Sunteți pe pagina 1din 5

Journal of Philosophy, Inc.

The Socratic Elenchus


Author(s): Gregory Vlastos
Source: The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 79, No. 11, Seventy-Ninth Annual Meeting of the
American Philosophical Association, Eastern Division (Nov., 1982), pp. 711-714
Published by: Journal of Philosophy, Inc.
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2026548
Accessed: 23-05-2016 01:10 UTC

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Journal of Philosophy, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The
Journal of Philosophy

This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Mon, 23 May 2016 01:10:10 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Mon, 23 May 2016 01:10:10 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
712 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY

question-and-answer adversative argument, which normally pro-


ceeds as follows:

1. The interlocutor, "saying what he believes," asserts p, which Soc-


rates considers false, and targets for refutation.
2. Socrates obtains agreement to further premises, say q and r, which
are logically independent of p. The agreement is ad hoc: Socrates
does not argue for q or for r.
3. Socrates argues, and the interlocutor agrees, that q and r entail not-p.
4. Thereupon Socrates claims that p has been proved false, not-p true.

Novel features of this analysis are the following:

I. Since only moral truths are debated, the elenctic method is not
itself investigated elenctically. As a purely moral inquirer Socrates
abstains on principle from inquiry into the theory and method of
moral inquiry. For the same reason he does not use the elenctic
method to investigate the logical conditions of the right answer to
a "What is F?" question. These he lays down and demands com-
pliance. The interlocutor is not portrayed as having dissenting
views about them, but as needing instruction on their very rudi-
ments, which Socrates is ever ready to provide.
II. Observance of the "say what you believe" rule is vital, for this
is what marks off decisively the practice of elenchus from that of er-
istic. In the latter, where the prime object is to win the argument,
one can say anything that will yield a debating advantage. In the
former, where the prime object is to discover truth, one does not
have that option. One must say what one believes even to the detri-
ment of one's fortunes in the debate. One must prefer to be re-
futed-to lose the argument-if what one believes is not true. (Ex-
ceptionally, the rule may be waived: as a pis aller, to induce a
worsted opponent to stay in the argument and face the music.)
III. The premises q and r obtained at 2, from which Socrates de-
duces the negation of p at 3, are logically unsecured within the ar-
gument. Though Socrates has undoubtedly reasons for each of
them, he does not bring those reasons into the argument. He asks
the interlocutor whether he agrees, and if he gets agreement he goes
on from there. So in elenctic argument the question of referring to
a court of last appeal for settling philosophical disagreement does
not arise. In particular, there is no appeal to what Aristotle takes to
serve this purpose: None to those "primary," necessary, self-evident
truths which he regards as the foundation of demonstrative argu-
ment, and none to "what is commonly believed" (ta endoxa),
which is for Aristotle the foundation of dialectical argument. If
this fundamental feature of the elenchus is missed, it will be con-

This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Mon, 23 May 2016 01:10:10 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
THE SOCRATIC ELENCHUS 713

flated with ordinary dialectical argument from endoxa. So it is in


one of the landmark studies in the field, the volume on Socrates in
Eduard Zeller's Philosophie der Griechen: Zeller is misled by his re-
liance on Xenophon. The mistake has been frequently repeated,
most recently in W. K. C. Guthrie's History of Greek Philosophy,
volumes 3 and 4. In these and many other works the elenchus dis-
appears from view.
IV. My interpretation of the elenchus has affinities with that of
Richard Robinson, Norman Gulley, and Terry Irwin, all three of
whom recognize that the elenchus is used by Socrates not merely
destructively, to expose his adversaries' "conceit of knowledge,"
but also constructively, to provide rational support for his own
moral doctrines. But I differ from each in important ways. I reject
Robinson's claim, which has been widely influential, that Plato
"habitually thought and wrote as if all elenchus consists in reduc-
ing the [interlocutor's] thesis to a self-contradiction"': the claim is
textually baseless. I disagree with Gulley's view that elenchus
makes implicit appeal to self-evidence2: Socrates allows himself the
use of premises which are anything but self-evident and may even
be contra-endoxic. I dissent from Irwin's view that "not all [of Soc-
rates'] positive doctrines rely on the elenchus; some rely on the
analogy between virtue and craft"': the arguments by which Soc-
rates draws conclusions from that analogy are themselves elenctic.
I also dissent from his view that Socrates "normally" imposes cer-
tain constraints on what the interlocutor can say in arguing
against him" (ibid., p. 39): the textual evidence appears to be that
Socrates always allows, indeed requires, the interlocutor to say any-
thing he believes.
V. The most radical feature of my understanding of the elenchus
shows up at 4 in the above analysis: Socrates claims to prove the
falsehood of the refutand. I accept the burden of proof in holding
that Socrates really makes this claim, so unjustified in point of
logic, on the face of it, since from the fact that not-p is entailed by
the conjunction of q and r (for neither of which has any argument
been given), all that follows is that p is inconsistent with those
premises, so that if the interlocutor chooses to stick by the premises
he must consider p false; whereas what Socrates is driving for is
universally valid, true, results whose discovery is "a common good
for practically all mankind" (Charmides 166D). Is Socrates really

'Richard Robinson, Plato's Earlier Dialectic (New York: Oxford, 1953), p. 28.
2Norman Gulley, The Philosophy of Socrates (New York: St. Martin's, 1968), pp.
43/4.
'Terence Irwin, Plato's Moral Theory (New York: Oxford, 1977), p. 37.

This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Mon, 23 May 2016 01:10:10 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
714 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY

claiming to get such results, or should suggestions of his to that ef-


fect be discounted as hyperbole? I argue that the claim is made in
dead earnest and then proceed to ask how Socrates could have felt
entitled to make it. I argue that it was predicated on two assump-
tions of his which can be teased out of some of his remarks in the
Gorgias:

A. Every person's set of beliefs always includes a subset of beliefs which


entails the negation of each of that person's false moral beliefs.
B. The set of moral beliefs held by Socrates at any given moment is
consistent.

From A and B Socrates would naturally infer that his own set of
moral beliefs is the true set. For if it contained any false moral be-
lief then, by A, it would include beliefs entailing the negation of
that belief, and then it would be inconsistent, contrary to B. On
these assumptions, to prove the inconsistency of the opponent's
thesis with the premises to which Socrates had agreed would be to
prove that thesis inconsistent with the true set and, hence, to prove
it false.
For A and B Socrates could have had only inductive evidence-
probable inference from his own experience in elenctic argument.
The inference is doubly insecure-glaringly so in the case of A,
more insidiously so in the case of B: success in elenctic argument
need not show that one's own beliefs are consistent; it may show
only that the opponent's efforts to probe their inconsistencies have
been blocked by one's superior dialectical skill. Socrates could
hardly be unaware of these hazards. This must contribute to his
sense of the fallibility of his method, which I take to be the right
clue to his disavowal of knowledge even concerning beliefs that
have been "clamped down and bound" elenctically "by arguments
of iron and adamant" (Gorgias 508E-509A).
GREGORY V'LAST OS

University of California/Berkeley and the Hastings Center

This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Mon, 23 May 2016 01:10:10 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

S-ar putea să vă placă și