
acterization ofthephyseidikaion as “what nent nature is made a gulf. With God and
is right by nature in its tension between nature separated and their continuing
divine immutable essence and human relation ignored, nature’s movement or
existentially conditioned mutability,” we coming-to-be is obscured. It appears full
may infer that the nature in Aristotle’s of “relatively autonomous things,” stuck
“right by nature” is t o be regarded not as in their own static forms, while a tran-
an immanent, autonomous order, but as scendent God keeps to himself.
a realm open to divine order.35Voegelin Voegelin regards this assumption of
seeks the source of closure in the conflict an immanent order of things, or an order
of two conceptions of nature found in of immanent things, as the heart of dog-
Empedocles and dealt with by Aristotle. matism. Against this view he argues that
The first regards nature as a coming-to- all things at every level of being, from
be, the second as form. Voegelin thinks particles of matter to human beings, pos-
that the conflict between them is still sess a transcendence and a “coming-to-
unresolved, and attributes the main diffi- be” which raises them above immanence:
culty to an “emotional b l o c k caused by “Things existingin this world, in addition
the presence of God in our experience of to the order of their autonomous exist-
being.36Elsewhere,h e contends that “the ence and that of their relations to each
encounter between God and man ...can other, also have a dimension of order in
have a dead center of inarticulateness,” relation to the divine ground of being.
of which Paul’s blindness is the leading There are no things that are merely im-
example.37 manent.”40Just as modern theoretical
Whether Voegelin regards the block physics has run into trouble by trying to
in dealing with nature a consequence of neglect the transcendence of matter, so
awe or of an understanding of God as the he thinks ethics has failed in its attempts
imposer of form, is not clear from the to find permanent principles in an imma-
context. However, he believes that view- nent ~ o r l d .For
~ ’ Voegelin their transcen-
ing God as the demiurge has the unfortu- dence puts human beings in continuing
nate consequence of making the formal relation to the divine and supports the
element of nature dominant over the existential tension that leads us to seek
developing part, its coming-to-be. This attunement. We cannot properly avoid
neglect of the movement in being is this tension by making our moral lives a
clearly pronounced in the metaphysics matter of fitting actions to the formulas
of Aristotle’s successors. Such neglect of natural law.
tends to reduce nature and man t o form It is true that Voegelin qualifies our
and fact and therebythreatens the search transcendence by holding that nothing
for order: “If man’s existence were not a in the world, including man, is “merely
movement but a fact, it not only would immanent” and that transcendence is
have no meaning but the question of something “in addition to” the order of
meaning could not even arise.”38 our autonomous existence. In an impor-
For Voegelin,the context for the prob- tant essay on the classical view of rea-
lem of nature is the “primary experience son, he distinguishes seven different lev-
of the cosmos.” We all share this experi- els in the hierarchy of being in which
ence because “the faculties and experi- human beings p a r t i c i ~ a t eIf. ~we
~ are as
ences of man are always present in their immanent a s we are transcendent,
entirety.”39Thinkers gradually sharpen though, one might wonder what is wrong
their distinctions among the elements of with a natural law derived from the sta-

Modern Age 37

LICENSED TO UNZ.ORG
ELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED
bilities in nature, from the semi-autono- insights gained by a theory of the nature
mous orders Voegelin admits. It may be of man into the language of obligatory
true that Voegelin finds no level of being purposes.” As an example, he says that
completely autonomous, but one might we might translate Aristotle’s insight that
suppose that to the extent autonomy the bios theoretikos represents the “full
exists, to that degree a tentative natural unfoldingof human nature” into the moral
law might be useful. Voegelin sees in us rule: “Man should strive to find this ful-
that which seeks order as that which is fillment in his personal existence.” We
least immanent. Furthermore, reason, or might similarly derive the rule of justice:
nous, does not seek only external goods “Society should be organized in such a
or arrangements, but, even more, an or- manner that the fulfillment of the pur-
der in which it is itself fostered and hon- pose is possible, at least for those who
ored. The reflexive quality of this search wish to attain it.”46That rule might very
is probably the main reason forvoegelin’s well open the way for further, more par-
rejection of natural law. ticular implementing rules. As we have
From this perspective, the famous seen, Voegelin surely moved beyond this
passage in Grotius concerningautonomy position, justifiable as it might be, to a
misses the point: “What we have been more radical experientialism or a more
saying would have a degree of validity consistent mysticism, a movement which
even if we should concede that which continued throughout his career.
cannot be conceded without the utmost A very different approach to law may
wickedness, that there is no God, or that be found in Voegelin’s 1927 article on
the affairs of men are of no concern to Hans Kelsen’s positivistic pure theory of
Him.”43 Without the tension to the ground, law. In that very early piece he takes a
ethics would simply vanish. view of natural law standards just as
In Order and History,Voegelin writes negative as that examined above, but for
approvingly that “the prophets recog- the opposite reason: “The content of law
nized that any letter, as it externalized is shown to be what it is: not an eternal,
the spirit, was in danger of becoming a sacred order, but a compromise of bat-
dead letter, and that, consequently, the tling social forces-and this may be
Covenant written on tablets had to give changed every day by the chosen repre-
way t o the Covenant written in the sentatives of the people according to the
heart.”44With natural law, too, as we wishes of their constituencies without
have seen, he believes the letter must fear of endangering divine law.”47Al-
give way t o the forming experience of though clearly superseded by his later
divine order in the soul. Indeed, the insig- writings, it is interesting that here, too,
nificance of the letter causes Voegelin t o Voegelin looks upon the legal as a pro-
remark in passing, in another context, cess rather than as a set of fixed rules.
that “there is nothing wrong ...with occa- H. Richard Niebuhr, in his Responsible
sional indulgences or excesses.”45 Self, argues that human beings have
Brief notes on natural law Voegelin thought of the moral life using three
probably wrote about the same time as metaphors. The first, or teleological view,
this account of the Covenant show a less pictures us as makers of ourselves, con-
radical, more appreciative approach to structing ourselves according to some
natural law and to the “letter” than that pattern. The second sees us as citizens,
presented in the interpretation exam- living under laws we are obliged to obey-
ined above. In these notes Voegelin as- the deontological view. The third, or
serts that “natural law has theoretical cathekonticview, portrays us as respond-
justification insofar as it translates the ers to questions put to us by life. Niebuhr

.38 Winter 1999

LICENSED TO UNZ.ORG
ELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED
thinks that each metaphor is illuminat- ultimate basis of the right by nature.
ing and that each emphasizes what is an Once this perspective is gained, the
important element of the whole. How- story of natural law is revealed as a tale
ever, he regards the third as owing the of misplaced concreteness, of how a
most to Christian insights.48 reification of our tension toward the di-
Voegelin’s interpretation of Aristotle’s vine ground or a prematurely closed
right by nature, and his hostility to natu- conception of nature, or of our nature,
ral law, suggest something like a may lead us into making idols of rules.
cathekontic ethic. The spouduios, or Voegelin’s analysis is meant to serve as a
morally mature man, deciding how to act grammar of ascent, showing us how to
not by rules but by seeing what is re- speak of the order of being in terms that
quired through openness to the divine, will not congeal into dogmas, but retain
resembles the Christian who seeks the their transparency to our continuing
correct responses to the questions posed experience of the divine.
by life not through the Law but through To forestall dogmatism, Voegelin is
grace. It is fascinating that Voegelin finds quite willing to give up a symbolism as
evidence for such a view in Aristotle, old and influential as natural law. How-
generally regarded as the chief architect ever, when we have other goals, such as
of teleological ethics. The similarities organizing our moral views or habituat-
could be taken as evidence Voegelin was ing ourselves to the good conduct which
imposing a religious interpretation on a will help us and our communities to be-
philosophy. He would argue that he had come truly good, it seems that natural
simply gotten beyond a dogmatic read- law remains helpful. Having innoculated
ing to Aristotle’s experiential meaning. ourselves with Voegelin’s analysis, we
Although his reading is open t o question, can probably be trusted to keep natural
it has the great merit of clarifying the law’s tentativeness firmly in view.

1. “What is Political Reality?”and “What is Nature?” The Natural Law (New York, 1947), 19. 18. Ernest
in Anamnesis, trans. and ed. Gerhart Niemeyer Barker, The Political Thought ofPluto and Aristotle
(South Bend, 1978); The Nature of the Law and (NewYork, 1959), 326.19.Aristotle,Rhetoric,trans.
Related Legal Writings,in Collected Works, ed. Pas- Lane Cooper (New York, 1960), 1373B (I, 13), 73-74.
cal, Babbington and Corrington (Baton Rouge, 20. Ibid., 1374A (I,13), 76. 21. Rhetoric in Basic
1991). 2. For an overview, see Steven R. McCarl, Works,ed.RichardMcKeon (NewYork,1941). 1374A
“Eric Voegelin’s Theory of Consciousness,” APSR, (I,13), 1371. 22. Ibid., 959. 23. “Right By Nature,”
W V I , 1, 106-111. 3. Order and History (5 vols.; Journal ofPolitics, LIII, 2, 318-338. 24. Ibid., 322. 25.
Baton Rouge, 1958-1987), IV, 38. 4. Review of The Nature oftheLaw, 79;Anamnesis,60.26. Ibid.,68-69.
Myth of the State,Journal ofPolitics,IX, 446.5. Order 27. Ibid., 62-63. 28. Ibid., 60-61. 29. Ibid., 61. 30.
and History, IV,38.6. Ibid., 39. 7. Anamnesis, 55. 8. Politics in Basic Works, 1331 (VII, E), 1293. 31.
William C. Havard, “The Changing Pattern of Nature o fthe Law, 65.32.Nature ofthe Law,53; Order
Voegelin’s Conception of History,” Southern Re- andHistory,Ill, 350-354.33.Nature oftheLaw, 54.34.
view, VII, 1, N.S., 62. Voegelin’s own account may be Ibid., 82. 35. Anamnesis, 60. 36. Ibid., 81. 37. Order
found in his Autobiographical ReRections, ed. Ellis and History, IV, 244.38. “The Gospel and Culture,”
Sandoz p a t o n Rouge, 1989). 9. “Equivalences of in Jesus and Man’s Hope, I1 (Pittsburgh, 1971), 63.
Experience and Symbolization in History,” manu- 39. Nature of the Law, 78.40.Anamnesis,77-78.41.
script copy, 3. 10. “On Debate and Existence,” Ibid.,78.42.Ibid., 114.43. The Law ofWarandPeace,
Intercollegiate Review, Ill, 45, 143152; Order and trans. F. W. Kelsey (Indianapolis,n.d.), Prolegomena,
History I, 438-440. 11. Anamnesis, 22. 12. Wilhelm 11,13.44.OrderandHistory, I, 440441.45. “Reason:
Windleband, A History o f Philosophy (New York, The Classic Experience,” in Anamnesis, 100. 46.
1958). 11,397n.13. Nature oftheLaw, 38.14.Ibid.,42- Nature ofthe Law, 81-82.47. “Kelsen’sPure Theory
48. 15. Anamnesis, 58. 16. Ibid., 56-59. 17. Ibid., 59. of Law,”Political Science Quarterly,XLII, 2,276.48.
See also: Nature of the Law, 81; Heinrich Rommen, New York, 1963.

Modern Age 39

LICENSED TO UNZ.ORG
ELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED

S-ar putea să vă placă și