Sunteți pe pagina 1din 6

Eclectic Orthodoxy

"I'm a blogger, dammit, not a
theologian!"

Ipsum Esse Subsistens: The God Who is Verb


Posted on 2 October 2016

Five ways, five philosophical proofs for the existence of God. Yet one might wonder whether the Angelic Doctor
has demonstrated the existence of a single ultimate being. Perhaps the unmoved mover of the first way is a
different being than the perfect being of the fourth way … so on and so forth. Perhaps … but unlikely. St Thomas
clearly intends each proof to identify an ontological deficiency, namely, the incapacity of beings to provide a
metaphysical account of their existence. Only a being who is the transcendent fullness of being, who is self-
existent Being, can provide an answer to the question, Why does the world exist instead of nothing? “On
Aquinas’s view,” Edward Feser explains, “there can in principle be only one being whose essence and existence are
identical, and thus which is Pure Being. Hence it is necessarily one and the same being on which all five proofs
converge” (Aquinas, p. 121). The persuasiveness of the five ways, therefore, depends on our grasping the critical
Thomist insight—the essence of God is his existence.

Orthodox Christians have always claimed for the triadic Deity the attribute of aseity. The divine self-sufficiency
would seem to logically follow from the dogmatic claim that God freely and needlessly created the world from out
of nothing. God possesses life, power, being within himself. He does not derive it from any other source. Thus St
Athanasius:

For if it is an admitted truth about God that He stands in need of nothing, but is self­sufficient and
self­contained, and that in Him all things have their being, and that He ministers to all rather than
they to Him, how is it right to proclaim as gods the sun and moon and other parts of creation,
which are of no such kind, but which even stand in need of one another’s help?  (Contra Gentes 28)

Yet as standard and commonplace as the confession of God’s aseity may be within the tradition, many theologians
find Thomas’s formulation of the doctrine incisive and fresh, even innovative. Even a theologian as critical of
Hellenistic construals of divinity as Robert W. Jenson appreciates the Thomistic contribution:

According to Thomas Aquinas, the difference between Creator and creature is that in the case of
creatures, existence and essence are distinct, whereas they are not in God. Essence is, of
course, what something is; existence, in Thomas’ here innovative use, is the fact that something is.
Simplifying greatly, we could know absolutely everything about what a putative creature would
be, without knowing whether the thing so described actually exists. Not so with God: could we—as
short of the Kingdom we cannot—know what God is, we would merely therein discover that he is.
God contains within what he is the reason that he is; we do not.

In my view, Thomas’ brilliant move must surely suffice for all ordinary theological purposes, and I
invoke it regularly. Yet I am haunted by the feeling that it also is too abstract to quite fit the
biblical narrative. For Thomas himself, the non­distinction of existence and essence in God belongs
to his doctrine that God is Being. I agree, but I note that the Eastern doctrine that God is above
Being seems to exegete Scripture with equal plausibility, which suggests a certain loose fit in both
cases. (“Creator and Creature,” Theology as Revisionary Metaphysics, pp. 158­159)

What Jenson sees as a weakness of the Thomistic claim of the identity of the divine essence and existence—
namely, its abstraction from the biblical story—I see as its strength. The proper distinction between Creator and
creature cannot be adequately stated in the terms of the biblical narrative, though it first emerges and is
apprehended within this narrative. At this point the Scriptures point us to a mystery they cannot say.

On the surface the Thomist assertion that the essence (essentia) of God is identical to his existence (esse) merely
restates in scholastic idiom what the Church has always taught about the divine aseity and the contingency of the
world: God is uncreated; everything else ain’t. But some Thomists believe that the formulation illuminates the
nature of being in a way that was unavailable to earlier Christian philosophers. This illumination is expressed in
Thomas’s use of two words—esse (being, existence; infinitive form of the verb to “to be”) and ens (entity, a being;
plural: entia). Etienne Gilson recommends that English translators use “being” to render ens and “act of being” to
render esse.

Thomas begins his metaphysical reflection, not with ideas and concepts, but with the beings that we apprehend
with our senses. We see a rock, we hear a tree falling, we smell a flower, we taste the Cabernet Sauvignon, we feel
the caress of our lover. By an act of intellect we apprehend the nature or essence of these things, i.e., we grasp
them as substantial forms, but by an act of judgment we penetrate to their metaphysical act of existing and are
thus able to affirm of each “it is.” Our judgment, Gilson says, “reaches the very act-of-being. When we speak of the
being of any being (ens), we are speaking of something having an act-of-being (habens esse)” (The Christian
Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas, p. 40). To be is not a static state of existence or even presupposition for
thought and action. It is event, a dynamic presence and self-revelation. A being exists, explains Gilson, “only in
virtue of the existential act which makes it a real thing” (p. 34):

Thus understood, the act of existing lies at the very heart, or if one prefers, at the very root of the
real. It is therefore the principle of the principles of reality. First absolutely, it even precedes the
Good, for a being is only good in so far as it is a being, and it is a being only in virtue of the ipsum
esse which permits us to say of it: this is “being.”

To understand this doctrine in its proper nature, it is necessary to remember that esse, like every
verb, designates an act and not a state. The state in which the esse places that which receives it is
the state of ens, that is to say, of that which is a “being.” Because essences are the proper object of
human understanding, we tend ceaselessly to step down from the plane of the act­of­being to that
of things (res). This is a natural inclination, but the metaphysician must make every effort to
remount, that is to emphasize that being has meaning only in relation to actual existence. Beyond
what is most perfect and most profound in the real, there is nothing. Now, what is most perfect is
the act­of­being (ipsum esse) “since it is related to all things as their act. In fact, nothing has any
actuality save in that it exists. The act­of­being (ipsum esse) is the actuality of everything else, even
including forms. Its relation to other things therefore is not that of receiver to received but of
received to receiver. Indeed, when I say of a man, or of a horse, or of anything else: that exists, the
act of being (ipsum esse) is taken as formal and received, and not as that to which the act­of­being
belongs.” St. Thomas is here noticeably making, as it were, a supreme effort, so much so that the
meaning fairly rings through the formulae, to express the unique character of ipsum esse and its
transcendence. But precisely because it is the summit of the real, it is also its heart. “The act­of­
existing is more intimate to anything whatsoever than is what determines it.” (p. 34)
One might think, as philosophers both before and after Aquinas did, that existence should be described as a
property that something possesses (my Collie has the properties of sable-and-white fur, a long nose, and a sweet
disposition … and by the way, she also exists), but Thomas denies this. In his view to say that something exists
does not describe any given ens; it does not tell us about its nature or qualities. Alvin Kimel is a man and Tiriel is
his favorite dog, but they are distinguished from each other not by their respective acts of existing but by all sorts
of other features. As Brian Davies writes, “For Aquinas there is nothing which can be characterized simply by
saying that it is” (Aquinas, p. 29; see “Aquinas, God, and Being“). Esse is more fundamental than ens or
even essence. To make matters a tad clearer, consider fictional or mythological beings. If you have read Lord of
the Rings or watched The Two Towers, you know what Ents are. If you don’t, zip on over to The Encyclopedia of
Arda and check out the entry: “A race of giant, tree-like people whose purpose was to protect the forests of
Middle-earth.” If it had also stated, “But they don’t exist in the real world,” nothing about Ents qua Ents would
have changed. Whether they exist or do not exist, their Entish nature remains the same.

And so it is with all beings. Their existence is not identical to their essence. Men and dogs have esse and
participate in esse, but they are not esse. They do not contain existence within themselves but must receive it from
their transcendent source. Only with the uncreated Deity may we say that he is his existence. As the Lord told
Moses on Mount Sinai, “I AM.”

“God is not only His own essence,” declares Thomas, “but also His own esse” (ST I.3.4)—or perhaps we should
render, “his own act of existing.” God is the Act that underlies and grounds the cosmos. He is not a thing (ens), not
even the supreme Thing. He is the doer and doing of existence, perfectly realized activity and energy, unbounded
actuality unconstricted by limiting essence, the infinite plenitude of Being. “God exists as the doing of all being,”
elaborates Timothy McDermott, “the existence that acts in all existence, an existence in the world’s existing but
not of it, no thing, but not therefore nothing” (Preface to Summa Theologiae, p. xxxii). Not a noun, we might say,
but a verb. Thus Gilson:

Why, Saint Thomas asks, do we say that Qui est is the most proper name among all those that can
be given to God? And his answer is because it signifies “to be”: ipsum esse. But what is it to be? In
answering this most difficult of all metaphysical questions, we must carefully distinguish between
the meaning of two words which are both different and yet intimately related: ens, or “being,”
and esse, or “to be.” To the question: What is being? the correct answer is: Being is that which is, or
exists. If, for instance, we ask this same question with regard to God, the correct answer would be:
The being of God is an infinite and boundless ocean of substance. But esse, or “to be,” is something
else and much harder to grasp because it lies more deeply hidden in the metaphysical structure of
reality. The word “being,” as a noun, designates some substance; the word “to be”—or esse—is a
verb, because it designates an act. To understand this is also to reach, beyond the level of essence,
the deeper level of existence. …

A world where “to be” is the act par excellence, the act of all acts, is also a world wherein, for each
and everything, existence is the original energy whence flows all that which deserves the name of
being. Such an existential world can be accounted for by no other cause than a supremely
existential God. (God and Philosophy, pp. 63­65)

At this point I suspect some readers may have lost all sympathy with Aquinas. Perhaps you have even begun
chanting the famous memorial of Pascal: “God of Abraham, God of Isaac, God of Jacob—not of the philosophers
and scholars!” I know this response well and intimately, but before giving up on him, remember that St Thomas
was a man of deep prayer, thoroughly formed by the Bible, Mass, and the Offices of the Church (see Denys
Turner, Thomas Aquinas—I cannot recommend this book too highly). He did not see a conflict between faith and
reason. Perhaps neither should we.

Protestant and Orthodox theologians commonly claim that Aquinas, along with his fellow scholastics, presents us
with a static understanding of divinity, an immutable, impassible, impersonal substance, the unmoved mover of
Aristotle, certainly not the living God of Israel and the apostolic Church. This was a common theme of my
catechetical teaching when I was a parish priest. I am feeling pretty silly now. As apprehended by Thomas, esse is
the very opposite of the static and inert. But more, of course, needs to be said. In particular we want to see how the
God whose essence is his existence is also personal, indeed Person. As Eleonore Stump has recently argued,
Thomas had no problem speaking of God as one who hears prayers and acts within the world he has made. Read
his biblical commentaries, she urges, and you will find that “Aquinas’s God is highly responsive to human beings
and engaged with them in personal and interactive ways. He is a God who is a particular and personal friend to
every person of faith. And he looks very like the biblical God” (The God of the Bible and the God of the
Philosophers, p. 108). I suspect that Gilson would object to Stump’s downplaying the metaphysical side of Thomas
(she pointedly criticizes scholars like Brian Davies and David Burrell who assert that God is not a being); but he
certainly would agree with her that no conflict exists or can exist between the Esse whom Thomas thought about
and the Father to whom he prayed.

The infinitely creative God of the Bible meets the self-existent God of the philosophers, and surprise of surprises,
they are the very same God—Ipsum Esse Subsistens. 

Advertisements

Report this ad Report this ad

Share this:

 Facebook 28  Google  Reddit  Twitter  Print

Like

7 bloggers like this.


Related

St Thomas Aquinas and the Contuition of Can Reason Prove the Existence of God? Thomas Aquinas, Eleonore Stump, and the
Divinity In "Aquinas" Maverick Philosopher: Is God "a" being
In "Aquinas" among beings?
In "Philosophical Theology"

This entry was posted in Aquinas and tagged Aquinas, aseity, being, esse, essence, Etienne Gilson, existence, Existential Thomism, God. Bookmark the permalink.

6 Responses to Ipsum Esse Subsistens: The God Who is Verb

Robert Fortuin says:
2 October 2016 at 7:43 pm

Ipsum Esse Subsistens, the coincidence of God’s essence with His existence is another way of expressing divine simplicity:
‘no-thing’ other than God is self existent, and self existence is unique, not shared, imparticipable. Only in God does the act of
being and existence coincide, simply, without distinction.

Jenson misreads Aquinas (and/or the eastern tradition) to suppose there’s an opposition between ‘Ipsum Esse Subsistens’
and God’s transcendence above being. It appears he’s applying an univocal understanding to the concept ‘being’ to divinity.

 Liked by 1 person

Fr Aidan Kimel says:
3 October 2016 at 3:20 pm

Contrast St Thomas’s understanding of God is Ipsum Esse Subsistens with Greg Boyd’s new article “How Classical
Theology Gets it Wrong.

 Like

Robert Fortuin says:
7 October 2016 at 4:49 pm

It is difficult not to appear dismissive. I can only conclude there are two possibilities: either Boyd hasn’t studied
classical theism; or, if he has done so, Boyd doesn’t fully understand classic theism on its own terms.

 Like

brian says:
8 October 2016 at 1:03 pm

Boyd is posing the question in an either/or fashion. He creates a binary choice between a supposedly philosophically
construed God of classical theism or the Biblical God of revelation. Pascal makes a similar gambit, as does Lev Shestov. I have
some sympathy for the latter two, but the “God of the Philosophers” they shake a fist at is not the God of classical theism. I
don’t know Boyd, but I think he is a friend of Tom’s. Yet the choice has been posed badly. One does not have to choose
between classical theism and biblical revelation. Nor does classical theism mean subordinating Biblical truths to
philosophical truth; nor is accommodation properly understood as a weakening of Biblical images to the point where they no
longer signify.

What is true is that Biblical interpretation always presupposes a metaphysics and bad metaphysics yields bad theology. For
example, David Bentley Hart asserts that nominalist and voluntarist conceptions are imported into modern theology (both
Reformation and Counter-reformation sensibilities are affected by significant distortion.) Such “unconscious” ideological
allegiances have shaped translation, theological emphasis, methodology, etc. Ironically, Boyd’s interpretive paradigm is also
an example of modern amnesia that can no longer lucidly think pre-modern ways of thinking. A true “post-modern” must
retrieve the tradition in a living, existential manner. At minimum, Boyd should wonder why patristic practice makes use of
allegory in order to avoid saying unworthy things about God. Any substantial revelatory sense should be aware of the
necessity of rising above a literalist positivism and hence, the need for some kind of hermeneutic that understands the holism
of revelation granted finally by the Gospel.
One will recognize at least that Incarnation and Trinity were not primitive elements of revelatory awareness (though
retrospectively one might discern traces in the manner in which Rublev sees the Trinity in Abraham’s table with the angels.)
One might then consider that the metaphysical implications of a fuller revelation could potentially introduce paradox and
insight lacking in more naive approaches. As Robert surmises, there is a univocal tendency in Boyd’s conceptions that
precisely misses the value of analogy. Further, the flourishing of Pure Act is not the static thing he seems to imagine, nor is
Eternity the same as “timelessness” the way he has conceptualized it. Indeed, Eternity is exactly God interacting with each
moment as it is dynamically and dramatically realized. God does not need to descend into the temporal in order to
authentically interact with creation. Transcendence, intimacy, and genuine drama are all properly founded by the classical
understanding, not subverted by it.

 Liked by 1 person

Robert Fortuin says:
10 October 2016 at 12:15 am

Brian and all,

I suppose Brian that the hangup is just how it is that eternity is (or can be) an interaction with each moment, how divine
simplicity and perfect actuality is dynamically and dramatically realized, how there can be an authentic and temporal
encounter, and so forth. Recourse to analogy I suspect is viewed as an escape into absurdity, a flight into the unknown about
which nothing (at least nothing sensible, intelligible) can be predicated. Unfolding of timelessness is a contradiction in terms;
as is dynamism and drama to omniscience. One then is left with the univocal theological project, which clings to the familiar,
the sure, the understood. The arena of the sure and the familiar is after all the setting in which God manifests Himself, so it is
argued. Such however risks the conflation (if not complete identification) of the revelation of God with God. Moreover it is
misleading in that it presents only two possible and opposing modes of theo-logizing: pure univocity vs. equivocity. The God
of Scripture, however, transcends His revelation of Himself, as well as the dialectic of the univocal/equivocal predication. The
God in whom their is no difference between What­He­Is and the That­He­Is (meaning, He is the Cause of His existence)
supersedes affirmation and negation, and the dialectic between them. He in Whom Being self-exists, the Fullness of Being,
remains ever beyond all that we can affirm and negate. That is to say, univocation and equivocation must ever account for the
infinite modal disjunction between our contingent existence and transcendent Self-existence. To avoid the devolution of
affirmation into idolatry and negation into nihilism, theology which accounts for divine transcendence can only be done
properly by analogy. Analogy accounts for divine likeness within creation whilst upholding an ever greater unlikeness of God
to creaturely existence. Only analogy rightly acknowledges that, as my compatriot Henk Schoot put it, ‘God differs
differently.’ Without this ‘different difference’ all conceptions of God are on the level of object among objects.

 Liked by 1 person

Robert Fortuin says:
10 October 2016 at 12:30 am

As a follow up –

Not that I think analogy is persuasive to Boyd. I suppose that for open/process theists who share his position (or
should I say angst?) any predication, any theology, short of univocity cannot explain on creaturely terms the God
who is. This is a point of difference.

 Like

Eclectic Orthodoxy
Blog at WordPress.com.

S-ar putea să vă placă și