Sunteți pe pagina 1din 106

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/268300724

THE UNITY OF SUBSTANCE IN ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS Λ

Article

CITATIONS READS
0 476

1 author:

Luke Togni
Marquette University
1 PUBLICATION   0 CITATIONS   

SEE PROFILE

All content following this page was uploaded by Luke Togni on 19 November 2015.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


THE UNITY OF SUBSTANCE IN ARISTOTLE’S METAPHYSICS Λ

by

Luke V. Togni

Submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements


for the degree of Master of Arts

at

Dalhousie University
Halifax, Nova Scotia
December 2011

© Copyright by Luke V. Togni, 2011


DALHOUSIE UNIVERSITY

DEPARTMENT OF CLASSICS

The undersigned hereby certify that they have read and recommend to the Faculty of

Graduate Studies for acceptance a thesis entitled “THE UNITY OF SUBSTANCE IN

ARISTOTLE’S METAPHYSICS Λ” by Luke V. Togni in partial fulfilment of the

requirements for the degree of Master of Arts.

Dated: December 12, 2011

Supervisor: _________________________________

Readers: _________________________________

_________________________________

ii
DALHOUSIE UNIVERSITY

DATE: December 12, 2011

AUTHOR: Luke V. Togni

TITLE: THE UNITY OF SUBSTANCE IN ARISTOTLE’S METAPHYSICS Λ

DEPARTMENT OR SCHOOL: Department of Classics

DEGREE: MA CONVOCATION: May YEAR: 2012

Permission is herewith granted to Dalhousie University to circulate and to have copied


for non-commercial purposes, at its discretion, the above title upon the request of
individuals or institutions. I understand that my thesis will be electronically available to
the public.

The author reserves other publication rights, and neither the thesis nor extensive extracts
from it may be printed or otherwise reproduced without the author’s written permission.

The author attests that permission has been obtained for the use of any copyrighted
material appearing in the thesis (other than the brief excerpts requiring only proper
acknowledgement in scholarly writing), and that all such use is clearly acknowledged.

_______________________________
Signature of Author

iii
For Lucy,
so that I could finally come home.

iv
TABLE OF CONTENTS
ABSTRACT...................................................................................................................... vii
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS ............................................................................................. viii
CHAPTER 1 INTRODUCTION ........................................................................................ 1

1.1 THE ORIGIN OF THE QUESTION ........................................................................... 4


1.2 THE UNITY OF A SCIENCE .................................................................................. 5
1.3 PREVIOUS INTERPRETERS .................................................................................. 6
1.4 DIVERGENCE FROM THE INTERPRETERS ............................................................ 8
1.5 THE ANALOGY OF THE GENERAL AND THE ARMY ............................................ 10
1.6 OUTLINE OF THE ARGUMENT ........................................................................... 12

CHAPTER 2 PERISHABLE SENSIBLE SUBSTANCE ................................................ 15

2.1 THE FOUR CAUSES OF SENSIBLE SUNSTANCE ................................................... 16


2.2 THE ANALOGICAL UNITY OF THE FOUR PROXIMATE CAUSES............................ 28
2.3 THE GENERAL, THE ARMY AND PERISHABLE SUBSTANCE ................................ 34
2.4 CONCLUDING SUMMARY ................................................................................. 40

CHAPTER 3 IMPERISHABLE SENSIBLE SUBSTANCE .......................................... 42

3.1 THE STRUCTURE OF THE HEAVENS IN Λ.8 ........................................................ 43


3.1.1 THE PROBLEM OF THE REVOLVING SPHERES .................................................... 44
3.1.2 THE RESOLUTION ............................................................................................ 47
3.2 THE CAUSES OF IMPERISHABLE SENSIBLE SUBSTANCE..................................... 48
3.2.1 THE SCOPE OF THE STUDY OF HEAVENLY SUBSTANCES ................................... 50
3.2.2 THE APPLICABILITY OF THE CAUSES AND PRINCIPLES OF SUBSTANCES
LISTED IN Λ.2-5 TO THE HEAVENLY SUBSTANCES. .................................................... 51

3.2.3 THE UNMOVED MOVERS CORRESPOND TO THE GENERAL ................................. 55


3.2.4 EACH UNMOVED MOVER IS THE UNIQUE CAUSE OF A SPHERE .......................... 56
3.2.5 THE UNMOVED MOVERS AS EFFICIENT CAUSES ................................................ 58
3.2.6 THE UNMOVED MOVERS AS EXEMPLARY CAUSES ........................................... 62
3.2.7 THE UNMOVED MOVERS AS FINAL CAUSES ..................................................... 65
3.3 CONCLUDING SUMMARY ............................................................................... 71

v
CHAPTER 4 SEPARATE SUBSTANCE AND CONCLUSION ................................... 73

4.1 THE LIMITS OF THE ANALOGY APPLIED TO SEPARATE SUBSTANCE .................. 73

4.2 GOD, ACTUALITY AND POTENTIALITY ............................................................. 77


4.3 THE UNITY OF THE COSMOS ............................................................................. 80
4.3.1 THE TWO DIMENSIONS OF COSMIC UNITY ........................................................ 82
4.3.2 GOD AS THE EFFICIENT CAUSE OF ALL SUBSTANCES ........................................ 87
4.3.3 GOD AS THE EXEMPLARY CAUSE OF ALL SUBSTANCES .................................... 89
4.3.4 GOD AS THE FINAL CAUSE OF ALL SUBSTANCES .............................................. 91
4.4 CONCLUSION ................................................................................................... 92

BIBLIOGRAPHY ............................................................................................................. 93

vi
ABSTRACT

This thesis investigates whether Aristotle is actually presenting substance as the subject
of a single science in Metaphysics Λ. It proposes that he is, and that the common
principles of all substances, which are required for there to be a single science of
substance, are those found in Λ.2-5. Although these causes and principles describe
change, the analogy of the general and the army, which describes the relationship
between God and the cosmos, also describes the relationship between causing and caused
sensible substances. The analogy of the general and the army is used to the show that the
principles that describe the actuality and effects of separate substance are analogically
similar, and that the cause of this similarity is God’s ordering of the cosmos to be like his
own eternal actuality as far as possible.

vii
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS

I would like to extend my sincere gratitude first to Dr. Eli Diamond, my thesis supervisor,
whose patience, dedication and insights saw this project to its completion. I do not mean
it lightly when I say that I could not have asked for a better supervisor. I would also like
to thank Dr. Michael Fournier and Dr. Emily Varto (who stepped to in at the last minute)
for reading my thesis and taking the time to offer advice about the this project and the
task of thesis writing itself. To all three, I am glad to have had the pleasure to have
worked under you in your respective classes. My maturation as a student, and perhaps,
scholar and teacher has come through these collaborations.

I would also like to thank the other members of the department, especially Drs. Wayne
Hankey, Leona MacLeod and Peter O'Brien, with whom I learned a great deal in the
course-work portion of the MA programme. Furthermore, I would like to thank Br.
Christopher McKelvie, who walked this path a little before me, and kept my eyes on the
goal, and to Mr. William Cochran, who, having recently finished his thesis, has been a
constant source of encouragement in recent weeks.

Donna, you deserve your own paragraph. Your eye for detail and organization has, on
more than one occasion, kept me from sabotaging myself. I would not have received my
SSHRC had you not spotted that I had, perhaps typically, filled out the wrong form. I
thank you, most sincerely.

To my family, I owe you my gratitude. First and foremost, to Lucy, my dearest wife, who
has been most patient and supportive through this whole process, especially in the past
few, rather trying, months. Your love, spoken and unspoken, kept me working to the end.
to beautiful Emmanuel, your efforts at staying awake late into the night to greet me when
I arrived home will not be forgotten, at least, by your parents. Finally to my parents and
brothers, with whom I found the first school of truth, goodness and beauty, the home.

viii
CHAPTER 1 INTRODUCTION

That the means by which we can understand substance is through its causes (αἴτια)

and principles (ἀρχαὶ) is made clear by the opening lines of Metaphysics Λ, “περὶ τῆς οὐσίας

ἡ θεωρία: τῶν γὰρ οὐσιῶν αἱ ἀρχαὶ καὶ τὰ αἴτια ζητοῦνται.”1 The contemplation of substance

is also the contemplation and investigation of its causes and its principles. Within the space

of the first chapter of Λ, Aristotle brings before us one of the main questions for the

interpretation of Metaphysics Λ: whether all three kinds of substance (sensible perishable,

sensible eternal and separate, immoveable substance) can be considered through one science,

or whether the immoveable, invisible kind must be considered apart from sensible substance.

The project laid out in Metaphysics A, the search for Wisdom or the divine science,

prescribes a science which grasps the principles of all things,2 showing that Aristotle

conceives of a science that could embrace all three kinds of substance. A single science,

Aristotle says in Λ, requires a common principle (ἀρχὴ κοινή).3 Since Aristotle never

explicitly answers the question, establishing the plausibility that Λ does present a single

science of substance requires one to prove that a common principle of all substances is

present in the book’s argumentation. The difficulty lies in determining how Aristotle can

provide a common principle, or even principles, to substances which exhibit changeableness,

1
Aristotle, Metaphysics Λ, 1069a18-19.
2
982a1-9; 983a5; 993b26; 1003a21-30. These passages from Metaphysics A point to the study of the highest
science as the science of substance generally, such as it is considered in Metaphysics Λ. The first passage
describes what wisdom is, namely, a knowledge of all things, but not it detail. The second passage calls this
science, or wisdom, divine in two ways: 1) because it has eternal and divine things as its object, and 2) because
of all sciences, it would be possessed by God. In the third passage Aristotle reaffirms that what is sought is the
first principle, God, who as the “most true” is the cause of all derivative truths. The fourth differentiates
Aristotle’s study of being qua being from those sciences, which as part of a whole, study only one section of
being. Here he associates knowing the first principles and highest (ἀκροτάτα) causes with the study of being
which is universal (καθόλου).
3
1069b1.

1
and those which do not, but exist immutably, especially since he excludes intelligibles, such

as being and unity, which are common, from being principles of substance.4

The science of sensible, changeable substance, appears at other places throughout the

Metaphysics, and is given an especially rigorous treatment in Z, H and θ. In these books

scant reference is given to divine, or separate, substance. Even in Λ, where all three kinds of

substance are studied, there is no declaration either way about whether there is or is not a

single science of substance. The first half of Λ, chapters two through five, present the

principles that explain the being and changing of sensible substances: form, matter, privation

and agency.5 These chapters even acknowledge the role of the divine as a cause in their being

and changing,6 but chapters six through ten, which consider separate substance, do not refer

to the same principles. Some conclude, therefore, that the project of the Metaphysics does not

succeed in seeking the single science of being qua being. Joseph Owens, S.J. describes the

Metaphysics’ supposed failure:

In one respect this study of the Metaphysics has led to a negative result. Nowhere in any of
the treatises is separate Entity explained in the way required by A-E. A-E had projected a
science of separate Entity which should treat universally of all Being. Λ and – as far as can
be gathered from the indications – the positive treatment presupposed by N develop the
theme of Entity only in itself and as the final cause of all sensible Entity. They make no
attempt to show that the Being of the separate Entities is the Being expressed and studied in
all other Beings. Yet a treatment from this viewpoint is the only kind that could fill the
requirements of A-E.7

If there is to be a unified science of substance, it must be shown how, as Owens says, “the

Being of the separate Entities is the being expressed in all other beings”. In this thesis, I

4
1070b7. “οὐδὲ δὴ τῶν νοητῶν στοιχεῖόν ἐστιν, οἷον τὸ ὂν ἢ τὸ ἕν:…”
5
1071a34.
6
1070b35.
7
Owens, 298. (Owens translates οὐσία as ‘Entity’.)

2
intend to show that common to all substances there is such a principle, or more accurately,

principles. These common principles must be found in the highest kind of being, the separate

substances and in lower and less perfect beings. The causes and principles sought are those

which belong to the highest substance, and yet also belong to changeable substance, without

attributing changeableness to separate substance.

The principles that govern the relationship between a causing substance and caused

substance are of this sort. The relationship of cause and caused even applies to God and the

cosmos, as expressed in the analogy of the general and the army, 8 in addition to every other

substance, since even those which are not the cause of anything else are caused. Every

substance besides the first depends upon an already actual substance for its existence (or

simply for its coming to be). Even the unmoved mover, although it has no potency, is not

without a relation to potency in that it actualizes the first sphere’s potential for motion. Every

substance is involved, in a like way, in the relationship of an actual substance actualizing a

potential substance. In this thesis, I argue that the interpretive key of Metaphysics Λ is the

analogy of the army and the general from Λ.10, an image Aristotle provides for

understanding how God is the good and cause of the cosmos. I will show that all substances

are involved in the kind of causal relationship contained in the general-army relation,

although some substances are only ever on one side of the causing/caused dichotomy.

Furthermore, Aristotle’s account of causality in Λ.3 shows that everything that is caused is

conformed to its efficient cause,9 so that both its existence and essence have their origin in it.

The implication of this causal relationship is that the common structure we are invoking in all

substances is not a loosely connected series of likenesses, but is rather grounded in the

8
1075a14.
9
1070a4-5.

3
continuity of causes which stretch between the unmoved mover, the heavens, and the

sublunary realm. Consequently, there is a likeness of God’s eternity and power to actualize

found throughout the other two kinds of substance which make up the cosmos.

1.1 THE ORIGIN OF THE QUESTION

Metaphysics Λ does not open with a question, but a basic statement about substantiality and

how the investigation is to proceed.10 The contemplation of substance-being (οὐσία) proceeds

by seeking out and investigating the principles of substances. In Λ.1 Aristotle does not say

whether these principles will be the same for all or not, but instead reflects on a number of

other questions, including what substance’s place in the whole universe is and whether

universals or particulars are substances.11 The question of whether Λ is divided into two

sciences does not emerge as such. When Aristotle introduces the distinction between the

three kinds of substances, it is already clear that the sensible substances are studied by

physics.12 Separate substance, however, since it does not change in any way, cannot be

studied by physics, and so must be the subject of another science. The question Aristotle

raises is whether the science which studies separate substance also includes the substances

studied by physics. Aristotle does not make it his goal to determine whether or not there is a

common principle that would allow this, nor does he deny the possibility. Nevertheless, the

question remains an important one to consider. Without a common science of substance it is

doubtful that there could be a θεωρία περὶ τῆς οὐσίας, but only of the distinct kinds of οὐσίαι.

10
Elders, 69-70. Elders cautions against the use of “substance” as a translation of οὐσία, as does Owens
(Owens, 150), who prefers to translate it as ‘entity’. The investigation is not about a single being, but about
primary being generally, or the “beingness of things”. Elders also remarks that it refers to particular subsistent
beings when used in the plural.
11
1069a18-30.
12
Ibid. 36.

4
1.2 THE UNITY OF A SCIENCE

The existence of a single science for all kinds of substances, or for substances generally,

depends upon the existence of a common principle. The causes and principles of all things,

Aristotle is careful to remark repeatedly, are different. 13 Causes and principles are, properly

speaking, particular substances.14 Does Aristotle argue that sensible substances and separate

substances all share a single substance as a cause as a requirement of belonging one science?

If having a common principle, or principles, is the measure of belonging to the same class of

being, what is the common principle which makes second philosophy or physics a single

science? Every sensible substance has a form, matter and privation, common universal

principles, despite the fact that what these are for each substance is particular and different

for each: e.g., houses have matter; this matter is bricks. Another possible similarity which

might give unity to physics as a science is the capacity for all natural substance to suffer

change or motion. This principle is matter, but the matter is different in each sensible

substance, and the capacity for change, or potency qua potency, is not a subsistent substance.

Therefore, in the case of those substances that are studied by physics, what is alike in each of

them, seems to be an analogically common principle. We must be cautious, however, since

substances have more than one principle. The potency of natural substances would be

nothing, after all, without the actuality of form for which any potency exists, and an external

agency to actualize the potential in the matter. Without these analogical principles, potency

would simply be non-being, not a potency at all. The existence of analogical principles does

not at all rule out that a particular principle can also be common and even related to the

13
1070a30-31. “τὰ δ᾽ αἴτια καὶ αἱ ἀρχαὶ ἄλλα ἄλλων ἔστιν ὥς”.
14
1070b8-9. The elements are either relative beings or substances, and relative beings cannot be the principles
of substances, nor vice versa.

5
analogical principles of substances. Examples of this include the Sun 15 and the unmoved

mover, without which neither substances, nor even non-substantial beings, would exist at

all.16 Proximate causes are analogically like, but the more remote and universal causes are

particular substances. By investigating the relationship between analogical and particular

common causes we will come to understand how there can be common causes of both kinds.

1.3 PREVIOUS INTERPRETERS

Commentators on Λ differ widely on what the subject, structure and goal of the book

is. Some take it to be primarily devoted to ontology, either divided into one or two sciences;

others take it as theology, to which physics is subordinated. Aquinas views Λ as the single

science of first philosophy.17 He holds that there is a common principle, namely, being a

substance, which he takes first philosophy to study, a science which must therefore study all

beings. His interpretation of the whole of Λ is justified by Aristotle’s introductory statement

about the book: that is it is a “περὶ τῆς οὐσίας ἡ θεωρία”, i.e. that the whole work is

conducting the science of substance-being qua substance-being. Owens, like Aquinas, takes

Λ to be primarily ontological, or ousiological, but as we noted above, he denies that the

subject of physics and separate substances are studied, or as he states it, “a study of Entity

first in sensible Entity and then in immobile Entity.”18 Ross holds, in contrast with this

ontological interpretation, that Λ is a work of theology, ordered towards establishing claims


15
1071a15-16.
16
1071a35-36. The first unmoved mover is the cause of all things, and so all substances, without which
substances there would be no other beings of any of the other categories.
17
Aquinas, §2426; Lang , 261. Lang agrees with Aquinas, saying “But if, as I am arguing, the subject of inquiry
is substance, a topic recognized even by the ancients, then the division of substances into kinds is the first step
in implementing the inquiry into substance. Consequently, these three kinds must possess a common principle
sufficient to include them within a single investigation…”
18
Owens, 453; Lang, 257.

6
about divine being rather than making claims about substance.19 Helen Lang is critical of

both Ross’ and Owens’ approaches. She agrees that the work as a whole is not theology, but

she grants that theology is its culmination of a single account of substance.20 If there is no

common principle then there are either two equal investigations (as per Owens), or one

investigation for which the rest of is an instrument (as per Ross). If there is a common

principle, there is one investigation which equally involves the whole of the book.

Interpretations about whether Λ includes common principles of all substance also

depend upon how God and the other unmoved movers are conceived of, either as efficient

causes or as final causes, or perhaps both. If God and the other unmoved movers are causes

in a way entirely unlike the other substances, it is difficult to see a likeness between the

causes that govern sensible substances and their interactions, and the principles which

describe the existence and activity of the separate substances. If on the other hand, separate

substances are understood as efficient causes, this association becomes much more plausible.

Averroes considers God and the unmoved movers to be efficient causes, in addition to being

formal and final causes of the spheres. Averroes regards the efficiency of the unmoved

movers as concomitant with their existence. He says that “…it is impossible that any of these

noble principles exists without any activity, as it is impossible that no ignition originates

from the essence of fire. These principles are active [principles], just as the Sun generates

light by its nature.”21 In this case the unmoved movers cause something besides themselves,

just as light is distinct from the Sun. Averroes does not recognize this efficiency as a kind

motion by impulse, but as the cause of the very existence of the sphere, which in turn moves

19
Ross, xxix, cxxx-cliv.
20
Ibid. 258, 263.That is, if Λ.1-8 is taken as a whole, rather than divided into two separate, but similar
investigations. Lang takes the last two chapters as answering questions which the main treatment in Λ.1-8 raises
but does not answer.
21
Averroes, 149.

7
through desire for the unmoved mover.22 Kosman’s description of the unmoved movers’

efficiency differs insofar as he considers it to be like the soul of one of the heavenly bodies.23

Whereas Averroes considers the spheres to have their own souls, Kosman does not. Neither

regards any of the unmoved movers as efficient in the sense of causing motion physically.

Elders sees Aristotle’s position that God is a “subsistent thinking” in Λ as being is in tension

with God as described in Physics VIII as an efficient cause. For Elders, God, as the Good, is

a final cause in Λ and not an efficient cause.24 In such a view God is regarded as the ordering

principle of all things, but not a principle of the existence of all things. Simplicius, however,

regards Aristotle’s God as a creator, immediately, of the spheres, and more remotely, of the

perishable substances through the motions caused by the spheres.25

1.4 DIVERGANCE FROM THE INTERPRETERS

I agree with Lang’s view that the theology does not dominate the work but rather

stands as the culmination. I also agree with Owens that the work itself is primarily aimed at

describing substance, but I depart from his position which regards the account of separate

substance and sensible substances as two separate accounts. The two accounts in Λ are one

by virtue of both a hierarchical relationship and an analogical relationship. I will argue that

the analogical likeness of the principles of all substances are a likeness to the principles

which belong to the causal relationship between God and the cosmos, as described by the

analogy of the general and the army in Λ.10. The validity of this analogy depends upon

22
Ibid. 151.
23
Kosman, 1994, 145.
24
Elders, 13-4.
25
Simplicius, 115-6.

8
accepting that the unmoved movers are efficient causes in virtue of their actuality, and the

efficient causality that belongs to other substances is a likeness of the unmoved movers’

causality. Furthermore, this excludes the possibility that the unmoved movers are like a soul

or a form, since they would not correspond to the distinction between intrinsic causes (form,

matter, privation) and the extrinsic efficient cause. These four causes are the analogically

common principles of all substances, which though different numerically, all share in the

structure described by analogy of the general and the army.

I will also argue that the analogical likeness of all principles of substance depends

upon the order or nature of the cosmos, as described by the same analogy of the general and

the army. By reading the two central analogies of Λ.10 together, i.e. the analogy of the army

and the analogy of the household, along with Aristotle’s concluding invocation of Homer’s

saying that “many kings is not good; let there be one king” so that “the things that are will

not be governed badly,”26 Lang seeks to explain how substances share a πρός ἑν relationship,

explained with reference to one order originating in the divine ruler, God as the one (and

only)27 unmoved mover. I agree with Lang, on her point that Λ.10 completes the discussion

of substance by examining a common principle of all substance, which she identifies as a

πρός ἑν principle.28 I argue, however, that this one order also allows the particular principles

of substance to be seen as analogically like. The order which governs all substances, also

orders individuals substances, or rather, the order of the whole is manifested in and through

the individual natures of all substances. The chain of causality, beginning with the first

26
1076a3-5. τὰ δὲ ὄντα οὐ βούλεται πολιτεύεσθαι κακῶς. “οὐκ ἀγαθὸν πολυκοιρανίη: εἷς κοίρανος ἔστω.” All
translations from the Metaphysics and De Anima are my own.
27
Lang, 266-7. She takes Aristotle’s conclusion in Λ.8 and the argument about matter to be an answer to the
question whether there are one or many movers. She is not referring only to the first unmoved mover, but any
unmoved mover at all.
28
Ibid, 277.

9
mover, orders the whole by causing the first motion, which in turn orders the next, etc. so

that it is clear that God is the first principle of all substances. Theology has priority in Λ

because it studies the principle upon which everything else depends. This common structure

is strong evidence that Metaphysics Λ presents a unified study of substance by providing

common principles, both in the analogical structure of all three kinds of substance, and in the

role played in the cosmos by God and the other unmoved movers, whose efficient, ordering

causation explains the existence of the analogical structure which unites the three kinds of

substance.29

1.5 THE ANALOGY OF THE GENERAL AND THE ARMY

The analogy of the general and the army is indispensable insofar as it provides an

analogical structure applicable to all substances, both sensible and separate. Applying it

correctly requires a careful analysis of the meaning of the image of the general and the army

and the context in which it is introduced, which is to explain the relationship between God

and the cosmos. Aristotle introduces the analogy of the general and the army in the last

chapter of Metaphysics Λ:

It ought to be considered in what way the nature of the whole possesses the good and best,
whether as some separate thing itself by itself, or as its own order. Or is it in both ways, just

29
Averroes, 156, 158. Averroes regards God as the cause of the world’s unity as a whole, rather than an
accidental unity: “On the whole, the world is one because it has one principle, otherwise its unity would be
accidental or it would follow that it does not exist at all.” Averroes does not only interpret God as an ontological
or ousiological first principle, but as ordering things through providence (ibid. 179). The question of providence
in Λ cannot be avoided if one reads Λ.10 with any seriousness. Providence and ontological causality need not
be distinct however, especially if the cause of the order in the whole is equally the cause of actuality of all the
substances.

10
as an army? For its well-being is in its order and its general, but more the general. He does
not exist because of the order, but the order because of him.30

In this analogy, the army is representative of the whole, which has its actuality in virtue of its

order, since it would not even be an army without an order. We must keep in mind that this

analogy is responding to a very specific question about the nature of the whole, that is, the

whole as a distinct being, which has its own primary motion and order. In particular,

Aristotle considers where its good, i.e., its perfection and actuality, lies. The structure of the

analogy is reminiscent of Aristotle’s response to the Platonic Ideas,31 seen through the

examples of art and reproduction:32 a sensible substance truly possesses its nature in itself,

yet the origin of its nature is an external cause similar in nature to it (either as the same form

biologically, or as the artist’s pattern). In a similar manner, the general gives his army its

order but remains, nevertheless, distinct from it. This order, however, does not just originate

in the general arbitrarily but according to the general being a general. The army’s order

depends upon the general to such a degree that Aristotle suggests that the good belongs more

to general than to the army’s possession of its own order. Aquinas’ explanation of this is that

the army exists for the sake of doing the general’s will, but the general does not exist for the

sake of the army.33 This is a valid reading of the text so long as it is interpreted in such a way

that it is not subject to the Aristotle’s criticism of Anaxagoras, that νοῦς moved all things for

an external end, and thus does not stand as the good of the whole.34 The army (and its order)

30
1075a11-15: ἐπισκεπτέον δὲ καὶ ποτέρως ἔχει ἡ τοῦ ὅλου φύσις τὸ ἀγαθὸν καὶ τὸ ἄριστον, πότερον
κεχωρισμένον τι καὶ αὐτὸ καθ᾽ αὑτό, ἢ τὴν τάξιν. ἢ ἀμφοτέρως ὥσπερ στράτευμα; καὶ γὰρ ἐν τῇ τάξει τὸ εὖ καὶ
ὁ στρατηγός, καὶ μᾶλλον οὗτος: οὐ γὰρ οὗτος διὰ τὴν τάξιν ἀλλ᾽ ἐκείνη διὰ τοῦτόν ἐστιν.”
31
1071b14-15. Aristotle says that the Ideas will not be principles of sensible substances if they do not have a
principle which can effect change, i.e., generation.
32
1070a27. The causes of the sensible substances are also sensible substances, which have a capacity to cause
either something like themselves, or to make something according to a pattern or plan contained in the mind.
33
Aquinas, §2630.
34
1075b9.

11
is the direct effect of the general’s actualizing activity (i.e., organizing or raising the army),

and through his activity the army caused to become like its ruling principle out of an initial

unlikeness.

The general of course represents God, the separate substance and first mover, who

already possesses complete actuality and causes the actuality of the cosmos. All four causes

and principles of substance are present in this analogy: form, matter and privation on the side

of the whole which is given order and actuality, and the agency of separate actuality and

form, on the side of God. These principles describe the relationships between substances, and

thus as part of an ordered whole. Both perishable and imperishable sensible substance are

thus shown to possess a very real likeness to the cosmic order, whereby the three elements of

the natural whole depend upon a transcendent agent, which is always already actual. In order

to establish the validity of this interpretation of Metaphysics Λ, the analogy of the general

and the army must be shown to be operative in the accounts of all three kinds of substance.

For each in its own way, the transcendent character of agency and actuality is distinct from

and prior to the principles associated with potentiality.

1.6 OUTLINE OF THE ARGUMENT

Chapter 2 first examines the principles that Aristotle attributes to sensible substances,

and explains how these four principles (form, matter, privation and agency) apply to the

perishable sensible substances. By understanding how these four principles work in relation

to perishable sensible substance, I will establish in the subsequent chapters the extent to

which these principles can be attributed to all substances by analogy, a claim which Aristotle

makes in Λ.4. Secondly, I examine sensible perishable substances as an example of an

12
analogical unity within a class of substances. I will then show that analogy that alone cannot

be the ground of such a unity, and what is needed for it to be express a real unity. Since

Aristotle already accepts that “perishable sensible substance” is a meaningful division of

substance showing that unity of such substances is analogical will affirm the possibility that

such a unity might also be applied to all substances. Finally I will show how the analogy of

the army and the general applies to the sensible perishable substances, demonstrating that it

is possible to employ this analogy in a meaningful and helpful way which clarifies these

perishable substances and their principles in themselves. Understanding perishable sensible

substances according to this analogy is also a first step in showing how these seemingly

lowly substances have a certain structural likeness to the divine. Chapter 3 addresses how the

principles of sensible substance apply to the eternal sensible substances, and will take stock

of the difficulties involved, especially whether these principles can be applied in the same

way as they are to the perishable sensible substances. As with the second chapter, it will

examine how the analogy of the army and the general applies to them. In order to do so we

will also consider vexing problems posed by Aristotle’s astronomical account in Λ.8,

difficulties introduced by the revolving or rewinding spheres. Besides providing a basic

understanding of how the heavens are ordered, I show how Aristotle tried to establish a

heavenly system that allowed each of the unmoved movers to be counted by being an

immediate cause of one of the heavenly motions. Finally, the chapter shows how the

unmoved movers are the efficient, exemplary, and final causes of the spheres. Since in

Aristotle’s system each sphere has its own unmoved mover, this examination of the operation

of the principles of substance in heavenly beings opens up the question of the final chapter,

how the analogy of the general and the army applies to the separate substances in themselves.

13
Chapter 4, the final chapter and conclusion, turns to immaterial, unmoving substance,

showing that of the four causes from Λ.2-5, only agency applies to the unmoved mover, but

that this need not threaten the possibility that all substances can be described by these

analogical principles. The analogy itself describes the relationship between two substances,

one caused and one uncaused. The unmoved movers do belong to this relationship, but do not

have any causes. While the form of the caused substance is often taken to be the most

important of the causes, agency is actually primary, since it is an actuality prior to form. This

helps illustrate the complete primacy of the general over the army in the analogy. Having

established that even the unmoved movers belong to the analogical structure that explains the

causes of both eternal and perishable substance, the fourth chapter concludes by showing

how the three kinds of substances are ordered together by the unmoved movers. The reason

the analogy holds between the three kinds of substance is that all substances approximate the

divine actuality as far as they are able. The four analogical principles discovered in the

analysis of sensible perishable substances are thus shown to apply to all three kinds of

substance, once these are understood through the analogy of the general and the army.

14
CHAPTER 2 THE PERISHABLE SENSIBLE SUBSTANCES

The first kind of substances to be considered are the sublunary sensible substances,

both natural and artificial. In chapters two to five of Metaphysics Λ, Aristotle establishes the

initial list of causes and principles of sensible substance. Beyond the insight gained into

sensible substances through an examination of these opening chapters of Metaphysics Λ, a

careful reading of this section also shows us what kind of causes and principles of a

substance Aristotle is seeking. A second reason for the importance of this first section is its

implicit and explicit reliance upon analogical unity. On more than one occasion 35 Aristotle

makes a distinction between the way in which the causes of things are different and the way

they are the same for individual substances. Aristotle rejects separate universals, e.g. the

Platonic Ideas. The principles of each substance are a certain form, i.e. the actuality of the

individual substance, a particular matter (potentiality for this actuality), along with a

substance which causes the potentiality to become actual. Each set of causes is particular, and

no substance shares all of the same causes with another.36 The principles of substance can

only be the same, and understood universally, through a structural or analogical likeness.

Since there cannot be a science of individuals for Aristotle, but only of universals, a science

of substance, i.e. a science of its principles and causes, depends upon such an analogy to

provide the common principles for such a science.37 I will first show how the analogy of the

35
1070a30; 1071a34.
36
The particular form and matter must be different, though the efficient cause could be one and the same
substance.
37
The particular causes could not be known as causes without a universal knowledge of causes. In Metaphysics
M, Aristotle concludes that “knowledge has a double meaning, just as knowing does, knowledge potentially and
knowledge actually. The potential knowledge as matter is universal and indefinite and is knowledge of a
universal and indefinite object, but actual knowledge is definite and has a definite object, it is a particular
knowledge of a particular thing”. (“ἡ γὰρ ἐπιστήμη, ὥσπερ καὶ τὸ ἐπίστασθαι, διττόν, ὧν τὸ μὲν δυνάμει τὸ δὲ
ἐνεργείᾳ. ἡ μὲν οὖν δύναμις ὡς ὕλη τοῦ καθόλου οὖσα καὶ ἀόριστος τοῦ καθόλου καὶ ἀορίστου ἐστίν, ἡ δ᾽
ἐνέργεια ὡρισμένη καὶ ὡρισμένου, τόδε τι οὖσα τοῦδέ τινος…”) Metaphysics M, 1087a15-19. (All the

15
general and the army sufficiently describes, and even illuminates the principles and causes of

sensible, perishable substances. By establishing just how the principles enumerated in the

first half of Λ relate to this analogy we will set a standard against which we can compare the

how the same analogy is applied to the other two kinds of substances, and thereby, to

substance as a whole.

2.1 THE FOUR CAUSES AND PRINCIPLES OF SENSIBLE


SUBSTANCE

The relationship we are now considering is that between the intrinsic causes (form,

matter and privation) and extrinsic cause (agency) of substance.38 These causes must be

carefully understood, both in terms of what each cause is in itself and how they relate to each

other. Once properly understood the structure of the causes and principles of perishable

substances can be related to the analogy of the general and the army, and thereby, ultimately,

also to God and the cosmos. Similarly, as per the proportional nature of Aristotelian analogy,

the structure of God and the cosmos might also be understood as analogically descriptive of

the causes of all substances. As we noted in the introduction, there is a difficulty regarding

the universal applicability of matter and privation as causes of substances. Nevertheless, they

are, certainly, causes of all the substances in the sublunary realm. It is essential to understand

these four principles Aristotle initially gives, and is indeed, satisfied with,39 to explain

translations from the Metaphysics are my own.) Lynne Spellman, in Substance and Separation in Aristotle,
concludes that Aristotle’s conception of knowledge acknowledges that particular substances are what is known
but as being “numerically the same” and “indistinguishable from other species of the same kind.” (Spellman,
82.)
38
1070b29-32; 1071a34.
39
1071b1. Aristotle begins Λ.6 with definitive statement about the state of the investigation of the principles of
sensible substance, and the complexities of their sameness and difference, that is, that “they have been said.”
“τίνες μὲν οὖν αἱ ἀρχαὶ τῶν αἰσθητῶν καὶ πόσαι, καὶ πῶς αἱ αὐταὶ καὶ πῶς ἕτεραι, εἴρηται.”

16
sensible substances. How any of these grander relationships and puzzles are to be understood

depends upon a solid understanding of the substantial principles laid out in the first half of

the work.

The beings that are described by the structure of these four causes are not kinds of

being, but particular beings. Just as one real general gives order to an individual army, and

God is the cause of the one and only cosmos,40 so are all substances individual actualities

with equally individual causes. Aristotle points this out in chapter three by giving two

examples, saying:

It is indeed evident because of these causes that Ideas are not necessary, for a man begets
another man, and each man a particular man. Likewise in the case of the arts; for the medical
art is the form of health.41

It is individual substances that cause others individuals to come to be and to be what they are;

a man begets a man in virtue of being a man, and a doctor health in virtue of the medical art.

Similarly in chapter five Aristotle notes that “…and so these [proximate causes] are not the

universals; a principle of an individual substances is individual.”42 Aristotle uses these

principles to explain how substances can both be and be involved in generation, destruction

and change generally. In Λ, specifically in Λ.2, Aristotle gives an account of change, which

40
1074a32-38. Here Aristotle argues against the possibility of multiple cosmoi on account of the prime mover
being one (and immaterial).
41
1070a27-28: “φανερὸν δὴ ὅτι οὐδὲν δεῖ διά γε ταῦτ᾽ εἶναι τὰς ἰδέας: ἄνθρωπος γὰρ ἄνθρωπον γεννᾷ, ὁ καθ᾽
ἕκαστον τὸν τινά: ὁμοίως δὲ καὶ ἐπὶ τῶν τεχνῶν: ἡ γὰρ ἰατρικὴ τέχνη ὁ λόγος τῆς ὑγιείας ἐστίν.” ‘ἐκεῖνα’, in the
neuter plural, refers to the two neuter predicates of the previous sentence, “πάντων δὴ πρῶται ἀρχαὶ τὸ ἐνεργείᾳ
πρῶτον τοδὶ καὶ ἄλλο ὃ δυνάμει.” Following Ross, I take the subject ‘πάντων δὴ πρῶται ἀρχαὶ’ to mean
proximate rather than first principles. Ross, however, takes the ‘ἐκεῖνα’ to refer to universal causes, which
would mean 1071a20 would read “And so these universals do not exist”. (W.D. Ross, Aristotle's Metaphysics,
Vol. II. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1970) 365.)
42
1071a18-20. “ἐκεῖνα μὲν οὖν τὰ καθόλου οὐκ ἔστιν: ἀρχὴ γὰρ τὸ καθ᾽ ἕκαστον τῶν καθ᾽ ἕκαστον:...”

17
is essential for understanding substantial being, especially of the perishable sort. The

relationship between change and actuality hearkens back to two of the pillars of Platonic

idealis, Parmenidean being and the Heraclitean flux, between which Aristotle’s theory

intends to navigate. In so doing it establishes the analogically similar causes of all sensible,

and therefore changeable,43 substances, which explain the being and becoming of substances

through their relation to other substances that are their principles.

Two points emerge from a close reading of Λ.2 and 3: first, form, matter and

privation are the logical parts of a sensible being, rather than its corporeal parts, and second,

these principles explain how actuality includes potentiality. They describe, respectively, the

actuality of a substance (form), a potency for the actualization of the same substance

(matter), and the other substance in which this potency exists, and is regarded as being in a

state of privation relative to the form. David Charles’ analysis of matter in Λ.2 provides an

alternative to the misconception that form is imposed upon matter as if the two were distinct

beings at odds, or even conflicting natures forced into one actuality. Charles offers a

description of matter which is equally applicable to the perishable and eternal sensible

substances, saying that “Matter, in both cases, might be taken to be what is directly required

if the relevant substance is to carry out its requisite changes…”44 These changes are

43
Charles, 83. Charles considers whether sensible substances are changeable in virtue of being sensible, a point
which Aristotle states matter-of-factly. Charles’ suggests that because all sensible things are abstracted from
matter in perception, they must also have matter, and if matter, potentency of some sort, and are therefore
changeable.
44
Charles, 91. Much of Charles’ essay on Λ.2 engages with the difficulty of assigning matter generally to all
sensible substances when some have matter for change and others, the eternal sensible substances, do not. One
of Charles’ aims is to determine whether they can share matter as principle by way of analogy, so that matter
plays an equivalent role in each. He determines that the analogical likeness shared by all matters, as descriptive
of substance being, is “just the potentiality to change or be changed in the ways required by the form.” (Ibid.)
This agrees with what I am proposing, insofar as it accepts that all sensible substances are caused in virtue of a
capacity that is actualized by an agent. Charles is most helpful for showing that though the heavenly bodies do
not come to be, they do have a matter in a way that is analogous to the sublunary substances.

18
described by the form.45 Gadamer describes Aristotle’s concept of matter thus, “Was erst so

und dann anders sein kann, ist ein Sein, das weder so noch anders ist, das beides nicht ist: ein

Sein, das durch sein Seinkönnen charaktisiert ist.”46 Matter is nothing, except a capacity for

some being or substance to become actual. Therein lies the wonderful sufficiency of

Aristotle’s example of colour and a surface. A surface has a capacity to be coloured. Its

capacity to be coloured is not a colour, yet it must always be coloured, either white or not-

white—and it must always be specific capacity, e.g., colour, rather than for sound. Matter,

understood as this, cannot be a corporeal part of anything, nor can it be opposed to an

actuality. Therefore, Aristotle explicitly rejects the crude interpretation in Λ.10, saying that

some thinkers make the mistake of assigning matter as one of the two contraries, i.e. as form

or privation, which negate each other.47 We must be cautious, however. The three principles,

or elements, as Aristotle also terms them, do exist contemporaneously, but in a qualified

way, which explains the changeable nature of a substance rather than its constitutive parts

(e.g., H2O is a constitutive description).48 Aristotle’s introduction to Λ.2 establishes as much

in its simple opening phrase, “substance is changeable”.49 Immediately thereafter he notes

that a pair of contraries is necessary to explain change,50 but that they themselves do not

change.51 These contrary actualities, one of which is the form proper, and the other the

privation explain change, along with the matter. The capacity to be other, i.e., the matter, is

45
These changes could include all the changes that are involved in the growth and daily activities of a natural
sensible substance.
46
Gadamer, 52.
47
1075a33.
48
Cf. Charles, 95. Charles notes that Aristotle’s strategy for defining matter deliberately avoids a definition that
describes matter as the physical constituents of a substance, rather than a principle describing the potential
being of an actuality.
49
1069b2. “ἡ δ᾽ αἰσθητὴ οὐσία μεταβλητή”.
50
He specifies that it is contraries, rather than mere opposites which are necessary to explain change. The
opposites must belong to the same genera.
51
1069b6. “οὐ γὰρ τὰ ἐναντία μεταβάλλει.”

19
actualized otherwise, so that one form is replaced by another. This is possible because the

capacity to be otherwise existed in the first actuality, which relative to the new form is a

privation. These three causes, along with the efficient cause, suffice to explain how one thing

can change into another.

There are four kinds of changes: substantial, qualitative, quantitative and local

change. The first kind is the generation or destruction of a substance, while the last three are

changes in relative or πρός τι beings, for which a substance and its capacities are the matter.52

In these latter changes, the matter of the change is the substance which persists through the

change unchanged with regard to its essence. Essential change, the change of one substance

into another, is the kind of change which concerns us, since its principles are the principles

which govern sensible substances. Aristotle’s approach to explaining essential change

depends upon the potency that exists in a substance in virtue of its form, since what it is

determines its potentialities. Matter is not like Anaxagoras’ One, in which everything was

mixed and needed only to be sorted out.53 On the contrary, the matter of any change exists in

virtue of and through the actually existing substance, which defines the changes it is capable

of undergoing. Matter is not a substance but the matter for a substance is in a substance, in

virtue of its form. The form is what some being is, it is its distinct actuality, which either

orders itself in virtue of itself (in the case of nature),54 or is simply an imposed order (in the

52
1069b9-13. “εἰ δὴ αἱ μεταβολαὶ τέτταρες, ἢ κατὰ τὸ τί ἢ κατὰ τὸ ποῖον ἢ πόσον ἢ ποῦ, καὶ γένεσις μὲν ἡ ἁπλῆ
καὶ φθορὰ ἡ κατὰ τὸ τόδε, αὔξησις δὲ καὶ φθίσις ἡ κατὰ τὸ ποσόν, ἀλλοίωσις δὲ ἡ κατὰ τὸ πάθος, φορὰ δὲ ἡ
κατὰ τόπον, εἰς ἐναντιώσεις ἂν εἶεν τὰς καθ᾽ ἕκαστον αἱ μεταβολαί.”
53
1069b21. “καὶ τοῦτ᾽ ἔστι τὸ Ἀναξαγόρου ἕν: βέλτιον γὰρ ἢ ὁμοῦ πάντα…”
54
The discussion of nature in Metaphysics Δ.4 is helpful for understanding form and substance. Nature is the
source of the primary motion in a natural being, a non-artificial substance (1014b19). The primary motion of a
being is actuality. For animals it is to grow and live as an animal, for the elements to move into their proper
place, and for the heavens to move with an eternal circular motion. Aristotle extends this notion of an internal
and proper principle to substances of all kinds by way of analogy because it describes it as the attaining and
attainment of substantial form, “φύσις δὲ ἥ τε πρώτη ὕλη…καὶ τὸ εἶδος καὶ ἡ οὐσία: τοῦτο δ᾽ ἐστὶ τὸ τέλος τῆς

20
case of art). It is true that sensible substances, at least perishable ones, have parts, i.e. distinct

body parts,55 but they are actualized as a whole and refer to the form, just as eyes and feet are

distinct parts which belong to and serve a whole substance. Form is the actuality of the whole

of a being, and all parts of a body are subordinate to this one, internally actualized, order. 56

This actuality, however, as sensible and thus corporeal does have the potential to be

actualized in a different way by a different form, but how it can change is dependent upon its

actuality. One form, as a principle of order, does not change into another, but is replaced by

another by the agency of something else.57

The relationships between the principles of substance are clear, particularly that

matter and privation are dependent upon form. Matter is a capacity of certain forms or

changes, and is thereby defined as relative to forms. Like form, it is does not come to be in

the process of change, but already exists and is changed or actualized differently.58 The

matter is not something absolutely but is in the privation. In the process of change the

privation is the actuality that has the matter or capacity for whatever form comes to be. While

in itself it is an actuality, relative to the generated substance it is a negation, an absence of the

γενέσεως” (1015a7,11), and thus says that every substance is called a nature, “μεταφορᾷ δ᾽ ἤδη καὶ ὅλως πᾶσα
οὐσία φύσις λέγεται διὰ ταύτην, ὅτι καὶ ἡ φύσις οὐσία τίς ἐστιν (ibid, 12).
55
The definition of forms always includes parts, in the way that one would call a human being a two-footed
animal (1037b14). In another way, since human being has parts, hand, eye, foot etc., on account of its form, we
may also say that the form has parts.
56
Aristotle, De Anima, 412a17-21.The form itself is immaterial, such as the soul in living things in the De
Anima, in which Aristotle says , “the couldn’t be a body; for body is one of the things that depends upon a
substratum, or rather, is a substratum and matter. It is necessary that the soul is a substance, the form [and
actuality] of a potentially living natural body.” (“…οὐκ ἄν εἴη τὸ ψυχή· οὐ γάρ ἐστι τῶν καθ’ὑποκειμένου τό
σῶμα, μᾶλλον δ’ ὡς ὑποκείμένον καὶ ὕλη. ἀναγκαῖον ἄρα τὴν ψυχὴν οὐσίαν εἶναι ὡς εἶδος σώματος φυσικοῦ
δυνάμει ζωὴν ἔχοντος.”) Aristotle, nevertheless, acknowledges that informing can even be seen as effected
through heat and concoction. This is considered in depth by Gad Freudenthal. In his work Aristotle’s Theory of
Material Substance he considers the role of heat in transforming the ‘logos’ of a corporeal entity so that it
becomes something else, such as the case of reproduction. (Freudenthal, 22-24.)
57
1069b36. “μετὰ ταῦτα ὅτι οὐ γίγνεται οὔτε ἡ ὕλη οὔτε τὸ εἶδος, λέγω δὲ τὰ ἔσχατα. πᾶν γὰρ μεταβάλλει τὶ
καὶ ὑπό τινος καὶ εἴς τι:”.
58
Ibid.

21
form of the newly generated substance.59 Aristotle’s example of the house in Λ.4 is helpful.

A house is constructed from bricks, which were without the order of the house previously.60

They were not disorderly bricks in themselves, but only the disorderly bricks of a house.

Once the house is built there are no longer any disorderly bricks, but a house. The nature of

the bricks in themselves is not destroyed, but assimilated to a greater form, of which they

were previously deprived. Likewise the corporeal parts of a sensible substance changed into

another are reorganized. We might call these parts the ‘first matter’ of a substance, 61 like the

parts of the body, having the capacity to be moved with the characteristic motion of the

nature of a form if we recall the Aristotle’s description of nature as “that immanent thing

from something which a growing thing grows, or still, the source of the primary motion in

each natural being in virtue of which [a natural being] exists.”62 The matter has the capacity

for this first motion to be actualized by the form and the efficient cause.

We must pause to consider Aristotle’s language in Λ.3 which appears to grant matter

substantiality and independence, against which we have so far been arguing. All sensible

substances are an actualization, by the form, of some capacity, or matter. Nevertheless,

Aristotle says that in some cases form is able to be considered distinctly from the matter, and

in other cases it is identical with its matter. The prior kind are natural substances; the latter

are the objects of art,63 which, though they were denied substantiality in Z and H,64 are

59
With the proviso that privation cannot be applied like this in every change. Aristotle would not call health,
one of his common examples of a substance in the process of change, the privation of disease.
60
1070b28.
61
Cf. 1017b23-25. Here Aristotle says that substance can indeed refer to both the form and last matter, the body
of a particular substance, which is what it is only as ordered by the form.
62
1014b18-20. “ἕνα δὲ ἐξ οὗ φύεται πρώτου τὸ φυόμενον ἐνυπάρχοντος: ἔτι ὅθεν ἡ κίνησις ἡ πρώτη ἐν ἑκάστῳ
τῶν φύσει ὄντων ἐν αὐτῷ ᾗ αὐτὸ ὑπάρχει…”
63
1070a14. In those those substance which exist only by contact Aristotle does not recognise them as
possessing a nature or form of their own, except in their arrangement. He says, “On some occasions, the
particular being is nothing apart from the composite substance, such as the form of a house, unless in the sense
of the art [of housebuilding]…” (“ἐπὶ μὲν οὖν τινῶν τὸ τόδε τι οὐκ ἔστι παρὰ τὴν συνθετὴν οὐσίαν, οἷον οἰκίας

22
counted as substances in Λ.65 To show the way in which each is a substance, Aristotle makes

a second list of the three kinds of substance, saying:

The [kinds of] substances are three in number: the matter is an individual thing existing
visibly (those beings which exist by contact rather than a natural unity are matter or
substratum); the nature is an individual thing and a condition for possessing this nature; the
third kind of substance is that according to both matter and nature, such as Socrates or
Callias.66

Is Aristotle seriously suggesting that matter and form exist independently of each other? No.

Instead, his consideration of the combination of matter and form answers two questions

about sensible substances: how do artificial substances exist, and what is relationship the

between members of the same natural species?

Λ.3’s list of three kinds of substances is contextualized by its location in the text. It

appears directly after the description of generation in Λ.3 which introduces the efficient

cause. In that discussion, Aristotle makes the distinction between artificial and natural

substances, and also substances caused by chance or by spontaneity. 67 The common factor in

every case of generation is that “each substance comes to be from something of the same

name (both natural substances and all the rest).”68 This is referring to the likeness of agent

τὸ εἶδος, εἰ μὴ ἡ τέχνη…”)The form of such substance is nothing more than the arrangement of their parts,
which possessing the capacity to be so arranged, are called the matter.
64
1041b29-30. “ἐπεὶ δ᾽ ἔνια οὐκ οὐσίαι τῶν πραγμάτων, ἀλλ᾽ ὅσαι οὐσίαι, κατὰ φύσιν…” Here in Metaphysics
Z on Aristotle says that some things are not substances, and only those which are according to nature, or a
nature, are substances.
65
1070a5.
66
1070a9-13. “οὐσίαι δὲ τρεῖς, ἡ μὲν ὕλη τόδε τι οὖσα τῷ φαίνεσθαι (ὅσα γὰρ ἁφῇ καὶ μὴ συμφύσει, ὕλη καὶ
ὑποκείμενο), ἡ δὲ φύσις τόδε τι καὶ ἕξις τις εἰς ἥν: ἔτι τρίτη ἡ ἐκ τούτων ἡ καθ᾽ ἕκαστα, οἷον Σωκράτης ἢ
Καλλίας.”
67
1070a5-6.
68
1070a4-5. “μετὰ ταῦτα ὅτι ἑκάστη ἐκ συνωνύμου γίγνεται οὐσία (τὰ γὰρ φύσει οὐσίαι καὶ τὰ ἄλλα).”

23
and its effect.69 Aristotle is not describing human conventions of naming, but the ontological

basis that explains why names are shared. That lions beget lions and bakers make baked

goods describes an essential relationship between the cause and the caused, that any cause

causes something like itself, albeit with some differences, depending on the nature of the

cause.70

The substances that Aristotle associates with matter have two primary attributes:

visibility and external unity. This is contrasted with the form, which is described with no

reference to a corporeal existence, but rather a principle, a nature, which animates bodies.

Both artificial and natural beings are substance, but the artificial have a cause of their

apparent unity externally, while the natural possess it intrinsically. They consist of parts

which have a nature, e.g., the tree-ish nature of the wooden bed,71 but considered as a whole,

it is an externally imposed contact rather than nature that is the unifying principle. This

contact is a not a nature, but is still a form, since it gives the product of art its shape or

essence, e.g. to be a chair rather than a table. It is against this likeness of form that Aristotle

establishes what form is in itself. Whereas each of the parts of a natural substance has a

69
Aristotle does not specify whether “that from which it comes” is of the matter or the agent, or somehow both.
Elders cites Ross and Aquinas as taking this claim to refer to the likeness of agent and its effect, although he
cautions that elsewhere in the Aristotelian corpus similar expressions have primarily referred to the agent, but
“material and formal causality are connoted.” (Elders, 99-100.) Aristotle lists four ways for things to come to
be, by nature, art, chance and spontaneity, all of which describe kinds of agency, rather than an ex quo,
suggesting that above Aristotle is referring to the likeness of the agent and its effect. Additionally, when
Aristotle gives an example of the precept just stated, he offers the familiar “man begets man.” Man here is not a
matter, since the man that is begetting does not change, but the efficient, agent cause which produces a
substances like itself. This likeness of agent and effect is very important one for understanding Aristotelian
causality, and will become central to this project.
70
Aquinas, §2444. The likeness, if not specific, insofar as the artist differs specifically from the artefact, is still
grounded in a similarity. The artist has the form of the art in his mind (1070a16-17; the form is the art), the
possession of which makes him an artist (of some sort).
71
Aristotle, Physics II, 193a12-17. In this section Aristotle distinguishes two senses of nature, one referring to
the form and another to the substratum or matter. His example of the nature as a matter is the persistence of
wood as wood though it is shaped into a bed. He claims that if such a bed were buried it would sprout a tree, in
accordance with the nature of wood, rather than a bed. All parts of artificial beings likewise have an underlying
“nature”.

24
relation to all its other parts, the parts of an artificial substance are indifferent to each other.

Their plan or order exists in the mind of the artist or as the art itself, but not in the parts

themselves.72 That they are called matter initially seems to be in a kind of tension with the

claim that matter is nothing, but it is not. An artificial substance is nothing its parts ordered

by art; it does not possess its form by nature. Considered in themselves, the products of art

are identical with their matter.

Natural substances have an intrinsic unifying principle, a cause of their σύμφυσις, or

growing-together of their parts to be a whole.73 This is the nature, which describes precisely

what those things that grow together grow into.74 It is the order of the sensible parts. What

the nature orders is sensible, but as distinguished from matter, which has the capacity to be

ordered, it is not visible in itself, and hence can be considered separately from the composite,

particular substances, although it does not exist apart. Hence, particular natural substances,

such as Socrates and Callias, are said to be according to matter and form because they are not

only one by contact, having corporeal parts, but this contact is caused and determined by the

ordering nature.

Aristotle’s description of nature explains natural generation and unity of species.

While Aristotle eschews Plato’s Ideas and the possibility of a universal existing substantially

and apart from its instances, he nevertheless accounts for the sameness of form within a

species through generation, and more specifically, reproduction. In generation the efficient

cause exists prior to form that it generates, but the form is simultaneous with the existence of

that which is generated. Aristotle thus says,

72
1070a14-15-17. “ἐπὶ μὲν οὖν τινῶν τὸ τόδε τι οὐκ ἔστι παρὰ τὴν συνθετὴν οὐσίαν, οἷον οἰκίας τὸ εἶδος, εἰ μὴ
ἡ τέχνη…”
73
Cf. 1070a10. Aristotle does not attribute σύμφυσις to natural substances positively, but notes that this is what
those which do not have a nature lack.
74
1070a11.

25
It is indeed evident because of these causes that Ideas are not necessary, for a man begets
another man, and each man a particular man. Likewise in the case of the arts; for the medical
art is the form of health.75

The form in two men is at once the same and different, especially in the case of parent and

child. One causes a like form to come to be in an appropriate matter. The informing power of

an efficient cause allows Aristotle to reject separate universal forms because there is an

explanation for how a like form comes to be in substance, while retaining a certain

universality of forms, since an identical form is perpetuated through a species. Natural

substances in the sublunary realm have the power to make other substance like themselves,

not in addition to their form, but in virtue of it. The generative powers are part of a nature.

Art too is works in a similar way. The pattern of the product is one with the power that

makes it: the science of health both makes doctors doctors, i.e., the ability to make others

healthy and share according to understanding the causes of health. Nevertheless, nature is

superior to art, because a natural being makes another like itself, which can in turn make

another like it, so that the species exists eternally.76 A natural species remains the same

through the generation and corruption of its individual members, just as the sections of a

circle are always in a different location on account of its rotation, which is the cause of both

its difference and sameness. Art, however, resembles rectilinear motion, which has a set

beginning and end. With each completed pair of shoes the shoemaker must begin again; the

75
1070a28-30. “φανερὸν δὴ ὅτι οὐδὲν δεῖ διά γε ταῦτ᾽ εἶναι τὰς ἰδέας: ἄνθρωπος γὰρ ἄνθρωπον γεννᾷ, ὁ καθ᾽
ἕκαστον τὸν τινά: ὁμοίως δὲ καὶ ἐπὶ τῶν τεχνῶν: ἡ γὰρ ἰατρικὴ τέχνη ὁ λόγος τῆς ὑγιείας ἐστίν.”
76
Aristotle, De Anima, 415a27-415b1.

26
shoes don’t continue the activity of the shoemaker. While natural substances are self-

perpetuating, artificial substances do not themselves produce anything.

The structure of substantial change is clear. The matter for a certain substance is

actualized, and hence this initial form is called a privation. The matter of a change always

exists prior to the change, in another actuality, and this determines its potencies. This is why

the matter is not said to ‘come to be’ at 1069b36. These three elements, as Aristotle calls

them, do not explain why there is a change, or in what way the form also exists before the

change occurs. The role of the agent answers both of these questions. The agent is not an

intrinsic cause, but extrinsic.77 The agent is also a substance, and thus is actual and has form.

The agent acts upon the matter and actualizes a form which was previously only a potency.

What the agent effects is in virtue of its own form, in the case of nature, or some form that it

possesses in mind, in the case of art, which still depends on rational and productive human

nature. Regarding this, Aristotle remarks that “each substance comes to be from a [substance]

of the same name.”78 It is in this way that a man begets a man by nature, and a sculptor and

statue by his art. The agent’s role in substantial change not only begins the process of

change, but directs what changes occur. The agent brings a matter into accord with his own

form (or art), such that the form and agent can be viewed as one. The form does not come to

be, but comes to be actualized in another substance, as with the medical art and health, or the

begetter and begotten man.79

77
1070a1.
78
Ibid, 7-8.
79
1070b33.

27
2.2 The analogical unity of the four causes and principles of
sensible substance

The four proximate causes are always particular substances. Aristotle acknowledges

therefore, that they are always “different for different substances, but if we should speak

universally and according to analogy, they are the principles of all.”80 A science of substance

depends upon this analogical unity. Even if some substances did share a particular efficient

cause, or had, at different times, come from the same matter,81 their forms, which are

simultaneous with and identical to their distinct actualities, are different. There cannot be a

shared set of substances which are the proximate causes of all sensible sublunary substance,

and there would not be common principles of substance, and thus no science. 82 In Λ.5,

Aristotle distinguishes between three ways in which the principles of sensible substance can

be considered as common despite their differences: 1) they each have, by analogy, form,

matter, privation and agent; 2) everything depends upon substances, without which nothing

that is would be; and 3) that that which is first in “complete reality”, God, is the cause of the

rest.83 The third recognizes that substances depend upon a first cause, a point which will

prove important for explaining the ground of their analogical unity. The second establishes

something common about substances, i.e., that they are causes of themselves and all other

being. Only the first, however, can show that all the causes of sensible substance are

common.

80
1070a30-31. “τὰ δ᾽ αἴτια καὶ αἱ ἀρχαὶ ἄλλα ἄλλων ἔστιν ὥς, ἔστι δ᾽ ὡς, ἂν καθόλου λέγῃ τις καὶ κατ᾽
ἀναλογίαν, ταὐτὰ πάντων.”
81
That this is even possible is rather tenuous, since we have denied that matter has any being on it own.
82
See footnote 37.
83
Cf. 1071a33-5. “…πλὴν ὡδὶ καὶ πάντων, ὡδὶ μὲν ταὐτὰ ἢ τὸ ἀνάλογον, ὅτι ὕλη, εἶδος, στέρησις, τὸ κινοῦν,
καὶ ὡδὶ τὰ τῶν οὐσιῶν αἴτια ὡς αἴτια πάντων, ὅτι ἀναιρεῖται ἀναιρουμένων: ἔτι τὸ πρῶτον ἐντελεχείᾳ:”

28
It is necessary to understand how analogy makes the principles genuinely common to

all substances so that we might later see how they apply to all substances by a similar

analogy. Analogy by itself need not be the ground of the unity of a genus. An analogy

represents a structural likeness between at least four terms, e.g., A is to B as X is to Y. The

existence of such an analogy does not make A and B belong to the same science as X and Y.

Music and medicine could share such an analogy, perhaps, between harmony and health, and

the instruments used to achieve them, e.g., a lyre and a potion. Music and science, however,

would not fall under a single science. If an analogy is to describe the unity of sensible

substance, and perhaps all substance, in one science there must be something which enables

analogy to ground the unity of the causes and principles of substance.84

In Λ.4 and 5 Aristotle shows how the causes and principles are both different and the

same. Their difference is stated most simply as the familiar “the principles of different things

are different,”85 and the reason he gives is that the proximate principles of any substances are

always particulars themselves. A particular actuality actualizes a particular potentiality in

something else,86 and thus is not the principle of anything else, and certainly not a

universal.87 In Λ.4 Aristotle gives several parallel examples of particular causes to show that

they are structured in the same manner and fulfill the role of the form, matter, and

84
Crubellier, 139. Crubellier suggests that for Aristotle every substance has, in a sense, its own first principles,
since particular substances are “in a sense the most real beings.” Crubellier suggests that principles which are
“the same” will therefore have to be considered in a weaker, less strict sense that numerical unity. I think his
point is a fair one, but we should not take from it that recognizing an analogical unity is a secondary, trifling
abstraction. On the contrary, we will see that analogy provides insight into the nature of individual substances.
85
1070a30. “τὰ δ᾽ αἴτια καὶ αἱ ἀρχαὶ ἄλλα ἄλλων ἔστιν…”
86
1071a19-20.
87
We must also acknowledge on this point that Aristotle does admit that some causes can be stated universally,
which he states at 1071a18 (“ἔτι δὲ ὁρᾶν δεῖ ὅτι τὰ μὲν καθόλου ἔστιν εἰπεῖν, τὰ δ᾽ οὔ…”). Such a universal
cause would have to be a single, particular substance which affects all substances, or at least some whole, such
as that which is first in perfection is a universal cause by causing the rest (1071a35).

29
privation.88 He gives the examples of a house, of daytime, of colour, and of health and

describes each of their particular intrinsic causes, showing how the structure is the same in

each.89 These examples, though referring to beings that might not be considered substances,

point to a similar structure in art, the natural world and even accidental qualities. The

examples in Λ.4 point towards a universal structure in all beings and categories, which

Gadamer notes exists in endless variety, expressing its universality neither being a

hypostatized universal nor collapsing the differences between the proximate causes of

substances.90 Nevertheless, Aristotle says that Plato was “not speaking badly” when he

applied the Ideas to natural substances, which share and pass on a like form.91 This

commendation shows that Aristotle affirms that there is a way in which universals are

applicable to substances, and that there can be a specific unity, such as is found in living

substances. Universals, though they do not exist apart from particular substances, are

essential to science. Without them nothing common could be said; no predication would be

possible.

To begin to understand what allows an analogy to provide for meaningful unity we

can start with an example of where this is, for Aristotle, certainly the case. A natural species

88
1070b21
89
1070b20-22, 28-29. Aristotle gives the structure most explicitly in his account of the house, describing it as
having a form, some disorder (a privation), bricks (the matter) and a house-builder. Likewise the causes of
health are health, disease, the body and the medical art. For colour they are white, darkness and a surface; for
day and night the causes are light, darkness and air. The repetition makes manifests the same structure present
in each. Although we are investigating the causes of substances, in another way the causes of all beings are
being explored at the same time. (“οἷον ἐν χρώματι λευκὸν μέλαν ἐπιφάνεια: φῶς σκότος ἀήρ, ἐκ δὲ τούτων
ἡμέρα καὶ νύξ… ὑγίεια, νόσος, σῶμα: τὸ κινοῦν ἰατρική. εἶδος, ἀταξία τοιαδί, πλίνθοι: τὸ κινοῦν οἰκοδομική
καὶ εἰς ταῦτα διαιρεῖται ἡ ἀρχή.”)
90
Gadamer, 53. “Gegen Plato betont er also in unermüdlicher Variation die bloß analogische Selbigkeit der
Prinzipien.” The omnipresence of this analogy stands against the distinct Ideas for each kind of being, since
everything can be shown to share the same being in some sense. This is not necessarily a devastating attack on
Platonic idealism, but it does suggest the universal applicability of intrinsic causes, which do not participate in
an Idea.
91
1070a18-19. “διὸ δὴ οὐ κακῶς Πλάτων ἔφη ὅτι εἴδη ἔστιν ὁπόσα φύσει, εἴπερ ἔστιν εἴδη ἄλλα τούτων οἷον
πῦρ σὰρξ κεφαλή…”

30
is one such example. A specific unity is also an analogical unity. 92 The point which Aristotle

makes about the difference and sameness of the principles of Callias and Socrates describes

the relationship between members of the same natural species. Insofar as the causes of each

thing are particular, they are distinct causes. Callias has a different form than Socrates, and I

have a different form (i.e., actuality) than your form.93 As we discussed above, the causes and

principles of substances are themselves substances, and as such the same causes would be the

cause of one and the same substance. It is necessary that their causes be different.

Nevertheless, the members of the species share not only a similar form, but all the same

principles analogically. In our example, all have the form of humanity, and a human parent

and a like matter and privation, the (potency for human generation in) blood of the mother.94

Some analogies liken the structures of disparate beings to each other, but this is not the case

in the species, in which the likeness is not between desperate things, but substances which

seem to differ only in their individuality. The possibility of this specific unity, while it is

described by analogy, belongs to capability of the species to cause other beings of like form

92
Metaphysics Δ, 1016b35-6; Crubellier, 139. Crubellier lists the four kinds of being one listed towards the end
of Δ.6 (numerical, formal, generic, and analogical) as those which (besides the numerical unity) describe the
sameness of different priciples. That the specific or generic is distinct from the analogical does not preclude the
specific and generic from also being analogical unities. Aristotle makes this very point, saying “the latter
always follow with those prior”, so that the primary sense includes the broadest sense too, but not vice versa.
“ἀεὶ δὲ τὰ ὕστερα τοῖς ἔμπροσθεν ἀκολουθεῖ…”.
93
1071a27-29. “καὶ τῶν ἐν ταὐτῷ εἴδει ἕτερα, οὐκ εἴδει ἀλλ᾽ ὅτι τῶν καθ᾽ ἕκαστον ἄλλο, ἥ τε σὴ ὕλη καὶ τὸ
εἶδος καὶ τὸ κινῆσαν καὶ ἡ ἐμή, τῷ καθόλου δὲ λόγῳ ταὐτά.” Elders comments that the use of the second
person in refers to the concrete matter, i.e. the body. He also comments that the use of τὸ εἶδος in line 29 refers
even to personal characteristics, reflecting particular characteristics (see Freudenthal below). In this way my
form and yours really are different, and not just one form in different substances, which Aristotle sometimes
calls “τὰ ἔσχατα εἰδή”. Nevertheless these forms are still one universally. (Elders, 1927, 134). Aquinas speaks
similarly saying that the my form and your form differ as soul and body. Whether soul is quite the same as the
cause of the different characteristics of an individual he does not say. The form, as soul in the human, and
matter are one according to their universal intelligibility, i.e. the same in definition. (Aquinas, §2483.)
94
Freudenthal, 24-25. Freudenthal explains Aristotle’s physical account of generation according to vital heat.
The heat of the male semen concocts (literally, an evaporation of the cold water) the menses of the mother into
a similar form. The variation in the child produced depends upon the strength of the vital heat from the father.
The hotter the heat the more perfect the concoction, and the more the child resembles the father. Less heat will
result in either a form closer to a another relative, but not the father, or even a female child. While Aristotle
does not express this detail in Metaphysics Λ, it does show that the efficient cause is understood as being an
agent by conforming matter to itself.

31
to come to be. And because they are of a like form, they must have a like agent, 95 matter and

privation96. As man begets man, and a lion another lion, the possibility of a special unity

depends upon a cause which effects a likeness, power of agency. Aristotle will not go along

with Plato in accepting that this shared form has a separate existence, but the unity of the

species is nothing accidental—it belongs to the essence of natural beings to propagate a form

through analogically like offspring.

If we take the above conditions for analogy to be descriptive of a real unity, i.e., that

the analogy explains or manifests a kind of a formal likeness in virtue of a like, or even

common,97 origin, we can apply them to the level above the natural species, to the broader

category of natural sensible substances, or even to all substances. Sensible substances, taken

generally, differ more radically than members of the same species do since they do not all

share the same form. They do, however, share something in form, being or individual

actuality, or substance-being, i.e., existing apart and sensibly, whereas all accidental beings

depend upon them. This is the likeness that unites them, something common to them, either

prior to or in them. This likeness has a common cause which underlies this unity in

substance-being. It cannot be reproduction of a single form, as it is for the natural species,

but it must explain the actuality and potential for these substances to be actual.

There are a few possibilities as to what might provide the basis for this analogical

likeness. The first is the general capability of all substances to actualize other substances, or

at least, affect other substances. The sensible substances are always affecting each other in

some manner; some generate new substances by art or nature, some consume or destroy

95
Cf. 1070a4-5. Recalling the claim that things are generated from something of the same name, this would
apply across a whole species.
96
The matter and privation must be similar within a species because they must have the potential to become the
same form.
97
The same form exists throughout a species through reproduction.

32
others (and in so doing generate something else), others are incidentally involved in the

process of change, e.g., as a sword is used in destroying a living being (which in turn is

consumed or dissolved into its elements). This characteristic capacity of sensible substance to

actualize potentialities, and to be changed,98 even in many different ways, can be thought the

common cause of their likeness.

If we contend that the actualizing power of agents amid the infinite potential of the

sublunary realm is akin to reproduction insofar as it accounts for actualities coming to be and

their continuing activity of actualizing other substance, we can also trace this back to a single

cause. The second common originative principle we can consider is the Sun, which governs

and causes this cycle of generation and corruption in the course of the seasons.99 Aristotle

mentions it only once in Λ.5, where it is counted as cause of change even besides the

proximate agent. In Λ.4 and 5 God is mentioned twice, first at that end of Λ.4 as that which

“as first of all things moves all things”100 and then in Λ.5 God is described as universal cause

of all substances, since it is first in perfection or complete reality. 101 The Sun is not God, but

it is given a similar role as a remote, or even first cause 102 as the common cause of all

sublunary substances. Sublunary substances are subject to the Sun, which is itself a sensible,

albeit, eternal, substance. It is the cause of the actuality of sublunary substances in virtue of

its movement on the ecliptic, by which it governs the similar cycle of generation and

destruction in the sublunary realm.103 Moreover, it might be likened to the general of the

98
Even as actual they are still able to be changed or destroyed, and are themselves potentials.
99
1071a15-16; Aristotle, On Generation and Corruption, 336b16-20.
100
1070b35. Aquinas, §2474. Aquinas notes that Aristotle makes the proximate agent the first cause of
substance that it generates, and following this pattern, as per Physics VIII, we can find a first cause of this sort,
a first moving cause, God.
101
1070a36. “…τὸ πρῶτον ἐντελεχείᾳ.”
102
Relative to the sublunary realm.
103
Aristotle does not say any more about how it is a universal cause. It causes the natural world, probably by
effecting the agents in the world, which in turn also have particular effects. The Sun is therefore also involved

33
army, the army being the sublunary realm in this case, for which it is the extrinsic cause of

the pattern of generation, and thus also the cause of the actuality of all sublunary beings. The

reduction in Λ.5104 of the four causes to two, actuality and potentiality, under which matter

and privation are subsumed, fits easily with this analogy. The sublunary realm is a potential,

which is actualized, or ordered, by a prior actuality, the Sun. The actuality is in one way

effected by the Sun’s activity upon the potentiality of the natural substances, but this does not

negate the role of the proximate agent, e.g. the parent, which is the proximate cause of

actuality.105

The use of the Sun as a principle for describing the ground for the analogical unity of

the sensible substances by being the “remote” cause of the actuality of all of them can’t help

but lead us back to Plato’s own use of the Sun in the Republic. Insofar as the Sun is such a

cause, a universal cause, it seems not unlike that which as “first in perfection” 106 is the

universal cause. I will have more to say on this in the third chapter.

2.3 THE ANALOGY OF THE GENERAL AND THE ARMY AS


DESCRIPTIVE OF THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THE
PRINCIPLES OF SENSIBLE SUBSTANCE

The analogy of the general and the army illuminates the nature of the analogical

likeness of the causes and principles of substance. The analogy itself discusses the

relationship between the immanent and transcendent good of the cosmos. In particular, it

describes the structure of principles that all sensible substances share, expressing how a form

in the generation of beings, especially natural beings, whose reproduction, so influenced by the seasons (which
the Sun causes) is similar to the Sun’s cyclical activity.
104
Ibid,4-5. “ἔτι δ᾽ ἄλλον τρόπον τῷ ἀνάλογον ἀρχαὶ αἱ αὐταί, οἷον ἐνέργεια καὶ δύναμις…”
105
Cf. Ibid 13-17; Aristotle, On Generation and Corruption, 336b16-20; Aristotle, Physics II, 194b14.
106
1070a36.

34
comes to be actualized, which is its good, or alternatively the actualizing power of form,

which is the transcendent good, insofar as it the extrinsic cause of the good in a substance. It

describes, therefore, the relationship between substances in the sublunary realm, and even, if

we seriously follow Aristotle in acknowledging the Sun as the non-proximate cause of

actuality in the sublunary realm, the relationship between the whole sublunary realm and its

immediate transcendent good. In so doing, this analogy provides us with a general structure

that describes the unity of sublunary sensible substance to compare with the two other kinds

of substance and how they relate to the general and the army analogy.

As we have already noted, the analogy of the general and the army describes the

dependence of the good in a substance upon the extrinsic good. The analogy speaks not only

of the good but of the “good and the best”107 and answers the initial question: whether the

good and the best is separate from the cosmos (as the Platonic Ideas are separate) or is the

order of the cosmos in the cosmos (e.g. like the soul in a body). Aristotle answers that both

are true, but the former has priority, because the order in the cosmos depends upon an

extrinsic cause. What is meant by “the good and the best”? The use of τὸ ἀγαθὸν in Λ is

scant. It also appears in Aristotle’s description of Empedocles’ and Anaxagoras’ use of the

good as first principle.108 The question Aristotle poses about the nature of the cosmos does

not use ‘good’ to refer a distinct extrinsic cause, otherwise extrinsic cause alone would be

good. The good is also the order in the cosmos, i.e. to be just what it is, to possess its nature

fully. At the same time, like the form in the particular substances, it is the cause of it being

what it is. The cosmos’ unimpeded actuality is what is best about it (ἄριστον). Aristotle uses

ἄριστον elsewhere to describe the best states of being, especially with reference to God in

107
1075a11-12. “ἐπισκεπτέον δὲ καὶ ποτέρως ἔχει ἡ τοῦ ὅλου φύσις τὸ ἀγαθὸν καὶ τὸ ἄριστον, πότερον
κεχωρισμένον τι καὶ αὐτὸ καθ᾽ αὑτό, ἢ τὴν τάξιν.”
108
1075b1-11.

35
Λ.7, describing θεωρία as the best state to be in, and God’s life as this best, and God himself

as the best.109 In this way ἄριστον denotes the height or perfection of something. In the case

of the whole of nature, we would not be wrong to regard ἄριστον as the perfection of the

whole, the achievement of its best possible order. Framed in this way, the good is that which

causes this perfection to be in the whole of nature,110 or in the case of our particular

investigation, in any given sensible substance.

That the good of the army is found both in the general and its order leaves us with a

certain amount of difficulty in describing the situation with regard to sensible substances. If

the general is to represent the agent, and the army both the potential (the matter and

privation) and the actuality of what is caused by the agent, we will have to locate the good of

the sensible substance in its form (its immanent principle of order) and in its extrinsic agent.

In the case of an army and its general it is not difficult to see how the general would be the

good more than the order it the causes, since without the presence of the general the army

would disband, since its order would cease to exist. The Sun and its eternal motion which

effects the whole of generation and destruction in the sublunary realm are in a similar

position. When we take the analogy to describe particular sensible substances and their

proximate causes we encounter an apparent disparity between the analogy and sensible

substances. Unlike the general and the army, the agent need not exist alongside that which it

causes. The parent can die and the good of the offspring (already begotten) will not be

diminished, and certainly not destroyed. Likewise, a house once built does not collapse on

account of the death of its builder. Recall that only form is simultaneous with a substance.111

109
1072b24, 27-30.
110
In this way “τὸ ἀγαθὸν καὶ τὸ ἄριστον” is regarded as a single term, referring to both the origin and
continuing existence of the perfection of some being.
111
1070a21. “τὰ μὲν οὖν κινοῦντα αἴτια ὡς προγεγενημένα ὄντα, τὰ δ᾽ ὡς ὁ λόγος ἅμα…”

36
The solution to this difficulty would be to place the form in the place of the general as that

upon which the order depends, and regard the good of the order as the arrangement of the

corporeal parts of sensible substance as the good in the order of the army. The distinction of

the three kinds of substance made by Aristotle in Λ.3 might allow for this insofar as it

recognizes a certain distinction between form in itself and the concrete form, if the form is

seen as ordering something other than itself to itself. Nevertheless, this is not the view that

Aristotle has of substances, except for the artificial sort, in Λ. The actuality of a sensible

substance includes corporeality. Furthermore, as we have already noted, placing form in the

role of the general makes too strong a dichotomy between form and body, which Aristotle

does not put forth in his account of the causes, as if form were a constant imposition on

matter, rather than that from which a substance comes to be actual. The form cannot be the

separate good of a substance; it is the substance.

Given the immanence of form it cannot be represented by general. The analogy could

not account for extrinsic causality, which the analogy of the general and the army was

supposed to answer as representing the causal relationship between the cosmos and its

separate (κεχωρισμένον) cause.112 Since the efficient cause is one of the principles of

sensible substances, an analogy that describes these common principles must include it.113

When the analogy between the general and the efficient cause is not considered from a

temporal perspective, but from a logical one, it can be resolved. If we regard only the

relationships of substances, the primacy of the agent becomes intelligible. The caused and

causing substances are distinct and independent of each other in so far as each exists apart.

112
1075a12.
113
1070a31-2; cf. 1070b28-35.

37
The coming to be of the caused substance depends entirely upon its agent. 114 What it comes

to be is determined by this agent, not by the substance itself. The effects of the agent remain

ever with the caused substance. If the agent never existed, neither would the substance it

would have caused. Is this analogous to the relationship between the general and the army?

The army is conformed to what the general is, including the general’s own end and

purposes.115 Similarly, every sensible substance comes to be by being conformed to its agent.

This is the origin of its form. Hence a man begets man and not birds or elephants. The

influence of the agent or extrinsic cause as the external cause of the form and its actuality

does not cease even when the substance that was the agent perishes. If we were to push the

analogy of the army and the general even further, we might consider the cases of armies

which have secured their general’s goals even if the general has been killed or has abandoned

the army. Taking our understanding of the role of the general in this direction we must be

cautious that we do not regard the general a transient principle, but as the real good of that

which it orders. We must admit that this extrinsic good retains its influence after its

perishing, which is admittedly, a privation of the fullness of the relationship between the

general and the army, or the God and the cosmos, or even, the Sun and the sublunary realm.

Recall that in the second half of his description of nature in Λ.3, Aristotle calls it “the habit

for a particular nature”, i.e. a tendency towards a particular form.116 This form, which is

perfected in the parent, is the end of the neophyte substance, and remains so throughout its

existence as the form itself. In a sense the form of the agent is like the form of the form of the

114
Cf. Aquinas, § 2474.
115
Ibid, §2630-1. Aquinas takes the primacy of the general over the army not only on account of the general
being the cause of the order in the army, but also because the order of the army is directed towards achieving
the general’s goal. The men who are ordered into the army are conformed to the general’s own end. I think this
is a useful way of thinking about the analogy insofar as it explains how the intrinsic good is not only formed by,
but conformed to the extrinsic good.
116
1070a12. “ἡ δὲ φύσις τόδε τι καὶ ἕξις τις εἰς ἥν:”

38
substance it causes. As the end and perfection of the form of that which it causes, the form of

the agent (which even governs the agent’s agency) is indeed the primary good of the sensible

substance.

It is clear that no sensible substance can be understood through itself alone. Rather, it

is by understanding the role of other substances, which are its principles that we understand

what some substance is and how it comes to be. This is especially the case with the substance

regarded in the position of the army, as the positive form which comes to be, but other

substance are described in the analogy in the army and the general, especially the agent,

through which we come to understand the power that belongs to actualities (in varying

degrees, depending upon whether they are natural, artificial, etc...) to conform things to

themselves. On this point we must remember that the very same substance which is described

in the place of the army can also be considered from the place of the general too. That a man

begets a man does not preclude the man begotten from begetting another man. The causes

and principles that describe the coming to be, or even just the existence, of a substance do not

cease to be its principles if it is regarded from the position of the general. On the contrary,

the flexibility of the analogy is a testament to its ability to describe the relationships between

substances generally. Moreover, it recalls that substances are never understood in isolation,

but with reference to the other substances that they either effect or affect, or are effected or

affected by. The natural world is an ordered whole, and as such every substance exists in

relation to the others. The principles which describe substances must take the variety and

variability of these relationships into account, which the structure of the general and the army

analogy allows.

39
Artificial substances do not exhibit the same flexibility as the natural substances in

being able to stand as either the general or the army. The products of artifice are more or less

restricted to the role of the army, having a positive form, matter and privation and an agent,

but are not able to be agents. The only exception to this case is if the natural parts of which

the product of artifice is constructed, but then, only in virtue of their natural tendency.

2.4 CONCLUDING SUMMARY

The proximate causes of sublunary substances are four in number, if one regards

them analogically. Every such substance has four causes, and they differ for each and every

sensible sublunary substance, both natural and artificial. What remains the same in every

account of a substance’s causes and principles is a structure outlining which substances

interact with each other and effect or affect substances in virtue of themselves. Sensible

substance can only be completely considered in such a structure. The structure of form,

matter, privation and efficient cause accounts for all the changes in the sublunary realm by

explaining how coming-to-be is possible. It can be reduced to a doctrine of actuality and

potentiality. Actuality is prior to potentiality in two ways: 1) a potentiality is a capacity in an

actuality, and 2) another actuality actualizes a certain potential in virtue of itself. The

relationship is well illustrated by the analogy of the general and the army, which describes

the actuality of a whole in terms of the good, both extrinsic and intrinsic. Moreover, this

analogy also serves to explain the sublunary realm as a whole, with the Sun as its intrinsic

good. In this sense the same analogical structure of causes and principles is able to apply to

both individual substances, and the whole sublunary realm. Thus when Aristotle says that

40
there all substance share the same causes, we need not add several other remote causes, such

as God or the Sun to complicate the structure, but rather, understand that the causes of

particular substances belong to a grander structure, but one which is analogically one.

41
CHAPTER 3 THE IMPERISHABLE SENSIBLE SUBSTANCES

Metaphysics Λ.8 has generally been treated as one source, alongside the De Caelo, of

Aristotle’s opinions regarding astronomy and metaphysics, and even theology. The real focus

of Λ.8 is first philosophy, counting the unmoved movers, which it does with its instrument,

astronomy. Astronomy helps to explain the nature of the heavens in virtue of their motions,

and also points out certain characteristics of unmoved movers which cause these motions.

Astronomy is not accidental to the study of heavenly and separate substance. Aristotle’s

ousiology is not indifferent to the particulars of the astronomical system. We must also

appreciate that although Aristotle had interest in, and need of, astronomy, he was by no

means a dedicated astronomer.117 Controversies about such topics as the idle spheres (which

I shall treat briefly) and the plurality of unmoved movers have dominated the more recent

scholarship, especially as taken up by Jonathan Beere and István Bodnár. Far from

discounting the importance of Λ.8 in light of the problems of the astronomical account, we

must appreciate the limits of Aristotle’s competence in astronomy and focus on

understanding what Aristotle does with the astronomy, as a kind of instrument.118 We can

tolerate the problems in his astronomical account so long as we can understand what

Aristotle is trying to demonstrate about heavenly and separate substance. Although

Aristotle’s astronomy is not perfect, it should not be treated superficially. On the contrary,

the details of the astronomical account are required to understand the metaphysical claims of

Λ.8.
117
Lloyd, 245. Lloyd’s analysis of this point is very important, at least insofar as he probes what Aristotle was
actually drawing upon to make his conclusions by looking at his other uses of astronomy in the De Caelo and
Meteorology.
118
Rosen, 13-31. The astronomical system Aristotle uses is not instrumental in the sense that some, perhaps
erroneously, ascribe to Ptolemy, saying that Ptolemy’s circles, which describe the motion of the heavenly
bodies, are conceptual and descriptive of the motion, rather than the real parts of the heavens.

42
3.1 THE STRUCTURE OF THE HEAVENS IN Λ.8

The structure of Aristotle’s cosmos is based upon the systems of Eudoxus and

Callipus.119 Λ.8 describes the number of substances and motions in the heavens, and numbers

the substances which cause the motions of the heavens,120 i.e. the motions of the spheres and

stars.121 All of the stars, both the fixed stars and the wandering stars,122 are moved by

spheres. The stars with complex motions are moved with the motion of more than one

sphere, with one sphere as the cause of each one of the stars’ motions. All the spheres are

concentric and contiguous, like the layers of an onion. As the first unmoved mover123 moves

the first sphere, that of the fixed stars,124 there is, likewise, an unmoved mover for each other

sphere,125 causing a particular motion. The spheres also transfer their motions downwards by

contact, so that in addition to a motion proper to its nature, each sphere is also moved by the

motions of the spheres above it. The sphere in which a star is contained moves with all of the

motions exhibited by that same star. Accordingly, our schematic of the heavens consists of: a

number of unmoved movers126, which move a number of spheres equal to the number of

unmoved movers, which move the stars, both fixed and wandering. There are, then, three

different kinds of beings that describe and explain the actuality of the heavens: one kind

119
1073b17-33.
120
1073b14-15.
121
1074a25-28; cf. ibid.19-20. Motions do not exist for their own sake or for the sake of other motions, but for
that which is moved, and in the case of the heavens, this is the stars.
122
The fixed stars are those which are embedded in the first heaven and have only one motion. The wandering
stars are those which, relative to the fixed stars, “wander” by possessing a number of different motions.
123
This is how Michael Frede refers to the unmoved mover considered in Λ.6 and 7 in his introduction to
Aristotle’s Metaphysics Lambda.
124
1072a9-11. The sphere of the first stars is that which possesses the first and unchanging cycle. It is distinct
from the other spheres, the second and third, which are the causes of variety, generation and corruption, while
they depend upon the first sphere as being always the same, as that which actual is prior to that which is
potential.
125
1074a14-16. Here Aristotle equates the number of spheres with the number of movers.
126
These are not in the heavens, but simply related to the heavens as moving causes. De Caelo places these
invisible substances outside the cosmos where there lies no spatial extension (Aristotle, De Caelo, 271a12-15).

43
unmoved and moving, another moved and moving, and another which is simply moved but

does not move anything. The scheme appears simple: there are unmoved movers,

intermediary moved moving substances and moved substances.

3.1.2 THE PROBLEM OF THE REVOLVING SPHERES

As simple as it seems, this scheme is complicated by the interactions of the spheres

with each other. The sphere of the fixed stars is said to carry the others spheres with it, yet

Aristotle assigns an unmoved mover to all other spheres that have diurnal motion as their

proper motion. Moreover Aristotle accounts for the effect the lowest sphere belonging to

each star has on the sphere below127 it by assigning additional spheres to counteract its

effects upon the motion of the lower sphere.128 Thus there are, in one sense, two kinds of

movers for the stars: 1) the unmoved movers, and 2) spheres that move another sphere,129 one

of which must cause the diurnal motion of the spheres. In one way, all the causes of the

motions of the stars are, ultimately, the unmoved movers, insofar as every motion has its

origin in such a mover, but that will not solve this problem. We are concerned with the

proximate movers of the stars.130 If a sphere’s motion is only caused by that above, it will not

127
E.g., the effect of the motion of the last sphere of the Jovian system upon the first sphere of the Martian
system.
128
Lloyd, 259. The rewinding spheres are Aristotle’s contribution to astronomy. The rest comes from Eudoxus
and Callipus, and Lloyd thinks he leaves many of the particulars of their system out.
129
We might expect such a sphere to have a complex motion if it also has its own unmoved mover. It is difficult
to say whether this is a problem or not. The stars are seen to move with a complex motion, but they are moved
by spheres within spheres, and it might be said that they only possess the motion of the last sphere properly, but
the others accidentally, as a man carried on a ship (De Anima II.1, 413a9). Whether the motion is imparted to
the spheres directly or accidentally is not entirely clear. If directly, we might assume that the motion of the
spheres properly can have ‘component forces’, to borrow from the vocabulary of contemporary physics.
130
Cf. Beere, 3. Beere refers to this as the per se cause of motion. We might also relate is to the mover’s
motions which are for the sake of some star, “εἰ γὰρ πᾶν τὸ φέρον τοῦ φερομένου χάριν πέφυκε καὶ φορὰ πᾶσα
φερομένου τινός ἐστιν” (Cf. 1074a26-7). The use of φέρον τοῦ φερομένου χάριν πέφυκε is a strong statement
of the special relationship between movers and their objects, prior to any other accidental relations. This does,

44
have an unmoved mover, or rather it will have an unmoved mover that does not cause

motion, or worse, it would have two proximate causes of one motion. Jonathan Beere offers a

solution that is at once insightful and, as Bodnár points out, problematic. Beere suggests that

if these so-called idle spheres do not receive the rotation of the sphere above they will, by

necessity, need to be moved by an unmoved mover to accomplish the diurnal rotation. He

offers a solution that would allow this to be the case without rejecting that the spheres do

move each other:131 that the motions of a sphere are not transferred across a shared axis, i.e.

the poles which are at rest relative to each other.132 Motion would be imparted only when the

poles of the spheres are in motion relative the poles of the sphere below does, when the poles

are translated.133 By this suggestion Beere intends to show that all the spheres in the heavens

are necessary because they are causal, both contributing to the whole motion of heaven and

also having their own motion. If all the spheres have a proper motion, they can be said to

have a per se cause of motion, i.e. not in virtue of another sphere, and thus a proximate cause

which is not a sphere, but an unmoved mover, which can be counted.134

Beere’s intended solution introduces other problems, which Bodnár points out. He

notes that Beere’s suggestion that motion is not imparted through stationary axes affects the

however, raise questions about the supposedly final nature of the movers, taken up in the second half of this
chapter.
131
The rewinding spheres are an implicit admission of the direct influence of spheres upon each other, and they
in turn revolve with a motion caused by an unmoved mover—motion which no other sphere could have
imparted to them, since they revolve in an opposite direction to the spheres which influence them.
132
Beere, 8-9. “The last of Saturn’s unwinding spheres has a special feature, because its resultant motion, unlike
that of most other spheres in the system, is an equable rotation. The special feature is that it has two sets of
poles, the poles around which its unmoved mover rotates it and the poles around which its resultant rotation
occurs. The latter set of poles corresponds to the poles of the fixed stars. The first set of poles is in motion; the
second set of poles is at absolute rest (like the poles of the sphere of the fixed stars). The latter poles, at absolute
rest, are the very points in which the poles of the next sphere, Jupiter’s first, are fixed. Hence, the upper sphere
imparts no motion to the lower, which in turn needs its own unmoved mover in order to move at all. The same
obtains for every ‘idle’ sphere. Hence each ‘idle’ sphere requires its own mover, without which it would be at
absolute rest.”
133
Ibid, 9.
134
Ibid, 3.

45
motion of the whole heaven, so that it would exhibit radically different motions. If it were to

retain the same motion, another cause explaining why certain motions would not be imparted

based on “external considerations” must be invoked,135 frustrating the possibility of counting

the causes of the heavenly motions based on the number of motions alone. The problem is

not limited to Beere’s solution, and Bodnár criticizes two others.136 The first of these

suggests that some of the spheres are not actually in motion, denying that all spheres

contribute a real motion, even the rewinding spheres. The second, which was also rejected by

Simplicius and Sosigenes,137 is to eliminate the first sphere of each planetary system, i.e. that

which contributes the diurnal motion. No single solution solves the difficulties. Each solution

raises another problem. This tension is strung between the parts of what Aristotle is trying to

establish: an account of the causes of each heavenly substances individually and an account

of heavens motion as a hierarchically ordered whole.

135
Bodnár, 266-70. Istvan Bodnár also criticizes Beere’s position for making the unmoved movers of the
rewinding spheres at best “unmoved axis setters”, setting the axis of the first sphere of the next planetary system
without transferring any motion to it along the axis. Beere’s suggestion “will mean that a major presupposition
of homocentric spheres is overruled in this in this instance…that the way revolutions of two consecutive
homocentric spheres are combined does not depend on external factors”. Bodnár wisely points out that we will
need a cause for this exception, and or “it will have to remain a special pleading and hence suspect”(268). On
the other hand, if it applied in all cases, then the motion of the last rewinding sphere and the first sphere of the
star below will be different, if the sphere before the last rewinding sphere revolves on a different axis, so that,
no longer being stationary, it will transmit motion along its axis and add its motion to the sphere in contains in
addition to what it mover moves it. The result would be heavenly phenomena vastly different from what
Aristotle is describing.
136
Ibid, 259-266. The first suggestion he criticizes suggests an extra rewinding sphere could free up the idle
sphere to be moved by its own mover.
137
Ibid., 263. Bodnár notes that Simplicius in his Commentary on De Caelo rejects this because it would not
add up to the number of spheres Aristotle gives. Bodnár does not think this is a strong reason, but instead takes
up Sosigenes’ reason, preserved by Simplicius for rejecting this solution, that the rotation of the first sphere of a
planetary system is “adequate”, i.e. that its movement is the same as the first heaven, and that the rotation of the
last rewinding sphere is not the same, but has a complex motion which only results in the diurnal motion.

46
3.1.3 THE RESOLUTION

In the face of these difficulties and equally problematic solutions, Bodnár holds

that Aristotle’s system “cannot be rejected outright”,138 and in fact he looks upon this

impasse positively, saying:

Aristotle intended to arrive at a causally perspicuous system, which also unifies the different
planetary motions into a single overarching system, with a unified account of the integration
of the motions of different planetary systems[…] Metaphysics XII 8, then, on this
understanding, is a chapter where Aristotle set the outlines of such a celestial system, but he
did not appreciate the internal tensions involved and did not work out all of the ramifications
of the principles operative in his celestial system.139

Bodnár’s position is liberating. Indeed, if we ask with Lloyd, “why did Aristotle give just the

information he gives here?”140 we will be able appreciate that Aristotle’s astronomy does not

have to be perfect, it need only explain what he intends to do with it, i.e. study metaphysics

according to the motions apparent in the heavens. The essential elements and relationships to

do so are in place in the system as described in Λ.8. We learn from it that the heavens include

two kinds of causes: that caused by the unmoved movers, which is the primary kind, since it

introduces the different motions; and the kind between the spheres, which distributes the

motions through the heavens, accounting for the wandering stars. We would do well to

remember that Aristotle invokes astronomy rather than commands it, saying “It is necessary

to examine the multitude of [heavenly] motions with the mathematical science closest to

138
Bodnár, 270.
139
Ibid, 271.
140
Lloyd, 257.

47
philosophy, astronomy.”141 He is calling on science besides his own, first philosophy in this

case, and uses what it has determined already to establish his own understanding of the

heavens. He makes no claims to be an astronomer, and even shows diffidence regarding it, as

noted by Lloyd.142 It falls to other thinkers to prove the necessity of forty-seven or fifty-five

spheres.143 Despite his problematic solution, Beere’s words on this situation may be best:

His primary goal is not that we accept that there are 55 pure intellects, but rather that
we accept that, as far as his account of the ultimate principles is concerned, nothing is
lacking for such a demonstration.144

Λ.8 is nothing other than an ousiology and an aitiology, a study of the causes, i.e., the

unmoved movers, of the primary heavenly bodies, the spheres. The analogy of the general

and the army is well suited to discussing the relationship between theses separate substance

and the substances, the spheres, that they immediately not only affect, but effect.

3.2 THE CAUSES AND PRINCIPLES OF IMPERISHABLE SENSIBLE


SUBSTANCES

Both the spheres and the unmoved movers are agents of local change for the stars.

Both are productive of a change in something other than themselves. A sphere causes a

motion like its own in another, as is claimed of the first heaven, which is thought to cause the

141
1073b3-5. “τὸ δὲ πλῆθος ἤδη τῶν φορῶν ἐκ τῆς οἰκειοτάτης φιλοσοφίᾳ τῶν μαθηματικῶν ἐπιστημῶν δεῖ
σκοπεῖν, ἐκ τῆς ἀστρολογίας:..”
142
Lloyd, 251;1074a16.
143
1074a17. Aristotle suggests two possibilities for the number of spheres, one given by Eudoxus, suggesting
47 spheres, and another by Callipus, who added two spheres each to the Sun and Moon, and one to the other
planets, so as to better account for motions. Aristotle’s ambivalence on this point shows how he depends upon
the opinions of the astronomers.
144
Beere, 2.

48
diurnal motion throughout the heavens.145 An unmoved mover, however, does not cause a

motion that is like itself, since it does not move or change in any way. Instead, it causes

motion as an object of desire moves the desirer by being what it is and does not suffer any

change, either in place, quality or essence. Despite this difference, the relationship of that

which is moved to either the unmoved movers or one of the other spheres can be understood

through the analogy of the general and the army. In both cases the mover is an extrinsic cause

of motion in some mobile substance. Just as the army exists because of an immanent order,

thus do the motions of a sphere really belong to that sphere. All cases of heavenly motion,

whether caused by an unmoved mover or another sphere, are an actualization of a potential.

The heavenly substances are not generated, and their existence and cyclical motion have

neither beginning nor end. In the course of their motions the stars come to be in a new place

in every moment. This is a likeness to the causality of the sublunary realm: a certain state, a

being in a location, is generated on account of the agency of another substance. The eternal

motion, while not generated, is equally also caused, and has, as Aristotle points out, the

potential for local change as its matter: Aristotle writes that “as many of the eternal

(substances) are not generable but mobile by a motion [have matter], not for generation but

for moving here and there.”146

Since we are acquainted with the sublunary causality the unmoved movers may seem

to cause something less significant than substantial change, e.g. reproduction. It may even

seem that the spheres are independently existing eternal bodies, necessary in virtue of

145
At 1072a19-25 Aristotle recounts what he has done in Λ.6. He has established that actuality precedes
potentiality, rejecting the reverse view, which the theologians hold, that everything came to be “out of night”.
This being the case he determines that the movement of the “first heaven” must have a cause of its motion,
since motion is not a perfect actuality. Aristotle describes the “first heaven” as an intermediate mover, moved
and moving, because it causes regular, cyclical motion in other things. At1072a16-17 Aristotle points out its
cosmic significance lies in being the cause of perpetual variety, when it regular motion is united to a second,
different motion. Its effects are found throughout the whole cosmos.
146
1069b25. “καὶ τῶν ἀϊδίων ὅσα μὴ γενητὰ κινητὰ δὲ φορᾷ, ἀλλ᾽ οὐ γενητὴν ἀλλὰ ποθὲν ποί.”

49
themselves, that just happen to be moved by the unmoved movers and that the being of these

spheres is not dependent upon the unmoved movers.147 We will see that this not the case, but

that the whole world depends upon God, so that the good and cause of the cosmos is found

more properly in God than in the cosmos itself. Furthermore we shall also see that the agency

that causes the proper motions of the spheres is the cause of their actuality, which is both

desirous and divine.148

3.2.1 THE SCOPE OF THE STUDY OF HEAVENLY SUBSTANCES

One caveat before proceeding any further: we must not confuse the stars and the

spheres, or substitute one for the other. Λ.8 does speak of both, especially about the

numerous movements of the stars, calling them by name and examining their relationships

with each other. As I have noted above, the stars are not moved by the unmoved movers

directly, but by the spheres. Insofar as it is meant to establish the number of unmoved

movers, Λ.8 first deduces the number of spheres by counting the motions of the stars. We

are, therefore, primarily concerned with the spheres as the primary heavenly substances,

whose unmediated causes are the unmoved movers. For our investigation, we can assume

that the stars are embedded in the spheres and benefit from the spheres. As Aristotle

establishes at 1074a18-19, it will be possible to count the unmoved movers “if there is no

147
Cf. Aquinas, O.P., Summa Theologica, I-I, Q.44, art. 1. Aquinas explains the force of this problem in the
second objection: “Further, a thing requires an efficient cause in order to exist. Therefore whatever cannot but
exist does not require an efficient cause. But no necessary thing can not exist, because whatever necessarily
exists cannot but exist. Therefore as there are many necessary things in existence, it appears that not all beings
are from God.” The consequence of this mistaken argument is that the unmoved movers are unrelated to the
actuality of the spheres.
148
1072b2;1074b1-2. The unmoved movers move by being loved, thus the spheres, which they move, must be
seen as desiring the unmoved mover. At 1074b1-2 Aristotle acknowledges that the tradition is correct in
acknowledging that the heavenly bodies are divine.

50
such motion that does not exert itself upon the motion of a star.”149 Additionally, we will

only focus on the causes of heavenly substances individually, in order to establish a careful

account of the ousiology of the eternal sensible substance. We will consider the whole

cosmos in the next chapter when we investigate God as the first cause as the cosmos

considered as a distinct substance.

3.2.2 THE APPLICABILITY OF THE CAUSES AND PRINCIPLES OF


SUBSTANCES LISTED IN Λ.2-5 TO THE HEAVENLY SUBSTANCES.

The analogy of the general and the army applies to every level of substance. In every

account of the causes of a substance there is an army that is really dependent upon a general,

who, relative to the army, is self-dependent and actual.150 Among the sublunary substances

this is expressed by a potential substance that is made actual in virtue of a substance that is

already actual. This potential and actualization, i.e. change, is described by the immanent

‘elements’, form, matter, privation and the (transcendent) agency. We can begin with one

certainty about the change and agency in the heavens: that local change comes about on

account of the immaterial, invisible substances, the unmoved movers. It is the spheres which

undergo this change, and because the spheres do, so too the stars that they carry.151 In terms

of the language of Λ.2, which we used in the previous chapter, we can call these spheres in

their motion a form or actuality, recalling what Charles says about sensible substances, that

149
1074a18. “εἰ δὲ μηδεμίαν οἷόν τ᾽ εἶναι φορὰν μὴ συντείνουσαν πρὸς ἄστρου φοράν…”
150
Cf. 1069b36. “μετὰ ταῦτα ὅτι οὐ γίγνεται οὔτε ἡ ὕλη οὔτε τὸ εἶδος, λέγω δὲ τὰ ἔσχατα. πᾶν γὰρ μεταβάλλει
τὶ καὶ ὑπό τινος καὶ εἴς τι.” As in the case of substantial change (i.e. the coming into being of a new substance),
the causes of the change must already be actual for the change to occur. In a like manner, the general must
possess his actuality or perfection in order to be a principle and cause.
151
1074a30. “ ὥστ᾽ ἐπειδὴ οὐχ οἷόν τε εἰς ἄπειρον, τέλος ἔσται πάσης φορᾶς τῶν φερομένων τι θείων σωμάτων
κατὰ τὸν οὐρανόν.”

51
each express its being in how it changes or moves.152 Their matter, the potential to be what

they are, is in this case not a matter for generation but for movement.153 The agents of the

spheres must be the unmoved movers, which are described as κινητικόν or ποιητικόν.154 We

must also be careful when speaking of the form, and thus also the privation. If the motion is

the form, and the spheres never cease, we can say that there is no privation. The motion of

the sphere is always moving from place to place, and never rests in one part of its location.

These moments of its rotation, like the disorderly bricks which make up the whole house, fit

this role. These moments remain in the motion, but subordinated to it.

The proximate causes from Λ.2-5 are principles and causes of the heavenly

substances in their proper motions. But applying them to accidental change of place in the

heavens is not as easy. At the sublunary level the four causes and principles describe the

generation and actuality of substances. In the heavens these proximate causes describe only

the actuality and its causes, and obviously, not generation. The heavenly bodies and their

motion never existing potentially,155 but this does not make the individual spheres self-

subsistent. Indeed they do have a matter, a capacity to be moved by the unmoved movers. As

we will see, apart from the unmoved movers the spheres would not be actual, nor anything

which depends upon their motion, i.e. the sublunary realm.156

Although it is not mentioned in Λ.8,157 we would not be wrong to consider its

heavens as composed of aether, and if not aether, or some other extended, mobile, stuff. The

152
Cf. Charles, 91.
153
1069b25-26. “καὶ τῶν ἀϊδίων ὅσα μὴ γενητὰ κινητὰ δὲ φορᾷ, ἀλλ᾽ οὐ γενητὴν ἀλλὰ ποθὲν ποί.”
154
1071b12.
155
Metaphysics Θ, 1050b16-22.
156
Cf. 1071a35.
157
The exclusion of aether from the chapter is likely due to the nature of the work as first philosophy aided by
astronomy, and not a work of second philosophy. As we noted in the first part of this chapter, the spheres are
not the object of the investigation, but a means to understand this investigation. Moreover, that the spheres are a

52
form of the each sphere must delineate the corporeal limits of each sphere. The form cannot,

however, merely delineate sections of the heavens arbitrarily, as a surveyor might arbitrarily

divides land into farm plots, but must have a reason for so delineating, i.e. a sphere’s nature.

This delineation is not something imposed externally,158 but belongs to the sphere as its

proper motion. Motion is the common feature of the stars 159 and spheres, and the differing

motions distinguish each sphere, just as the immanent forms in sublunary substances

distinguish one substance from another. Each sphere is distinguished by its motion, and if

indeed the spheres are composed of aether, all the aether of one sphere shares in the same

rotation, which is caused by an unmoved mover, and also the other rotations imparted by the

spheres above. The motion of each sphere is not at all accidental, but is even the actuality of

each sphere.

The dependence described here is not one which is perishable, but is eternally

enacted. The cause of the actuality of the spheres is unchanging and imperishable, but

beyond this, Simplicius notes that that “the will of God supplies the goods not to this and that

at random but to those things that are suitably disposed.”160 He argues that though the body

of the sphere might be both finite and divisible, it need not therefore be destructible. As in

the sublunary realm the matter of the actuality is a potential for certain forms, such as the

familiar example of the mother’s menses, which is a suitable form being actualized as a

human being, but not, for instance, a house. Likewise, if we consider the analogy of the

means to consider the unmoved movers, rather than the object of the study themselves, suggests that what we
need to know about them can also be found in the sections dedicated to sensible substance, even if it is scant.
158
This does not preclude that it is caused externally, only that this delineation cannot be alien to the sphere’s
nature.
159
The stars are visibly distinct from each other.
160
Simplicius, 124. Alexander of Aphrodisias makes a similar point in his Quaestiones, that the whole world
could not be preserved in existence by God if it were not possible for it to be imperishable in its own nature.
(Alexander of Aphrodisias, Quaestiones 1.1-2.15, 66.)

53
general, so long as the men and the general were both immortal, there is nothing to prevent

the army itself from existing eternally.

The proper motion of a sphere, caused by an unmoved mover, is its actuality, but not

all motions are identical with a form. This is what Beere argues for by preserving a distinct

per se cause of motion for each sphere, against motions imparted by another sphere. Whereas

spheres move each other through some kind of contact,161 an unmoved mover does not move

by contact. It cannot move by contact since, as described in the De Caelo, an unmoved

mover is “of such a nature as not to occupy any place, nor does time age it; nor is there any

change in any of the things which lie beyond the outermost motion; they continue through

their entire duration unalterable and unmodified, living the best and most self-sufficient of

lives.”162 The motion imparted from one sphere to another is not only between two bodies,

which the unmoved movers are not, but it is imparted through change of place in the agent—

regular, perpetual change, but change nonetheless. The principle which expresses this is

given in the seventh chapter: “[the unmoved mover] moves as being loved, but all other

things move being moved themselves.”163 The unmoved movers cause motion in some other

way, which Aristotle describes as moving by being desired.

How the unmoved movers move causes difficulties of interpretation, allowing for at

least two possibilities: 1) the unmoved mover causes motion by effecting motion in some

way besides contact, seemingly in contrast to the principle above; or 2) the unmoved movers

161
It may not be friction, as Beere argues, but it must be through some kind of contact, since motions are
transferred between spheres that touch each other. They must touch each other because nature is continuous
(Aristotle, De Caelo, 280a19-22; cf. 279a15-17). This contact is noticeably different from terrestrial contact
because only one of the bodies in contact, the lower, is affected. Moreover, if the spheres did exert a kinetic
influence upon each other over a distance, there would be a vast multiplication of motions downwards, since the
spheres do impart their whole component motion. If every sphere imparted its whole component motion to
every sphere below it, the moon should display dazzling mobility.
162
Ibid, 279a19-23; cf. 1072
163
1072b2. “κινεῖ δὴ ὡς ἐρώμενον, κινούμενα δὲ τἆλλα κινεῖ.” This kind of final cause is described just before
as for the sake of something (or of an action in Ross’ translation) rather than for something.

54
stands as an end of motion, but the spheres are the agents of their own motion, and are really

self-movers. This difficult is solved, I propose, by conceiving of the unmoved movers as the

cause of the spheres’ natures, which are directed back towards the unmoved movers as an
164
end, just as the general orders his army towards his own end. This solution, it shall be

seen, accommodates both claims about the way the unmoved movers move, as a final cause

and as an efficient cause.

3.2.3 THE UNMOVED MOVERS CORRESPOND TO THE GENERAL IN THE


ANALOGY OF THE GENERAL AND THE ARMY

We have established the way in which the heavenly substances are dependent upon

the first movers. The proper motion caused by each unmoved mover constitutes the actuality

of a sphere.165 Final, efficient and even formal causality are attributable to the unmoved

movers as the causes of the spheres,166 but each must be understood carefully, lest we expect

causality to function exactly as it does in the sublunary realm. The unmoved movers cannot

be final causes as contingent objects of desire or rational will, nor can they be efficient

causes as if they were moving the spheres for some objective.167 Moreover, if formal

causality is to be attributed to the unmoved movers, it cannot be as an immanent formal

164
Aristotle, De Anima II, 415a30-b2.
165
1075a12-14.
166
Aquinas, Summa Theologica, I.I, Q.44, art. 1-4. Aquinas associates efficient, exemplary and final causality
with God. It is not impossible to attribute the same to Aristotle’s unmoved movers or God. Where Aquinas
speaks of exemplary causality he speaks of the way in which one being is the pattern of another, “…for the
production of anything an exemplar is necessary, it is in order that the effect may receive a determinate form”
(art. 3). We will keep this threefold causality in mind throughout the following section. In the same section
Aquinas also attributes the creation of prime matter to God, however whether this too is applicable to
Aristotle’s theory is a more difficult question. Whether Aristotle has subscribes to a theory of prime matter is a
point of controversy. Nevertheless, since Aristotle says all things depend upon God, we cannot avoid some
comment on just how they are dependent.
167
Alexander of Aphrodisias, Quaestiones 1.1-2.15, 102. Alexander of Aphrodisias rightly points out that God
does not have a function, but is a pure actuality that does not achieve anything.

55
cause, for they would be the spheres that they move and the separated substances would

move themselves accidentally.168 These caveats aside, as with the army, which would not

even exist without the general giving it order (an order which makes it an army of such a sort

for his own end), the spheres are entirely dependent upon the unmoved movers. The very

actuality of the spheres, and not just local motion, depends upon these movers, and it is in

this sense that, as we shall soon see, that we call the movers κινητικόν and ποιητικόν,169 i.e.,

agents which move and actualize another substance.

3.2.4 EACH UNMOVED MOVER IS THE UNIQUE CAUSE OF A SPHERE

The nature of this agency is best understood by the relationship between the unmoved

mover and the sphere. The relationship exists in virtue of the unmoved mover rather than in

virtue of the sphere. The relationship is a part of its nature.170 We read in Λ.10 that “the

general does not exist because of the order [of the army], but the order is because of [the

general].”171 If the unmoved movers were merely final causes in the sense that they were

only objects of contemplation or desire, upon which the heavenly spheres pattern their

motion, as if choosing between a higher and lesser good, we would have to establish why it is

that each sphere has one mover as its final cause rather than another.172 Another cause to

make this determination would be needed; otherwise the relationships between the spheres

168
This is not possible of the separate substances, which cannot be moved, even accidentally.
169
1071b12.
170
Especially so if it has the unmoved mover as its final cause, i.e. has that end in virtue of its nature as a
sphere.
171
1075a15. “οὐ γὰρ οὗτος διὰ τὴν τάξιν ἀλλ᾽ ἐκείνη διὰ τοῦτόν ἐστιν.”
172
Cf. Bodnár, 266-270.

56
and their unmoved movers will not be governed by necessity.173 We would invalidate the

presupposition that Aristotle uses to make astronomy describe the number of unmoved

movers, that each distinct motion has its own cause, immutably and eternally. Moreover, if

there were no principle binding one sphere to a particular unmoved mover they might all

have one unmoved mover as their end as an object of imitation,174 and each sphere would

move differently on account of its own nature rather than as caused by distinct unmoved

mover, e.g. according to its place in the heavens. That Aristotle does not endorse this is a

strong suggestion that this kind of final causality, either with regards to one or many

unmoved movers, is not what Aristotle holds to be the principle of motion (and actuality) for

the heavenly bodies.175

On the assumption that what we have said is true, the identification of the distinct

movements of the heavens with particular unmoved movers is not arbitrary. Each unmoved

mover is a per se cause of a motion in the heavens, which Beere admirably defends. Each

mover is the cause of only one motion; the complex motions are caused by the spheres’

interactions with each other. From the perspective of the heavenly bodies, this effected

motion, and their own actuality, is necessary on account of the eternal and perfect actuality of

the unmoved movers, the cause of a unique and immutable relationship between a sphere and

its unmoved mover.

173
I don’t mean to suggest that it would be mutable, but only that there is no intrinsic relationship between a
sphere and its mover, which would undermine Aristotle’s attempt to number he unmoved movers based upon
the motion of the spheres.
174
Berti, 187; cf. Broadie, 375-411.
175
Elders, 239. Elders points to Alexander, as referenced by Simplicius, as one who suggests that if the first
unmoved mover is a final cause it should move many worlds, but that it does not implies that the passus at
1074a31-8 presents a God as an efficient cause.

57
3.2.5 THE UNMOVED MOVERS AS EFFICIENT CAUSES

The unmoved movers’ actualization of the spheres is not a production in time, but

according to the priority of the actuality of separate substances over the (qualified)

potentiality of the spheres. Attributing productivity to the unmoved movers, as the cause of

the sphere’s actuality, is not the most common interpretation, as we shall see below. The text

of Metaphysics Λ does indeed associate final causality with the unmoved movers in two

places: 1) insofar as it distinguishes how they cause motion from how moved movers cause

motion;176 and 2) as something which moves as loved, while everything else causes motion

by already being in motion.177 We are concerned with the first because it likens the

movement (i.e. setting in motion) of an unmoved mover to things that are not efficient

causes. The second, however, distinguishes the unmoved mover from all other things, and

therefore does not deny that it is also efficient. In the first passage, the mover of the first

heaven is described at 1072a26 as moving “as [ὧδε] desirable and intelligible objects [do];

they move without being moved.”178 Λ.9 does consider the noetic nature of separated

substance, but in the context of separated substance in se, not as the cause of other beings.

1072a26 involves an important ambiguity: does an unmoved mover cause motion because it

is desirable and intelligible, and thus unmoved, or does it cause motion as desirable and

intelligible things cause motion without, i.e, without being in motion itself. The first has the

support of Joseph Owens and Elders, 179 both of whom deny that any of the unmoved movers

are efficient causes, since as objects of desire, they cannot be efficient. Indeed, if such a

176
1072a23-25.
177
1072b4. “κινεῖ δὴ ὡς ἐρώμενον, κινούμενα δὲ τἆλλα κινεῖ.”
178
1072a26. “κινεῖ δὲ ὧδε τὸ ὀρεκτὸν καὶ τὸ νοητόν: κινεῖ οὐ κινούμενα.”
179
Owens, 286; Elders, 68.

58
cause were to be efficient in the way that the moved movers are, its “work” would never be

complete, though it could remain perpetually the same. It would be directed towards some

action outside of itself, a final cause outside of itself, which is a position untenable for that

which is complete actuality in itself, as Alexander observes.180 Relative to itself, an unmoved

mover needs nothing to be actualized.181

We ought, however, to reject this first position for three reasons in favour of the latter

position, that it moves but without undergoing any change. First, if the unmoved mover

moved only as desired, it would be passive and would move as being a part of a whole

system of causes, and depend upon the nature of the moved as capable of desiring and

knowing. Second, the latter half of 1072a26 gives κινεῖ οὐ κινούμενα, a plural, indicating

that the previous τὸ ὀρεκτὸν καὶ τὸ νοητόν are two examples of a way of moving unmoved,

but not descriptors of the unmoved mover.182 Third, there are positive reasons in the text

which indicate that the unmoved mover must be considered κινητικόν and ποιητικόν, without

ever undergoing change itself.

Owens and Elders, would be hard-pressed to deny that these unmoved movers do

cause an effect, the actualization of a potentiality, motion, in the heavenly substances. If not,

whatever effects this motion towards a final cause will be their efficient cause, since all

things in potential cannot come to be “as if out of night”, i.e. without an actualizing

principle.183 In no way can a causal series continue to infinity, but only as far as that which

possess complete actuality.184 Λ.6 gives us Aristotle’s reason for defining his unmoved

180
Alexander, Quaestiones 1.1-2.15, 102. “That thing [the first, the Unmoved Mover], is not one of those things
that have a function, if by function [Aristotle] means an activity that is its end [telos], But [God] has no end.
For his being is [itself] activity; it is not that he is first something else and then activity.”
181
1071b21.
182
Berti, 203.
183
1071b27.
184
Ibid, 21.

59
movers as agents and the first (or last) member of a series of causality. He states that any

suitable first principle must be capable of causing change, and that even if it is κινητικόν or

ποιητικόν185 it must not merely possess these attributes potentiality, but as always in act.

Should we go so far as to attribute κινητικόν and ποιητικόν univocally to the separate

substances directly, or limit these terms to examples of how the unmoved movers move, as

we did with τὸ ὀρεκτὸν and τὸ νοητόν?186 One might argue that these terms only refer to the

necessity of being entirely and eternally in act, rather than ascribing real efficiency, and that

while they are principles of change they are not necessarily efficient. Aristotle, however, is

arguing for an agent separate substance against the Platonists’ Forms. A separate Form

cannot explain the how another substance possesses a form even in Plato’s own system, and

Aristotle looks to avoid the same problem. The Greek is clear on this point:187 such eternal

substances would be just like the Forms, “unless a principle (δυναμένη) capable of causing

change is in it.”188 It must be capable of change, not in the sense that the presence of a final

cause allows for a change as an end, but in the sense that without an agent no change will be

185
Ibid, 12.
186
Berti, 186-7. In his contribution to the tenth Symposium Aristotelicum, argues that the unmoved movers are
efficient causes and acknowledges others who share this position, including Kosman and Broadie.
187
1071b14-16. “οὐθὲν ἄρα ὄφελος οὐδ᾽ ἐὰν οὐσίας ποιήσωμεν ἀϊδίους, ὥσπερ οἱ τὰ εἴδη, εἰ μή τις δυναμένη
ἐνέσται ἀρχὴ μεταβάλλειν: οὐ τοίνυν οὐδ᾽ αὕτη ἱκανή, οὐδ᾽ ἄλλη οὐσία παρὰ τὰ εἴδη:”
188
1071b16. Rendering “δυναμένη” in English is a little awkward, but affirms that there must be a capability of
making a change, and would permit the application of κινητικόν and ποιητικόν. Aquinas attributes them to the
unmoved mover, and has no qualms about a mover which would hypothetically bring the world into existence,
in Aristotle’s scheme, if the world were not eternal (Aquinas, §2493, 2498). Elders takes this passage to refer to
the necessity of a being that is completely actual, but does not make any significant remarks about whether this
indicates a divine efficiency. He does, however, point out Aristotle’s reference to Anaxagoras as an argument
for the need of an efficient cause. Later on, Elders refers to the activity of the first mover as radiating its ever-
same activity, which in conjunction with the natural motion of the spheres and elementary bodies, causes
eternal variety (Elders, 143-5, 158). Hence even Elders, who resists calling the unmoved movers efficient,
cannot do so entirely. Berti adds two helpful points, that κινητικόν or ποιητικόν grammatically imply a
capability, and that both apply to unmoved movers, and not just κινητικόν (as if Aristotle introduced one or the
other), since Aristotle criticizes the Platonists for not having either attribute in their principles and thus implies
that “his own principle is both.”(Berti, 186-7).

60
effected. Aristotle gives a number of examples from nature showing that an actual agent

cause must precede its effect in actuality:

For how will it be moved unless there is a cause in actuality? For wood itself will indeed not
move itself, but carpentry will [move it], nor will the menstrual blood or the earth [move
themselves], but the semen and the seeds will move them.189

In a like way, the first unmoved mover must actualize everything dependent upon it. Unlike

these natural examples, however, the spheres are never independent from their agent, as the

statue is not always being made. Nor are the spheres being made, but the dependent

relationship is ever the same, both in the order of substance and time. Hence, three major

points are raised in Λ.6: separate substance must be eternal and unchanging (i.e. having no

potential), and consequently is it is efficient it is eternally efficient. Actuality and efficiency

are thus linked in Λ.6, hence the first mover, and the other movers, must be eternally actual

and so eternally agents.190

It might be objected that the unmoved movers need only be causes of kinetic change,

given the formulation κινητικὸν ἢ ποιητικόν at 1071b12, as if it were one or the other. Enrico

Berti points out that Λ.10 criticizes those who make contraries principles because “they are

not kinetic and productive” (emphasis mine).191 Whatever its status as final cause is, the first

189
1071b30-2. One might argue that since the spheres are always in actuality they may fulfill the requirements
that these examples give even if the unmoved movers are only final causes. In this case, the spheres themselves
will have to be the efficient cause and their motion will still “come out of night”. If the spheres are final causes
they must also be productive of their motion. We will examine how these two kinds of causality need not
exclude each other below.
190
Berti notes that the seeming potentiality expressed in the passages above need not put them in opposition to
the complete actuality of the substance to which they belong, because they are part of the thinking about what
such a first principle must be, not necessarily its final definition (Ibid,190). I take Berti to be implying that in a
perfect definition the efficiency of these causes would remain, but any suggestion of their potentiality would be
carefully pruned.
191
Berti, 197; 1075b31. “ἀλλὰ μὴν οὐδέν γ᾽ ἔσται τῶν ἐναντίων ὅπερ καὶ ποιητικὸν καὶ κινητικόν;”

61
unmoved mover and all the other separated substances are agents of actuality, especially of

all those things through which their existence is inferred, e.g. the distinct motions of the

heavens. The general not only commands an army, but causes its actuality by ordering it,

without which the army would be a horde. Although the unmoved mover causes the actuality

of the sphere without any beginning and of necessity, so that the spheres are also

necessary,192 which is unlike agency in the sublunary realm, it is no less an efficient cause. It

is an extrinsic cause of actuality and motion in another substance.

3.2.6 THE UNMOVED MOVERS AS EXEMPLARY CAUSES

The unmoved movers do not depend on the spheres which they move, but rather,

those spheres depend on the unmoved movers for their existence. The efficient cause of a

substance does not cause just anything, but actualizes a specific potentiality, as we saw in the

case of art and reproduction in the sublunary realm. On account of this some have suggested

that these movers may be the souls of the spheres, which would serve as a formal cause of

the ungenerated spheres.193 There are two related difficulties with this view: 1) the movers

would then be accidentally moved movers since they would be immanent principles of the

spheres; and 2), if they were the souls of the spheres, the unmoved movers would not really

be separate immaterial and immobile substances, but would have a body, since a soul is the

192
Aquinas, Summa Theologica, I.I, Q.44, Art 1, ad. 2. Aquinas reminds us that efficient causality can be
attributed even to necessary things, pointing to Aristotle distinction between kinds of necessity. Efficient
causality does indeed belong to those beings which are necessary because of their cause, rather than themselves.
The spheres, as we have seen above, are such beings.
193
Berti, 187-8; Kosman, “Aristotle’s Prime Mover”, 135-54. Berti resists likening the first unmoved mover to
a soul, preferring the comparison with an art. He does cite Kosman as one who likens the first mover to a soul,
who calls it a “psychic principle”, albeit entirely transcendent.

62
“first entelechy of an instrumental natural body”.194 To be a soul is to be the entelechy of a

body, and thus exists for the sake of being a living body. The body and soul are one

substance.195 Thus while both the unmoved movers and souls are immaterial in themselves,

their relationship to bodies differs. A soul is a formal cause, but the unmoved mover must be

the cause of the form, i.e. making the form what it is. It is the exemplary cause, an external

cause upon which the forms of the spheres are a likeness, insofar as they share in the divine

life.

The sphere’s essence or nature, its actuality as a sphere, is caused by an unmoved

mover, but the unmoved mover is not that sphere. As the general actualizes the army as an

army, so do the unmoved movers cause the spheres to be (but not to come to be) and to be

spheres. The unmoved movers cause the eternal motion which belongs to a sphere and

distinguishes each sphere from the others. As above, we must acknowledge that this is not

arbitrary, but that the unmoved mover is the cause of the relationship which exists between

the unmoved mover and the sphere, i.e. that a certain sphere is be moved by a certain mover,

as either loved or otherwise. Hence, when Aristotle discusses how the nature of the whole

has its good in itself and in another, as explicated by the analogy of the general and the army,

he says that the cause of nature’s order is the order itself, as an immanent formal cause, and

that agent which causes the order to be in a substance. Such an agent must also possess the

form in some way.196 It is similar to reproduction, in which the parent causes the form in

another without becoming the instantiation of its offspring. As per Λ.5, in one sense forms

194
Aristotle, De Anima,412b5. “…ἐντελέχεια ἡ πρώτη σώματος φυσικοῦ ὀργανικοῦ.”
195
Ibid. 412a20-23.
196
Cf. 1070a5. The causes of things share a name with what they cause. Lions beget lions, shoemakers make
shoes. This is not, in virtue of the name itself, but the name is in virtue of the actuality and power one has,
especially in the case of the arts, e.g. shoemaker. The unmoved movers are not the spheres themselves, but they
are of such an essence as to be able to order the spheres as eternally moving, loving substances.

63
are particular, so that my form and yours are not the same, even if they are of the same

species.197 It is in this sense that the parent or agent is not the formal cause of what it causes,

but it does not prevent the parent or agent from being the cause of essence in something else.

Aquinas calls God the exemplary cause of all things, rather than the formal cause. In his

estimation God is an exemplary cause in two ways, as containing the divine ideas, and as

being that of which all created things are a likeness.198 Aristotle’s unmoved movers

correspond to the second way of being exemplars.

Aquinas’ notion of God as an exemplar which all things approach as much as they are

able is in agreement with De Anima II.4’s claim that all substances imitate divine eternity as

far as they are able.199 II.4 refers to the divine, and whether one or many separated substance

are meant, it is applicable to the other separate substances besides the first because they are

all of “such a kind” and described as “loved” in Λ.7. If what is loved is a likeness to their

movers in the spheres themselves, then this second kind of exemplarity is present belongs to

the unmoved movers.

The unmoved movers are also the causes of the essence of the spheres. It is the very

nature of the spheres and the stars to be in motion eternally, and as we noted above each is

distinguished by a different motion and their motion’s dependence upon a particular

separated substance. Metaphysics Δ establishes that the nature of a thing is the source of its

primary motion.200 For the spheres, this primary motion is the proper motion of each that is

ontologically prior to any other received motions. The motion that Δ.4 calls primary is that

which belongs to a substance in virtue of being such a substance, the most basic instance of

197
1071a26-30.
198
Aquinas, Summa Theologica, I.I, Q. 44, Art. 3.
199
Aristotle, De Anima, 415a30-b2.
200
1015a13-15.

64
which is growth.201 Growth, i.e. maturation, is none other than the motion of a sublunary

living substance achieving its perfection. It is a motion intimately united with the substance

to which it belongs, such that its form is the cause of this growth. The primary motions of the

spheres possess just such a unity with the nature of the spheres themselves. The unmoved

movers do not need to move the heavenly substances by an impulse, but by imparting a

nature, as Averroes says in his Epitome, “…it is clear that [the unmoved movers] not only

move the celestial bodies but also provide them with their forms through which they are what

they are.”202 Like the general of an army, the nature that is caused is not unrelated to the

unmoved movers, but in accordance with them. As the army is, in a way an instantiation of

the general singular will in a thing made of parts, the eternal motion of these eternal

substances is a likeness of the eternal divine life which is described in Λ.7 through the

constant, but regular, change of place.203

3.2.7 THE UNMOVED MOVERS AS FINAL CAUSES

It remains for us to consider precisely how the unmoved movers are final causes in

the context of also being efficient and final causes understood as imparting an actualized

form or nature to the spheres. The late appearance of final causality in the text of Λ is itself

worth considering. It is not counted in the list of the list of causes in the first half of

Metaphysics Λ. Instead, privation is taken as the fourth cause, in order to more fully explain

all of the aspects of change. As early as Λ.3, however, final causality begins to appear, not

201
1014b16-20.
202
Averroes, 152.
203
Cf. 1072b26. “εἰ δὲ μᾶλλον, ἔτι θαυμασιώτερον”; the difference between divine life and the various degrees
of natural life is more than a matter of duration. Cf. De Caelo 279a30.

65
alone, but in conjunction with the formal cause, as the perfection, or good, of a form or

nature.204 In the case of mortal living substances,205 which are most properly substances in

the sublunary realm, their final cause, to possess their nature as fully grown, is the cause of

their primary intrinsic motion or activity,206 to preserve their own life and species. Indeed, we

are told that a nature is the end of growth, e.g. the oak to the acorn.207 The sublunary

substances are, therefore, moved by their final cause, which is in one sense properly the form

of an individual, its soul, in another, the species universally. A living substance is also the

efficient cause of its daily activities (working upon its body as an instrument, ὄργανον) and

of the generation of similar substances for the sake of this final cause, which is its own good

or perfection. Thus, as Owens remarks, “efficient and final causes seem….to be reduced to

the formal cause as to their primary instance.”208 In one sense the final cause for natural

sublunary substances, as entelechies, is the perfect actualization of their own form. In

another, God, or divine goodness, as Aquinas calls it, is the final cause of all things, in so far

as such an actualization approaches pure and eternal actuality.209 Do the spheres share divine

life as an end in just the same way all the other natural substances do? I suggest not, but

rather, that Aristotle attributes more to the unmoved movers as the final causes of the spheres

than Aquinas’ general desire for divine goodness. In Λ.4’s discussion of the four causes, he

notes that there is another cause still besides these, the first cause which moves all things in

virtue of being first. As we indicated above, final causality is reduced to the formal cause,

204
1070a11.
205
We might include all natural substances, insofar as the nature of the elements causes like elements to come
to be, e.g. as fire heats and dries the other elements, or water cools and moistens them (Aristotle, On Generation
and Corruption, 331a25-331b1).
206
1014b20. The end of growth is the possession of such a nature, which includes the capability to cause others
to grow in a similar manner.
207
1070a12. A nature is both a nature as such and a ἕξις for that nature. The possession of the perfection of the
nature is the final cause.
208
Owens, 286.
209
Aquinas, Summa Theologica, I.I, Q.44, Art. 4.

66
and each of the spheres is caused immediately by one of the unmoved movers. Like

sublunary substances, the spheres have their own perfection as their end, but this perfection

is the approximation of divine life in a natural substance, which describes what the stars are

in themselves. They do not merely serve the eternity of a species, but possess eternal

actuality for themselves. In this way divine substance is the proximate final cause of the

spheres, rather than a further end achieved in virtue of a proximate end.

Is this likeness to the divine a to only one of the unmoved movers or is it to the first

unmoved mover? One possible interpretation of Λ.8 that Elders considers, but does not

adopt, distinguishes the unmoved movers as efficient from the first mover of Λ.7 as final.210

The text of Λ does not, however, provide support for the thesis that some movers are

efficient, rather than final, causes. When Aristotle moves to the eighth chapter he says “we

must inquire whether there many or one of such substance (τοιαύτην οὐσίαν),”211 the

τοιαύτην οὐσίαν being nothing other than God as described in Λ.7. Aristotle does not give us

a reason to consider kinds of unmoved mover; he gives no principle by which we can exclude

some of the attributes listed in chapters Λ.6, 7 and 9, except perhaps one. Λ.7 calls the first

mover that upon which nature and heaven hang or depend (as in Ross).212 This first mover

does have a certain significance that distinguishes it from the other unmoved movers. 213 It is

likely that this difference gives an apparent basis for those who are wont to make the other

movers strictly efficient to do so, knowing that the first unmoved mover fulfills the role of

final cause while efficiency is emphasized elsewhere.214 This solution does not, however,

210
Elders, 65.
211
1073a14. “πότερον δὲ μίαν θετέον τὴν τοιαύτην οὐσίαν ἢ πλείους;”
212
1072b14. ἐκ τοιαύτης ἄρα ἀρχῆς ἤρτηται ὁ οὐρανὸς καὶ ἡ φύσις.
213
Cf. 1076a4. The conclusion of the whole work rejects the rule of many as good.
214
Doubts about the authenticity of Λ.8 as a part of Metaphysics Λ appear on the point, as noted above, since its
doctrine seems to jar with the single separate substance taught in Λ.7,9 and 10 (Elders, 60-63). Elders holds that
many of the point of doctrine of the Metaphysics are contained in Λ.8, e.g. the necessity of an eternal mover and

67
explain how the unmoved movers are to be efficient as exclusive of final causality. One need

not move from “metaphysics to mechanics”,215 in order to make sense of this efficient

causality. Instead, if we follow the text we must admit that the unmoved movers are both

final and efficient causes, and that each kind of causality sheds light on each other, especially

in light of the reduction of both to formal, if we take it to mean exemplary, causality.

If each unmoved mover is a final cause, one must confront the claim that the motions

are for the sake of the stars.216 Just as the spheres do not choose an unmoved mover as their

final cause, we should not consider the unmoved movers as choosing to move a certain star,

since the movers cannot exist for an end external to them, as this would be in contradiction to

their perfection, as noted above. Any confusion that this passage might stir up about whether

final causality belongs properly to the stars or to the unmoved movers can be cleared up by

recognizing the distinction Aristotle makes about the way things can be an end. An end may

be either the recipient of some action or as something achieved or perfected. 217Aquinas

points out that this claim is made to refute the possibility that there should be other movers

besides those Aristotle has already numbered:

For one could say that there are many more motions in the heavens than have been
counted, but that these cannot be perceived because they produce no diversity in
motion of one of the celestial bodies which are perceived by the sense of sight and are
called stars.218

its priority to what it moves, but goes on to say that “in spite of these numerous points on which there is
agreement in doctrine and formulation between chapter eight and other parts of the Corpus, there are serious
difficulties which make it doubtful whether the chapter, as it is now, was written by Aristotle himself” (ibid,
65). He concludes that though containing Aristotelian doctrines, it isn’t written by Aristotle. Plurality and
efficiency are the difficulties. I hope to show, at least, that efficiency need not be.
215
This is a criticism Elders levels against Λ.8 generally.
216
1074a25.
217
Lloyd and Elders both make this point, applying the distinction made at 1072b2: ὅτι δ᾽ ἔστι τὸ οὗ ἕνεκα ἐν
τοῖς ἀκινήτοις, ἡ διαίρεσις δηλοῖ: ἔστι γὰρ τινὶ τὸ οὗ ἕνεκα καὶ τινός, ὧν τὸ μὲν ἔστι τὸ δ᾽ οὐκ ἔστι.” It is in
virtue of attaining some good that a the good of another is achieved (Elders, 234; Lloyd, 264-5).
218
Aquinas, §2590.

68
If so, it would not necessarily be the case that the movement of these imperceptible spheres

lack a per se relationship with their mover, but it would undermine the possibility of

astronomy aiding philosophy in counting the separate substance. Aristotle thus introduces

this principle of the stars as an end of motion to avoid this, as Aquinas explains:

And in order to reject this he had already said that there can be no celestial motion which is
not connected with the motion of some star. His words here are that there cannot be other
motions in the heavens besides those which produce the diversity in the motions of the
stars…This can be taken as a probable conclusion from the bodies which are moved; for if
every mover exists for the sake of something moved, and every motion belongs to something
which is moved, there can be no motion which exists for itself or merely for the sake of
another motion, but all must be for the stars…Now since an infinite regress is impossible, it
follows that the end of every motion is one of the celestial bodies, as the stars.219

As Aquinas explains, Aristotle’s point is that there is no act of moving which does not move

something, i.e. a substance. Thus there is no substance which moves without moving

something; to be a mover one must move something, even as a doctor doctors himself as

other.220 There can be no motion of a sphere which does not contribute motion to another

through contact, and since, if there is a mover it must move something (and spheres are direct

recipients of such motion in the heavens), its effect must be discernable in the motion of the

stars. It is in this manner that the unmoved movers are for the sake of the stars, i.e. as moving

them, but moving them not their purpose. It is only in relation to the spheres and stars that

they are called ‘movers’, because they accord with the substances that are moved, and
219
Ibid, §2592.
220
Aristotle, Physics II, 199b30.

69
movements are for the sake of substances rather than other movements. This principle

prevents a proliferation of other unmoved movers, and reaffirms Aristotle’s conviction that

each motion in the heavens, i.e. each moving sphere, has a substantial cause.

The unmoved movers move as final causes, but in conjunction with being efficient

and exemplary causes. Averroes presents the integration of these three kinds causality

succinctly: the nature that each unmoved mover causes is a nature ordered back towards the

very same unmoved mover.221 This is quite like the general, who orders the army to his own

end, but remains apart.222 The general provides the army with its existence, order and

purpose, i.e. its good and perfection, a purpose which shares in the general’s purpose. The

unmoved movers, as Alexander remarked, do not have an end, and thus have no external

purpose. The analogy stands, nevertheless, as the army shares in the life of the general, each

of spheres shares very closely in the life of its unmoved mover. The unmoved movers cause

the nature of the spheres and cause it to be oriented towards themselves so that this nature

itself takes the spheres as the object of desire. They do not merely imitate the eternity of the

separated substances, but they exhibit pure actuality as far as they are able, since as they are

without potentiality, except in the sense of “whence and whither” in their motion223 and, we

should add, qualifiedly as dependent upon the unmoved movers. As we learn in Θ, the

heavenly substances never tire or labour, their actuality is unchanging, and pleasurable. 224 As

221
Averroes, 2010, 152: “Consequently these [movers] are, from this point of view, in a certain way the
efficient causes of the substance of the [celestial bodies], since it is the efficient [cause] which provides the
substance of a thing, no matter, no matter whether it acts eternally or discontinuously (to act eternally is [of
course] better). Meanwhile they are from another point of view, formal [causes] for them, for the forms of the
celestial bodies are nothing else than that which the [celestial bodies] think of these [movers]. And [finally] they
are also final [causes] for them because the [celestial bodies] are moved by them by way of desire…”
222
Aquinas, §2630.
223
Metaphysics, Θ 1050b24.
224
1050b24-27. Cf. 1072b16.

70
Aristotle writes in Λ.7, “a life such as the best (i.e. the divine life) is ours for a short time”,225

and in a similar way the spheres have such a life, but imperishably. As nearest to the divine

separate substances in their share of divine life, their actuality is the greatest of all natural

substances. The simplicity of their existence is like that of their causes, the unmoved movers.

Their efficient, formal, final and causes of each sphere come together as one, as Owens

noted. The essence of the unmoved mover is such that it causes and orders another towards

itself in virtue of simply being itself.226 That these causes coincide227 is fitting. As the

unmoved movers are simple their causality should be equally simple, the effect of pure

actuality upon potentiality a potentiality.

3.3 CONCLUDING SUMMARY

We have now examined the principles and causes of the sensible substances, both

perishable and eternal. They do indeed share, analogically,228 the intrinsic causes, form,

matter and privation, and an extrinsic cause, the agent or efficient cause. Form is the very

actuality of a substance, and it applies to both perishable and eternal sensible substances

univocally. Matter and privation depend upon form, or actuality, and describe

changeableness, of substance (and all other accidents) in the case of sublunary substances,

but only of place in the case of the heavenly substances. The most important are the agent

and the form, since matter depends upon these. The analogy of general and the army explains

the relationship of form and agent. As the relationship between the army and the general is

225
1072b15. “…οἵα ἡ ἀρίστη μικρὸν χρόνον ἡμῖν.”
226
Berti, 203. “As we see later…this subject is the unmoved mover itself, and moves the heaven having itself as
its aim, i.e. the same unmoved mover”.
227
Lloyd, 264; Berti, 206. Both agree that it is reasonable for these causes to coincide.
228
Cf. 1070a32-33.

71
not at all arbitrary, neither is the relationship between form and the agent. Indeed, the agent,

which is prior in actuality, determines the form of the substance dependent upon it in virtue

of its own activity. The agent is an actuality which effects another actuality. This relationship

is visible in the natural sublunary (and even artificial) substances, which effect the cycles of

change in the natural world, especially in reproduction or art, where all the causes are

ordered to the end of an agent in virtue of its nature, but it is clearest in the case of the

heavenly spheres. In the heavens the relationship between perfect actuality and what it causes

is perpetually preserved. Indeed, the unmoved movers cause the spheres, not in time, but

eternally. The unmoved movers cause the existence and nature of the spheres, a nature which

is ordered towards the very same movers as the exemplar of perfect actuality. The pure

actuality of the unmoved movers exhibits all final, formal (extrinsically) and final causality

by virtue of simply being actual. The spheres are utterly dependent upon their particular

movers, but by no means at the cost of their own individual actuality—they are distinct

substances, as distinct as the general is from his army. He is not a part of the battle-line, but

without him it will collapse. Aristotle’s claim that the good exists in both the external cause

of a substance and the substance itself is an affirmation of the reality of the sensible

substances, without a denial of their dependence on transcendent causes. We must now turn

to these transcendent causes, the invisible substances, to complete our sketch of principles of

substance in Metaphysics Λ and determine how this analogy of the general and the army, of

the power of one actuality to actualize another, applies to the highest of beings.

72
CHAPTER 4 CONCLUSION

Three tasks remain: 1) to examine the how the causes and principles of the separate

substances are related to the common principles of sensible substance through the analogy of

the general and the army; 2) to show that the causes and principles of individual substances,

shown to be analogically alike through the analogy of the general and the army, are also the

common principles of the cosmos considered as a whole; and 3) that the principles of the

whole cosmos are the causes and origin of the causes and principles of all the sensible

substances. Completing these tasks so provides the ground for understanding how this

analogical unity of substances really describes the common principles of all substances.

Furthermore it will be shown that by considering separate substance in itself, the theology of

Metaphysics Λ illuminates our understanding of the causes and principles of all substances,

since separate substance, as described by the analogy of the general and the army, becomes

the prototypical instance of all causality and actuality. This theology is an account of the first

principle of all substances, it also belongs to first philosophy.

4.1 THE LIMITS OF THE ANALOGY APPLIED TO SEPARATE


SUBSTANCE

When the analogy of the general and the army is applied to the heavenly bodies, the

heavenly bodies, like the sublunary substances, are able to take both the position of the

general, insofar as they affect or even effect other substances, and the position of the army,

insofar as they are caused by the unmoved movers. But in the case of the first unmoved

mover, there is neither potentiality nor dependence upon a prior, external cause. Unlike both

eternal and perishable sensible substances, the first unmoved mover cannot take the role of

73
the army. The only way the analogy applies to the first unmoved mover is as cause, or

general, of the outermost sphere, as the good of the cosmos. The first unmoved mover is

uncaused, and hence has no extrinsic cause. It has no cause or principle beside itself, but is

the cause of its own actuality.

Aristotle does not, however, refrain from describing this divine actuality. It is not

bare “being”, but life best and eternal229 and also a thinking.230 This description of divine

blessedness does not describe principles of God’s being, but rather, what God’s actuality is.

It may seem problematic to describe God through a relational structure when God’s blessed

actuality is already described as not depending upon anything else. In light of God’s

complete priority as the first unmoved mover, the first actuality and the first substance, any

attempt to explain why God is as he is by other principles would be an empty investigation.

Without considering God relative to God’s effects, the only description which remains is

simply the fact of God’s own actuality. By looking at God’s effects in a relational structure,

however, one gains an insight into God’s actuality. Averroes notes that being a cause of other

substances is a part of the divine nature: “For it is impossible that any of these noble

principles exists without activity, as it is impossible that no ignition originates from the

essence of fire. These principles are by nature active [principles], just as the Sun generates

light by its nature.”231 God’s life and excellence are not known immediately, but through that

which they cause, the life of the heavenly bodies. All substances must take the role of the

general or the army, even the separate substances, since they cause motion necessarily. It is

229
1072b27-29. “καὶ ζωὴ δέ γε ὑπάρχει: ἡ γὰρ νοῦ ἐνέργεια ζωή, ἐκεῖνος δὲ ἡ ἐνέργεια: ἐνέργεια δὲ ἡ καθ᾽
αὑτὴν ἐκείνου ζωὴ ἀρίστη καὶ ἀΐδιος.”
230
1072b26-27.
231
Averroes, 149.

74
not a mistake to describe God as the general, but rather, it best describes God’s actuality in

relation to what it effects in virtue of itself.

Any other attempt to apply the analogy of the general and the army to separate

substances is tenuous. If it does apply to some of the separate substances, it will be to some

but not all. In that case, it must describe some kind of dependence of the numerous separated

substances of Λ.8 upon the first unmoved mover. A number of commentators who have tried

to work out the relationship between the many unmoved movers of Λ.8 and the first mover of

Λ.6 and 7 have suggested there may be some kind of dependence between them. Avicenna’s

position is that the unmoved movers are intelligences and emanations of from the Supreme

Mind, which is their cause.232 Aquinas, likewise, makes them angels, created by God.233

Kraemer adopts a different route, and suggests that the fifty-five unmoved movers are

essences contained in the unmoved mover as thoughts, but not existing separately from the

first mover.234Averroes says that the first mover is the cause all other movers, not differing in

species, but only in virtue.235 Lang says that there is only one unmoved mover, both in

number and definition.236 None of these interpretations, it seems to me, is necessitated by the

text itself, which remains frustratingly silent on the matter, besides its clear recognition that

the rule of one is best.237 Deciding this ambiguous point, however, is not essential to the

question about the how the analogy of the general and the army applies to the separated

substance. If it can apply to separate substance as it does to the sensible substances, this

would only be in the case of those separated substances which are dependent upon another

232
See Elders, 59.
233
Ibid.
234
Ibid, 63.
235
Averroes, 154-5.
236
Lang, 267.
237
1076a4.

75
separated substance. Like the spheres, as eternal they will not exhibit any potentiality for

existence. In this chapter, however, we must consider a separate substance which is not

caused in any way.

There is another possibility to be considered: that the analogy does not apply within

the unmoved mover. The simplicity of the first mover prevents this, since it is without parts.

There is no relationship in the first mover which can be the subject of analogy. 1073a6 attests

to this point in saying that the first mover is without magnitude, parts or divisibility. Thus it

has no sensible parts, nor logical parts, and cannot be divided. It is wholly one. Many take

Λ.9 to explain the nature of the first unmoved mover’s simplicity, and also to clarify the

nature of the divine as a thinker.238 This has been, of course, one of the most common

interpretations, although the Aristotelian corpus does not suggest this in every case. 239 In Λ.9

Aristotle shows that if God is νοῦς, such νοῦς will be simple by being both the knower and

its own object (if it must think the noblest of objects).240 On the other hand, if the association

of νοῦς and God is not meant, except as an image of simplicity, God is simply pure actuality

without qualification.241 Pure actuality does not admit of difference, since it is without

magnitude, and does not have intelligible parts, being indivisible and without potentiality. As

Alexander reaffirms, God is simple.242 In God there is neither priority nor potentiality, but

only one actuality. God is simple, not a whole, and cannot be treated by the analogy as such.

238
Elders, 248; Ross, 397; Aquinas, §2600.
239
Aristotle, Eudemian Ethics, 1248a26-29.
240
Aquinas, §2542-3; 1072b19-20.
241
Kosman, Metaphysics Λ.9: Divine Thought, 311; Lang, 270-3. Kosman thinks that νοῦς reflects something
about substance as pure actuality. Lang, on the other hand does not think that the examination of νοῦς has to do
with substance per se but relates to a question raised about mind in the course of the discussion about substance
about the nature of mind. Aquinas’ interpretation certainly takes the position that this study clarifies something
about divine substance in se, since according to his reading the nature of the first mover is an intellect which is
pure actuality.
242
Alexander of Aphrodisias, Quaestiones 1.1-2.15, 102.

76
4.2 GOD, ACTUALITY AND POTENTIALITY

One should not shrink from applying the analogy of the general and the army to God.

God appears in the original use of the analogy, although the analogy is meant to uncover how

the nature of the whole possesses its good. The conclusion the analogy leads to, however,

indicates another manner in which we might read the analogy. The investigation at the

beginning of Λ.10 determines that the good and perfection of the cosmos, its order or nature,

really does belong to the cosmos as something distinct from the first mover, but depends on

the first mover. God is actually the primary cause of the substance, even more so than the

imminent form in the caused substance. The conclusion of the chapter, especially the

quotation from Homer, makes the point that the world is, in fact, governed, not badly by

many rulers, but well by one ruler. On one hand we draw conclusions about the cosmos: it is

ruled well and depends upon something outside of it—conclusions that remain true about

sensible substances, and perhaps some separate substances, but not all substances. We can

also invert the perspective of the analogy, so that the general, God, is the substance in

question. We thus draw other conclusions: God, the first mover and substance, is of such a

nature that it is the eternal cause of the cosmos, simply in virtue of being a pure actuality. In

the first substance, being actual and actualizing another substance are not distinct actions.243

God’s pure actuality exists for itself and is productive in virtue of this actuality.

When the analogy of the general and the army focused upon the general it loses none

of its explanatory force. In the analogy the general exists alongside the army, but is prior to it

by virtue of being its cause—efficiently, exemplarily, and finally. The general is not,

243
We might recall what Aquinas says about divine knowing and knowing all other things in this, and translate
it to the divine actuality, so that the actuality of God and the actualizing of other things are not distinct, but one
is through the other.

77
however, the general in virtue of the army. Armies do not find generals, but generals cause

armies. Nor is he a general without the army. As God does not exist without the cosmos

existing, nor does the general exist as a general without his army. The general pursues some

end for himself, but not for the army. Likewise God does not seek an external end, and and

neither does the general: he exists to do things a general does. The analogy should not be

pushed too far, however, a few important points can be noted: 1) both the general and God

are actual prior to that which they cause, not in time but in the order of causation; 2) both

cause something in virtue of their actuality, not in addition to their actuality; 3) both exist

alongside their effects, which they necessarily effect, and can be known through them. Since

these points describe both God and the general, we may state with confidence that the

analogy does describe the transcendent substance in the analogy as well as the caused

substance without changing the nature of the analogy.

It is clear that applying the analogy of the general and the army to separated uncaused

substance is possible, but within certain limits. Whereas the caused substances can stand in

both positions, either that of the army or the general, an uncaused substance can only hold

the position of the general. Does change in focus indicate that there must be two sciences of

substance, one from the perspective of caused substances and one from the perspective of

uncaused substances? Not necessarily. There is nothing to say that the general’s side of the

analogy is necessarily uncaused, but only relative to what it causes, in the same way that Λ.3

informs us in the process of change that matter and form never come to be, nor the agent, but

only substance which is generated.244 In themselves, they may have very well come to be, or

they may not have, but in a causal relationship, which the analogy of the army and the

244
1069b35-1070a2.

78
general describes, they have not come to be.245 Generals themselves do come to be, and even

die, but not the generalship relative to the army. All substances, likewise, exhibit both

actuality and a capacity to have effects according their actuality. To examine actuality, which

properly belongs to all substances, is considering what is universal to substances.

Considering caused substances in themselves however only studies one aspect of substance,

and insofar as all substances approximate the divine life, it would be the less important

aspect.

The relationship between the first mover and the cosmos, represented by the analogy

of the general and the army is the most perfect example of the relationship of cause and

caused. It is a distillation of that relationship which belongs to all substances, and even all

beings, since there is no substance which either has no effect or is not caused. 246 It is a

distillation because it has none of the attributes, such as time or appearance, which disguise

the relationship, e.g. as in the order of becoming when potentiality seems to precede

actuality. In the case of the first mover we can see quite clearly that a perfect actuality

precedes a caused actuality. Moreover, we also see that potentiality qua potential is also

dependent upon actuality, since without God, the cosmos could not be. And finally, we also

see that what is caused is not just anything, but conformed to its cause (for without this

causality would not be reasonable, but entirely random), since the eternal cause also effects

something eternal and like itself, and as Alexander says, it could not be otherwise since their

eternity does not only come from the eternity of their cause, but of the nature which is

caused.247 These attributes of the relationship between causing substance and caused

245
1069b35.
246
All pure actualities have an effect, the whole cosmos or the individual spheres, and all others beings are
caused in one way or another, both the substances and the categories which are predicated of them.
247
Alexander, Quaestiones 1.1-2.15, 66.

79
substance, or a prior actuality, potentiality and a caused actuality are universal. These are the

causes and principles of every varied case of causation.

God and his effects are explicable by the same analogy that describes the relationship

of any agent actualizing another substance to that substance which it actualizes. Matter and

privation, is not present in God’s actuality, but they are, nevertheless, directly related to

God’s actualizing power. The analogy of the general and the army, representing the

analogically common principles of substance, describes the causal relationship between

God’s actuality and all substances, e.g. the first heaven, dependent upon it. The same

framework of causes and principles that applies to the perishable sensible substances is also

able to describe the relationship between God, who has no external cause, and either the

whole cosmos, as per Λ.10, or the first heaven as per Λ.7. The same structure can be applied

to all: a perfect, uncaused248 actuality causes another actuality out of some potentiality. In the

case of the heavenly bodies they have a matter with a capacity for motion. They do not come

to be, but are caused by an eternal and necessary substance, upon which they depend. In this

way, all substances are described in the framework of the army’s relation to the general,

representing the relation of something ordered to an ordering substance.

4.3 THE UNITY OF THE COSMOS

We have seen that the applicability of the general and the army analogy is a fitting

description of the principles of all the kinds of substances. The analogy applies, however,

248
The agent is never caused in the course of causing, as Aristotle explains in Λ.3. This does not preclude the
agent could have been caused in another relationship of causality, as we explained in the first chapter.

80
first of all to God249 and the whole, i.e., the natural world.250 It distinguishes the whole world

from its extrinsic cause of goodness, which is order in the analogy, specifically the order or

arrangement of the army. This order has not been absent in the previous chapters. The

investigation of the sublunary substances shows that the heavenly bodies, through the Sun,

effect generation in the sublunary realm. Likewise, the heavenly bodies depend upon the

separate substances. I will now show that this cosmic order, which is described by the

analogy of the general and the army, also orders individual substances just as it is ordered.

The principles of the world as a whole and of individual substances explain how causes and

principles of all substances share analogically like causes.

The majority of the descriptions of cosmic unity are found in Λ.10. The first is the

simple fact that Aristotle acknowledges the possibility that the whole has a nature. By asking:

“how the nature of the whole possesses the good and the best?”251 The second states that

individual substances of the same kind (i.e. sensible perishable substance), fish, birds, etc…

are also ordered together.252 Third, Aristotle provides another analogy to describe the order in

the whole, the analogy of the household and its members, which describes how different

parts of the whole contribute hierarchically253 to its good (the immanent good, the order in
254
the army). Λ.5 informs us that the Sun is one of the causes of change in the sublunary

249
Recalling along with Lang, Ross, Aquinas and others that the good referred to in Λ.10 is referring to the First
Unmoved Mover, i.e. God.
250
Where the others unmoved movers belong is a difficult question. Do they belong on the side of God, as all
sharing in “such a substance”, i.e. divine (1073a14-15). Aristotle does not indicate an answer to the question.
The claim at the end of the chapter that there must be one ruler, one external principle of the good of the whole
suggests that they must be subordinate to the first somehow.
251
1075a11. “…ποτέρως ἔχει ἡ τοῦ ὅλου φύσις τὸ ἀγαθὸν καὶ τὸ ἄριστον…”
252
1075a16. “πάντα δὲ συντέτακταί πως, ἀλλ᾽ οὐχ ὁμοίως, καὶ πλωτὰ καὶ πτηνὰ καὶ φυτά…”
253
Aristotle does not use the “hierarchy” himself, which emerges in later Greek writers, nevertheless he does
recognize that some substances are more perfect than others, at that each contributes to the whole according to
its perfection.
254
Ibid. 19. “πρὸς μὲν γὰρ ἓν ἅπαντα συντέτακται, ἀλλ᾽ ὥσπερ ἐν οἰκίᾳ…”

81
realm as an efficient cause.255 Λ.6, 7, and particularly 8256 show that the separate substances

are the causes of the motion and actuality of the heavenly spheres, and that these sperhes

form a whole system. Finally, Λ.4, 5, and 7257 attest that God is not only the first mover of

the outermost sphere, but even of all sensible substances. An account of cosmic order in Λ

must come out of, and conform to, these passages.

4.3.1 THE TWO DIMENSIONS OF COSMIC UNITY

The cosmic order includes what I will call a vertical dimension as well as a horizontal

dimension. In the vertical dimension, a higher, more perfect kind of substance orders a lower

kind. There are two general cases of this: 1) the unmoved movers as the efficient, exemplary

and final causes of the heavenly spheres; 2) the motion of the heavens, particularly, the Sun

in its ecliptic orbit, which is neither “matter, form, nor privation [of what it causes], nor of

the same form, but is a moving cause.”258 The unmoved movers are the immediate causes of

the spheres, but the Sun’s changing position on the ecliptic is a remote efficient cause, unlike

the father or artist, which are proximate efficient causes. The Sun’s orbit on the ecliptic is

associated with the cycle of the seasons,259 and so described as κινῶν in the broader sense of

causing change. This seasonal change governs the substantial changes of the natural

substances in the sublunary realm, their generation and destruction, albeit, in a remote

255
1071a16-17. κινοῦντα.”
256
1071b18-19; 1072b7-10; 1073a32-34.
257
1070b35; 1071a36; 1072b14.
258
1071a16-17.” καὶ παρὰ ταῦτα ὁ ἥλιος καὶ ὁ λοξὸς κύκλος, οὔτε ὕλη ὄντα οὔτ᾽ εἶδος οὔτε στέρησις οὔτε
ὁμοειδὲς ἀλλὰ κινοῦντα.”
259
Aristotle, On Generation and Corruption, 336b16-20; Ross, 365.

82
manner. It does not cause any single substance to come to be immediately, but does cause the

eternal cycle of generation and destruction in the sublunary realm, as Simplicius explains:

And [how much better] on the other hand [to say] that the sublunary [region], which came to
be through eternal and eternally moving things created by him, possesses parts that come to
be and pass away, in order that even the remotest thing of the world be generated through the
creator’s goodness. But he who always exists produced it, and it is eternal too because the
destruction of one thing is the generation of another, since he has made generation
perpetual.260

The Sun is the source of the order, even the existence,261 which is manifest in the generation

and destruction of the sublunary realm. The Sun’s own cycle is the cause of the cycle below

it, a cycle which involves many substances.

The horizontal dimension of the order is expressed in the description of the

interactions within the kinds of substances: the interactions of the sublunary substances and

the interaction of the heavenly spheres with each other. The heavenly and sublunary realms

each constitute a whole, a system in which the activity of all the parts contribute to an eternal

order. The heavens are arranged so that the motions of the planets in their spheres do not

disturb each other. The system of revolving and counter-revolving spheres, which we

discussed in the previous chapter, indicates that all the parts must be perfectly balanced, lest

one exert an excessive influence.262 The perfect rotation of all the spheres and stars is the

result of the movement of all of the parts of the heavens ordered together. Similarly, the

sublunary substances are also ordered together (συντέτακταί), as Aristotle describes:

260
Simplicius, 116.
261
In the same manner the unmoved movers cause the spheres by eternally actualizing a capacity.
262
Bodnár, 268. Changing the conditions of even one of the spheres would produce a radically different
appearance of motion in the heavens. The revolving spheres prevent proliferation of motion in the heavens, e.g.
all the motions of one star being superadded to the motions of the star below it through the interaction of the
spheres which move each of these stars.

83
“Everything is ordered together as fish and birds and plants are, but not all in the same way.

Nor does it hold that one thing is unrelated to another, but there is [a relationship].”263

Aristotle completes his description of this order by describing it as an order towards one

thing, like a household. How all substances are ordered will be considered below, but for

now it is enough to note that Aristotle regards the living creatures in the sublunary realm, in

their variety of species and genera, as ordered together in some way. Within a species it is

easy to see that there is an order, since the species reproduces itself. Furthermore, the whole

cycle of life and death involves a relationship between all the species. Some animals eat

others, others eat plants, and some help plants grow.264 The spheres and the species in the

sublunary realm265 are thus ordered together in a similar way. Each species, including all of

its members, is ordered to the good of the whole, which includes the preservation of every

other species, both by preserving itself and serving another species. Thus the ecosystem of

the sublunary realm is preserved eternally.266 Likewise each sphere in the heavens

contributes some motion so that the motion of the heavens is the eternal and regular, and this

is accomplished through the interactions of the spheres with each other.

Both the sublunary realm and the heavens are ordered towards an eternal order, which

exists in them, but also on account of an external, eternal cause. The unmoved movers are

causes of the eternal motion which characterizes the heavens. Similarly, the Sun is the cause

of eternal generation which characterizes the sublunary ecosystem’s persistence, and so is a

263
1075a16-18. “πάντα δὲ συντέτακταί πως, ἀλλ᾽ οὐχ ὁμοίως, καὶ πλωτὰ καὶ πτηνὰ καὶ φυτά: καὶ οὐχ οὕτως
ἔχει ὥστε μὴ εἶναι θατέρῳ πρὸς θάτερον μηδέν, ἀλλ᾽ ἔστι τι.”
264
Cf. Aquinas, §2632. We should not find this notion of an ecosystem surprising, given his remarkable effort
as a biologist.
265
The species must be seen as taking up the elements too, since they are also natural bodies. What role can be
assigned to the products of art is debatable. As composed of natural parts, they are not outside the system. As
distinct substances, however, they may be seen as subordinate to human life. Political life is not discussed here,
but it too could be subordinated to the eternal continuation of the human species.
266
Cf. Aristotle, De Anima, 415a30-b2; Cf. Simplicius, 116.

84
cause of every single sublunary substance. The sublunary realm and the heavens are not

merely ordered towards themselves, but towards a likeness of that which causes them. Recall

the general and the army. The army is not ordered together for itself, but for the general. This

is the second aspect of the vertical dimension. Whereas the first is the relationship of an

efficient cause causing another substance, the second is the ordering of what is caused

towards that which caused it and stands above it. This recalls Aristotle’s description of the

generation of living beings: the substance that is generated is ordered towards the same form

as the substance which generated it.267 Likewise, every substance within the sublunary realm

or in the heavens is ordered together towards a whole beyond themselves. Aristotle explains

how all things are ordered together:

Everything is ordered together to one [end], but just as in a house there is little done at
random by the freemen, for them most everything is already ordered, but for the slaves and
the beasts, who contribute little to what is common, there is much to be done at random: for
the [governing] principle of each of these is his nature. I say such, that is indeed necessary
for everything to come to its dissolution, but also that everything also shares in contributing
to the whole.268

The household is greater than any of its members, even the highest of its members.269 The

whole has its own nature,270 a position which Aristotle takes at the beginning of Λ.10’s

267
Cf. 1070a27-29.
268
1075a19-25. “πρὸς μὲν γὰρ ἓν ἅπαντα συντέτακται, ἀλλ᾽ ὥσπερ ἐν οἰκίᾳ τοῖς ἐλευθέροις ἥκιστα ἔξεστιν ὅ τι
ἔτυχε ποιεῖν, ἀλλὰ πάντα ἢ τὰ πλεῖστα τέτακται, τοῖς δὲ ἀνδραπόδοις καὶ τοῖς θηρίοις μικρὸν τὸ εἰς τὸ κοινόν,
τὸ δὲ πολὺ ὅ τι ἔτυχεν: τοιαύτη γὰρ ἑκάστου ἀρχὴ αὐτῶν ἡ φύσις ἐστίν. λέγω δ᾽ οἷον εἴς γε τὸ διακριθῆναι
ἀνάγκη ἅπασιν ἐλθεῖν, καὶ ἄλλα οὕτως ἔστιν ὧν κοινωνεῖ ἅπαντα εἰς τὸ ὅλον.”
269
It is worthwhile noting here that the freemen are not in the same position of the general. The freemen serve
the whole house, and while they are the best members, and perhaps benefit from and to the household the most,
they are still ordered by it. We might later consider the similar role played by the outermost sphere of the
heavens, as the first principle order within the household, ordered and ordering, rather than simply ordered.
270
The definition of nature in Metaphysics Δ.4, and the concept of nature in Λ.3 suggest that the attribution of a
nature to the whole is not to be taken lightly. The whole has real existence, and even a priority over the
particulars, just as the nature has priority of the parts of a body.

85
investigation and never relinquishes. The common nature of the sublunary realm outlasts any

single one of its members, and even directs the continuation of all the species. In the case of

the heavens the motion of the whole is distinct from the motion of any one of its spheres. In

each case all the members of a whole contribute something distinct from every other

member, not by compulsion, but by their nature. The nature of the whole is seen in the

interaction of the multiplicity of natures within the whole. The order of the whole does not

exist by constraining the individual substances within it, but recalling Aristotle’s definition of

nature as that which has the source of motion and rest in itself, 271 it exists through the

freedom of all of it members. Just as the shared form exists through each of its members and

is thus both contemporaneous and also prior to it, so the nature of a whole is to all of its

members.

The sublunary realm and the heavens make up the whole cosmos, and as such

constitute the whole Aristotle is discussing in Λ.10. These two halves both have an extrinsic

cause and immanent cause of their eternal actuality, i.e. the nature of each of these two

wholes. The extrinsic cause of the sublunary realm’s unity, the Sun, is a member of the

heavens; the Sun depends on the whole heavenly system. The nature of the whole heavens is

the cause of the Sun’s activity, which in turn is the cause of the eternal actuality (through

change) in the sublunary realm. A chain of causality, beginning with the first unmoved

mover, as noted by Simplicius in the passage cited above, causes even the most remote thing

to be produced. Even the least substance, however, has a role in the eternal actuality and

motion exhibited by the whole. The analogy of the household from Λ.10 describes this

hierarchy by stating that some members, the freemen, are highly ordered and do little

randomly, while the slaves and beasts contribute little to whole and do much at random. The
271
Aristotle, Physics II, 192b15.

86
heavenly bodies’ regular motion is not only highly ordered, they are the cause of the

generation, and therefore the actuality, of the sublunary substances; substances which are,

individually, both contingent and ephemeral. The heavenly bodies, especially the outermost

ones, insofar as they are causes of motion in the whole cosmos, 272 contribute to the actuality

of the sublunary bodies in virtue of their own eternal actuality. The sublunary bodies,

however, contribute nothing to the heavens. Their role is to be a part of the eternity of

actuality in the sublunary by being involved through constant generation and destruction.

Each substance contributes to the actuality of all whole in all of its parts, but in degrees

according to the perfection of each. This perfection is measured against the first cause, which

is the cause of actuality in all substances.273

4.3.2 GOD AS THE EFFICIENT CAUSE OF ALL SUBSTANCES

God, the first mover, is regarded as the extrinsic cause of the good of this whole. As I

have shown in the previous chapters, this good is nothing less than the possession of actuality

and perfection. Aristotle asks of the good of the nature of the whole whether it is the order

(τάξις) or the extrinsic, separate cause of that same order (κεχωρισμένον).274 The order

should not be thought to be something distinct from the nature of the whole, for the whole is

not merely its parts, but as we have seen above, its very nature is its wonderful arrangement,

272
1072a15. According to Λ.6 the first heaven is a cause of regular motion in the heavens. The revolving
spheres seem to contradict this claim. Averroes recognizes this difficulty: “Such [is their number] when we
suppose that there is [only] one mover for the diurnal motion of all spheres [together]. But when we regard this
motion in such a way that every single sphere has its [own] peculiar mover for this [diurnal motion], the number
of [celestial] movers will amount to forty-five. Prima facie, this seems to be what Aristotle teaches. However,
Alexander [of Aphrodisias] states explicitly a different view in his treatise known as On the Principles of the
Cosmos [where] he considers [only] one mover for these diurnal motions of all spheres [together]. And indeed,
it is an unsettled question which of the two views is more appropriate and suitable” (Averroes, 147).
273
1071a36.
274
1075a13.

87
through which it and all its parts (or species) exist and even live eternally. Likewise, an army

is not yet an army if it is not ordered for warfare. It needs officers and divisions and all the

other arrangements that make it a fighting force able to carry out the commands of its

general. As the general is to the army, and even the Sun to the sublunary realm, so is the first

unmoved mover, God, to the whole cosmos. God is the ruler which rules the cosmos well,275

through which the cosmos has its order in itself, which makes it what it is.

God is the cause of the actuality of the whole. Λ.5 notes that God is “first in

actuality”, and as such is the common cause of all substances. 276 God is not, however, the

proximate cause of the actuality of every substance. God, as the first unmoved mover, is the

cause of the first moved mover, and also the cause of the whole. We are also told that God is

that which moves all things, and that God moves by being loved.277 These three ways in

which God is a cause are connected. God causes a dependent actuality, the outermost sphere.

The outermost sphere approximates God’s life as far as it is able, and in turn it also

influences the motion of the whole of the heavens, which as a whole also shares this eternal

life and actuality as far as possible.

275
1076a4. “οὐκ ἀγαθὸν πολυκοιρανίη: εἷς κοίρανος ἔστω.”
276
1071a35. “ἔτι τὸ πρῶτον ἐντελεχείᾳ”. Elders takes this phrase to mean that God is first in actuality, but
offers no suggestion why ἐντελεχεία is used rather than ἐνέργεια. (Elders, 136) Aquinas reads the phrase
differently, and takes it to mean that “[all] principles are ‘complete reality’, i.e. actuality and potentiality.”
(Aquinas, §2484) Aquinas seems to be taking “complete reality” to mean, everything that is, both actually and
potentially. Aquinas difficulty may stem from his Latin text, perhaps obscuring the meaning of ἐντελεχεία,
which refers to an actuality (although one entelechy may be the potential for another). “τὸ πρῶτον ἐντελεχείᾳ”
refers to a particular being. If it were read as being the first actuality like the soul in each thing it could not be
the same for all substances. This specific entelechy must be a cause of all things, and God is the only such
particular entelechy.
277
1070b35; 1072b3-4.

88
4.3.3 GOD AS THE EXEMPLARY CAUSE OF ALL SUBSTANCES

God, being both uncaused and perfect, is both a proximate and remote cause. What

God causes immediately, the outermost sphere, approximates God’s perfection as far as

possible. Its actuality is in being a sensible likeness of the first of the separate substances.278

Similar to the generation of the sublunary realm, there is a likeness between cause and

caused, and what is caused depends upon its cause. The other unmoved movers cause the rest

of the spheres, but these spheres are subordinate to the sphere caused by the first unmoved

mover (as movers subordinate to the first mover), their order and actuality is in reference to

its invariable motion. Each sphere approximates the perfection of its unmoved mover, but

most are also moved by the spheres above. The principles that explain the interaction

between spheres are analogous to the principles of their existence. Whereas the unmoved

movers are the cause of the motion which constitutes the essence of each sphere in virtue of

its actuality as separate substance, for which the spheres have potential,279 each sphere effects

motion in the sphere below it in virtue of its own actuality as a sphere with a certain motion.

The principles in each case are a prior actuality, a caused actuality and a potential for this

caused actuality. The principles of the sphere’s interactions exist in virtue of the principles of

the sphere’s existence. The unmoved movers cause the spheres to move as they do and the

spheres interact accordingly. Moreover, the spheres also have the power to order the

substances below them, much like the unmoved movers order the spheres.

A similar relationship exists between the heavens and the sublunary realm, insofar as

the heavens are a cause of the actuality of the sublunary substances. The principles of

278
Kosman, “Aristotle’s Prime Mover”, 151.
279
Charles , 91. This potential is the matter for motion, which is, following Charles, not a matter for accidental
change, but the matter for what the spheres are. It is analogous to the matter for generation in the sublunary
substances.

89
sublunary substances, which are also a prior actuality, a potential and a caused actuality

(expressed in the four principles, where privation describes one side of the substantial

change) are caused by the heavens, particularly mediated through the motions of the Sun.

Each sublunary substance is caused by a substance already possessing its perfection, either

an adult or a something with the capacity to effect change, and out of some potential in

another substance. Each species exists without beginning or end in time because of this

relationship, but it has its origin in the motion of the heavens, which also goes through

cycles, albeit without destruction.

The actuality of the whole can be traced back to the first unmoved mover, in more

than one way. While God is not the proximate cause of every substance, God is the first of all

substances (and even of the unmoved movers, although how they are subordinate to God

remains a questions, whether it be some kind of dependence or not), and is the cause of the

first of the sensible substances. Insofar as the other unmoved movers are subordinate to God,

each of the other caused spheres also has God as a remote cause. The actuality of the

heavens, thus, depends upon God. The sublunary realm, insofar as it depends upon the

heavens, also has God as a remote cause of its actuality. Apart from God no substance would

exist.

Besides this, the principles which explain God’s actuality and effects are found in all

the substances dependent upon God. Hence, not only do all substances depend upon God, but

their interaction with each other is governed by like principles present in all of them. The

cause causes something like itself in virtue of itself, and so like principles describe each

substance, if somewhat differently in each case. In this sense God is the cause of the

interaction between substances, albeit, often mediated through other substances.

90
4.3.4 GOD AS THE FINAL CAUSE OF ALL SUBSTANCES

The third way in which God is the cause of all substances is as a final cause, i.e. by

being desired. Not every substance is capable of “desire” strictly, but this is mitigated if we

consider what is “desired.” God is identified with that which is desirable in itself,280 and God

is also described as actuality, life best and eternal.281 This actuality, which is something

divine, is what is desired. Substances desire their own actuality, this is what they preserve, as

far as they can. In the sensible substances change and motion approximates simple actuality

by being directed towards some changeless form. God is a final cause not in addition to the

distinct final causes of every natural substance, but in that final cause itself. Every substance

loves in itself what God is in God’s own self. In this way the actuality which all substances

have because of God is also directed towards God in the way we just described. Some

substances - perhaps the spheres and humans - may be aware of this relationship, and even

think of God as an end, or share in this perfect actuality by thought,282 but all substance are

ordered towards being as much like the divine as possible, insofar as they share something

divine in virtue of their actuality and its causes. The whole cosmos is ordered to achieve this,

both in its parts and as a whole.

It is not difficult to see how this understanding of God as a final cause explains how

God orders the universe as described in the conclusion of Λ. God does not constrain the

cosmos with some order, but is the cause of its natural ordering towards its own eternal

actuality. Just as the army exists for achieving the end of its general, so does the cosmos exist

to approximate God’s actuality. This is what nature’s order is for, and why its order is good.

280
1072a34-35.
281
1072b28-30. “ἐνέργεια δὲ ἡ καθ᾽ αὑτὴν ἐκείνου ζωὴ ἀρίστη καὶ ἀΐδιος. φαμὲν δὴ τὸν θεὸν εἶναι ζῷον ἀΐδιον
ἄριστον, ὥστε ζωὴ καὶ αἰὼν συνεχὴς καὶ ἀΐδιος ὑπάρχει τῷ θεῷ: τοῦτο γὰρ ὁ θεός.”
282
1072b15. “διαγωγὴ δ᾽ ἐστὶν οἵα ἡ ἀρίστη μικρὸν χρόνον ἡμῖν…”

91
As the army could not achieve its purpose without its order, neither could the cosmos have

eternal actuality without its order.

4.4 CONCLUSION

All substances have a common origin of their actuality, and therefore, also their

causes and principles. Our examination of actuality, both as causing and caused, has shown

that the analogy of the general and army which expresses this relationship, applies to all

substances, although the details vary from substance to substance. Common to all three kinds

of substance is the structure of one substance causing another like it in some degree, in virtue

of itself out of some potency, whether logical or temporal. This includes all substances, even

those which are uncaused, (even if this ultimately is only the fits the unique instance of the

unmoved mover). All substances have God as a common principle, as the cause of the

actuality of the whole, and more than this, as the cause for the shared principles. The

principles described by the analogy of the general and the army are thus present in all three

kinds of substance, as well as in their relation to each other. Since there are indeed principles

common to separate and sensible substance there is no need to exclude sensible substances

from the science that also investigates separate substance.283 It is, therefore, possible to have

a science of substance qua substance, a genuine “περὶ τῆς οὐσίας ἡ θεωρία”284 that accounts

for a universal order in the cosmos and recognize that individuals are substances.

283
Cf. 1069b1.
284
1069a1.

92
BIBLIOGRAPHY

TEXTS AND TRANSLATIONS OF ARISTOTLE

Aristotle. Aristotle's Metaphysics. Edited by W.D. Ross. Oxford: Clarendon Press. 1924.
Perseus Digital Library. Web. 11 December, 2011.

______. Metaphysics. Translated by W. D. Ross. Edited by Richard McKeon. Random


House: New York, 1941. Print.

______. The Metaphysics, Vol I. Translated by H. Treddenick. Cambridge: Harvard


University Press, 1962. Print.

______. Metaphysics, Vol. II. Translated by G. C. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.


Loeb Classical Library, 1989. Print.

______. On the Soul. Translated by W.S. Hett. London: Heinemann. Loeb Classical Library,
1936. Print.

______. De Anima. Edited by W. D. Ross. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1961. Print.

______. Aristotle. De Caelo. In The Basic Works of Aristotle. Ed. Richard McKeon.
Translated by W. D. Ross. New York: The Modern Library, 2001. Print.

______. On Generation and Corruption. In The Basic Works of Aristotle. Ed. C.D.C. Reeve.
Trans. Harold H. Joachim. New York: Modern World Library, 2001. Print.

_____. Eudemian Ethics. Translated by H. Rackam. Cambridge: Harvard University Press,


1952. Print.

93
ANCIENT AND MEDIEVAL SOURCES

Alexander of Aphrodisias. On Aristotle’s Metaphysics I. Trans. W.E. Dooley, S.J.. Ithaca,


New York: Cornell University Press, 1989. Print

______. On Aristotle’s Metaphysics V. Translated by W.E. Dooley, S.J.. Ithaca, New York:
Cornell University Press, 1989. Print

______. Quaestiones 1.1-2.15. Translated by R.W. Sharples. Ithaca: Cornell University


Press, 1992. Print.

Aquinas, Thomas, O.P. Commentary on the Metaphysics of Aristotle, Vol. I & II. Translated
by J. P. Rowan. Chicago: H. Regenery Co., 1961. Print

______. Summa Theologica of St. Thomas Aquinas. 2nd ed. Translated by the Fathers of the
English Dominican Province. London: Burns, Oates & Washburne, 1920. New
Advent: Web. 11 December, 2011.

______. Aristotle's De Anima, in the Version of William of Moerbeke; and the Commentary of
St. Thomas Aquinas. Translated by K. Foster O.P. and S. Humphries O.P.. London:
Routledge and Keegan Paul Ltd, 1951. Print

Averroes. On Aristotle's Metaphysics. Tranaslated and Edited by R. Arnzen. New York: De


Gruyter, 2010. Print

Simplicius. “Simplicius against Philoponus on Aristotle’s argument that no infinite capacity


can reside in an infinite body.” Place Void and Eternity. Translated by Christian
Wildberg. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1991. Print.

MODERN SOURCES

Anscombe, G.E.M. “The Principle of Individuation” Articles on Aristotle: 3. Metaphysics.


Edited by Jonathan Barnes, Malcolm Schofield and Richard Sorabji. London:
Duckworth, 1979. Print

94
Bodnár, István M. “Aristotle’s Rewinding Spheres: Three Options and their Difficulties.”
Apeiron: A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science, 38.4, 2005: 257-275.
Philpapers. Web. 28. 28 July 2011.

Berti, Enrico. “Metaphysics Λ.6.” Aristotle’s Metaphysics Lambda, edited by Michael Frede
and David Charles. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000. 181-206. Print.

Beere, Jonathan. “Counting the Unmoved Movers: Astronomy and Explanation in Aristotle’s
Metaphysics XII”, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 85.1, 2003: 1-20.
Philpapers. Web. 28 July 2011.

Bos, Abraham. “Aristotle on God as a Principle of Genesis.” British Journal for the History
of Philosophy, 18.3, 2010: 363-377. Philpapers. Web. 12 December 2011.

Broadie, Sarah. “Que fait le moteur d’Aristote? (Sur la théologie du livre Lambda de la
«Métaphysique».” Translated by Jacques Brunschwig. Revue philosophique de la
France et de l’Etranger, 183, 1993: 375-411. JSTOR. Web. 12 December 2011.

Burnyeat, Myles. Aristotle’s Divine Intellect. Marquette University Press, 2008. Print.

______. A Map of Metaphysics Zeta. Pittsburgh: Mathesis Publications, 2001. Print

Charles, David. “Metaphysics Λ.2.” Aristotle’s Metaphysics Lambda, Edited by Michael


Frede and David Charles. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000. 81-110. Print.

Code, Alan. “Metaphysics Λ.5.” Aristotle’s Metaphysics Lambda, Edited by Michael Frede
and David Charles. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000. 161-180. Print.

Crubelier, Michael. “Metaphysics Λ.4.” Aristotle’s Metaphysics Lambda, Edited by Michael


Frede and David Charles. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000. 137-160. Print.

Elders S.V.D., Leo. Aristotle's Theology. Assen: Van Gorkum & Comp, 1972. Print

Frede, Michael. “Metaphysics Λ.1.” Aristotle’s Metaphysics Lambda, Edited by Michael


Frede and David Charles. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000. 53-80. Print.

95
Freudenthal, Gad. Aristotle’s Theory of Material Substance. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995.
Print.

Furth, Montgomery. Substance, Form, and Psyche: An Aristotelian Metaphysics. New York :
Cambridge University Press, 1987. Print.

Gadamer, Hans-Georg. Aristoteles Metaphysik XII. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche


Buchgesellschaft, 2006.

Jaeger, Werner. Aristotle: Fundamentals of the History of his Development. 2nd ed.
Translated with the author’s corrections and additions by Richard Robinson. Oxford :
Clarendon Press, 1948. Print.

_____. Aristoteles; Grundlegung einer Geschichte seiner Entwicklung. Berlin: Weidmann,


1923. Print.

Judson, Linday. “Metaphysics Λ.4” Aristotle’s Metaphysics Lambda, edited by Michael Frede
and David Charles. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000. 245-274. Print.

Kosman, Aryeh. “Metaphysics Λ.9: Divine Thought.” Aristotle’s Metaphysics Lambda.


Edited by Michael Frede and David Charles. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000. 307-
326. Print.

______. “Aristotle’s Prime Mover.” Self-Motion from Aristotle to Newton, edited by Mary
Louise Gill and James G. Lennox. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994. 135-
154. Print.

______. “Substance, Being and Energeia: the Argument of Metaphysics Theta” Oxford
Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Volume II, Clarendon Press, Oxford: 1984. Print.

Lang, Helen S. “The Structure and Subject of Metaphysics Λ.” Phronesis 38.3, 1993: 257-
280. Philpapers. Web. 12 December 2011.

96
Loux, Michael J. Primary Ousia: An essay on Aristotle’s Metaphysics Z and H. Ithaca, New
York: Cornell University Press, 1991. Print

Lloyd, G.E.R. “Metaphysics Λ.8” Aristotle’s Metaphysics Lambda, edited by Michael Frede
and David Charles. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000. 245-274. Print.

Mansion, Suzzane. “The Ontological Composition of Sensible Substances in Aristotle


(Metaphysics VII 7-9).” Articles on Aristotle: 3. Metaphysics, edited by Jonathan
Barnes, Malcolm Schofield and Richard Sorabji. London: Duckworth, 1979. Print

Owens, Joseph. The Doctrine of Being in the Aristotelian 'Metaphysics': A Study in the Greek
Background of Mediaeval Thought. Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies,
1978. Print

Sorabji, Richard. “Aristotle on the instant of change.” Articles on Aristotle: 3. Metaphysics.


Edited by Jonathan Barnes, Malcolm Schofield and Richard Sorabji. London:
Duckworth, 1979. Print

Solmsen, F. “Aristotle and Prime Matter: A Reply to Hugh R. King,” Journal of History of
Ideas 19: 243-252. 1958. JSTOR. Web. July 28 2011.

King, H. R., “Aristotle Without Prima Materia,” Journal of the History of Ideas 17: 370-
389. 1956.

Rosen, Edward. “The Dissolution of the Solid Celestial Spheres,” Journal of the History of
Ideas 46: 13-31. 1985. JSTOR. Web. 28 July 2011.

Ross, W.D. Aristotle's Metaphysics. Vol. II. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1970. Print

Spellman, Lynne. Substance and Separation in Aristotle. USA: Cambridge University Press,
1995. Print

Sedley, David, “Metaphysics Λ.10” Aristotle’s Metaphysics Lambda, edited by Michael Frede
and David Charles. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000. 327-350. Print.

97

View publication stats