Sunteți pe pagina 1din 4

The Journal of Socio-Economics 41 (2012) 772–775

Contents lists available at SciVerse ScienceDirect

The Journal of Socio-Economics


journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/soceco

What can sociology teach us about the ideational origins of modernity?


Comments on McCloskey’s Bourgeois Dignity
Joshua T. McCabe
Department of Sociology, University at Albany, SUNY, United States

a r t i c l e i n f o

Article history:
Received 30 July 2011
Received in revised form 12 March 2012
Accepted 9 April 2012

1. Introduction The Protestant Ethic was challenging the materialist conceptions of


the rise of capitalism popular among economists and historians of
In Bourgeois Dignity: Why Economics Can’t Explain the Modern his day. In Weber’s view, culture and ideas matter. While Weber
World, Deirdre McCloskey makes the bold claim that none of the took aim at Karl Marx, McCloskey sets her sights on Douglas North
usual factors used by economists to explain the rise of the modern among others.
world provide a satisfactory answer. In contrast to the majority In this volume (only the second of six planned), McCloskey
of her colleagues in economics, McCloskey looks beyond tradi- makes the negative case that it was not material factors which
tional materialist explanations such as the presence of natural led to the high living standards we take for granted today. She
resources, changes in agriculture, and the rise of particular institu- employs Mill’s method of residues: “The idea is, after getting rid
tions. Instead, she focuses on the rise of a particular kind of rhetoric of everything else that is measurable, the residuals can be taken as
in several countries which blazed a path to the modern world. The the real cause–in this case it is rhetoric (McCloskey, 2010, p. 33).”
most influential fact was the “Bourgeois Revaluation” which took She makes a good case that none of the material factors she cov-
place in Holland, Britain, France, and the United States. She argues: ers are responsible for the modern world in any significant way;
“An old class of town dwellers, formerly despised by the clergy and therefore rhetoric matters. If showing that rhetoric matters is her
the aristocracy and the peasantry, began to acquire a more dignified only task then Bourgeois Dignity makes that point but does little
standing, in the way people thought and talked about it, in Euro- else. As Skocpol (1992, p. 22) famously asks of ideational-centered
pean rhetoric about middle-class activities. And along with a new approaches, “Whose ideas and values? And ideas and values about
dignity the bourgeoisie began to acquire a new liberty. Both were what more precisely?” In order to make a significant contribution to
rhetorical events” (McCloskey, 2010, p. 10). this area, McCloskey must show us exactly how and when rhetoric
In many ways, McCloskey’s work parallels that of one of history’s matters. With this in mind, this paper will explore the possible
most famous sociologists, Max Weber. Both Weber and McCloskey directions McCloskey could take her argument as she continues
work in the “grand narrative” tradition and seek to explain the writing the next volume in the series.
rise of the modern world. In The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of I am a historical-comparative sociologist by training; therefore I
Capitalism (1905, p. 88), Weber argues that the rise of Calvinist will limit my discussion to work in this subfield. The first part of the
theology and its concomitant “valuation of the fulfillment of duty discussion will examine several theories from political sociology
in worldly affairs as the highest form of moral activity which the and political science in which ideas play a central role in shap-
individual could assume” helped usher in an era of what sociol- ing institutions (and vice versa). Ideas are defined here to include
ogists call “instrumental-rationality” or what economists would both cognitive (beliefs/perceptions) and normative (values/morals)
call rational self-interest which led to the rise of capitalism. As elements of human action. The attempt will be to rehabilitate the
it turns out, Weber was largely wrong about the relationship view of institutions so that they move beyond the prescribed role of
between Calvinism and capitalism (as McCloskey points out) but “merely” providing constraints on actors. Political sociology, for all
this misses the larger point of his work. Weber’s real contribution in the stereotypes that perceive it as still mired in Marxist class anal-
ysis, long ago moved beyond simple interest-based explanations of
historical change. The last two decades can largely be character-
ized as a debate on the relationship between institutions and ideas.
E-mail address: joshmccabe@hotmail.com I will focus on new work that seeks to dispel the notion that this

1053-5357/$ – see front matter © 2012 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.socec.2012.04.013
J.T. McCabe / The Journal of Socio-Economics 41 (2012) 772–775 773

is an either/or explanation by looking at the interaction between collective minds (see Aldrich, 2011 for a critique of the concept).
ideas and institutions at the macro level. The second part will exam- While this makes for a good story, it is not what drives historical
ine the role of ideas in influencing actors on the micro level within change. Informal constraints, in McCloskey’s (2010, p. 303) view are
the market. Economic sociology has much to offer McCloskey here. “continually renegotiated” so we need a framework which enables
I will use examples from McCloskey’s work throughout in order to us to account for dynamic change. In other words, McCloskey must
shed some light on the rise of capitalism, modernity, and Bourgeois be able to endogenize social change. Recent work on “discursive
Dignity. institutionalism” may provide the answer for which we are looking.
Schmidt (2008, 2010) is at the forefront of developing this
approach by synthesizing and extending several strands of new
2. The macro level: ideas and institutions institutionalisms under the banner of discursive institutionalism.
This approach takes account of the “substantive content of ideas
Economists have long known that institutions, broadly con- and the interactive processes by which ideas are conveyed and
strued, matter for economic development. Baumol (1990) makes exchanged through discourse (Schmidt, 2010, p. 3).” Schmidt, a
the distinction between two kinds of entrepreneurship as they political scientist, aims her analysis at political institutions but we
relate to institutions. Productive entrepreneurship includes trade can also apply her framework to the informal institutions of the
and innovation which creates economic value. Unproductive economy. She breaks down ideas in terms of their “levels of gen-
entrepreneurship includes rent-seeking and war-making which erality (policies, programs, and philosophies) and type of content
simply redistributes economic value or even destroys it. He (cognitive and normative)” as well as “two basic forms of discourse:
argues that different institutions encourage different kinds of the coordinative discourse among policy actors and the commu-
entrepreneurship from the same people. The early work of North nicative discourse between political actors and the public (Schmidt,
(1990) makes arguments along these same lines. 2008, p. 305).” What does this mean for McCloskey?
Institutional change, on the other hand, remains under- McCloskey would need to demonstrate how the normative
theorized by economists. More recent work by North (2005) philosophy of Dutch and British elites transformed views of the
integrates the concept of cognitive ideas into a theory of institu- bourgeois through communicative discourse. The focus on elites
tional change that purports to account for the rise of capitalism is important because they possess what Schmidt calls “foreground
in Europe but as Wilkinson (2005, p. 175) points out in a review, discursive abilities.”
“North’s discussion is merely suggestive, and does not dwell on the
These foreground discursive abilities are essential to explain-
possible mechanisms hinted at in early chapters by which belief
ing institutional change because they refer to peoples’ ability
systems, preferences, institutional structures, technologies, and
to think outside the institutions in which they continue to act,
cognitive processes might interdependently evolve.” Blyth (2002),
to talk about such institutions in a critical way, to commu-
in his study of the resurgence of neoliberalism in Sweden and the
nicate and deliberate about them, to persuade themselves as
United States, makes similar efforts but suffers from the same limi-
well as others to change their minds about their institutions,
tations. He gives us the famous dictum: “Structures do not come
and then to take action to change them, whether by building
with an instruction sheet.” In other words, actors aren’t always
‘discursive coalitions’ for reform against entrenched interests
aware of what is in their best interest as many new institution-
in the coordinative policy sphere or informing and orienting
alist models assume. He lays out an alternative theory of the causal
the public in the communicative political sphere (Schmidt,
power of ideas: (1) “In periods of economic crisis, ideas (not insti-
2010).
tutions) reduce uncertainty.” (2) “Following uncertainty reduction,
ideas make collective action and coalition-building possible.” (3) It is not enough for McCloskey to show that attitudes toward
“In the struggle of existing institutions, ideas are weapons.” (4) the bourgeoisie changed in Holland and England during the 17th
“Following delegitimation of existing institutions, new ideas act as and 18th century. She must show us exactly how this happened
institutional blueprints.” (5) “Following institutional construction, through a thorough process tracing (a great method for picking up
ideas make institutional stability possible (Blyth, 2002, pp. 34–44).” on those mechanisms missed by North) of the events in question
Like North, Blyth’s emphasis on the cognitive aspect of ideas stems (George and Bennett, 2005, pp. 205–224). At any given point in
from the belief that ideas serve as important tools for overcom- time, there are almost an infinite number of ideas floating around
ing Knightian uncertainty. Thus ideas, as powerful as they are in about an infinite number of subjects. What made Bourgeois Dignity
times of crisis, are only causally powerful for those very limited so special? A number of questions spring to mind. Where did these
periods. This leaves little room for ideas in “normal” times except ideas come from and how did they gain such broad acceptance?
as reinforcing institutions via expectations. Why did it begin in Holland and Britain? Hirschman (1977) argues
The problem, as McCloskey (2010, p. 296) aptly notes, is that that the rise of what he calls commercial liberalism was a rational
“institutions cannot be viewed merely as incentive-providing con- response to desires to repress man’s dangerous passions. Somers
straints.” North and Blyth fall short because they simply expand (1993), looking at the rise of citizenship rights in England (some-
the concept of institutions to include cognitive ideas. McCloskey’s thing akin to McCloskey’s concept of Bourgeois Dignity), finds that
objection echoes critics of rational choice and historical institution- the connection between political culture and citizenship rights was
alism. For rational choice institutionalists like North (1990, 2005) highly contingent on a number of other factors including law, the
culture is mainly a set of norms which constrain the behavior of constellation of elite social networks, and the structure of agricul-
actors to a set of socially acceptable actions. Much like the Ten ture in rural areas. Which actors are responsible for the changes
Commandments, culture is given from up high and remains outside in attitude? What other factors explain their timing? Popp Berman
of the actors themselves. Similarly, historical institutionalists like (2012), looking at the rise of market logic in university science,
Dobbin (1994) rely too much on path dependency arguments which finds that changes were closely tied to discussions about innova-
leave little room for social change once certain feedback mecha- tion among dispersed political, academic, and business elites in
nism have been put in place. Instead of a theory of institutional response to international economic competition from Japan and
change, we get a series of punctuated equilibriums where social Europe and took place over several decades. These are the impor-
change is always exogenous to the model, set off by some outside tant questions which must be answered for McCloskey to include
force. Often times, the task is left to an amorphous “institutional ideas and rhetoric in a convincing explanation for the rapid rise in
entrepreneur” who swoops in to magically change everyone’s living standard which led to the modern world.
774 J.T. McCabe / The Journal of Socio-Economics 41 (2012) 772–775

3. The micro level: moralizing markets economists and some earlier sociologists. She does this by looking
at the areas of social life thought to be most at risk for cooptation
Another issue with North’s conception of the growth of the by market logic – sex, children, care giving, death – and the areas
institutions is that he sees their evolution as a form of “adaptive thought to be purely economic – money and firms. Most impor-
efficiency” (North, 2005). People are rational and, given the right tantly, she explores the process through which economic logic gains
kind of institutional feedback mechanisms, their actions will result legitimacy in new areas of social life.
in efficient institutions. This leads to a naturalistic view of mar- According to Zelizer (2010), there is nothing “natural” about
kets as institutions which will arise because of elements inherent markets. The best example is the case of life insurance in 19th cen-
to our human nature. Polanyi (1944) challenges this idea of human tury America. She finds that life insurance was at odds with cultural
nature and the naturalness of the market in The Great Transforma- values that held life as sacred. The idea was that life insurance was
tion. He argues that commodification, the process in which objects a commercial form of betting on death and thus highly immoral.
are produced for sale on the markets, is far from natural. It had to Actors had to work to legitimize life insurance. Attempts to con-
be imposed on people through changes in the law such as the cre- vince the public based on what McCloskey would call a “prudence
ation of labor markets in England under the 1795 Speenhamland only” argument were tried and failed miserably because this would
system. McCloskey, despite different normative evaluations than have changed something sacred, the death of a loved one, into
Polanyi, takes the same view of the malleability of “human nature.” something profane. Instead they began to bring in other virtues,
If markets are so natural, why is the handle on McCloskey’s hockey such as love and justice, with more success. Life insurance became
stick of material living standards so long? Smith (1776) famously a sacred symbol of caring for your loved ones after you died. She
begins chapter two of An Inquiry Into the Nature and Causes of the finds the similar stories for adoption markets and care giving. Quinn
Wealth of Nations by discussing how the division of labor gives rise (2008) looks at the secondary market for life insurance and finds
to trade. He says, similar results. In this case, anonymous investors are betting on the
fact that the person will die sooner rather than later. Although it
This division of labour, from which so many advantages are
was been legal for almost a century, moral aversion to trading life
derived, is not originally the effect of any human wisdom, which
insurance policies has left the practice almost unused until recently
foresees and intends that general opulence to which it gives
despite widespread profit opportunities. Whereas earlier rhetori-
occasion. It is the necessary, though very slow and gradual con-
cal efforts aiming to legitimize life insurance spoke about providing
sequence of a certain propensity in human nature which has in
for loved ones after you died, rhetoric aiming to legitimize the sec-
view no such extensive utility; the propensity to truck, barter,
ondary market focuses on having the financial means to “die with
and exchange one thing for another.
dignity.” Each of these may be characterized as part of the contin-
Many economists take this passage as evidence that Smith uation of the modern bourgeois revaluation. In contrast to what
believes homo economicus is in the nature of man, but critics some see as the feared rationalization of social life, Zelizer (2010, p.
question this particular reading of Smith (Polanyi, 1944; Kennedy, 41) sees a “sacralization” of economic life where profane economic
2005). There is good reason for this. In the next passage, Smith goes exchanges are given moral or religious meaning. Just as we take for
on to question his own assertion: granted the idea that life insurance is a dignified endeavor today,
we also take for granted the ideas that trucking, bartering, and
Whether this propensity be one of those original principles in
consuming was seen as a dignified endeavor in the 16th century.
human nature, of which no further account can be given; or
Moreover, these market exchanges were all legal during the
whether, as seems more probable, it be the necessary conse-
periods in question. Despite all the requisite legal institutions in
quence of the faculties of reason and speech, it belongs not to
place, people had a moral aversion to these kinds of transactions.
our present subject to enquire [emphasis added].
Economists such as Roth (2007) have begun to pay attention to the
It is no wonder Smith attributed this propensity to human role of ideas such as repugnance in constraining markets but like
nature as he was writing at a time when the industrial revolution North, the focus on their role as constraints avoids the question
was already well underway in England and the men all around him of social change. In contrast, Zelizer and Quinn use newspapers
were involved in a vigorous commercial life where they trucked, trade journals, interviews, and other media sources to examine
bartered, and exchanged on a daily basis. But why hadn’t these changes in discourse over time. The difference is important because
industrious men figured this out earlier? When most economists economists are often unfamiliar with textual and content analysis
see the metaphorical “big bills left on the sidewalk,” as was the which offers a superior way to empirically explore the effects of
case with England 100 years earlier, they attribute this problem to changes in discourse and rhetoric on other political and socioeco-
improper or counterproductive institutions (Olson, 1996). Accord- nomic outcomes. Alongside elite discourse, McCloskey must also
ing to McCloskey (2010, pp. 296–345), the usual suspects do not examine popular discourse. This will prove especially challenging
pan out. Institutions thought to be counterproductive were present given the dearth of popular media sources from earlier centuries
while many of the most “necessary” institutions did not appear which have survived today for proper analysis.
until later. Such institutions assume homo economicus, or “Max
U” as McCloskey calls him, so maybe it is best we reexamine this
assumption. 4. Conclusion
Viviana Zelizer is a sociologist who does exactly this. For the past
30 years, she has looked at the relationship between markets and Having spent the bulk of this paper discussing theoretical and
society. Zelizer (2010, p. 72) is most critical of what she calls “hostile methodological insights from sociology which can help McCloskey
world” and “market work” approaches to the economy. The former establish that it was indeed ideas and rhetoric which led to the rise
argues that rational economic action is poisoned by emotions and of the modern world, I want to take some time to touch upon her
sentiments and poisons social life in turn. The latter argues that it larger point about markets and morals.
only counts as economic if there is monetary calculation involved. Fourcade and Healy (2007) break the literature on “moral views
In each case, there is a strict separation of economy from society. of market society” down into three camps building on Hirschman’s
In both cases, each particular view of the market is an assumption (1982) rival interpretations of market society. In the vision of cap-
rather than an empirical fact. Zelizer finds that the interesting ques- italism as a “commodifying nightmare” put forth by Marxist and
tions lay in exploring the reality behind the assumptions made by Polanyi-inspired economists, markets destroy community through
J.T. McCabe / The Journal of Socio-Economics 41 (2012) 772–775 775

a process of commodification while in the feeble version, markets Dobbin, F., 1994. Forging Industrial Policy: The United States, Britain and France in
are overpowered by culture and institutional legacies. Fourcade and the Railway Age. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Fourcade, M., Healy, K., 2007. Moral views of market society. Annual Review of
Healy put McCloskey’s earlier work on The Bourgeois Values into Sociology 33, 285–311.
a third category they call the “liberal dream” which sees markets George, A.L., Bennett, A., 2005. Case Studies and Theory Development in the Social
as exerting positive forces on civil society. As they point out, in the Sciences. The MIT Press, Cambridge.
Healy, K., 2006. Last Best Gifts: Altruism and the Market for Human Blood and Organs.
commodifying nightmare and liberal dream models of markets, the University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
causal arrow points one way from markets to morality (Fourcade Hirschman, A.O., 1977. The Passions and the Interests: Political Arguments for Cap-
and Healy, 2007, p. 299). Either market society makes us moral or italism before its Triumph. Princeton University Press.
Hirschman, A.O., 1982. Rival interpretations of market society: civilizing, destruc-
immoral.
tive, or feeble? Journal of Economic Literature 20 (4), 1463–1484.
In light of Bourgeois Dignity, Fourcade and Healy’s assessment Kennedy, G., 2005. Adam Smith’s Lost Legacy. Palgrave Macmillan, New York.
of McCloskey needs to be reclassified into their fourth category McCloskey, D.N., 2010. Bourgeois Dignity: Why Economics Can’t Explain the Modern
World. University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
as an example of the “moralized markets” approach where the
North, D.C., 1990. Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance.
arrow goes both ways. Throughout Bourgeois Dignity, McCloskey Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
(2010, p. 11) repeatedly reminds us that liberty (markets) and North, D.C., 2005. Understanding the Process of Economic Change. Princeton Uni-
dignity (morals) are intertwined “and both were necessary” for versity Press, Princeton.
Olson, M., 1996. Big bills left on the sidewalk: why some nations are rich, and others
the rise of the modern world. Beyond its normative implications poor. Journal of Economic Perspectives 10 (2), 3–24.
about the uses and limits of markets, it opens up a number of Polanyi, K., 1944. The Great Transformation: The Political and Economic Origins of
new research questions for McCloskey and other scholars inter- Our Time. Beacon Press, Boston.
Popp Berman, E., 2012. Creating the Market University: How Academic Science
ested in the relationship between markets and morals. Under what Became an Economic Engine. Princeton University Press, Princeton.
circumstances does market logic lead to human dignity and under Quinn, S., 2008. The transformation of morals in markets: death, benefits, and
what circumstances is human dignity a requisite for properly func- the exchange of life insurance policies. American Journal of Sociology 114 (3),
738–780.
tioning markets? While sociologists such as Healy (2006), Zelizer Roth, A.E., 2007. Repugnance as a constraint on markets. Journal of Economic Per-
(2010), and Almeling (2011) have been at the forefront of answering spectives 21 (3), 37–58.
these questions, economists have shown almost no interest in such Schmidt, V., 2008. Discursive institutionalism: the explanatory power of ideas and
discourse. Annual Review of Political Science 11, 303–326.
issues. Without speculating on the reasons for this, I will end on the
Schmidt, V., 2010. Taking ideas and discourse seriously: explaining change through
hope the McCloskey’s future contributions rejuvenate economists’ discursive institutionalism as the fourth ‘new institutionalism’. European Polit-
interest in morals and ethics. ical Science Review 2 (1), 1–25.
Skocpol, T., 1992. Protecting Soldiers and Mothers: The Political Origins of Social
Policy in United States. Harvard University Press, Cambridge.
References Smith, A., 1991 [1776]. An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of
Nations. Prometheus Books, Amherst, NY.
Aldrich, H.E., 2011. Heroes, villains, and fools: institutional entrepreneurship, Somers, M.R., 1993. Citizenship and the place of the public sphere: law, commu-
NOT institutional entrepreneurs. Entrepreneurship Research Journal 1 (2), nity, and political culture in the transition to democracy. American Sociological
1–4. Review 58 (5), 587–620.
Almeling, R., 2011. Sex Cells: The Medical Market for Eggs and Sperm. University of Weber, M., 2003 [1905]. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. Dover
California Press, Los Angeles. Books, New York.
Baumol, W.J., 1990. Entrepreneurship: productive, unproductive, and destructive. Zelizer, V.A., 2010. Economic Lives: How Culture Shapes the Economy. Princeton
Journal of Political Economy 98 (5), 893–921. University Press, Princeton.
Blyth, M., 2002. Great Transformations: Economic Ideas and Institutional Change in Wilkinson, W., 2005. Review of understanding the process of economic change by
the Twentieth Century. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Douglas North. Cato Journal 25 (1), 172–176.

S-ar putea să vă placă și