Sunteți pe pagina 1din 16

The Journal of Socio-Economics 38 (2009) 843–858

Contents lists available at ScienceDirect

The Journal of Socio-Economics


journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/soceco

A simple theory of ‘meso’. On the co-evolution of institutions and


platform size—With an application to varieties of capitalism and
‘medium-sized’ countries
Wolfram Elsner ∗ , Torsten Heinrich
University of Bremen, iino - Institute of Institutional and Innovation Economics, Faculty of Economics and Business Studies,
Hochschulring 4, D-28359 Bremen, Germany1

a r t i c l e i n f o a b s t r a c t

Article history: This paper deals with institutional emergence in the well-known ‘evolution of cooperation’ framework
Received 4 April 2008 and focuses on its size dimension. It is argued that some ‘meso’ (rather than ‘macro’) level (to be numeri-
Received in revised form 9 April 2009 cally determined) is the proper level of cultural emergence, diffusion, and retention. Also Schumpeterian
Accepted 3 May 2009
economists (K. Dopfer et al.) have discussed institutions as ‘meso’ phenomena, and Schelling, Axelrod,
Arthur, Lindgren, and many others have dealt with ‘critical masses’ of coordinated agents, including
JEL classification:
related segregations of populations. However, the process and logic of emergent group size has rarely been
B52
explicitly explored so far. In this paper, ‘meso’ will be explained, in an evolutionary and game–theoretic
D02
D85
frame and a population perspective, in terms of a cooperating group smaller than the whole population
involved. Mechanisms such as memory, monitoring, reputation chains, and active partner selection will
Keywords: loosen the total connectivity of the deterministic ‘single-shot’ benchmark and thus allow for emergent
Evolution of cooperation ‘meso’-sized arenas, while expectations to meet a cooperative partner next round remain sufficiently
Emergence of institutions high. Applications of ‘meso-nomia’ include the deep structure of ‘general trust’ and the surprisingly high
Group size
macro-economic and macro-social performance in ‘small’ and ‘well-networked’ countries which helps to
Network size
explain persistent ‘varieties of capitalism’. A strategy for empirical application of the theoretical approach
Expectations
Social capital and some first empirical indications of its relevance are presented.
Trust © 2009 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
‘Meso’-economics
Varieties of capitalism
Small countries

1. Introduction require the simultaneous constitution and size determination of the


institution’s carrier group. This paper investigates the simple logic of
This paper deals with the well-known issue of the emergence that group’s co-evolution and the determination of its size dimen-
of a social institution of cooperation. However, emergence here sion, the numerical value of which, however, can be determined
will constitute some ‘meso’-sized group of institutionally coordi- only in specific models and simulations.
nated agents. Using the standard game–theoretic argument of the Critical here will be the (subjectively perceived) importance of
‘evolution of cooperation’ in a Prisoners’ Dilemma (PD), the ‘folk the- the common future, i.e. expectations either to meet the same inter-
orem’, the dilemma can in principle be overcome by the emergence action partner again next round or to meet any agent of a particular
of coordination through cooperation which in turn is achieved by type (cooperator or defector) next round which will determine the
an (learned, informal) institution (see, e.g., Schelling, 1973, 1978; individual’s decision on his behavior and in this way determine the
Schotter, 1981; Axelrod, 1984/2006).2 However, this will basically size of the emerging carrier group of the institution.
In a n-person setting, the fully deterministic ‘single-shot’ logic of
the ‘folk theorem’ implies a (weak) total connectivity among agents
where everyone may interact with everyone else with the same
∗ Corresponding author. Tel.: +49 421 218 7535/6; fax: +49 421 218 4974.
E-mail address: welsner@uni-bremen.de (W. Elsner).
1
http://www.iino.de.
2
We refer to ‘coordination’ in a wide sense as an umbrella for ‘coordination’ in
a narrow sense (n.s.) and ‘cooperation’. Particularly, a ‘coordination problem’ (in a a n.s. plus the habitual sacrifice of the short run extra pay-off), gained only through
n.s.) is solved by successful ‘coordination’ (n.s.) gained through some social ‘rule’. In an institution (i.e., a social rule plus endogenous sanction). For this use of terms, see,
contrast, a ‘dilemma problem’ can only be solved by ‘cooperation’ (a coordination in e.g., Schotter (1981).

1053-5357/$ – see front matter © 2009 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
doi:10.1016/j.socec.2009.05.001
844 W. Elsner, T. Heinrich / The Journal of Socio-Economics 38 (2009) 843–858

probability p in every round. While ‘strong’ total connectivity is In addition to that approach, the present paper seeks to estab-
defined here as p = 1.0, i.e. everyone definitely interacts with every- lish that the emergence, i.e. generation, adoption and diffusion of
one else in every round, ‘weak’ total connectivity is given if p < 1.0. an institution, can be traced back to a specific but general prob-
We will show that in order to explain a ‘meso’ carrier group we will lem which agents have continuously to solve both individually and
have to ‘loosen’ connectivity and in this way get beyond (weak) total collectively through that very process of institutional emergence.
connectivity. Gibbons has recently advocated ‘to bring interests back into our
Particularly, in a population perspective, the individuals need to thinking about (. . .) routine production’ (Gibbons, 2006, p. 381;
experience the population shares of the types of strategies [be it italics added), referring to the ‘folk theorem’: ‘building an equilib-
the shares of types of agents or of types of actions (when agents rium means that interests creep in; one cannot analyze just the
may behave this or that way, depending on the constellations of evolution of beliefs’ (p. 385). In fact, the game–theoretic approach
critical factors which are to be discussed)]. Expectations then will is about a complex interest structure to be solved through mutual
have to be considered ‘contingent trust’, i.e. the expectation to meet adaptations of behaviors and expectations becoming consistent.
a cooperator (or a cooperating action) next round. In the present paper, thus, we will explore a simple logic of
‘Agency’ capabilities and mechanisms such as memory, moni- the co-evolution of (1) a complex incentive structure, (2) ‘experi-
toring, reputation building and using reputation chains, as well as enced’ expectations (‘to meet . . .’), indicative, in turn, and in varying
active partner selection based on respectively gained knowledge degrees, of (3) the group size, and of (4) the institution as such (as
then ‘loosen’ connectivity, i.e. dissolving (weak) total connectiv- both quest and outcome of the individuals’ efforts to improve their
ity. With random encounters given every round, agents will be well-being).
assumed to be able to form some ‘contingent trust’, based on some This might contribute to a general ‘meso’-economics wherein
empirically gained knowledge about some agents, and, within lim- ‘meso’ groups, ‘meso arenas’, or ‘platforms’ in manifold socio-
its, to reject the next random interaction partner. In this way, economic areas (regional, industrial, or professional clusters,
agents will be able (within limits) to generate and ‘assort’ their networks, agglomerations, segregation and neighborhood struc-
individual relevant groups of interaction partners, i.e. their peer tures, etc.) may become the theoretical locus of emergent structure.
groups. Coordinated (and cooperative) systems of such ‘relevant’ sizes
In this way, these mechanisms will allow for relevant group sizes may have a specific capability of learning, innovative collective
to increase from ‘very small’ (as with total connectivity) into ‘meso’ action, and thus eventually high macro performance, under different
sizes while keeping expectations ‘to meet’ sufficiently high. Expec- parameter configurations (for the large field application of different
tation then still can be supportive to institutional emergence even game structures in small-scale societies with different configura-
in a growing group, i.e. make cooperation still appear to be the tions, including group size, see Henrich et al. (2004).3
superior strategy for the individual even if group size increases. However, a heroic implicit presumption of most game–theoretic
However, if these agency mechanisms for some reason loose arguments is complete information. Agents are assumed to have a
power and efficacy or reach some limits, and cooperative payoffs direct observable connection between actions and outcomes and
will approach some maximum (for instance reputation chains may thus intense incentives or pressure to learn. This transparency is rarely
generate decreasing information gains) with growing numbers of the case in reality where the direct connection of action to feed-
cooperators, while defectors increasingly profit from the growing back and thus the pressure to learn typically is much weaker. Real
numbers of cooperators, the co-evolution of institutional emer- societies, even ‘primitive’ and small-scale ones, display a surpris-
gence and group size will yield some group smaller than the whole ing variety of degrees of learned and institutionalized cooperation
population involved, in this way disconnecting the ‘whole population’ and reciprocity (see again Henrich et al., 2004) since mankind
and the ‘maximum relevant group’, thus qualifying informal insti- is much more detached and freed from evolutionary pressure to
tutionalized coordination (i.e. cooperation) as a ‘meso’-economic adapt and learn than the game–theoretic argument of complete
phenomenon. transparency presupposes. Thus, empirically, even ‘meso’-sized and
However, some initial ‘minimum critical mass’ of cooperators ‘primitive’ groups sometimes may have low degrees of cooperation.
has to come into being stochastically through some motivation to They can afford certain levels of non-cooperation and conflict. Typ-
diversify behavior as we start from common defection. This may ically, the ‘backup capacity’ of humans to improve their position
first lead to the ‘takeover’ of the whole population by cooperators with low levels of cooperation is exploiting the commons of nature
but, if the relative success of common cooperation (as supported and this does not immediately and transparently feedback to the
by the agency mechanisms above) should become exhausted with agent.
the growing share of cooperators as mentioned (a sigmiod curve or We will apply below the theoretical considerations of this
a curve with constantly decreasing growth of cooperation payoffs), paper to ‘trust’ and macro-performance of some ‘small’ highly
the process will yield that ‘relevant cooperating group’ smaller than industrialized countries being ‘well-structured’ into ‘meso’-sized
the whole population (a ‘maximum critical mass’). arenas. We will discuss a potential empirical research strategy
when ‘meso’-sized structures are already historically given and
their co-evolution with institutional emergence just means their
2. Size and ‘meso’ size in the literature so far further reproduction, generating high levels of trust, cooperation,
social capital and, finally, high macro-performance. If ‘meso’ size
Some evolutionary economists have elaborated in recent years, is relevant it could be used even for political design to generate
in a Neo-Schumpeterian perspective, on the ontology of ‘meso’ in institutional emergence and high macro-performance.
terms of ‘meso rules’ and the process of their generation, adoption,
diffusion and retention (see, e.g., Dopfer et al., 2004; for the respec-
tive groundwork, see Dopfer, 2001, 2005, 2007; Dopfer and Potts, 3
Group size is there but one critical factor among others and interferes with
2008). They have argued that, and described how, origination, adop- other factors to form different interaction conditions and trigger different resulting
tion, diffusion and retention of a rule take place in a ‘meso’-sized degrees of institutionalized cooperation, although these real societies explored are
group of carriers with a ‘meso’-sized population of actualizations of all ‘small-scale’ (ranging in size between 75 and 1219). This, however, does not imply
that relative smallness of interaction arenas, or ‘meso’ group size, as such would not
an ideal generic rule. However, they have not elaborated specific tend to be a favorable condition of institutional emergence. In fact, size was found in
causal mechanisms by which ‘meso’ comes into existence to solve that large cross-cultural field experiment to be a good predictor (similar and related
specific problems. to anonymity and complexity) for payoff to cooperation.
W. Elsner, T. Heinrich / The Journal of Socio-Economics 38 (2009) 843–858 845

Also, institutionally coordinated systems may possibly also concluded that there is no complex modeling without a proper
become ‘petrified’, ‘sclerotic’ or ‘locked-in’, in the course of their life qualitative evolutionary ‘process story’ (see also Gruene-Yanoff and
cycles if collective action cannot be renewed to lock the system out Schweinzer, 2008). We will ‘embed’ a simple logic in such a frame
when necessary (for a formal model of merely technological ‘lock- below. We confine ourselves to some simple formalism and graph-
in’, see, e.g., Arthur, 1989; the classic for institutional lock-in, David, ical illustration along Schelling’s and Axelrod’s lines.
1985; and for lock-in and -out recently, Dolfsma and Leydesdorff, It has often been suggested that the ‘macro’-level, convention-
2009). ally understood here as the national level of formal organization
Many have paved the way for exploring critical size. For instance, and public agency, has become less relevant in a (global) cul-
there has been a renewed interest in Schelling’s (1969, 1973, 1978) tural emergence perspective. However, it is disputable whether it
early investigations in the emergence of coordination in attendance still is more appropriate to consider informal institutional emer-
problems and in emergent spatial segregation (see, e.g., Vinkovic gence still under a ‘micro-to-macro’ perspective and terminology
and Kirman, 2006; Aydinonat, 2007; see also already Elster, 1989). rather than to conceptualize ‘meso’ as a socio-economic level of its
Also, Axelrod’s 1980s approach to a quasi-evolutionary simulation own (for a ‘micro-to-macro’ terminology, see, e.g., Hodgson, 2000;
of emergent cooperation and evolutionarily stable critical mass (incl. Ayres and Martinás, 2005). We will argue here that there are con-
segregation) is still widely discussed (e.g., Axelrod, 1984, see the siderable theoretical and empirical reasons to envisage a specific
statistics in Dawkins’ foreword to the 2nd ed., 2006), and the iter- level of informal cultural emergence below, and perhaps across,
ated PD is still much applied and elaborated on (e.g., Knudsen, conventional ‘macro’ jurisdictions (which typically are the loci of
2002; Devezas and Corredine, 2002; Eckert et al., 2005; Goyal, enculturation through more formal and often ceremonial institu-
2005; Traulsen and Nowak, 2006). Arthur’s ‘El Farol’ attendance tions). And since emergent structure is not reducible to its initial
coordination problem (Arthur, 1994) also has triggered research micro-components (agents of different kinds) it is of course above
on coordination success and failure which implied a size issue. the ‘micro’ level. In all, what complex evolutionary-institutional
Game theorists have found some confirmation of the relevance of theorizing, modeling or simulation, and real-world clusters, net-
(‘meso’) group size also in lab experiments (see, e.g., Yamagishi, works and all kinds of group cultures are all about may require a
1992). Generally, group (or ‘network’) formation processes have been theoretical space of its own—‘meso’ (see, e.g., Chen, 2008, p. 121).
a continuing issue (e.g., Demange and Wooders, 2005; Page and Thus, we define micro as the level of individual agents and their
Wooders, 2007). The evolutionary dynamics in a PD, when control- interactions. As soon as some ‘structure’ (institution) has emerged
ling for a broad range of initial conditions and allowing for a variety that exists independently from any individual agent’s action, we
and an ongoing generation of ever more complex strategies, has understand this to belong to the meso level if also a ‘meso’-sized
been developed far beyond standard PD-supergame equilibria or relevant interaction arena or ‘carrier group’ has been co-evolving
well-defined attractor solutions such as a clear-cut Axelrodian TFT with that structure or can be identified. A meso-sized group, in turn,
dominance (e.g., Lindgren and Nordahl, 1994; Binmore, 1998; Foley, is defined as any ‘relevant’ (i.e. actually emerged as cooperating)
1998; Watts, 1999). group of a size equal to or smaller than the larger whole population
Institutionally oriented game-theorists, such as Schotter, Field, involved. Finally, if the ‘relevant’ group can be shown to be smaller
Hargreaves Heap or Ostrom, have built bridges between game than the whole population the latter may be considered to belong
theory and evolutionary-institutional theorizing, and the size to the macro level, mirroring perhaps the real-world ‘national’ level
dimension has often played some role (for an overview of the as mentioned.
issues, see, e.g., Dosi and Winter, 2000; Ostrom, 2007.) Also, many Note that we will consider a population later that is ‘structured’
evolutionary-institutionalist economists have elaborated on insti- only between (TFT-) ‘cooperators’ and ‘defectors’ (where the par-
tutional emergence and group or ‘network’ conceptions of the ticular division structure will change with ‘emergent structure’),
individual (e.g., Hodgson, 2000; Davis, 2007, 2008). And some par- with no opportunity to leave this arena and population and migrate
ticularly have contended that institutions are ‘meso’, would emerge among several populations, i.e., no population of populations,
at some ‘intermediate’ level, being effective in ‘mid-sized’ groups, which may be an important framework for other game–theoretic
etc. (e.g., van Staveren, 2001, 179f; Elsner, 2000). settings (e.g., Knudsen, 2002; Traulsen and Nowak, 2006).
Group size has also been an obvious issue of the collective good In the following, we will first present our argument in the frame
problem since Olson’s (1965) Logic of Collective Action where the col- of a simple static and deterministic ‘single-shot’ logic. Then we
lective good has a better chance of being produced the smaller the will consider group size in a co-evolutionary process of institutional
relevant group which is constituted to generate the good (see, e.g., emergence and group constitution. In the context of ‘embedding’
Dejean et al., 2008). Also, some have investigated ‘critical masses’ this logic in a ‘process story’, we will adopt a population perspec-
in collective action along Olsonian lines considering large contrib- tive based on some motivational considerations where the portions
utors to the collective good. The latter can either produce the good of cooperating and defecting agents in the population become a
alone or mobilize a selected minimum producer group (see, e.g., stochastic variable at the outset. The evolutionary stable ‘mini-
Marwell and Oliver, 1993). This, however, is not done in an evolu- mum critical mass’ and the (maximum) ‘relevant cooperating group’
tionary emergence perspective, thus what we pursue in this paper. are identified, the latter immediately being the whole population
If game–theoretical arguments would be applied this would prob- at first. Memory, monitoring, reputation chains and (some) active
ably be a case for cooperative game theory.4 partner selection then allow for a smaller minimum critical mass
However, in all, the question as to why and how institutions through faster increasing cooperative payoffs. They also allow for
emerge and become effective at some proper ‘meso’ level has rarely the ‘relevant’ group size to increase above a ‘very small’ group
been explicitly delved into and the basic logic of the size dimension, through loosening connectivity, i.e. ‘contingent trust’ can be kept
and particularly ‘meso’ emergence has rarely been focused on. This high then while the ‘relevant group’ may increase, through better
is what this paper seeks to do. assorted individual peer groups. However, when those mecha-
Dosi and Winter (2000) have attempted an overview on evo- nisms wear out with increasing portions of cooperators the relevant
lutionary theorizing, games, and emergent processes and have group size may become a ‘maximum critical mass’ smaller than the
whole population. Finally, we will consider some recent applica-
tion, namely persistent national differences in ‘general trust’ and
4
We owe the idea of considering cooperative game–theoretical arguments in corresponding macro-performance, an interesting dimension of
different respects throughout this paper an anonymous referee. the topical ‘varieties of capitalism’ issue. A strategy for empirical
846 W. Elsner, T. Heinrich / The Journal of Socio-Economics 38 (2009) 843–858

application of the theoretical approach and some first empirical nial’ dimension of the institution (e.g., Bush, 1987). A ‘ceremonially
indications of its relevance will be discussed. dominated’ institution would appear in reality as an ‘abstract norm’.
The existence of proper and improper ‘solutions’ may not even
be realized as such by the agents who perhaps do not know bet-
3. The ubiquity of the dilemma problem and ‘emergent ter. The ‘surface’ of institutionalized everyday ‘solutions’ (including
structure’ institutional lock-in and ‘non-action’) typically is more easily visi-
ble than the complex problem structure in the background and its
The prominent relevance of the collective-good/social dilemma/ alternative and perhaps more adequate potentialities.
PD problem requires a most careful explication. Its theoretical Given ubiquitous dilemma problems, individualist decision-
prominence in fact stems from its ubiquity as an (actual or latent) making may lead to inferior results, and ideal markets, or
practical everyday problem. There is in fact a collective-good prob- close-to-ideal de-regulated real markets, and the prices resulting
lem involved in every single economic decision, even in the most in them may fail to generate and diffuse the shared knowledge and
simple supermarket purchase, but also in any more demanding expectations required for some ‘reasonable’ behaviors and outcome.
technological coordination problem in the fragmented value-added A solution (superior to mutual individualist blockage or lock-in)
chain. If a full-fledged institution already exists with zero defection, then may require a ‘higher’ form of rationality than a dis-embedded
then typically any agent actively contributes to the reproduction of market can provide by itself.
the institution, and of the corresponding expectations of others, That ‘higher’ form of rationality allowing for shared knowl-
through cooperative behavior. However, if this is not the case and edge and informal coordination cannot be comprehended other
if an agent may expect another agent to behave in a cooperative than an institutionalization of cooperation through a learned and
way next interaction there is, under certain conditions a dominant habituated social institution, in the face of a dominant incentive
incentive for him not to contribute. These conditions include, besides ‘rationally’ to defect. This is because coordination has to assume
the payoff structure, the expectations ‘to meet’, memory, monitoring, the specific form of cooperation, i.e. coordination plus sacrifice.
reputation, related sanctioning and the danger of being rejected and Rational behavior in a short-run (‘one-shot’) perspective will be
excluded from many interactions. By not contributing he may take unable to overcome the dilemma. In a dilemma-prone, decentral-
the opportunity of a potential short-run one-shot extra gain, for ized system, the dilemma problem can be overcome, if not through
instance, by running away without paying, by somehow cheating, formal and authoritarian mechanisms, only by ‘habitualized’ and
avoiding own costs, exploiting some commons, exploiting positive ‘semi-conscious’ behavior. Consequently, any proper (‘instrumen-
externalities from others, etc. For instance, under certain circum- tal’) solution requires recurrent interaction, in historical time, to
stances in the fragmented value-added chain, the incentive to free open up room for joint learning, long-run and mutually adapting
ride, by saving R&D expenses and profit from incoming knowledge expectations, and path-dependent cumulative behavior to solve the
spillovers which are ‘inappropriable’ by their creators, may become dilemma (or not).
virulent. Similarly, even in a purely technological Arthurian random There is a fallacy of aggregation involved in dilemma-prone
net-technology choice problem, agents may be dominantly incited direct interdependence, reflecting the fact that decisions which
to free ride by waiting until others have made their decisions, in may appear, at first glance, ‘right’ and ‘optimal’ from an isolated
this way avoiding later regret (if they can afford to wait). individual(ist) point of view may unintentionally turn out to be
Generally, agents in a more or less individualistic culture may collectively, and often even individually, ‘wrong’ and inferior (‘unin-
be incited to defect in manifold ways, and will do so insofar as tended consequences’).5 Since the ‘aggregate’ here results from a
the situation is not fully governed by institutions (not considering more complex decision structure and process it is ‘non-additive’.
formal hierarchical control). So any socio-economic (trans-) action Evolutionary-institutional economics conceives the outcome of
is embedded in a larger dilemma problem and will, or will not, a complex system and process as ‘emergent structure’, specifically
contribute to the production or reproduction of the general frame as institutionalization (e.g., Hodgson, 2000, 113ff.). Emergence of
of expectations which in turn allow for, or undermine, institutional structure implies an ‘entity (that) has properties which cannot
emergence to overcome that basic dilemma. be deduced from prior knowledge of the elements’ (113f.). The
Along these lines, and according to a large literature of applied micro–macro levels’ interdependence contributes to the ‘micro-
game–theoretic argument, we have argued elsewhere that any foundation of macro’ and to a ‘reconstitutive downward causation’
production, information and innovation system, under conditions of individual behavior through institutions, i.e. a ‘macro-foundation
of fragmented value-added chains (in face of complex integrated of micro’ (see also Foster, 2005, on complex systems).
products), of (competing) net-technologies, and the collective-good This is, of course, not to suggest that a formal mechanism, mod-
character of basic information, can be modeled as a system of eling, and simulation of emergent process can generate ‘something’
mutual externalities, collectivities and cumulative actions, such from ‘nothing’. For instance, some ‘common culture’, ‘cultural’
that it can be reconstructed as a PD where any transaction is embed- capabilities, and social ‘agency’ competence (such as searching
ded in (Elsner, 2005). and learning, risk-taking, being not perfectly envious, monitoring,
However, the PD structure often exists only ‘in the background’, memorizing, and identifying others, expecting and anticipating,
while the observable social surface is dominated by some solutions, reputation building, and partner selection—see below) may have
i.e. some institutionalized arrangements. These may be ‘instrumen- to be assumed at the outset. Nevertheless, the complex process
tal’ (i.e. proper for ongoing problem-solving, which is the subject of is open-ended and path-dependent, i.e. its specific collective, or
this paper) or ‘locked-in’ on an inferior technology (being also an ‘social’, outcome at some point of time is not determined by the
inferior institution), or even completely mutually blocked through individuals and may sometimes even be surprising. In this way, the
general free-riding and non-action. emergent process may increase our understanding by directing our
In a life-cycle story of institutions, with emerging lock-in of coor- attention back to crucial properties of the initial structure, of the
dination and with improper collective action capability, improper
institutionalized coordination or complete mutual blockage of
action may easily be traced back to power and status positions 5
The current financial meltdown and different real-economic crises (business
established in the course of the repeated application of an institu- cycle, food, resources, climate) have provided ample evidence of processes of
tion beyond the point of its due change (to yield further economies unintended consequences because of improper incentives, false expectations and
of scale from the institution). This would be the Veblenian ‘ceremo- improper coordination, e.g., ‘herd behavior’.
W. Elsner, T. Heinrich / The Journal of Socio-Economics 38 (2009) 843–858 847

process and of the micro units that may have been presupposed relation to the ‘opportunity costs of common defection’ (b − c), and
only tacitly so far. the larger the importance of the future.
Agents will start in our as the same short-run maximizers which At first, note that ı strictly applies within a supergame only. The
may be considered a ‘worst-case’ condition. However, the solution supergame has an indefinite length, i.e. an indefinite number of inter-
of the problematic decision setting requires a change of behavior. actions, and its end is surprising for the agents so that the infinite
If those initial ‘worst-case’ maximizers can change their behaviors calculus above applies.
and can create cooperation through establishing a social institution However, this implies that within the supergame the two inter-
and a social carrier group something seems to be gained. action partners will not change. Thus the classical discount factor
This is prototypical of non-cooperative game theory compared applies where p1 is the probability that the next interaction takes
to other approaches such as cooperative game theory or exper- place with the same agents and r is the usual time preference (‘inter-
imental behavioral game theory that require or bring in more est rate’). Let the discount factor applying within a supergame be
assumptions such as preexisting norms (e.g., ‘inequality aversion’), ı1 :
perceptional framings, and other sorts of ‘conditional cooperation’ p1
(e.g., caring about others’ intentions).6 ı1 = . (2)
(1 + r)

4. Population size in a ‘single-shot’ perspective In order to introduce partner change, the probability to meet the
same again next round and, with this, population size we assume
4.1. A formal sketch a ‘structured’ supergame where, after an indefinite number of inter-
actions, a round will (randomly) end and a new round will for each
The simplest formal illustration of the static ‘single-shot’ solu- individual begin with random partner change (week total connec-
tion provides the logical condition for the superiority of cooperation tivity). That is we suppose a uniform periodization over time both
over defection. Assume within and between rounds. With uniform periodization, the first
interaction of the next round takes place in the very next time unit
a, a d, b so that a TFT player who has a memory length of one time unit (one
b, d c, c interaction) will remember if he meets the same interaction partner
with b > a > c > d, and a > (d + b)/2. As is well-known the payoffs P in again in the new round.
a supergame for the TFT player always encountering another TFT This is where group size comes in. The agent will meet the same
player, and for an ALL D player encountering a TFT player, with ı interaction partner again next round in a population of size n, with
being the common discount factor, are probability

PTFT/TFT = a + ıa + ı2 a + · · · 1
p2 = . (3)
a (n − 1)
=
1−ı Obviously, the probability to meet the same agent again next
and round is rather small and decreases with an increasing population
size.7
PALL/TFT = b + ıc + ı2 c + · · ·
c A discount factor for a series of rounds, including the probability
= + b − c, ‘to meet the same again next round’ after random partner change,
1−ı
then can be defined as ı2 8 :
respectively. Cooperation then pays if
 p + (1 − p )p  p1 (1 − p1 )
1 1 2
(b − a) ı2 = = + . (4)
PTFT/TFT > PALL D/TFT , → ı >! , (1) (1 + r) (1 + r) [(1 + r)(n − 1)]
(b − c)
Again, p1 is the probability to meet the same again within a
as popularized for instance by Axelrod (1984/2006).
round, i.e. that interactions within the round will go on (with the
According to inequality (1), cooperation (as an institution) may
same), (1 − p1 ) thus the probability that this will not be the case,
become logically possible in a single-shot decision, as an equi-
librium of a PD supergame different from the ‘one-shot’ Nash
equilibrium. It is the perspective of an individual agent to decide
7
before the very beginning of interactions which of the two strategies A note on memory and its implications may be in order here. As mentioned,
the cooperative (TFT) agent is supposed to have a memory length of one time unit
possible to choose.
(t = 1) which may considered to be equivalent to a required subjective ‘one-time-
This, however, does not tell much by itself about the individual unit probability to meet again’ perceived by agents. However, if cooperative agents
motivations to act and the process of emergence of a cooperative were assumed to remember longer time spans, e.g., a memory of t = T, the maximum
equilibrium. Therefore, we will consider some prerequisites and population size allowed for the institutionalization of cooperation c.p. will increase,
implications of this logical condition of institutional emergence since the probability of meeting a certain agent again in any of the future rounds
within their memory period T would considerably increase, given the population
often presumed only tacitly.
size. Again, by contrast, population size would increase with increasing memory
The critical factors are the given quantitative dilemma-prone periods while the extended ‘probability to meet again’, or ‘cumulated probability’,
incentive structure, i.e. the quantitative strength or weakness of the may remain constant. From n = 1/p2, t = 1 +1 (see Eq. (3)), for instance, would follow
collective-good problem, a, b and c, relative to the common discount the max. population size n1/[1 − (1 − p2, t = T )1/T ] + 1. Obviously, n increases with T.
For example, for b = 4, a = 3, c = 2, p2, t = 1 = 0.5, according to the single shot inequality
factor, also interpreted in a supergame as the ‘probability to meet the
(1) the related maximum population size for t = 1 would be 3. An increase from
same interaction partner again next interaction’, i.e. the importance t = 1 to t = 2 then increases n from 3 to about n = 4.4, for t = 3 to about n = 5.9, etc.
of the common future (ı). Cooperation will be the more superior the It is obvious that memory length is a most critical factor for structural emergence.
smaller the ‘opportunity costs of common cooperation’ (b − a) in However, in this paper, we will deal with memory not in the frame of the single-
shot logic but within the population perspective below when connectivity will be
loosened through certain mechanisms. Memory will be one of those.
8
We are aware that the two logics of intra- and inter-round or inter-supergame
6
An overview of research on pre-existing norms that real-world agents, i.e. the calculations should be explicitly modeled, not only under the restriction of ‘meet-
participants in laboratory experiments, carry into the experiments, in the frame ing the same again’ but also with its various potential outcomes. The pay-offs of
of applied experimental game theory and behavioral economics, is given, e.g., by a supergame of supergames would be the various potential capitalized pay-offs of
Camerer and Fehr in Henrich et al., 2004, Chapter 3, 55ff. individual supergames.
848 W. Elsner, T. Heinrich / The Journal of Socio-Economics 38 (2009) 843–858

i.e. a round will (randomly) end, and thus (1 − p1 )p2 the probability according to their subjective minimum requirements of ‘expecting
that, in case a round has ended, the agent will meet the same again to meet the same partner again’, in their efforts to create a solution
next round. superior to common defection.
Applying the discount factor for a structured supergame (which In the same vein, we may even consider the incentive struc-
mirrors the condition ‘to meet the same again next interaction and ture being adapted according to the other conditions given,
next round’)9 to both the cooperator’s and defector’s payoffs, we i.e. population size, expectations and the effort of problem-
yield the following formulation of the single-shot condition: solving. For instance, incentives to cooperate (payments, rewards,
a c awards, reputations, etc.) may be somehow increased or decreased
>! +b−c
(1 − ı2 ) (1 − ı2 )
or (5)
a c
>!
{1 − p1 /(1 + r) − (1 − p1 )[(1 + r)(n − 1)]} {1 − p1 /(1 + r) − (1 − p1 )/[(1 + r)(n − 1)]} + b − c
Focusing on population size we can determine the critical popu-
lation size for the agents to be indifferent between cooperation and by the agents in a myriad of interactions. Agents in this way may co-
defection, thus marking the border (maximum or minimum val- determine payoffs in the very process of their interactions, through
ues) of the variable settings (especially of the group size n) leading contributions of various kinds. In this way, even the incentive struc-
to cooperation: ture may be considered endogenous.
(1 − p1 )
ncrit = (6) 4.3. The cooperative area in numerical results and the limits of
{(1 + r)[1 − p1 /(1 + r) − (a − c)/(b − c)]} + 1.
the ‘single-shot’ logic
As will be shown below, ncrit is a maximum critical mass for the
relevant cases that may not be exceeded for cooperation to emerge. The condition for the emergence of cooperation in the fully
This condition holds the more (and population size may increase deterministic single-shot logic (agents play repeatedly but choose
the more) the larger the payoff advantage of the cooperator over their strategy only once in the beginning) is that a neutrally stable
the defector (a − c) relative to the initial advantage of the defector cooperative strategy (TFT) is available. ‘Neutrally stable’ is a strat-
over his later payoff (b − c). egy that performs best against itself. It is not possible to displace
an established ‘neutrally stable’ strategy. The advantage of TFT over
4.2. Co-evolutionary adaptation of size and expectations ALL D (both against TFT) is (a − c)/(1 − ı2 ), the disadvantage of TFT
is (b − c).
Population size now may be considered a condition of the supe- The condition for ‘neutral stability’ of TFT as given in Eq. (5)
(a−c)
riority of cooperation determining probabilities and expectations therefore can also be written as(5a)b − c =! (1−d2) .
‘to meet again’; but also the relevant cooperating population may The crucial variables here are the relation of the payoffs
be constituted, in turn, and its size explained and determined, under (a − c)/(b − c), with 0 ≤ (a − c)/(b − c) ≤ 1, and the population size n,
certain expectations, given the incentive structure and the striving with the relevant sizes 2 ≤ n. For each (a − c)/(b − c) there is a crit-
of the agents to solve the problem (and to improve their long-run ical minimum or maximum population size n that follows from Eq.
payoffs). (6). Whether ncrit is a maximum or minimum n depends on the
Considering p1 , n and the incentive structure as parameters, positivity or negativity of three expressions in Eq. (6).
three out of four complexes of conditions will have to be determined If we lift for a moment the restrictions on n, ı2 , and (a − c)/(b − c),
in a co-evolutionary process: (i) population size, (ii) consistent with we may get a continuous 2-dimensional space of n and (a − c)/(b − c)
given or emerging expectations, (iii) successful institutional emer- values (for given r and p1 ) that displays areas of defection and
gence and (iv) the quantitative incentive structure which may be areas of cooperation (see Fig. 1 for r = 0.05 and p1 = 0.1).10 A sub-
parametrically changed, however, without dissolving the dilemma space – marked in Fig. 1 – contains the permitted values for n and
structure as such. For instance, if the problem structure (a, b, c) is (a − c)/(b − c), while ı2 increases with decreasing n, even above 1,
given the maximum population size nmax , and minimum expectations which in turn marks a non-permitted area. Particularly, the val-
ı2min (or p1min , according to Eq. (6)) that still allow for successful ues between n = 1 and n = (1 − p1 )/(1 + r − p1 ) + 1 (which is the n-axis
institutional emergence will have to be determined in the very pro- intercept of ncrit ) involve ı2 > 1 and therefore are not part of the
cess of institutional emergence. Similarly, if the population size n permitted subspace.
and expectations are given, the dilemma structure (a, b, c) that still The graph of ncrit [(a − c)/(b − c)] has two asymptotes, a horizon-
is consistent with successful institutional emergence will have to tal one at n = 1 and a vertical one at (a − c)/(b − c) = 1 − p1 /(1 + r).
be determined in the process of institutional emergence. For exam- The maximum critical mass starts right above ncrit = (1 − p1 )/(1 + r −
ple, if b and c are given, amin is to be determined; if a and c are given, p1 ) + 1 for very small (a − c)/(b − c) (for (a − c)/(b − c) = 0, there is no
bmax to be determined, etc. cooperating population) and increases quickly towards infinity for
For instance, agents may determine the population size (e.g., rising (a − c)/(b − c) (given p1 = 0.1 as said). Also, to be sure, to the
through active partner selection as explained below) and some- right of the vertical asymptote, the area of cooperation continues
how experience this population size, while recurrently solving for permitted values until (a − c)/(b − c) → 1.
the dilemma, at a given incentive structure. They may adapt the The size of the area of cooperation obviously depends on the
maximum number of partners with whom they are capable of inter- position of the vertical asymptote. The more this asymptote shifts
acting (given the incentive structure) in order to solve the problem,

10
Note that p1 is to be interpreted as the probability that a round in the structured
9
The condition to meet the same again seems to be the perspective of the cooper- supergame explained above is extended by at least one more interaction, and px1 there-
ator. At least, the defector is indifferent in his behavior to whom he will meet (he is fore the probability that it is extended by at least x more interactions. The expected
assumed to always defect). However, he is not really indifferent since he would not value of the number of interactions per round therefore is x = logp1 0.5. For p1 = 0.1, the
wish to meet the same again but to meet a new cooperator every round whom he can expected value of future interactions is about 0.3. This is obviously a small number
exploit initially. Clearly the defector is interested in a small p2 or large population and a rather adverse condition for cooperation. Axelrod (1984/2006), for example, set
size n while the cooperator is interested in the contrary. some 200 future interactions implying a p1 of about 0.9965 as mentioned.
W. Elsner, T. Heinrich / The Journal of Socio-Economics 38 (2009) 843–858 849

5. A process story of institutional emergence and size

The logic of expecting ‘to meet the same again’ obviously is a


theoretical straightjacket that restricts the process of institutional
emergence to a narrow determinism based on an ex ante and
once-for-all decision (‘single-shot’) on strategy choice according
to the probability to meet again in order to sanction and sanc-
tify earlier behavior of others. The deterministic ex ante decision
applies simultaneously to all agents in a population; a relevant
cooperating group is always identical with the relevant popula-
tion, i.e. no group within a population, no population ‘structured’
by types of agents (strategies). Finally, it excludes agency. Thus,
both some stochastic process, i.e. a population perspective, and
agency need to be considered. The latter has to be overcome by
‘loosening’ the total connectivity among agents. In a first step, we
will lay down the theoretical frame in a short qualitative ‘process
story’.
Generally, it will be assumed that probabilities ‘to meet’ and thus
population structure and size can be experienced by the agents, as
has been assumed so far, so that agents forms subjective expec-
tations, i.e. probabilities for the future mirrored in the discount
Fig. 1. Area of cooperation and area with relevant values (i.e. n > 2) in a single-shot factor.
supergame model with p1 = 0.1 and r = 0.05. Note: The graph of the ncrit function is First, considering the solution above as a sequence or process, the
drawn black, the asymptotes are fat grey lines, and the borders of the area of relevant institutional solution cannot come about through narrowly ratio-
values (n > 2) are thin grey lines.
nal agents, i.e. short-run maximizers. It describes no process or
mechanism to achieve this result with short-run maximizers. These
would, in a process, only be capable of generating a series of one-
to the left, the larger the area of dominant TFT will get. The posi- shot Nash solutions. Thus, as mentioned, an institution can only
tion of the asymptote is (a − c)/(b − c) = 1 − p1 /(1 + r) and is governed emerge through habituation. The institution will have to be a ‘semi-
by p1 (which is the parameter for the expected remaining num- conscious’ phenomenon, and may be so as long as expectations of
ber of iterations in the current round as mentioned in Footnote conformity with it are met, supported, e.g., by a favorable numer-
9). In Fig. 1, the area of cooperation is relatively small, because ical result of the inequality (5a), and the incentive structure and
p1 is set to p1 = 0.1, a condition rather hostile to the emergence importance of expectations of a common future (to meet again)
of cooperation. Nevertheless, we can see that for an arbitrarily remain unchanged. Therefore, institutional emergence has to follow
set ‘meso’-sized population of, say, n = 5000, cooperation is feasi- a broader and long-run rationality. [In contrast, the institution may
ble. Eq. (6) yields the condition that (a − c)/(b − c) = 0.9045. Thus, a be abandoned through a more or less deliberate consideration when
rather weak dilemma in the incentive structure is required, given a new (‘rational’) single-shot calculation (after some condition has
the rounds of continuous interaction (the degree of continuity in changed) no longer justifies rule conformity, when ‘surprise’, ‘dis-
the social relations) are rather short, slightly above one interaction appointment’, ‘frustration’ or ‘getting exploited’ has occurred.] This
(again: p1 = 0.1). The value 0.9045 would be given, e.g., with a = 1810, broader rationality has also been elaborated under the perspective
b = 2001, c = 1 (d < 1). Obviously, as soon as we increase the length of a ‘horizonal’ effect, i.e., individual (cognitive, planning) horizons
of round (increase continuity in the social relations) agents can c.p. need to be extended, in a world of complementarity, cumulativity,
deal with stronger dilemmas or larger population sizes to generate etc., if effective agency is to be gained (cf., e.g., Jennings, 2005).
cooperation. Second, the institution, particularly an initial ‘minimum critical
Over all, the result is rather optimistic. Large areas of the per- mass’ of cooperators, may emerge on the basis of the individual
mitted and relevant value combinations are areas with ‘neutral motivations (1) to escape repeated frustration from common defec-
stability’ of TFT, i.e. population sizes that allow for the emergence tion (from aspiring b and receiving only c), and (2) to learn and
of cooperation, under given conditions. to increase knowledge, and particularly to explore what a differ-
However, these positive findings are subject to two limitations: ent behavior, namely common cooperation, may bring about (‘idle
curiosity’ or ‘instinct of workmanship’ as Veblen would have coined
(1) As said, neutral stability means that TFT cannot be driven out it), to find a way to improve one’s economic situation (to gain com-
of a population or, in our case, is statically the best ex-ante mon a’s rather than c’s). The payoffs for common cooperation may
response—to a population that is expected to consist of cooper- not even be known (incomplete information) and may then get
ators. This population is therefore not exploitable by defectors. explored by searching agents. The institution thus may emerge just
Nevertheless, this does not explain, how a cooperative popula- out of an agent’s vision that there is more to be gained than repeated
tion, or, in the single-shot case, the expectation of a cooperative frustration. Agents who then make contributions to cooperation
population may come into existence. need to be imaginative, ‘explorative’, and creative. Therefore, agency
(2) The critical population size still is derived from a simple for- needs to be carefully defined in an evolutionary process story.
mulation of the ‘probability to meet again’, a fully deterministic Third, the individual who then starts to search and experiment
perspective. with different behavior will have to contribute repeatedly to the
change of expectations in favor of cooperation. The process, thus, is
cumulative in the sense that all agents must repeatedly and interac-
Therefore we need to modify the model to include a stochastic tively (sequentially) contribute (or will have to cumulatively punish
population perspective, implying the possibility to engage in agency, each other).
and to investigate the possibilities of the initial development of a Fourth, these agents have also to be risk-taking and not be too
cooperative ‘culture’. envious. The first to send a signal for a potential better common
850 W. Elsner, T. Heinrich / The Journal of Socio-Economics 38 (2009) 843–858

future will have to take the risk of being exploited, at least once. He institution and exploitation, i.e. the incentive to defect, then may
also may never be able to compensate for this, as compared to the increase for individuals in a growing population of cooperators.
other, even if common cooperation starts in immediate response These defectors, though, would not want to ‘kill the goose that is
to his action. This agent thus needs to be mainly focused on his laying golden eggs’ (Axelrod, 1984/2006, p. 221). This may lead to an
own net gain which he has to compare only with his payoff under equilibrium ‘maximum critical mass’, being smaller than the whole
continued common defection. Compared to this, he clearly will be population involved, with a certain number of rule breakers that
better off over time. the institution and its carrier group can afford without breaking
Fifth, with agents starting to learn, search, experiment, and down.
diversify behavior (in our two-strategies world, this means start- An ‘embedding process story’, of course, does not sufficiently
ing cooperation), we may introduce a population perspective. Agents explain the logic of the process of emergence of ‘meso’ size. Some
then can no longer exactly tell the strategy of another agent whom further implications of the single-shot logic combined with its
they will meet next. Behavior thus may be considered random, evolutionary embedding shall be explored in two steps, first the
and agents will have to experience the ‘true’ population shares. population approach, second agency.
The ‘pure’ expectation ‘to meet’ will be replaced by the expected
‘probability to meet a cooperative agent next round’ that we call 6. A population perspective and the ‘minimum critical
‘contingent trust’.11 mass’—a graphical display
Sixth, the evolutionarily stable initial ‘minimum critical mass’ of
cooperators becomes crucial. With a ‘minimum critical mass’, insti- Behaviors may diversify, i.e. cooperation may occur now side
tutionalized cooperation may expand into a population initially by side with defection, motivated (in frustration experiencing,
consisting only of defectors. searching agents) as explained above. The number k of cooper-
Seventh, while agents will have to experience ‘contingent trust’, ative agents in a population n now becomes a critical variable,
they no longer remain focused on just (the ‘probability to meet’) a stochastic variable causing a stochastic process at the outset,
the same agent. They will have to know about many agents as i.e. until a ‘minimum critical mass’ is established, from where on
possible. Thus, more elaborated capabilities of agents have to be the new equilibrium will be reached deterministically as will be
considered. Instances of such agency will be memory, monitor- seen. A single-shot calculation still applies. (Note that k has been
ing, building and transmitting reputation, and some active partner zero or n in the fully deterministic logic as discussed so far.) In
selection based on the knowledge generated by these mecha- the following, the average payoffs per round for cooperation and
nisms. defection will be mapped over k. Some k then will indicate the
Eighth, group size of the relevant group then may be determined ‘minimum critical mass’ of initial cooperators required for insti-
by the individuals through some active partner selection. Agents tutional emergence, i.e. the ‘minimum size of any coalition that can
may in this way affect both the size and agent-type composition gain by abstaining from the preferred choice’ (Schelling, 1978, p.
of their individual ‘peer group’ of interaction partners. We may con- 218).
sider the ‘meso’ group size then to be co-determined by the agents Schelling’s illustration (1978, 217ff.; also applied, e.g., by Elster,
who actively adapt their ‘relevant group’ to a maximum size and a 1989, 27-44) of the case ALL C vs. ALL D illustrated the usual out-
composition which still allows them to contribute to institutional come of a PD one-shot Nash equilibrium: no individual incentive to
emergence, according to a given incentive structure and their con- cooperate and thus no mechanism for a viable cooperating group to
tingent trust. Specifically, they may even enlarge their relevant ‘peer emerge, at any k. This is equivalent to a very large population since,
group’ when they can increase their contingent trust sufficiently in both the cooperator’s and the defector’s perspectives, there is a
through some partner selection. zero ‘expectation to meet the same again’ in the very large fully
Real life has properties that may serve as criteria of partner anonymous population and, thus, a zero expectation to be able to
selection, i.e. proximity, or neighborhood, as either spatially, socially, sanction or to be sanctioned. Therefore, a zero commitment result-
or professionally defined. Agents then may confine themselves to ing. It follows ı1 , ı2 → 0, since p1 , p2 → 0 and, therefore, n → ∞. This
some group of interaction partners through mobility, choice of will serve as a benchmark in Fig. 2 below.
localization, ‘social exclusion’, or just actively picking out coopera- Obviously, for k = 0, the function of average payoffs for defec-
tors, etc., in an effort to keep the expectation of cooperation high tors will be fALL D (k) = c, and for k = n, the cooperator’s function will
while solving the dilemma problem. It is a rationality of ‘smallness’ be gALL C (k) = a. If all but one cooperate (k = n-1), the last defector
of the peer group of an individual (sometimes with the danger, in left in this large population will always (and thus on average) gain
turn, of too great a ‘cliquishness’, petrifaction or sclerosis of institu-
tions attained, and subsequent institutional lock-in on an inferior
path).
Technically speaking, we then will ‘loosen’ total connectivity of
agents in favor of some ‘weaker’ connectivity in the sense that the
scale of interaction possibilities among agents becomes smaller (cf.,
e.g., Batten, 2001, 89ff.; Watts, 1999, 204ff.).
Ninth, the system then adopts an endogenous dynamic with dif-
ferent equilibria (attractors). Not only relatively small ‘minimum
critical masses’ will be illustrated but also some specific dynamics
of cooperators’ and defectors’ payoffs. This includes some ten-
dency to destabilize the rule once it is established and has diffused
among agents beyond the equilibrium size of the carrier group.
The probability to gain more through unilateral deviation from the

11
Note, however, that as soon as the minimum critical mass has been established Fig. 2. Illustration of the payoff functions for TFT vs. ALL D, depending on the popula-
this way, our system below will still behave deterministically when moving to its tion size (ı2 ), yielding, in a ‘small group’, a ‘minimum critical mass’ for institutional
∗ ∗
new equilibrium. emergence, kSG , and the ‘relevant cooperating group’ at kmax = n.
W. Elsner, T. Heinrich / The Journal of Socio-Economics 38 (2009) 843–858 851

f(k) = b, while at k = 1, the remaining cooperator will always (and is the only interaction these particular two will have in that very
on average) gain g(k) = d. Note that f is not defined for k = n and g large population).
not defined for k = 0. In all, the payoff of a defector always exceeds • (1b) Accordingly, the first to cooperate in the very large popula-
that of an ALL C cooperator for any given k, hence no ‘minimum tion when all others defect (k = 1) will continuously receive d, i.e.
critical mass’ beyond which cooperation will pay for an individual 0a + [(n − 1)/(n − 1)]d, on average per round since he will always
agent. This has also been Schelling’s (1978) benchmark configura- be exploited in the first interaction with any defector where no
tion. further interactions with the same agent will follow in a round.15
In contrast, TFT is considered the prototype of a more realistic In contrast, if everyone cooperates (k = n), each will continuously
and less ‘pathological’ (less ‘masochistic’) type of cooperation than receive a in every period.
ALL C. It sanctions and thus makes future expectation relevant, as
reflected in the single-shot inequality. Using the general ı2 of Eq.
(4), the payoff functions will yield average payoffs according to12 It follows that f(ı2 → 0, k = [0, n − 1]) will always be above g(ı2 → 0,
k = [1, n]) in their common domain of k = [1, n − 1].
k k c
 
(n − k)
 c

fALLD = +b−c + (7a)
n n (1 − ı2 ) n (1 − ı2 )
• (2a) The situation changes as the population gets smaller. In a very
and small population, when ı2 → 1, defectors will receive c on average
k k a
 
(n − k)
 c
 per round when k = 0, as was the case in the very large popula-
gTFT = + +d−c . (7b) tion. However, if all but one agents cooperate (k = n − 1), this last
n n (1 − ı2 ) n (1 − ı2 )
defector will receive only slightly above c on average, since he will
This will explain the conditions of evolutionary stability of TFT in be able to exploit a TFT cooperator only once, then getting b, i.e.
an ALL D population. Note that this includes the earlier fully deter- [(n − 1)/(n − 1)][c/(1 − ı2 ) + b − c] + 0[c/(1 − ı2 )], and from then on
ministic approach (the single-shot of a ‘structured supergame’) will get c with him (over all rounds in the supergame. Note that, in
through ı2 in a partially stochastic approach. the smallest group possible (two), he will encounter the same TFT
According to Axelrod’s (1984/2006, Chapter 3) illustration, with agent again and again over all rounds, and the TFT will remem-
ı = 0.9, b = 5, a = 3, c = 1, d = 0, this yields fALL D = 14(k/n) + 10(n − k)/n ber him from one interaction to another and thus also between
and gTFT = 30(k/n) + 9(n − k)/n, i.e. for gTFT > ! fALL D , a minimum of rounds.)
k/n > !1/17 or about 5.9% TFT-cooperators would be sufficient to • (2b) If only one cooperates in the very small population (k = 1),
allow for the institution of cooperation to emerge. the TFT cooperator will receive zero from common cooperation,
Generally, this simple system has two stable equilibria and one i.e. 0a, but somewhat slightly below c, since he will be exploited
unstable equilibrium: k/n will assume either zero or one or the once and then will continue with virtually the same interaction
‘minimum critical mass’ kmin ∗ (given n) that supposedly has been partner with c on average per interaction for both. And again, if
attained through ‘stochastic’ behavioral diversification (search, all cooperate (k = n), they will receive a, as in the case of the large
experimentation, etc.)13 : population.

(i) 0 if f (kt ) > g(kt )
kt+1 As can be easily seen, the large population again yields the one-
= (ii) 1 if f (kt ) > g(kt )
n ∗ shot Nash situation, as in the ALL C case. In contrast, the very
(iii) kmin,t , if f (kt ) > g(kt ).
small group (SG) yields some minimum critical mass, kSG ∗ , beyond

We will shortly discuss the simple logic of the population which cooperation pays for all individual agents (see Fig. 1 below;
perspective with the expectation ‘to meet a certain agent next inter- note that all graphs go from k = 0 to k = n, for the sake of simplic-
action’. ity).
For cooperation to become ‘evolutionarily stable’ [case (ii)], the The emergence, or creation, of the minimum critical mass may
condition of Eq. (7b)>! Eq. (7a) yields the minimum critical mass be a ‘motivational’ problem as described, or an ‘organizational prob-
∗ ∗ lem’ (Schelling) (if we would refer to hierarchies or authorities), or
kmin or the critical portions (k/n)crit :
might require some policy design (on this see below).
 k ∗ (c − d) The ‘relevant cooperating group’ will be the whole population
= . (8)
n crit [(a − c)/(1 − ı2 ) − b − d + 2c] in this case as said, i.e. all defectors will switch to cooperation in a
logical second.
This, then, can easily be depicted in Schelling’s graphics as illus- There is a maximum group size (at some ı2min ) in which kSG ∗ comes
trated in Fig. 2 below (see also, e.g., Elster, 1989, pp. 37–39, who, ∗ ∗
into existence, i.e. f (ı2 , kSG = n) = g(ı2 , kSG = n). At this maximum
however, did not discuss a clear-cut analytical result in terms of ∗ = n, the ‘minimum critical mass’ and the ‘relevant cooperating
kSG
population or group sizes). The cases are obvious:14 group’ equal the whole population size. With decreasing group size
∗ will start moving, with an increasing ı , from the right end of
kSG 2
• (1a) In the very large population where ı2 → 0, when nobody coop- the k-axis to the left, stopping at some kSG ∗ , as illustrated. With b = 4,

erates (k = 0), the defectors continuously receive c on average a = 3, c = 2, d = 1, a calculation of ı2 that allows a kSG ∗ to come into

per interaction. However, when all others cooperate (k = n − 1), being at k = n (i.e., (k/n) = 1) of course yields ı2 = 0.5. (See also Fig. 3
the last remaining defector (the nth member of the population) below, where we enter the relevant area at (k/n) = 1 on the graph
will receive b, i.e. [(n − 1)/(n − 1)][c/(1 − ı2 ) + b − c], all the time from above [i.e., (k/n) = 1 at ı2 = 0.5].)
since he will always meet another cooperative interaction part- In the following, we will elaborate on the population perspective
ner whom he can exploit in each of their first encounters (which and build upon mentioned behavioral diversification, considering
agency, specifically information gathering and selection capabilities.
We start from ‘contingent trust’.
12
As said this still represents an ex-ante single-shot calculation.
13
We will consider agency capacity below.
14
Note that the agent who decides to cooperate or defect based on these equations
15
will not be part of the relevant k’s and n’s. Possibly, a case of pathological behavior similar to an ALL C player.
852 W. Elsner, T. Heinrich / The Journal of Socio-Economics 38 (2009) 843–858

their monitored actions. Assume the agent can monitor ten other
interactions.
Thus, a monitoring-memory funnel may exist where the most ‘dis-
tant’ monitored third-party interactions are memorized only for
one period, i.e. if they have been monitored in t−1 , the next less
distant only for two past memory periods, t−2 , etc., and the own
interactions from t−6 . For a simple numerical example of informa-
tion gathering on a ‘meso’-sized number of agents, see Fig. 4 for an
illustration.
Consider, for example, agents endowed with the ability to mon-
itor, for example, 10 other concurrent interactions at a time. Agent
A then will ‘know about’ 21 agents excluding himself from current
monitoring. From memory, he would know about 21 more from t−1 ,
17 from t−2 , 13 from t−3 , etc., in sum 87 other agents.
However, there is no perfect mobility in that monitored and
memorized part of the population. Assume that in addition to A all
Xs stand for immobile agents with fixed positions in the neighbor-
hood of A who appear repeatedly while only 50% of the monitored

and memorized part of the population are changing all the time;
Fig. 3. Graph of the function of (k/n)crit . (For Axelrod’s (1984, 2006) Incentive struc- assume for the sake of simplicity that these are the Ys. In this way,
ture a = 3, b = 5, c = 1, d = 0). Note: The graph of the function is drawn black, the
asymptotes are fat grey lines, and the borders of the area of permitted and relevant
A knows only about 58 different other agents.
values are thin grey lines. Also assume 50% observed cooperative different other agents (i.e.
ık = 0.5) (or actions, resp.). The agent’s ‘knowledge’ of (the behaviors
of) cooperative different other agents then is 29.
7. ‘Loosening’ connectivity: ‘contingent trust’, monitoring,
Compared to the ‘benchmark’ of ‘the 1’ he knows (and only needs
memorizing, reputation, and selection
to know) in the fully deterministic single-shot logic, thus the rele-
7.1. Contingent trust vant population size which was 3 at p2 = 0.5 in the logic so far, has
increased to 59, and the number of cooperators from a maximum
In the population perspective, i.e. in a ‘structured’ population of 3 up to 30 (including A), i.e., by 10.
with portions of (representatives of) different strategies, agents can
no longer focus on ‘the one’ interaction partner whom they know 7.3. Reputation chain
and need to meet again next interaction and next round in the
single-shot logic. Rather, they have to learn about many potential Third, reputation may further increase the ‘knowledge’ about
partners and the distribution of strategies among them, in order to other agents, i.e. it further increases the probability to meet a part-
increase their contingent trust ık in their inter-round transitions. ner next round whose (earlier) behavior the agent knows, in this
While we assume agents to face random occurrences of partners case through a third person.
with different behaviors, what counts now is their expectation to Assume, for example, that each agent has a monitoring-memory
meet a cooperative partner next round, i.e. funnel that includes 29 known cooperative different other agents
as above, and each agent can ask all of these cooperators about the
k behavior of third agents (being outside of his own funnel but inside
ık = (9)
n their funnels). Assume further, for the sake of simplicity,17 that only
(similarly, e.g., Elster, 1989, p. 34). half of them have own funnels that differ from A’s funnel. Thus A may
Compared to the ‘benchmark knowledge’ of only one interaction get new information only from 14 known cooperators about 28 new
partner, the population perspective, therefore, increases the num- third (different other) cooperative agents.
ber of agents that the individual has to ‘know’. At least, he must get In this way, the number of other agents ‘knowable’ by an agent
to know a representative sample of the population. will multiply and sum up over the number x of steps of the chain
Let us shortly consider which agency capacities specifically are according to k = x = 0 → ∞ 14x ·28, which, for instance, would yield
required in order to increase this expectation to a sufficient level. around 77,000 known agents in only three steps of the reputation
chain. This would definitely have to be considered ‘meso’-
7.2. Memory and monitoring sized if these agents would constitute a ‘relevant cooperating
group’.
First, knowledge of others will increase by adding some memory Of course, the reputation chain will not work with the same
capability (a memory of one period only has been implied in TFT so effectiveness across the different steps or links of the chain
far). (the ‘neighborhood’ geography), but rather may get ‘thinner’ and
Second, agents should be considered capable of monitoring con- ‘weaker’ with increasing distance from the interrogating agent.
current interactions between identifiable third parties (see also, Information feedback to the original agent will be increasingly
e.g., Elster, 1989, 40f.). In the fully deterministic single-shot he could incomplete and subject to leakage. Even if we assumed a consid-
only ‘monitor’ the same agent, so to speak. erable leakage of 50% per step, we would yield 14·7·3.5·28 ≈ 9600
Assume six memory periods for own interactions and fewer
memory periods for interactions among monitored third parties.
The agent memorizes only his own interactions over his maximum 17
A ‘half-distant’ neighbor’s funnel, of course, will not completely be identical with
number of memory periods, while the more ‘distant’ third parties A’s funnel but will overlap so that he might add, say 10 or 20 or more % informa-
are16 from the monitoring agent the shorter the agent memorizes tion (depending on his distance) to A’s knowledge from his own funnel. This would
require a more elaborated model of overlaps of funnels in a topology. We will neglect
this and simply assume that only 50% of cooperators in A’s funnel can add informa-
tion, these, however, may ask the complete set of their assumed 28 different other
16
We will consider a geographical or social topology, or neighborhood, below. third cooperative agents.
W. Elsner, T. Heinrich / The Journal of Socio-Economics 38 (2009) 843–858 853

Fig. 4. A monitoring-memory funnel—illustration.

agents which also may be considered to reach into ‘meso’ ject to ‘distance’, i.e. in a neighborhood topology the probability
sizes. of appearance of potential interaction partners to the individual
Also, the set of agents may ‘bend’ into a ‘spherical’ topology so decreases with decreasing proximity. But also knowledge about
that more remote agents may increasingly be already ‘known’ ones. agents decreases with decreasing proximity as discussed in the
In this way, it may easily be that k may reach some limit at some n. reputation chain.
In all, this should illustrate that these agency mechanisms, i.e. Assume further that in the process of search, experimentation
active acquisition of information about others, may easily lead us into and behavioral diversification motivated as described above, coop-
a ‘meso’-size scale of populations of ‘known’ agents and ‘known’ erators start to select agents (on such agency capacities, see, e.g.,
cooperators, and with this into the individual experience of the Davis, 2007, 2008; Dolfsma and Verburg, 2008; Leydesdorff, 2007).
‘true’ composition of the whole population. It is supposed that the cooperative agent has some capacity to reject
No further devices and mechanisms such as signaling and substi- interaction with a known defector, say, a capability to reject on
tute indicators such as sex, race, age, living area, formal education, average every second defector he encounters.
certifications, identity cards, corporate uniforms, appearance, cere- Cooperators also may prefer to interact recurrently with agents
monial behaviors or other signals would be needed. Note, however, they cooperated with in the past rather than with known defectors
that this is just a first intuitive understanding of a ‘relevant or new unknown agents. The size of the ‘relevant cooperating group’
meso-sized cooperating group’ while we develop a theoretical thus may be determined by myriads of acceptances and denials of
understanding below. interactions.
Note also that we have to assume ‘correct’ reputation here, i.e. Lab experiments have shown that agents indeed try to reduce
an information requested and received by A from B on a potential net complexity through active selection and active building of
interaction partner C is not subject to some ‘strategic’ tampering in neighborhoods (see, e.g., Harmsen-van Hout et al., 2008), and that
favor of B. network effects can informally be attained by groups constituted
Finally, if such verbal communication comes into considera- through the selective interactions of individuals (e.g., Tucker, 2008).
tion, this is something that non-cooperative game theory basically Spiekermann (2009), for instance, has recently shown that a selec-
would render senseless and ignore (the ‘cheap talk’ issue).18 ‘True’ tion mechanism (i.e. choosing or excluding/rejecting partners)
verbal communication itself can of course not be explained through allow may already allow for the emergence of cooperation in an n-
the same process and logic of institutional emergence that is inves- person public-good game. However, again, size way not an explicit
tigated here. Qualitative theorizing on institutions and multi-level issue in his analysis.
systems of reference among norms and institutions, of course, pro- In this way, the cooperator will be able to increase the ratio
vides more opportunities to go beyond such limitations (cf., e.g., of cooperators in his individual interactions. Individual i thus will
Hodgson, 2006) and cooperative game theory may have a major role be able to increase (ki /ni ) of the group of his past and present
to play here.19 interaction partners and in this way increase ıki ↑ = (ki ↑/ni ) while
However, why and how should a certain maximum percentage the surrounding population remains the same size n. He decou-
of cooperators above the critical minimum mass (which comes ples ıki from the general ık existent in the population, namely
into existence through another agency mechanism, as explained) ıki > ık . (Note that he is not assumed to be able to reject every
come into existence in the population? ‘Loosening’ the connection defector.)
between expectation, namely contingent trust, and population size Therefore, he will also increase his average outcome in a pop-
through active partner selection will help to understand group size ulation of given size and structure, and cooperators together
adaptation. can make cooperation increasingly more attractive. Particularly,
through selection cooperators can change their payoff curves and
7.4. Adapting group size through partner selection and a realize higher growth rates than in the linear case of the simple pop-
‘maximum critical mass’ smaller than the whole population—a ulation curve above which is dependent on ık rather than ıki (Eq.
graphical display (7b)). Since cooperators’ payoff cannot exceed a we have to assume
Monitoring, memorizing and using a reputation chain can be a degressively increasing payoff function. With a perfect selection
considered informational preconditions for selecting agents. Assume capacity, the curve would start at d at k = 1 and jump to a with
that interaction partners appear in some random sequence sub- k ≥ 2, i.e. cooperators would always interact only with cooperators.
Since selection, however, is not perfect the curve will increase more
slowly as will their ıki , in spite of the fact that they may become
18
more in the whole population through both initial experimenta-
This might be a point for a complementary use of cooperative game theory. We
owe the advice on cooperative game theory an anonymous referee and will denote tion and the increasing attractiveness of cooperation (through that
the logical points of its complementary use in two more places in our argument. very selection).
19
One referee has mentioned that there is no rule, institution or game in isolation, Specifically, we may assume that the effectiveness of the part-
but systems of games, rules and institutions, partially hierarchic, and by all means ner selection declines because the knowledge about agents does not
mutually interdependent, often mutually stabilizing. In our view another case for
grow by the same rate as new (potential) interaction partners occur.
a co-evolutionary analysis. This of course is not confined to informal institutions
but must include the state and formal institutions where, again, cooperative game Memory and monitoring provide knowledge about a limited num-
theory may be very promising. ber of agents and the reputation chain mechanism fades away with
854 W. Elsner, T. Heinrich / The Journal of Socio-Economics 38 (2009) 843–858

distance as said. So the more new partners occur and the greater The sigmoid function reflects the idea of initially exponentially
the distance they come from the less the agent will already know growing payoffs for cooperative behavior (cumulative learning,
about them. ‘synergies’, net-externalities, and the like) which later ends in
Overlapping individual partner selections may then constitute maturity, when the ‘resource of cooperation’ somehow becomes
the ‘relevant cooperating group’ [see also, e.g., Oestreicher-Singer ‘exhausted’ (see also Elster, 1989, 28f., pp. 32–34, for a logistics
and Sundararajan, 2008, for minimum relations and networks that curve, while discussing the ‘technology of collective action’).
still allow for institutional diffusion (‘small worlds’) and segregation While the composition and ‘contingent trust’ for the whole
of a population, see, e.g., Foley, 1998, 18ff., 38ff., 61ff.; Watts, 1999, population may remain relatively low cooperators increase the
204ff.; Batten, 2001, 89ff.]. composition of their own interaction partners (ki /ni ) and thus may
In all, the function thus may increase according to some factor increase their average payoffs above the level of the average payoff of
˛, 0 < ˛ > 1, connected to ki /ni , i.e. (ki /ni )˛ . defectors through selection. This in turn will increase the portion of
Defectors, on the other hand, will be sorted out to some degree by cooperators in the population and contingent trust. With degres-
the early cooperators and thus will not fully profit from an increas- sively increasing cooperators’ payoffs and progressively increasing
ing number of cooperators as in Eq. (7a). Their population payoff defectors’ payoffs this will occur at a relatively small ‘minimum criti-
curve thus will remain below the curve given by Eq. (7a) and coop- cal mass’ compared to the linear case of payoff functions above (Eqs.
erators’ payoff curves may rise above the defectors’ payoff curves (7a) and (7b)).
already for a small number of cooperators. Also, sorting out (to some degree) one’s interaction partners
However, while cooperators cannot get above a, defectors will is equivalent with the assumption that cooperators ‘self-commit’
still increasingly profit from a growing number of cooperators. Their to interact with ‘their kind’. Or: self-commitment to interact a cer-
payoff function may be considered progressively increasing, subject tain number of rounds among cooperators is equivalent to some
to (k/n)1/˛ . This may constitute a maximum critical mass, or rele- capability to select partners.
vant cooperating group below the size of the whole population (see Here, Axelrod’s use of ı applies. He focused on the number of
below). interaction rounds among agents with a somehow committed ongo-
In order to theorize and illustrate the simple logic of such seg- ing relationship. If two agents had a given (expected) round length
regation, different non-linear cooperation payoff curves have often of one interaction, the probability that the interrelation will end is
been considered in the literature. 1.0; accordingly the (expected) probability to ‘meet the same again’
For instance, Schelling (1978, 104f., 239ff.) has referred to net- is ı = 0 (i.e. p1 and ı1 according to our definitions would be zero,
externalities to explain progressively increasing cooperative payoff one-interaction rounds; if this applied also to the inter-round prob-
functions. This implies some additional positive mutual externalities abilities p2 , also ı2 became zero; this is equivalent with the very
among cooperators, perhaps even above what cooperators gener- large group). With two interactions in total, the probability that the
ate on average in the standard PD (i.e. a). Schumpeterian innovation interrelation (the round) will end is 0.5, and also ı = 0.5. Axelrod had
economists have argued in favor of the cumulative character of set up his tournaments in this way, with an average round length of
new knowledge, both inter-personally and inter-temporarily, so that 200 interactions, i.e. a probabilistically determined chance of about
cooperative payoffs may increase through an extra synergetic effect .003 of ending an interrelation after each interaction, corresponding
(through mutual learning, imitation, etc.) (see, e.g., Pyka, 1999, to ı ∼ 0.997 (1984/2006, 63ff., 212f.; see also footnote 10). While this
98ff.). is no advantage for defectors a high ı generates a relative advan-
Specifically, S-shaped curves have been considered in such con- tage for TFTs since a > c. In this way TFTs can be considered to be
texts. For instance, in his technology choice model with increasing self-committed for some 200 interactions per round see footnote
returns (i.e. net-effects), Arthur (1989, 123ff.) has made use of 10.
logistics curves. While a technology adoption function maps the In addition, Axelrod had assumed that an invading group of TFTs
probability of choice of a certain technology by the next choosing is relatively small so that it only marginally affects the ALL Ds’ pay-
agent against the number of those who have chosen this technology offs. Defectors’ payoffs are considered unchanged (!) since the great
so far, i.e. equivalent to a payoff function depending on the num- bulk of the ALL Ds’ interactions would still take place among them-
ber k who have ‘chosen cooperation’, some ‘improvement function’ selves. If, for instance, ı = 0.9 for both cooperators and defectors and
would mirror additional increasing returns to adoption. Particu- b = 5, a = 3, c = 1, d = 0 the defectors gain on average only 10 with each
larly, he considered cumulative learning (by using) effects and other (a simplified version of Eq. (7a). The TFTs, in contrast, have to
‘coordination externalities’ (p. 126). He also considered a ‘bounded take into account considerable portions of interactions with ALL
improvement function’ when effects become ‘exhausted’. The popu- Ds, according to Eq. (7b). The example yields k/n > ! 1/21, i.e. only
lation would split up then, in an equilibrium, with the coexistence around 4.8% of invaders can succeed and survive in a ‘hostile’ social
of more than one technology, one portion using the ‘dominant tech- environment.
nology’ another one some ‘minority technology’. In this way, Axelrod was able, through ‘committed’ large num-
Also, Cooper and John (e.g., 1988) elaborated on economies bers of interactions, both to keep expectations (ı) high and increase
with ‘strategic complementarities’, or synergies. Going beyond ‘pos- cooperators’ group size (k or k/n, resp.), while the minimum critical
itive externalities’ of agent A which just increase the payoff of mass would be very small (below 5% in the example). This implies
agent B, ‘synergies’ imply that an ‘increase’ in agent A’s strategy abandoning total connectivity by introducing selectivity through self-
increases the marginal return of agent B’s own action. A’s strat- commitment.
egy thus is an increasing function of agent B’s strategy, and vice We illustrate the effect of partner selection in Fig. 5. Coop-
versa. A ‘synergetic’ reaction function displays some ‘multiplier erative payoffs now may quickly exceed the average defector’s
effect’ and is be S-shaped (pp. 445ff.). It can be matched against payoff.
a benchmark of a linear curve representing a series of Nash equi- The payoff functions ‘with selection’, gsel. for cooperators and
libria. This involves multiple equilibria at the intersections of both fsel. for defectors, can be represented as explained by:
curves. The higher intersection basically is equivalent to a coop-
erative equilibrium. The economic examples that Cooper and John k  k 1/˛  c
  (n − k)
 c

discuss include net-externalities through coordination in supplier fsel.ALLD = +
n n (1 − ı2 ) + b − c n (1 − ı2 )
networks and demand coordination among multiple industries in the
business cycle. (10a)
W. Elsner, T. Heinrich / The Journal of Socio-Economics 38 (2009) 843–858 855

Also, we must not necessarily think of individuals being clear-


cut cooperators or defectors at any given point in time, but may
think of certain portions of cooperative and defective actions in the
sets of actions of every single individual.
Finally, note again that we must not and do not assume that the
average payoff from cooperation ever exceeds the original payoff
value a from common cooperation at any group size.

8. A real-world example: trust polls, country size, and


macro-performance

Before we come to conclude, a short example should suffice to


indicate the empirical, and topical, relevance of ‘meso’ size.
Trust polls, nowadays carried out regularly in most countries
on behalf of the World Bank and others major organizations (see,
e.g., Knack and Keefer, 1997; Keele and Stimson, 2002), namely the
Fig. 5. Illustration of the effect of partner selection (and ‘exhaustion’ thereof) on the World Value Survey, include general trust questions, such as: ‘Do you
payoffs from cooperation (gsel. ) and defection (fsel. ), indicating the ‘meso’-size area think you can trust the next person you will encounter?’ Obviously,

of the ‘relevant cooperating group’, kmax . this is fully equivalent to the expectation to meet a cooperative
agent in the next round, i.e. contingent trust.
Such polls have brought about surprising differences and even
and considerable divergence over time in trust levels among presumably
k  k ˛  a
  (n − k)
 c
 similar and converging countries (e.g., leading OECD countries).
gsel.TFT = + , However, this is particularly the case between large and small coun-
n n (1 − ı2 ) n (1 − ı2 ) + d − c tries. Similarly surprising was the fact that such trust levels have
0 ≤ ˛ ≤ 1. (10b) turned out to be highly correlated with economic and social perfor-
mance in broad areas (see also, e.g., O’Hara, 2008).
It has indeed been argued in the more recent ‘varieties of capi-
Note that the cooperators’ curve is set on top of the ‘worst-case’
talism’ literature that it may particularly be smaller countries which
cooperative function, the ALL C vs. ALL D case, equivalent to the
display such high trust and performance (see, e.g., Kesting and
very large group, where ı2 may be very small. This may illustrate
Nielsen, 2008; see also already Fukuyama, 1995, Chapters 3, 28,
that the constitution of a meso-sized relevant cooperating group
pp. 23ff., 335ff.). Conventional economics has mostly stressed the
may occur even in a large population, depending on the exponents
disadvantages and volatility of small countries (see, e.g., Barro and
˛ and 1/˛. This would of course be the case all the more on top of a
Sala-i-Martin, 2003; Alesina and Spolaore, 2003). The empirical
‘small group’, i.e. with flatter curves (as given in Fig. 2).
record of the relation between smallness and economic perfor-
As said, a reduction of the ‘minimum critical mass’ compared
mance is not obvious and clear-cut. Many have argued in favor of
to the linear case (Fig. 5) may occur, so that random diversification
advantages of smaller countries (see, e.g., Kuznets, 1960; Easterly
of behavior combined with early selection might bring about the
and Kraay, 2000), particularly their superior adaptability, learning
‘minimum critical mass’.
and cooperation conditions as dependent on proximity and inter-
A general solution to determine the lower and upper intersections
action density (see, e.g., Cantner and Meder, 2008).
of fsel. and gsel. , from the condition
Considering critical factors in the ‘deep structure’ of coun-
Eq. (10a) = ! Eq. (10b), is given by
tries, such as futurity (expectations) and size as investigated in this
 k 1/˛  c
 k  k ˛  a
 paper, specifically small countries that are internally structured
+ (d − c) − in overlapping functional, spatial, professional, organizational, or
n (1 − ı2 ) + b − c n n (1 − ı2 )
jurisdictional communities, groups, networks, associations, etc.,
= d − c. (11) have turned out to display such favorable trust (and high social
capital, indicated, for instance through membership and participa-
This yields a complex function of k which has solutions with at tion), and performance properties. It appears that the principle of
least two values of k. ‘smallness’ has been internally generalized by them (through cumu-
As a numerical example assume n = 1000, ˛ = 0.5, ı2 = 0.1, and lative historical process rather than deliberate political design, of

again b = 5, a = 3, c = 1 and d = 0. This will yield kmin ∗
≈ 82 and kmax ≈ course), so that they can make use of ‘meso’-sized ‘arenas’, ‘plat-
696. This illustrates that the equilibrium ‘relevant cooperating group’ forms’, and groups. In this way they may generate trust and facilitate
size is below the size of the whole population and a ‘meso’-sized the emergence of institutionalized cooperation, related innovative
institutional carrier group. action capabilities, and macro performance.
This also reflects the fact that the established informal institu- This typically applies to Scandinavian countries, given their
tion may bear, and even provoke, some degree of defection, by making overall sizes, residential structures, enterprise size structures, dom-
it, with increasing k, ever more profitable to deviate. Any institu- inant interactive workplace organization, general organizational
tion, in fact, exists, and may survive, in the face of a certain number participation, informal networks structures and policy frame-setting
of defectors. However, these defectors do no longer endanger the (particularly safeguarding some level of social integration, stability
institution as such.20 and security) (see for instance the rich material on the Danish case
in Jorgensen, 2002; Lundvall, 2002; Edquist and Hommen, 2008;
Christensen et al., 2008; Holm et al., 2008). In this way, even a 5.4
20
A referee has suggested here that wherever full rule adherence can be observed,
non-cooperative game theory would explain only the spontaneously voluntary part.
The ‘other segment involves cooperative game theory’, he argued. We basically game–theoretic argument, we will suggest a slightly different place for cooperative
agree. Regarding a role for policy with respect to the results of our non-cooperative game theory, though.
856 W. Elsner, T. Heinrich / The Journal of Socio-Economics 38 (2009) 843–858

Table 1 dimensions of contingent trust (expectations) and ‘meso’-sized


Indications of ‘meso’ structures, institutionalized cooperation, general trust and
group formation, might play a more important role in this field in
macro performance.
the future.
1.1 General trust survey data Other than the usual political, welfare-state, social integration
Selected countries 1990 1999/2000 2004–2008 and social-security argument explaining the ‘Scandinavia plus’ vari-
Denmark 57.7 66.5 71.3*
ety of capitalism, we would suggest to empirically investigate the
Finland 62.7 57.4 58.8 size dimension working in the ‘deep structure’ of the interaction sys-
Norway 65.1 67.2* 69.2* tems of countries as one critical factor among others.
Sweden 66.1 66.3 68.0 The methodological problem such an empirical study immedi-
Netherlands 53.5 60.1 44.5
ately faces is that many ‘meso’ structures are already historically
To compare: Germany 32.9 37.5 34.1
given in those countries, e.g., settlement systems (little urbaniza-
1.2 General trust correlations (13 smaller and larger OECD countries, if not tion, rural structures), membership and participation rates (i.e. social
indicated else) capital) network cooperations of firms and the like. Can we iso-
Indicators Correlations with general trust, survey wave late these factors and their impacts on institutionalization and
2004–2008 ‘meso platform’ emergence? On the other hand, can empirically
Population size −0.34 identify the crucial factors and mechanisms of our model, such
Membership 0.88 (9 countries) as incentives, expectations, reputation chains and partner selec-
Share of cooperating innovators 0.80 tion to trigger further ‘meso’ generation? We can expect only to
GDPpc 0.51
explain the continuing reproduction, sometimes the growth and the
GDP growth 0.34
sometimes surprising resilience under adverse conditions rather
1.3 Other correlations between empirical indicators of ‘meso’ and cooperation than the original emergence of meso structures, supporting expec-
tations (namely general trust), institutionalization of cooperation
Population size/share of cooperating innovators: −0.89 (6 countries)
Membership/share of cooperating innovators: 0.84 (5 countries) and, finally, macro performance. Specifically, can we explain further
trust growth in spite of fast change, partial de-regulation, global-
Source: Own calculations based on World Value Survey data;
http://www.worldvaluessurvey.org.
ization?
*
Estimated. The overall causal chain might overlap between the model and
empirical data in the following way:

mio population country may be sufficiently interconnected through


‘meso’-arenas to mobilize reputation chains and to generate high (1) given formal and informal inner ‘meso’ structures: empiri-
levels of trust, institutionalized cooperation, and socio economic cal (e.g., population size; settlement structures; membership;
performance. share of cooperative innovators)
Note that the Scandinavian countries (incl. NL, A, and some oth- (2) the ‘mechanisms’: model
ers) are not only leading in social areas like little poverty, even (3) reproduction of informal inner ‘meso’ structures: model, empir-
distribution, high employment, education, social security or subjec- ical (e.g.,  membership)
tive well-being but are also in the leading groups with innovation (4) high and increasing trust/institutionalization of coopera-
rates, GDP pc, speed of structural change, labor market mobility, tion/social capital regeneration: model, empirical (e.g., 
globalization rates, future expectations, etc. Also, they are largely general trust;  share of cooperative innovators)
not too much affected by the current financial meltdown. Find some (5) high macro-performance: model, empirical (e.g., GDPpc;
indicators of the relative positions of Scandinavian countries and GDP).
small countries in general in Table 1.
The World Bank, the OECD, EU, and others may have to pro- Fig. 6 gives an illustration of the sequence of an empirical
ceed to a more complex explanation of trust, and the theoretical research based on our model and focusing on trust and performance
framework of institutional emergence, with its co-evolutionary in ‘small (and well-structured)’ vs large countries.

Fig. 6. An empirical research setting: socio-economic conditions and results of ‘meso’-structures—empirical indicators (in circles) and theoretical mechanisms and predictions
(in rectangles) combined. A tentative scheme.
W. Elsner, T. Heinrich / The Journal of Socio-Economics 38 (2009) 843–858 857

9. Conclusion expectations attained by institutionalized coordination (see, e.g.,


Boudreau et al., 2008).
Against the background of an ‘evolutionarily embedded’ sim- The co-evolutionary process of ‘meso’-economics investigated
ple theory of ‘meso’ as investigated in this paper, the co-evolution here is far from being fully understood and sufficiently elaborated.
of ‘meso’ size, futurity (expectations), and institutional emergence, Although network formation and size has already been a dimension
given the incentive structure, will have to be further theorized, for- of many socio-economic approaches and complex models, fur-
malized, specified and finally quantified in simulations. The critical ther strengthening relevant, applied, empirical, and policy-oriented
factors explored here are: economic research, such as the topical research on ‘general trust’
and macro performance, may not least require further elaboration
(1) the incentive structure; and simulation of the logic and process of ‘meso’.
(2) a distribution of a population in a topology, i.e. proximity and
‘neighborhood structure’, with the corresponding rules of inter-
Acknowledgements
action, (e.g., mobility rules);
(3) an initial (stochastic, although ‘motivated’) distribution of strate-
The authors are grateful to K. Dopfer and the discussants of the
gies, and a ‘minimum critical mass’ of cooperators;
2006 Schloss Wartensee Workshop on ‘Evolutionary Economics’,
(4) ‘agency’ mechanisms such as monitoring, memorizing, reputa-
St. Gallen, CH, to the participants of a 2008 AFEE session in New
tion building and chain using, as well as partner selection based
Orleans and G. Hodgson, the discussant in that session, further to
on related information;
D. Foley (and the students of his complex-modeling workshop at the
(5) potential additional mutual externalities of cooperation, cumu-
New School, NYC), J.B. Hall (and the discussants at a PSU department
lative learning, or ‘synergies’, typically justifying a degressively
seminar, Portland, OR), J. Sturgeon (and the discussants at a UMKC
growing payoff curve; and, finally;
seminar, Kansas City, MO), and U. Witt (and discussants at a Seminar
(6) the ‘relevant cooperating group’, typically smaller than the whole
at MPI Jena) for comments on an earlier version. K. Dopfer has also
population involved and thus ‘meso’-sized. This may be repre-
commented on the paper at the EAEPE conference in Rome, Novem-
sented also by segregation patterns.
ber 2008. Also many thanks to M. Greiff. An earlier version has
also been presented at the ASSA meetings in San Francisco, January
The process, logic and critical factors discussed here may
2009. The authors are particularly grateful to Henning Schwardt
allow for a class of complex models and simulations focusing on
for numerous discussions of all details of the paper. Finally, we are
‘meso’. This may easily merge with lines of complex economic
grateful to an anonymous referee. However, the authors insist on
research based on increasing returns, positive feedback or cumula-
the property rights for all remaining deficiencies.
tive causation. Technically speaking, such models will escape total
connectivity among agents in patterned networks with a more
loose connectivity. While the bounds of the simple logic are nar- References
row, the space of formal modeling and quantitative simulation is
virtually infinite. Complex modeling and simulation, though, has Alesina, A., Spolaore, E., 2003. The Size of Nations. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Arthur, W.B., 1994. Inductive reasoning and bounded rationality (the El Farol prob-
been beyond the scope of this paper. lem). American Economic Review, 84–406.
A more general ‘meso’-economics might be envisaged, i.e. the Arthur, W.B., 1989. Competing technologies, increasing returns, and lock-in by his-
economics of the emergent ‘mid-size’ level for the coordination torical events. Economic Journal 99, 116–131.
Axelrod, R., 1984/2006. The Evolution of Cooperation. Basic Books, New York (rev.
and capability increasing of a population in an evolutionary pro- ed. 2006).
cess. Its applications, such as cultural emergence, production and Aydinonat, N.E., 2007. Models, conjectures and exploration: an analysis of Schelling’s
innovation standards, paradigms, and cultures, information gover- checkerboard model of residential segregation. Journal of Economic Methodol-
ogy 14 (4), 429–454.
nance and open source in a fragmented and interconnected ‘new’
Ayres, R.U., Martinás, K., 2005. In: Elgar, E. (Ed.), On the Reappraisal of Microeco-
economy, spatial industrial organization and agglomeration, general nomics. Cheltenham, UK, Northampton, MA, USA.
trust and macro performance, etc., have high practical relevance. Barro, R.J., Sala-i-Martin, X., 2003. Economic Growth. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Batten, D.F., 2001. Complex landscapes of spatial interaction. The Annals of Regional
Of course, our approach confirms that we cannot expect
Science 35 (1), 81–111.
a non-trivial, automatic emergence of a stable, self-sustaining, Binmore, K., 1998. Review of Axelrod, R., The Complexity of Cooperation. JASSS 1.1.
Pareto-efficient institutionalized equilibrium, i.e. no ‘deliberation- Boudreau, K.J., Lacetera, N., Lakhani, K.R., 2008. Parallel Search, Incentives and Prob-
free’, ‘hierarchy-free’, or ‘state-free’ stable private self-organization lem Type: Revisiting the Competition and Innovation Link. Harvard Business
School Technology and Operations Mgt. Unit Research Paper No. 1264038.
or ‘spontaneous order’. For instance, the initiation and generation of Bush, P.D., 1987. The theory of institutional change. Journal of Economic Issues XXI,
a ‘minimum critical mass’ may require considering the role of pub- 1075–1116.
lic policy (see, e.g., Schelling, 1978; Cooper and John, 1988; Elster, Cantner, U., Meder, A., 2008. Regional Effects of Cooperative Behavior and the Related
Variety of Regional Knowledge Bases. University of Jena, Germany, Mimeo.
1989, 31ff.; Elsner, 2001,2008; on the public provision of selective Chen, P., 2008. Equilibrium illusion economic complexity and evolutionary founda-
incentives and high futurity). This may lead to a new interactive tion in economic analysis. Evolutionary and Institutional Economics Review 5
public policy design, focused on specific ‘frame-setting’ to trigger the (1), 81–127.
Christensen, J.L., Gregersen, B., Johnson, B., Lundvall, B.A., Tomlinson, M., 2008. An NSI
causal factors, which in turn may allow for institutional emergence, in transition? Denmark. In: Edquist, C., Hommen, L. (Eds.), Small Country Inno-
co-evolving with meso structure, and collective action capability vation Systems. Globalization, Change and Policy in Asia and Europe. Edward
among private agents.21 This may particularly give space for the Elgar, Cheltenham, UK, Northampton, MA, USA, pp. 403–441.
Cooper, R., John, A., 1988. Coordinating coordination failures in Keynesian models.
emergence of the capability and inclination to learn and innovate,
Quarterly Journal of Economics CIII (3), 441–463.
where otherwise too much volatility and turbulence would under- David, P.A., 1985. Clio and the economics of QWERTY. American Economic Review
mine efforts to learn and innovate. Thus, innovative behavior may, 75 (2), 332–337.
Davis, J.B., 2007. Complexity theory’s network conception of the individual. In: Gia-
paradoxically, emerge through the stabilization of behaviors and
comin, A., Marcuzzo, M.C. (Eds.), Money and Markets. A Doctrinal Approach.
Routledge, Abingdon, UK, New York, USA, pp. 30–47.
Davis, J.B., 2008. Complex individuals: the individual in non-euclidian space. In:
Hanappi, G., Elsner, W. (Eds.), Advances in Evolutionary Institutional Economics:
21
This also would be the logical place for a major role of cooperative game theory Evolutionary Mechanisms, Non-Knowledge, and Strategy. Edward Elgar, Chel-
that one reviewer has suggested. We have put an interactive or institutional, i.e. tenham, UK, Northampton, MA, USA.
frame-oriented public policy in the focus of a ‘negotiated economy’ or ‘new meritorics’ Dejean, S., Penard, T., Suire, R., 2008. Olson’s Paradox Revisited: An Empirical Analysis
(see Elsner, 2001). This would have to be modeled using cooperative game theory. of Filesharing Behaviour in P2P Communities. CREM, Univ. of Rennes, F, Mimeo.
858 W. Elsner, T. Heinrich / The Journal of Socio-Economics 38 (2009) 843–858

Demange, G., Wooders, M. (Eds.), 2005. Group Formation in Economics. Networks, Holm, J.R., Lorenz, E., Lundvall, B.A., Valeyre, A., 2008. Work organisation and systems
Clubs, and Coalitions. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK, New York. of labour market regulation in Europe. In: Paper Presented at the 20th EAEPE
Devezas, T.C., Corredine, J.T., 2002. The nonlinear dynamics of technoeconomic Annual Conference, Rome (Mimeo).
systems: an informational interpretation. Technological Forecasting & Social Jennings, F.B., 2005. How efficiency/equity tradeoffs resolve through horizon effects.
Change 69, 317–357. Journal of Economic Issues 39 (2), 365–373.
Dolfsma, W., Verburg, R., 2008. Structure, agency and the role of values in processes Jorgensen, H., 2002. Consensus Cooperation and Conflict. The Policy Making Process
of institutional change. Journal of Economic Issues XLII (4), 1031–1054. in Denmark. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, UK, Northampton, MA, USA.
Dolfsma, W., Leydesdorff, L., 2009. Lock-in & break-out from technological trajec- Keele, L.J., Stimson, J.A., 2002. Measurement issues in the analysis of social capital.
tories: modeling and policy implications, Technological Forecasting & Social World Bank Working Paper.
Change. Kesting, St., Nielsen, K., 2008. Varieties of capitalism—theoretical critique and empir-
Dopfer, K. (Ed.), 2001. Evolutionary Economics: Program and Scope. Kluwer Acad. ical observations. In: Elsner, W., Hanappi, G. (Eds.), Varieties of Capitalism and
Publ., Boston, Dordrecht, London. New Institutional Deals: Regulation, Welfare, and the New Economy. Edward
Dopfer, K., 2005. Evolutionary economics: a theoretical framework, in: Id. (Ed.), The Elgar, Cheltenham, UK, Northampton, MA, USA.
Evolutionary Foundations of Economics, Cambridge Univ. Pr., Cambridge, pp. Knack, S., Keefer, P., 1997. Does social capital have an economic payoff? A cross-
3–26. country investigation. Quarterly Journal of Economics 112 (4), 1251–1288.
Dopfer, K., 2007. Schumpeter’s economics. The origins of a meso revolution. In: Knudsen, T., 2002. The evolution of cooperation in structured populations. Consti-
Hanusch, H., Pyka, A. (Eds.), The Elgar Companion to Neo-Schumpeterian Eco- tutional Political Economy 13, 129–148.
nomics. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, UK, Northampton, MA, USA. Kuznets, S., 1960. Economic growth of small nations. In: Robinson, E.A.G. (Ed.), Eco-
Dopfer, K., Potts, J., 2008. The General Theory of Economic Evolution. Routledge, nomic Consequences of the Size of Nations. Macmillan, London, pp. 14–32 (repr.
London, New York (Chapter 4). 1963).
Dopfer, K., Foster, J., Potts, J., 2004. Micro–meso–macro. Journal of Evolutionary Leydesdorff, L., 2007. The communication of meaning in anticipatory systems: a
Economics 14, 263–279. simulation study of the dynamics of intentionality in social interactions. In:
Dosi, G., Winter, S.G., 2000. Interpreting economic change: evolution, structures and Vice-Presidential Address at the 8th International Conference of Computing
games. LEM Working Paper Series 2000/08, Pisa, Italy. Anticipatory Systems, Liège, Belgium. Mimeo.
Easterly, W., Kraay, A., 2000. Small states, small problems? Income, growth, and Lindgren, K., Nordahl, M.G., 1994. Evolutionary dynamics of spatial games. Physica
volatility in small states. World Development 28 (11), 2013–2027. D 75, 292–309.
Eckert, D., Koch, St., Mitloehner, J., 2005. Using the iterated prisoner’s dilemma for Lundvall, B.A., 2002. Innovation Growth and Social Cohesion. The Danish Model.
explaining the evolution of cooperation in open source communities. In: Scotto, Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, UK, Northampton, MA, USA.
M., Succi, G. (Eds.), Proceedings of the First International Conference on Open Marwell, G., Oliver, P., 1993. The Critical Mass in Collective Action. A Micro-Social
Source Systems. Genova. Theory. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Edquist, C., Hommen, L. (Eds.), 2008. Small Country Innovation Systems. Global- Oestreicher-Singer, G., Sundararajan, A., 2008. The Visible Hand of Social Networks
ization, Change and Policy in Asia and Europe. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, UK, in Electronic Markets. New York University, Mimeo, New York.
Northampton, MA, USA (Chapters 1 and 12). O’Hara, P.A., 2008. Uneven development, global inequality and ecological sustain-
Elsner, W., 2000. An industrial policy agenda 2000 and beyond—experience theory ability: recent trends and patterns. GPERU Working Paper, Curtin Univ., Perth,
and policy. In: Elsner, W., Groenewegen, J. (Eds.), Industrial Policies After 2000. Australia.
Kluwer Acad. Publ., Boston, Dordrecht, London, pp. 411–486. Olson, M., 1965. The Logic of Collective Action. Harvard University Press, Cambridge,
Elsner, W., 2001. Interactive economic policy: toward a cooperative policy approach MA.
for a negotiated economy. Journal of Economic Issues XXXV (1), 61–83. Ostrom, E., 2007. Challenges and growth: the development of the interdisciplinary
Elsner, W., 2005. Real-world economics today: the new complexity co-ordination field of institutional analysis. Journal of Institutional Economics 3 (3),239–264.
and policy. Review of Social Economy LXIII (1), 19–53. Page, F., Wooders, M., 2007. Strategic basins of attraction, the path dominance
Elsner, W., 2008. Market and state. In: O’Hara, P.A. (Ed.), International Encyclopedia core, and network formation games. Center for Applied Economics and Policy
of Public Policy <http://pohara.homestead.com/Encyclopedia/Volume-3.pdf>. Research, Working Paper 2007-020.
Elster, J., 1989. The Cement of Society. A Study of Social Order. Cambridge University Pyka, A., 1999. Der kollektive Innovationsprozess. Eine theoretische Analyse
Press, Cambridge. informeller Netzwerke und absorptiver Fähigkeiten. Duncker&Humblot, Berlin.
Foley, D.K., 1998. Introduction to ‘barriers and bounds to rationality’. In: Foley, D.K. Schelling, T.C., 1969. Models of segregation. American Economic Review 59 (2),
(Ed.), Barriers and Bounds to Rationality: Essays on Economic Complexity and 488–493.
Dynamics in Interactive Systems, by Albin, P.S., with an Introduction by Foley, Schelling, T.C., 1973. Hockey helmets, concealed weapons, and daylight saving: a
D.K., Princeton Univ. Pr., Princeton, N.J. study of binary choices with externalities. The Journal of Conflict Resolution
Foster, J., 2005. From simplistic to complex systems in economics. Cambridge Journal XVII.3 (repr. in: Schelling, 1978, pp. 211–243).
of Economics 29, 873–892. Schelling, T.C., 1978. Micromotives and Macrobehavior. W.W. Norton, New York,
Fukuyama, F., 1995. Trust. The Social Virtues and the Creation of Prosperity. The Free London.
Press and Penguin Books, New York. Schotter, A., 1981. The Economic Theory of Social Institutions. Cambridge University
Gibbons, R., 2006. What the Folk Theorem doesn’t tell us. Industrial and Corporate Press, Cambridge, UK.
Change 15 (2), 381–386. Spiekermann, K.P., 2009. Sort out your neighbourhood. Public good games on
Goyal, S., 2005. Learning in networks. In: Demange, G., Wooders, M. (Eds.), Group For- dynamic networks. Synthese 168, 273–294 (Knowledge, Rationality & Action,
mation in Economics. Networks, Clubs, and Coalitions’, as given under Demange, 583-604).
Wooders, pp. 122–167. Traulsen, A., Nowak, M.A., 2006. Evolution of cooperation by multilevel selection.
Gruene-Yanoff, T., Schweinzer, P., 2008. The roles of stories in applying game theory. PNAS 103 (29), 10952–10955.
Journal of Economic Methodology 15 (2), 131–146. Tucker, C., 2008. Social interactions, network fluidity and network effects. NET Insti-
Harmsen-van Hout, M.J.W., Dellaert, B.G.C., Herings, P.J.J., 2008. Behavioral Effects tute Working Paper No. 08-30.
in Individual Decisions of Network Formation. Maastricht Research School of van Staveren, I., 2001. The Values of Economics. An Aristotelian Perspective. Rout-
Economics of Technology and Organizations RM/08/019. ledge, London, New York.
Henrich, J., Boyd, R., Bowles, S., Camerer, C., Fehr, E., Gintis, H., 2004. Foundations Vinkovic, D., Kirman, A., 2006. A physical analogue of the Schelling model. PNAS 103
of Human Sociality. Economic Experiments and Ethnographic Evidence from (51), 19261–19265.
Fifteen Small-Scale Societies. Oxford University Press, Oxford. Watts, D.J., 1999. Small Worlds. The Dynamics of Networks between Order and
Hodgson, G.M., 2000. From micro to macro: the concept of emergence and Randomness. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, Oxford, UK (Chapter 8).
the role of institutions. In: Burlamaqui, L., et al. (Eds.), Institutions and the Yamagishi, T., 1992. Group size and the provision of a sanctioning system in a social
Role of the State. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, UK, Northampton, MA, USA, dilemma. In: Liebrand, W.B.G., Messick, D.M., Wilke, H.A.M. (Eds.), Social Dilem-
pp. 103–126. mas. Theoretical Issues and Research Findings. Pergamon Press, Oxford, pp.
Hodgson, G.M., 2006. What are institutions? Journal of Economic Issues XL (1), 1–25. 267–287.

S-ar putea să vă placă și