Sunteți pe pagina 1din 14

CULTURAL HISTORY AND LlTERARY IMAGINATION Cultural Transformations

EDITED BY CHRISTIAN J. EMDEN & DAVID MIDGLEY


of the Public Sphere
VOL. 24
Contemporary and Historical Perspectives
EDITORIAL BOARD
RODRIGO CACHO, UNIVERSITY OF CAMBRIDGE
SARAH COLVIN, UNIVERSITY OF CAMBRIDGE
KENNETH LOISELLE, TRINITY UNIVERSITY Bernd Fischer and May Mergenthaler (eds)
HEATHER WEBB, UNIVERSITY OF CAMBRIDGE

III
t
I
11111

1->

.&.
PETER LANG
~
PETERLANG
Oxford • Bem • Berlin • Bruxelles • Frankfurt am Main • New York • Wien Oxford • Bem • Berlin • Bruxelles • Frankfurt am Main • New York • Wien
Bibliographic information published by Die Deutsche Nationalbibliothek

Die Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbiblio­


(:ontents
grafie; detailed biblio~raphic data is available on the Internet at http://dnb.d-nb.de.

Acatalogue record forthis book is available from the British Library.

of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data


IIERND FISCHER AND MAY MERGENTHALER

Cultural transformations ofthe public sphere: contemporary and historical perspec­ Introduction
tives / Bernd Fischer and May Mergenthaler (eds.).
pagesem

Includes bibliographical references and index.

PART I Historical Perspectives: Real and Imaginary,


ISBN 978-3-03-430991-2 (alk.

Inclusive and Exclusive Public Spheres 13


1. Communities.2. Civil society. 3. Public spaces. I. Fischer, Bernd, 1953- 11. Mer­

genthaler, May.

DOROTHEA VON MÜCKE


HM761.C852014

306.2--dc23
Public Space and the Public: Johann Gottfried Herder's
2014039259
Approach to Real and Imagined Communities I5

SUSANNE LÜDEMANN
Cover image: Public Sphere (detail), 2014 © Curtis Goldstein. Photographs from

magazines and advertisements, cardboard, glue, table, glass, LED lights. 54 x35 x 35
Fraternity as a Social Metaphor 41
in. overall. Reproduced with kind permission ofthe artist.

ISSN 1660-6205
PART II Cultural and Theoretical Transformations I:
ISBN 978-3-0343-0991-2 (print)
The Limits ofPublic Representation 61
ISBN 978-3-0353-0741-2

JADE LARJSSA SCHIFF


© Peter Lang AG, International Academic Publishers, Bern 2015

Repressive Democracy: Pathological and Ontological


Hochfeldstrasse 32, CH-3012 Bern, Switzerland

Distortion in Habermas' Theory of Communicative Action 63


info@peterlang.com, www.peterlang.com, www.peterlang.net

All rights reserved.


EDGAR LANDGRAF
All parts of this publication are protected by copyright.
Political Autonomy and the Public: From Lippmann to Luhmann 93
utilisation outside the strict limits ofthe copyright law, without the permission of
the publisher, is forbidden and liable to prosecution.
This applies in particularto reproductions, translations, microfilming, and storage and CHRISTIAN J. EMDEN
processing in electronic retrieval systems. Constitutionalizing the Public Sphere? Habermas and
the Modern State 12I
This publication has been peer reviewed.

Printed in Germany
vi

PART III Cultural and Theoretical Transformations II:

IHtRND FISCHER AND MAY MERGENTHALER


The Aesthetic Potentials ofPublic Spheres
155
JULIANE REBENTISCH Introduction
Mass - People - Multitude: A Reflection on the Source
ofDemocratic Legitimacy
157

CHRISTOPH MENKE
'11\1: idea for this volume developed during a larger interdisciplinary pro­
A Different Taste: Neither Autonomy nor Mass Consumption 18, Ieee on 'The Puhlic Sphere and Modem Sodal Imaginaries: a lecture senes
Imd a conference that took place at The Ohio State University hetween
KAM SHAPIRO
2.009 and 2012. We invited those participants and several additional col­
Biopolitical Reflections: Cognitive, Aesthetic and Reflexive
lellgues, who were particularly interested in conceptual work on the cultural
Mappings ofGlobal Economies
lmplications and aesthetic formations of the public sphere, to contribute
2°3
co this volume. Our thanks go foremost to the authors, who responded
HO convincingly to our invitation; to the participants of the conference
PART IV Three Case Studies: From Postcolonial
I\nd the lecture series; and to the colleagues from OSU's departments of
to Global Literary Public Spheres
229 Comparative Studies, History, Political Science, Spanish and Portuguese,
Imd Germanic Languages and Literatures who participated in the concep­
FERNANDO UNZUETA
tlon and organization ofthe larger project. Special thanks are due to Alice
National Novels and the Emergence ofthe Public Sphere Schlingman, who helped with the editorial work that felliargely into May
in Latin America Mergenthaler's hands. Finally, we would like to thank the College (now
23 1
})ivision) ofHumanities for generously supporting the lecture series, the
IGNACIO CORONA conference, and the publication ofchis volume.
Gendering the Public Sphere: Literary Journalism Pondering the potentials, limits, hopes and hazards ofexpounding the
by Women in Mexico and Brazil role ofaesthetics and culture in the formation ofpublic spheres and sodal
27 1
Imaginaries, it is perhaps helpful to search for possible beginnings. When
Immanuel Kant, in bis ~swer to the Question: What is Enlightenment?'
ODED NIR
(1784), introduced his notion ofa public [publikum] that has the potential
Totalizing Imaginaries: Collectiviry and Utopia in Modern to enlighten itself, bis anticipated model was a yet to be established uncen­
Hehrew Fiction fromAltneuland to Neuland sored intellectual exchange of ideas and arguments. Reason alone was to
3°5
determine the validity of any puhlished argument, and in the process of
Notes on Contrihutors its quasi-scholarly self-enlightenment, the public would not only debate
337
innovative and diverse ideas, it would also learn how to reason. Culture
Index and aesthetics did not come into view. For Kant, gratuitous rhetorical
34 1
devices, polemical structures and aesthetic emhellishments were, as he
CHRISTOPH MENKE

A Different Taste: Neither Autonomy


nor Mass Consumption

Recent theories and diagnoses of sodal states of affairs have attempted


to use the figure of the aesthetic to gain insight into central mechanisms
of contemporary society. These attempts rest on the assumption that the
aesthetic is a figure of subjectivity, or more precisdy, of freedom. This
assumption is correct: the last word ofaesthetics is human freedom. 1 More
pressing is the need for us to darify what aesthetics means by freedom. For
only when that is dear can we decide how compelling the attempt is to
describe, let alone to explain and evaluate, 2 today's emerging postmodern
society by referring to figures of thought daborated by the aesthetics of
modernity between the eighteenth and twentieth centuries. This attempt

Christoph Menke, Kraft: Ein GrundbegriffästhetischerAnthropologie (Frankfurt/M.:


Suhrkamp, 2008), 129; Christoph Menke, Force: A Fundamental Concept ofAesthetic
Anthropology, trans. Garrit Jackson (New York: Fordham University Press, 20I3), 98.
2 For a descriptive-phenomenological usage ofthe category ofthe aesthetic see Axel
Honneth, 'Organisierte Selbstverwirklichung. Paradoxien der Individualisierung', in
Axel Honneth,Das Ich im Wir: Studien zur Anerleennungstheorie (Berlin: Suhrkamp,
20m), 202-21. In contrast to this usage, see Luc Boltanski and Eve ChiapeHo 'Die
Arbeit der Kritik und der normative Wandel: in Marion von Osten, ed., Norm der
Abweichung (Zurich: Springer 2003), 57-80, as weH as Andreas Reckwitz, 'Vom
KÜllsclermythos zur Normalisierung kreativer Prozesse. Der Beitrag des Kunstfelds
zur Genese des Kreativsubjekts', in Christoph Menke and Juliane Rebentisch, eds,
Kreation und Depression: Freiheit im gegenwärtigen Kapitalismus (Berlin: Kadmos,
20II), 98-II7. These authors use the category ofthe aesthetic in order to explain the
development of certain social formations and figures, on the basis of a process of
aestheticization. On the use of the aesthetic and thc acsthcticization as categories
ofvalue assessment see the comprehcnsivc study by Juliane Rebentisch, Die Kunst
der Freiheit: Zur Dialektik demokratischer Existenz (Berlin: Suhrkamp,
184 CHRISTOPH MENKE A Different Taste: Neither Autonom] nor Mass Consumption I8S

attributes to modern aesthetics an antidpatory quality with regard to because) the concept of'good' taste designates yet another field in which
today's postmodern sodal developments. sodal distinctions and convertible forms of accumulated capital may be
In the following, I will argue that this recourse of sodal theory to generated... Rather, it is true first and foremost because the faculty of taste
aesthetics must fau: the emerging forrns ofa postmodern subjectivity (or, is crucial- though crudal in very different ways - both to modern sodety
as I will say, for reasons I will explain, a subjectivity that is both post~ and CO the emerging postmodern or post~disdplinary sodety.
disdplinary and post~autonomous) cannot be understood as the sodal
realization of a figure delineated by modern aesthetics. That is so for two
reasons that seem to be mutually contradictory: because the aesthetic
freedom ofmodernity is both less and more than the freedom ofthe post~ Autonomy
disciplinary subjectivity we currently see taking shape. On the one hand,
the post-disdplinary form ofsubjectivity goes beyond the idea offreedom
framed by aesthetic modernity; the former is not the lace sodal realization The category of taste, more than almost any other, is tied to the emer~
of the latter (but in fact a result of its crisis). On the other hand, however, gence ofaesthetics in the eighteenth century.5 It is here that the concept's
the idea of freedom framed byaesthetic modernity likewise goes beyond essential features take shape: 'taste: as aesthetics defines it, is a faculty of
the post-disdplinary form ofsubjectivity; the former is not the blueprint cognition and judgment that belongs to the 'sensible: which is to say, it
for the latter (but in fact energizes its critique). proceeds without predetermined rules or concepts. Taste is the faculty
I will explain this double hypothesis with a few desultory remarks of perceiving and judging the qualities of an object without methodical
about the concept oftaste. is an aesthetic category and at once a sodal verification or argumentative justification in an act ofsensible comprehen­
one. It is an aesthetic category because taste constitutes the exemplary figure sion. This conception is opposed at once to traditional doctrines ofartistic
ofaesthetic freedom. Taste is a faculty offreedom because it is a faculty of production and to the phuosophy of rationalism. Against the traditional
perception and evaluation in which the subject proceeds, quite radically, doctrines ofartistic production, it describes the aesthetic objects oftaste as
'without guidance from another':3 without the guidance of tradition, but incapable of regulation and as fundamentally exempt from theory and its
also without the guidance ofa generally defined method, and indeed even conceptual~discursive knowledge. It is not enough, aesthetics likes to say,
without the guidance of a determinate, which is to say, predetermined quoting Horace, that poems be beautiful (in accordance with the rules):
concept. At the same time, this possibility is available to all: whereas only 'let them be tender and affecting, and bear away the soul of the auditor
a few people can have genius, the freedom ofaesthetic creation, taste is that whithersoever they please: To have taste means to have understood that
faculty ofaesthetic freedom that everyone may develop. And taste is asocial
category because taste is offundamental importance for the subject's sodal
constitution and its sodal function. That is true not because (or not only 4 This is Pierre Bourdieus thesis (presented here in an abbreviated form), which is
part ofhis attempt to reverse the 'denial of the soda!' that tries to deflne taste and
to uncover its hidden sodal ti.mction. But perhaps the sodal element of taste lies
precisely in its denial ofthe sodal. CE Pierre Bourdieu, Distinction: A Sodal Critique
3 Kant darifles this formulation hom 'Beantwortung der Frage: Was ist Aufklärung?' oftheJudgment ofTaste (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1984), 11.
in Kritik der Urteilskraft [Critique of the Power ofJudgment] (§ 40, B IS8-9) as an For more detailed and exact analyses ofthe following see Christoph Menke, 'Subjekt,
overcoming of the 'passivity' of reason. To guide oneself constitutes the activity of Subjektivitär: in Karlheinz Barck et al., eds, Ästhetische Grundbegriffe: Historisches
reason, or transforms the selfinto a subjecr. Wörterbuch in sieben Bänden V (Stuttgart: Metzler, 2003), 734-87.
186 CHRISTOPH MENKE A Different Taste: Neither Autonom} nor Mass Consumption 187

a 'work mat is full ofbreaches of me rules can be excellent': taste savours Part and parcel of me aesmetic idea of taste is me awareness mat me
the 'irregularites heureuses [the happy irregularities]'.6 Yet me aesmetic form ofsubjectivity and me aspiration to objective validity are not given
category of taste is at once also opposed to me philosophy ofrationalism, and in mutual agreement by nature. Taste is a matter of'education': taste,
which had dedared me idea ofa faculty ofsensible judgment to be absurd: and mus aesmetics, is a product ofcultural formation, an artefact. There
operating in me sensible and wimout dearly defined concepts, rationalism is taste only in a culture. For only he who, setting out as a natural being,
had argued, we do not comprehend objects but project our impressions and has been formed into a participant in a culture has acquired mat form of
preferences (and men immediately forget mat we merely projected). Good subjectivity wh ich is capable ofobjectivity. This is where me internal con­
taste, as La Rochefoucauld purs it in a maxim aimed against me rationalist nection between modern aesmetics and me disdplinary sodety becomes
reduction of me judgment of taste to a mere projection of preferences, is apparent. This connection consists in how bom conceive the subject. The
distinguishable from bad taste, good taste being mat taste which knows disdplinary procedures mat 'in me course of the seventeenm and eight­
'me real value of things': it 'teaches us: Jean-Baptiste Dubos says, 'how eenm centuries, [... ] became general formulas ofdomination' manifest me
someming is in itself'; it disdoses mings as mey truly are. 7 'subjection ofmose who are perceived as objects and me objectification of
Aesmetics, men, defines taste as me conjunction of two conflicting mose who are subjected:9 Disdplinary procedures exerdse sodal power in
elements: the form ofsubjectivity and me aspiration to objective validity. such fashion mat mey turn mose mey subject into subjects who are capable
Taste is a subjective faculty: an abilitymat has been acquired mrough prac­ and willing of meir own accord to render me services required of memo
tice and is merefore irreducible to rules, an ability me subject can applyon The addressees of disdplines do not obey instructions whose normative
its own responsibility, wimout me guidance oflived tradition or rational substance they cannot understand (mat is me traditional definition ofme
memod. In taste, me subject itselfjudges. And yet taste is at once an objec­ servant or slave). Instead, me addressees ofdisciplines can orient themselves
tive aumority: me ability to see mings as mey are in memselves wimout in accordance wim me norms whose implementation mey are required to
me dissembling veil ofprejudice and na'ivete. Taste judges me thing itself. perform; merein lies meir being 'subjects'. That is why procedures ofexercise I

It is not me reason of scientific memod but reason as aesmetic taste mat and examination stand at me centre ofme disciplinary society, procedures
lends me dearest expression to me bourgeois ideal ofautonomy. For to be through which individuals become subjects. The educational institutions
'autonomous' means to unite wimin oneselfme freedom ofself-governed mat are in charge of mis process come to play an utterly fundamental role
activitywim me normativity implied by me 'law' ofme ming itself. Because in me disciplinary society; education becomes me institution of institu­
aesmetic taste can meet this normative requirement wimout rdying on tion, me meta-institution. 10
external guidelines for orientation, and because it can comprehend me In other words, by describing me subject as somemingmat has become,
thing according to its own constitution and valence, it is the exemplary or more precisely, that has been made, aesthetics merely repeats me new
autonomous agency. S

6 Jean-Bapriste Dubos, Rijlexions critiques sur la poesie et sur la peinture 11 (Genf: 9 Michel Foucault, Überwachen undStrafon: Die Geburtdes Gefängnisses (Frankfurt/M.:
Slatkine Reprints, 1967), 368. Suhrkamp, 1977),176 and 2.38. (With the formulation 'subjektivierende Unterwerfung'
7 La Rochefoucauld, 'Reflexions diverses' X, in CEuvres compu.~tes (Paris: Gallimard [subjectifying subjection] the German translation reflects the ambiguity ofFollcault's
1964), 517; Dubos, Rijlexions critiques, 343-4. concept of'assujettissement: CE ibid, 137 and 185.)
8 Taste is without laws, but not without Law: taste conforms without law - or rather ro Every institution in the disdplinary sodety is also an edllcational institution: the

without submitting itself to Iaw - tO the law of objecrivity. institution first produces the subjects that then are able co enter into sociery.

188 CHRISTOPH MENKE A Different Taste: Neithcr Autonomy nor Mass Consumption 18 9

sodal reality ofdisdplinary domination. l l Aesthetics is a theory and prac­ in the scene ofdisciplination. The aesthetic subject is the effortless subject:
tice of the procedures of subjectivation - of exerdse, of the heightening the subject to which its being a subject is natural; that did not need to first
and co ordination of forces, of examination that constitute the core of be made a subject but, even though it was first exercised and educated,
the sodal disdpline. Without the very sodal procedures that engender a appears as though it were or seems to be - a subject 'ofitself'. The aesthetic
sodal subject by way of the internalization of sodal norms, there would subject is the semblance of the subject; the aesthetic subject is ideologi­
13
be no aesthetic taste either. And yet aesthetic taste and hence the aesthetic cal, and the aesthetic ideology is the ideology of the subject. Aesthetics,
subject, are in one crudal regard antithetical to the faculties ofself-control as a theory and practice, means: aestheticization ofdisdpline. Not before,
that constitute the subject of the disdplines: in the disdplinary subject, and only in, the aesthetic subject of taste does the teleology of the disd­
the prehistory ofits disdplinary training remains inscribed in perennially plinary society - to make the heteronomy of disdplination disappear in
legible form. As a disdplinary subject it orients itself in accordance with the autonomous self-disdplination of subjects co me to fulfilment. The
the norms defined by the institutions in which it participates. Yet subject ofaesthetic taste is the epitome of the bourgeois idea ofautonomy
self-governance always retains the recollection ofthe heteronomous scene because autonomy exists only in aesthetic semblance.
of disciplination in which this faculty was first acquired. In the aesthetic That renders the beautiful, with its 'felicitous irregularity', the exem­
subject, by contrast, the prehistory oHts disdpHnary training has been Iefi: plary object of taste. 14 True, the domain of taste is much wider than the
behind forgotten or repressed. The way aesthetics portrays it in its con­ field of aesthetically beautiful or sublime things: it comprises everything
cept oftaste, the aesthetic subject not onIy orients itself in accordance with for whose cognition there is as yet no concept, whose assessment is not
sodal norms. It also does so in such a fashion that any difference between yet subject to any rule. The domain oftaste is a field that is expanding ever
what it is of itself and what the sodal norm wants from it seems to have more rapidly in the bourgeois sodety: the field ofthe unknown. Bourgeois
been effaced altogether. The aesthetic subject has entirely transformed its society needs taste in order to comprehend all those unfamiliar forms of
sensible forces into faculties oHts own: by developing fully and in compiete behaviour and objects with which it confronts the individual. Within this
freedom, its sensible forces agree of their own accord with the legal form field, the beautiful is not only an unusual case but also, and predsely there­
ofthe sodal norms 12 to which theywere subject to as an external compulsion fore, a comforting one. The beautiful as an object of taste is at once also ! i

the medium in which the aesthetic subject assures itself oHts possibility. In
the beautiful, taste becomes consdous ofitself: the taste for the beautiful
1I The connection between aesthetics and disciplinary society is so dose that Foucault assures the aesthetic subject that the labour ofeducation can succeed, that
could take the fundamental caregories ofhis theory ofthe disdplinary subject direccly the form of subjectivity and the aspiration to objective validity are capa­
from the programmatic writings ofthe emerging aesthetic disdpline, especially from
ble of a perfect union. The aesthetic taste for the beautiful is not merely
Baumgarten's Aesthetica. For more on this see Christoph Menke, 'Die Disziplin
der Ästhetik: Eine Lektüre von Überwachen und Strafen: in Gertrud Koch, Sylvia
an espedally cultivated and refined sort oftaste, it is the taste for taste. In
Sasse and Ludger Schwarte, eds, Kumt als Strafe: Zur Asthetik der Disziplinierung takingpleasure in the beautiful, the subject takes pleasure in the perfeetion
(Munich: Wilhelm Fink 2.003), 109-:tl; 'Zweierlei Übung: Zum Verhältnis von of its self-education: an education in whose course all heteronomy, which
sozialer Disziplinierung und ästhetischer Existenz', in Axel Honneth and Martin
Saar, eds,MichelFoucault: Zwischenbilanz einerRezeption (Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp,
2.0 0 3), 28 3-99.
12 For more on this description oftaste see Kant, Kritik der Urteilskrafi;, § 35, B 145-6. 13 See Terry Eagleton, Tbe Ideology ofthe Aesthetic (Oxford: Wiley, 1990), Ch. I.
In the aesthetic harmony between the sensuousness of'imagination' and the sodal 14 Cf. Paul de Man,DieJdeologie des Ästhetischen, cd. by Christoph Menke (Frankfurt/M.:
norms of'reason: Kant reformulates Baumgarten's ideal offelix acstheticus. Suhrkamp, 1993), Part I.
'I
:;1 '

19° CHRISTOPH MENKE A DijJerent Taste: Neither Autonomy nor ldass Consumption 19 1

defines the sodal existence of the disciplinary subject, has been sublated. with relation to which these commodities are to possess 'use value'17 in the
'Beautiful things: Kant writes, are evidence 'that man fits into the world: 15 system ofmass consumption are thus 'cultural' needs in an eminent sense:
theyare not just artificially generated but ofthemselves directed toward the
meaning that the commodity and the possession ofit are said to have. Mass
consumption accordingly does not just presuppose mass culture; rather,
Consumerism the systems of mass consumption and mass culture are identical. 18 In this
system, the economic consumer is thus essentially a cultural participant:
he needs taste. Ifthe mass-consumerist economy entails the unprecedented
The aesthecic of taste is tied to the contemporaneous emergence ofbour­ acceleration of the production of forever new commodities, their recep­
geois sodety; aesthetics supplies that society's disciplinary subjectivation don conversely requires a no less drastically heightened flexibility and
with the ideal ofautonomy: ofa subjectivity that can be purely self-govem­ enthusiasm for noveltyon the part ofthe consumer's faculty ofjudgment.
ing because it is capable offorming itself. This ideal ofautonomy is realized What the consumerist taste accomplishes is a new conjunccion ofcrea­
onIy in aesthetic semblance, but it is precisely therein that it constitutes don and adaptation. The consumerist taste is as creative as it is adaptive:
the sodal reality in which the disciplinary subject appears as the 'citizen'. it is adaptive by virtue of its creativity. The economy defined by mass con­
The subjectivity of the bourgeois citizen is made by social disciplination sumption continually produces commodities co satisfy needs that cannot
and yet capable ofobjectively comprehending the qualities and valences of even exist yet. That is what is called here 'innovation': going beyond what
things. In the citizen's taste, social disciplination is transmuted into objec­ is already known to be needed. And so production engenders what, by
tivityfreelyundertaken. Taste as aesthetic ideology is required so that the past and current standards, is pointless and useless: what is the human
disdplinary subject, as the cicizen, can believe itselfcapable ofan (objective) being of 2006 supposed to be able to do with the iPhone, a device that,
understanding ofits world based purelyon its own (subjective) judgment. Time magazine declared, was 'the invention of 200i? It is ofno use to hirn
In today's post-disdplinary capitalism/6 taste presents a vety differ­ until he has transformed hirnself into someone else: into someone who is 1'1
ent figure and serves an encirely different funccion: taste now becomes the equal to the presence of this device. Its producers bet on the creative per­
decisive precondition for mass consumption. 'Mass consumption' is not formance of consumers who, guided by advertisements and the culture
merely a quantitative term, describing the consumption oflarger amounts industry, in the first place engender those standards and the needs directed
ofcommodities by larger groups ofconsumers. Rather, 'mass consumpcion' toward their attainment that are a match for this device. Because this crea­
means that the central aim and motor ofeconomic activity is the mass pro­ tive performance of taste has become, in mass-consumerist capitalism, an
duccion ofcommodities that serve solely to satisfy needs that were generated
in the first place specifically for and by these same commodities. The needs
17 That, for this reason, the differentiation between use and value becomes
itselfproblematic is also the thesis in Theodor W. Adorno, 'Über den Fetischcharakter
IS Immanucl Kant, 'Handschriftlicher Nachlass: Logik', Akademie-Ausgabe vol. 16, der Musik und die Regression des Hörens: in Dissonanzen. Musik in der verwalteten
Berlin: Reimer, 1914, 1:1.7 [Nr. 18:1.0 aJ), <http://korpora.zim.uni-duisburg-essen. U0lt (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1969), 9-4S. According to Zygmunt
de/kant/aaI6/> accessed 1 April :1.OIS. Bauman's terminological suggestion this constitutes the difference between consump­
16 For more on this characterization see Gilles Deleuze, 'Post-scriptum sur les sodetes don and consumerism. CE Bauman, Consuming Lift (Cambridge, MA:
de controle' [Postscript on the Societies ofControl], inL'autrejournall (199 0 ) Polity Press, 2.007), :1.5-SI.
<http:/hlibertaire.free.fr/DeleuzePostScriptum.html> accessed 3]anuary 2.014. 18 Michael Makropoulous, Theorie der Massenkultur (Munich: Wilhelm Fink, 2.008).
I92. CHRISTOPH MENKl! /I Different Taste: Neither Autonom] nor Mass Consumption I93

essential precondition for its ongoing operation, taste has shed all aspects thing fit into my life? Or rather: which life fits this thing? And how does
of the sodal privilege that aesthetically good taste, despite its aspiration the life that fits this new thing fit my old life? How do I have to change my
to universalizability, still implied. 19 Taste is as widespread in the system life, to redefine and reinvent my life, so that this new thingwi11fit into it,
of mass-consumerism as the role of the consumer. Taste has accordingly or that I can make myself fit for this new thing? The harmonious mutual
become commonplace. It is no longer concerned only with the beautiful between the human being and the thing, of which the aesthetic taste
sides of life, but now with life in its entirety. At this moment, all oflife assured itself in the pleasure it took in the beautiful, is transformed into
is beautiful: there is no commodity that does not have its beautiful (or the continual effort to be fit for, and to adapt to, forever novel products.
less beautiful) side, no commodity whose consumption does not call for With all its creativity, the consumerist faculty oftaste pursues a single aim,
a judgment of taste. And so in contemporary capitalism, taste is also no to ensure the subject's fitness: pure self-preservation.
longer something anyone could take pride in: everyone has (or must have) Many observers have noted and lamented that 'self-preservation' in this
taste. Indeed, despite the pride which the new bourgeois take in their own sense cannot mean the realization or fulfilment of a self that, by virtue
'good taste', often hard-won against their petit-bourgeois backgrounds, it meaningful continuity oHts judgments, appears CO itself and others as
is precisely the avant-gardes of mass-consumerism, lusting after the day's identical to itself (and that consumerist mass culture talks so much about
newest product, who have the most highly developed faculty oftaste. They 'self-fulfilment' only because no fulfilment of the self in any demanding
perform the ongoing labour ofgiving meaning to what is meaningless by sense in fact takes place): ehe consumerist taste is the creativity of adap­
inventingcriteria bywhich to judge the new product. tation, which no longer has the resources to worry over such questions
At the same time, this heightening ofcreativity that distinguishes the of meaning and continuity; it is the expression of infinite flexibility.20
consumerist from the bourgeois taste serves the principle of adaptation. Yet it is important to note that the consumerist subject does not suffer
Taste is the faculty ofchoosing: it judges and thus prefers one to the other, chis 'corrosion ofcharacter' as Richard Sennett called it in the tide ofhis
slights the other in favour of the one. Like, and even more fundamentally book; on the contrary, it perflrms this corrosion. '[T]he playing down and
than, aesthetic taste before it, consumerist taste cannot rely on criteria that derogation of yesterday's needs and the ridicule and uglification of their
are already defined as it assesses products. It must first develop the criteria objects, now passes, and even more the discrediting of the very idea that
that wi11fit these products - it must creatively invent them. Yet unlike the consuming life ought to be guided by the satiifaction ofneeds'21: all these are
bourgeois-aesthetic taste, the consumerist taste does not seek to find these things the consumerist subject does itself, by virtue of its faculty of taste.
criteria in the things at hand; it instead looks to the practices and lifestyles Flexibility i8 the service it renders. And it does so for the one reason for
into which things are supposed to fit. It is not the things themselves but such which services are rendered in capitalism: in order to seIl them. The sole
relations offittingness that concern the mass-consumerist taste: does this

:tO Cf. Richard Sennett, Ihe Corrosion ofCharacter: Ihe Personal Consequences ofWOrk in
19 The acsthetic regime oftaste does not tolerate the originally proclaimed openness oHts the New Capitalism (New York: Notton, 1998), eh. 5. - For a more precise determina­
criteria in its sodal reality and '[die] so überzeugend vorgetragene Theorie rekurriert tion ofthe contemporary, sodoeconomic form ofcreativity as weH as its economic­
schließlich doch wieder aufSchichtung' [the (thus) convindngly presented theory aesthetic pre-history, see Ulrich Bräckling 'Über Kreativität. Ein Brainstorming: and
refers back to stratification]. Niklas Luhmann, 'Individuum, Individualität, Dieter Thomä, ~sthetische Freiheit zwischen Kreativität und Exstase: Überlegungen
Individualismus', Gesellschaftsstruktur und Semantik 3 (Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, zum Spannungsfeld zwischen Ästhetik und Ökonomik: both in Christoph Mcnke
I993), wS· Bourdieu's analyses refer co the mechanisms through which 'good' taste and Juliane Rebentisch, eds, Kreation und Depression, 89-97 and 149-70.
is defined as 'our' taste. 21 Bauman, ConsumingLift, 99.
194
CHRISTOPH MENKE A Dijferent Taste: Neither Autonomy nor Mass Consumption 195

purpose ofconsumption is to be capable ofbeing consumed _ to become


consumable: 'Members o/the society o/consumers are themselves consumer
Counter-taste
commodities [... J. Becoming and remaininga sellable commodity is rhe most
potent motive ofconsumer concerns.'22 In orher words, rhe social mean­
There are socioeconomic causes behind rhis transformation of rhe bour­
ing ofconsumerist taste, unlike rhat ofaesrhetic taste, no longer consists
geois-aesrhetic taste into rhe consumerist taste, but also cultural and intel­
in rhe ideological transfiguration ofdiscipline into autonomy. Its social
lectual ones. This second set ofcauses was at rhe centre of rhe debate over
meaning is instead immediately economic: it serves rhe 'recommoditiza­
postmodernism. For rhe rheories of postmodernism were rhe first ones,
tion' (Zygmunt Bauman's term) ofrhe subject, its self-representaoon and
self-advertisement as a commodity to be bought and used by orhers. As a since rhe bourgeois aesrhetics of the eighteenrh century, to focus again
on rhe concept of taste: rheyare apologies of rhe consumerist taste. 24 This
commodity, rhe subject is rhe commodity oflabour: by being a competent
apology is articulated in rhe name ofaesrhetic freedom: in rhe postmodern
participant in mass consumption as mass culture, rhe subject acquires, and
reading, rhe transformation of rhe bourgeois into rhe consumerist taste is
shows rhat it possesses, rhe very abilities - rhe creativity of adaptation _
an unleashing of its true aesrhetic potential - an act of 'aesrheticization':
rhat render its Iabour a commodity rhat is in demand. 23 In rhis fashion, rhe
only when taste, formerly a bourgeois privilege, becomes an egalitarian
consumerist subject reveals itself to be post-disciplinary: ifrhe disciplinary
possession of rhe masses, rhis interpretation argues, does it become truly
society defined commercially useful abilities in institution-specific ways (so
creative; only rhen does it truly break free, as its conception in aesrhetics
rhat rhe acquisition ofa given ability at once also entailed rhe certainty rhat
had already promised, from all predetermined ruIes and standards.
rhe subject would find its lifelong horne in rhe respective institution), rhese
The culture industry's control ofaesrhetic freedom and rhe fimctional
abilities now consist in rhe unspecific or meta-ability offlexible adaptation.
role it plays in capitalist exploitation belie its postmodern praise. Yet post­
The subject who can do rhat - which is to say, who can do anyrhing _ is

modernism remains right to reject rhe nostalgie apology ofbourgeois taste


marketable as rhe commodity ofits labour. And taste is where rhe subject

exercises and exhibits rhis ability.


as a faculty of autonomy. For rhere is a good reason for rhe demise of rhe
bourgeois taste in mass consumerism, a reason rhat blocks rhe return to
it: rhe bourgeois taste is false; rhe identity it asserts between rhe form of
subjectivity and rhe claim to objective validity is an ideological subreption.
When rhis taste comprehends rhings as rhey objectively are, it takes credit
for rhis success as being rhe fruit of its own subjective effort,25 which it

24 This is most clear in the programmatic writings ofarchitectural theory (Charies Jencks,
22 Bauman, ConsumingLift, S7. Robert Venturi) that oppose postlIlodernity to an elitist modernity in the name of
the 'popular'. Cf. Christoph Menke, 'Aporien der kulturellen Moderne' [Aporias of
23 Provided that 'dignity' characterizes the quaHtythatthe (bourgeois-autonomous) sub­
Cultural Modernity], in Hauke Brunkhorst, Regina Kreide, and Cristina Lafont,
;A~' ~._;.,< as it portrays its individual identity beyond its disdplinarily authenticated
eds,Habermas-Handbuch (Stuttgart: Metzler, 2009), 205-14.
institutional roIes, the formallyextrasodal performance ofdignity now becomes, in
2.5 What Kant says about the taste for beauty also applies to the bourgeois faculty of
postdisdplinaty society, the actual determination oflabour as commodity. Conversely,
taste in general: 'We can easily see that, in order for me to say that an object is beau­
this also means that the creation and maintenance oflabour now becomes an extra­
sodal, 'private' performance. tiJUl, and to prove that I have taste, what matters is what I do with this presentation
within myself. and not the [respect] in which I depend on the object's existence:
!~l
i

196 CHRISTOPH MENKE ..I Dijferent Taste: Neither Autonomy nor Mass Consumption 197

believes guarantees such success. The bourgeois subject performs this effort In light of this optimistic ideology of cultivation, wh ich defincs the
in its 'operation of reflection: which it understands as a re-enactment of hourgeois taste, the consumerist taste would seem to be not so much a
that Iabour of formation that engendered it in the first place. 'Nowwe do postmodern progression toward aesthetic freedom but rather the result
this as folIows: we compare our judgment not so much with the actual as of a disillusionment for which there are very good reasons: the promise
rather with the merely possible judgments ofothers, and put ourselves in oF the bourgeois model of taste that the subject's own reflection can form
the position of everyone else, merely by abstracting from the limitations taste into the authoritative source ofobjectivity has become implausible.
that happen to attach to our own judging'.26 In the work ofsubjectivation Pure reflection leads toward the 'precipice of bottomless profundity', a
28
associated with disciplination, comparing the subject's own judging to profundity that 'things, in the simplicity of their essence', elude. Yet the
that of the other and sloughing offits crudeness until it had become like disconsolate conclusion that the consumerist taste draws from this disil­
the other's, and hence ostensibly objective, was done by others and from lusioned insight merely replaces the aspiration to objectivity undertaken
outside the subject. Now taste is to accomplish the same oHts own accord by the subject, which the success ofa flexible adaptation ofthe consrunerist
and byvirtue oHts own faculty, in the operation oHts reflection.This free subject, in keepingwith the postmodern ist program, glorifies into aesthetic­
repetition of the work ofdisciplination by power ofself-reflection consti­ creative self-fulfilment: consumerist taste is not about comprehending
tutes the autonomy of taste: it proceeds soIely in accordance with its own objects as they themselves are, but rather about performingthe ever more
law, which enables it tocomprehend things in themselves. 27 demanding feats ofadaptation required, under conditions ofaccelerating
change, to attain the status of a consrunable commodity and to shore up
the illusion of an identity engaged in self-fulfilment. This double care ­
for the subject's own consrunability and for its self-fulfilment - supersedes
Immanuel Kant, Critique ojJudgment, trans. Werner S. Pluhar (Indianapolis: Hackett the idea of truth whose unregulated-subjective comprehension had been
Publishing, 1987), 46. at issue in aesthetic taste.
26 Kant, Critique offudgment, § 40, B 157, trans. Pluhar, 160.
***
27 It also holds true for consumerist taste that it 'ultimately rests on individual per­
Is there a conclusion to be drawn from the disintegration of bourgeois
fOrmanceS. The exercise of taste is a 'task that must be individually undertaken and
resolved with the help ofconsumer skills and patterns ofaction individually obtained]. taste that would be different hom consumerist taste (and its postmodernist
Bauman, ConsumingLift, 75. What differentiates consumerist taste from bourgeois theory)? Is there a different taste? A different taste can emerge only from
taste is that the latter's personal contribution consisted in the free repetition ofsocial the force with which taste turns against itself. Adorno weites:
disciplination, whereas consumerist society demands that the subject itselfturns itself
into a subject, becomes his own creator. What constitutes the post-disciplinarychar­
acter ofconsumerist taste is the ability to participate socially. Thus, the marketable
labour is no longer produced by those institutions which then consume it as it was
the case in the disciplinary society, instead, in today's mass consumerist society the
performance ofsubjectification-through-socialization is privatized. It is Ws paradox­
whose resolution overstrains everyone through which mass-consumerist sOciety
also produces mass depression. See Alain Ehrenberg, 'Depression: Unbehagen in requirements completely enough in order to become 'universal' and therefore capa­
der Kultur oder neue Formen der Sozialität: Texte zur Kunst 65 (2007),57-65. The ble ofobjectivity.
desperation of the mass-consumerist subject in the face of the impossible task of 28 Walter Benjamin, 'Ursprung des deutschen Trauerspiels: in Gesammelte Schriften VII I
producing its labour as a consurnable commodity replaces the unanswerable doubt of (Frankfurt1M.: Suhrkamp, 1974), 402-3, trans. Jackson. Cf. Walter Benjamin, The
the bourgeois subject oftaste as to whether or not it has appropriated the disciplinary Origin ofGerman Tragic Drama, trans. John Osborne (London: Verso, 200 3), 23 1•
198 CHRISTOPH MENKE A Different Taste: Neither Autonomy nor Mass Consumption 199

Taste is the most accurate seismograph ofhistorical experience. Unlike almost all
thetic force; me idea mat taste is indeed intrinsically antagonistic: it is
other faculties, it is even able to register its own behavior. Reacting againSt itself, it
recognizes its own lack oftaste. [... ] It is precisely the nerves most highly-developed
always already busy examining its imaginations in a reRective operation and
aesthetically that now find self-righteous aestheticism intolerable.29 recovering mem by supplying reasons and tuming mem into judgments
omers share for reasons. That is what elicits me 'repugnance' (Adomo) felt
Silvia Bovenschen explains: by taste as force: me force is me counter-will, me will against me will to
control me imaginations of taste in an operation of reRection. The force
By performing this idiosyncratic reaction against itself, taste can become a sort of oftaste expresses itself as 'impression soudaine' or 'sentiment subit'33 as a
aesthetic conscience. If taste guides the idiosyncrasies, the latter are conversely con­
sudden and unexpected sensation mat, abrupdy bursting form, disrupts
stitutive oftaste; theyare in a process ofinfinite one-upmanship - the other side
oftaste, ensuring that it does not degenerate into rule or diktat. 30 me steady progress of reRection and renders me subject incapable ofpro­
ceeding based on reason. And it is precisely mereby mat me force of taste
When taste turns against itself, it implies a break with me subject's cer­ makes possible for me subject what me subject cannot do by means ofits
tainty mat the reRective repetition of its disciplinary socialization will own faculty: to be open to me thing itself.The relation oftaste to me ming
render it free and capable ofcomprehending mings as meyare of its own has its locus exacdy where me two aspects it joins in an aporetic union of
accord. This break is an intervention of me 'nerves'; it is fed by me 'repug­ mutual repugnance collide.
nance for all artistic subjectivism: 31 Taste turns against itself, as a faculty The passion of taste is me individual at his core, me 'most particular'
of autonomous subjectivity, by virtue of me fact mat it is force - passion singularity mat defines him, yet it remains forever alien to him because it
(pathos) or energy.That is me motifwhich me programmaticwritings on is here mat me individual transcends hirnself; mat me possibility opens
aesmetics, as it emerges in me eighteenm century, incessandy encircle, me before him to approach mings as mey are. It is by virtue ofwhat is most
motifwim which aesmetics itself turns, from me very outset, against me particular to hirn mat the individual is most objective: only me 'repug­
bourgeois model of taste mat Baumgarten delineated and Kant mought nance' of taste against its own 'subjectivism' enables taste to comprehend
mrough to its condusion. Aesmetics itself mus already contains me idea me ming. Anomer taste cannot emerge but where me subject does not rely
mat leads beyond me - false, bad contradiction pitting me bourgeois­ on its ability to live up to its aspiration to objectivity by means ofits own
autonomous taste against me consumerist-postmodem one. It is me idea reflective accomplishments, while on me omer hand me individual does
32
of me 'aporia of taste: mat taste is split into subjective faculty and aes­ not expend his creativity on performing accomplishments of adaptation.
Taste is what constitutes us; and for mis very reason, taste is what discloses
mings to us as mey are. A different taste begins wim me insight mat me
2.9 Theodor W. Adorno, Minima Mora/ta: Reflections}rom Damaged Lift, trans. unconditionality of trum is owed to aesmetic force.
E. F. N. Jephcott (London: 2.005). 145; Germ. orig. Minima Mora/ta:
Reflexionen aus dem beschädigten Leben (Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp 1978), 191• Translated from me German by Gereit Jackson
30 Silvia Bovenschen, Über-Empfindlichkeit. Spielformen der Idiosynkrasie
[Hypersensitivity: Variations ofIdiosyncrasy] (Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 2.000).
89. trallS. Jackson.
31 Adorno,MinimaMora/ta, 145: Germ. orig. Minima Mora/ta, 19 1.
32. Adorno, Minima Mora/ia, 146; Germ. orig. Minima Moralta, 192.. On the develop­
ment ofthis aporia (oftaste) in programmatic writings ofaesthetics cf. Menke. Power,
31 -47; Germ. orig. Kraft, 46-66. 33 Dubos, Rej!exions critiques, VI. II, 3+3-4·
2.00 CHRISTOPH MENKE A Different Taste: Neither Autonomy nor Mass Consumption 2.01

Bibliography Ehrenberg, Alain, 'Depression: Unbehagen in der Kultur oder neue Formen der Sozi­
alität' [Depression: Unease in Civilization or New Forms ofSocia!ityJ, Texte zur
Kunst 65 (2.007),
Foucault, Michel, Überwachen und Strafen. Die Geburt des Gefängnisses [Discipline
Adorno, Theodor W, 'Über den Fetischcharakter der Musik und die Regression des
and Punish: The Birth of the Prison] (Frankfurt /M.: Suhrkamp, 1977).
Hörens' [On the Fetish-Character in Music and the Regression
'Organisierte Selbstverwirklichung. Paradoxien der Individualisierung'
in Dissonanzen. Musik in der verwalteten Welt (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck &
vrganlzcd Self-Realization: Paradoxes oflndividualization], in Axel Honneth,
Ruprecht, 1969), 9-45.
Das Ich im "Wir. Studien zur Anerkennungstheorie (Berlin: Suhrkamp, 2.010),
- - , Minima Moralia: Reflexionen aus dem beschädigten Leben (Frankfurt/M.:
202.-21.
Suhrkamp 1978), 191.
Kant, Immanuel, 'Handschrifilkher Nachlass: Logik:Akademie-Ausgabe 16
- - , Minima Moralia: Reflections ftom Damaged Lift, trans. E. F. N. Jephcott
Reimer, 1914) <http://korpora.zim.uni-duisburg-essen.de/kantlaal6l> accessedl
(London: Verso, 200S), 145.
April 2.015.
Bauman, Zygmunt, Consuming Lift (Cambridge, MA: Polity Press, 2.007).
- - , Critique ojJudgment, trans. Werner S. Pluhar (lndianapolis: Hackett Publish­
Benjamin, Walter, 'Ursprung des deutschen Trauerspiels', in Gesammelte Schriften VLI
ing,19 87)·
(Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 1974), 402.-3.
- - , Kritik der Urteilskraft [Critique of the Power ofJudgment 1(Frankfurt/M.:
- - , The Origin 0/ German Drama, trans. John Osborne (London: Verso,
Suhrkamp, 1991).
2.00 3).
La Rochefoucauld, 'Reflexions diverses' X, in La Rochefoucauld, Oeuvres complües,
Boltanski, Luc, and Eve Chiapello, 'Die Arbeit der Kritik und der normative Wandel'
Paris 1964.
[The Work of Critique and the Normative Change], in Marion von
'Individuum, Individualität, Individualismus: Gesellschaftsstruk­
Norm der Abtueichung (Ziirich: Springer 2003),57-80.
tur und Semantik [The Structure of Society and Semantics13 (Frankfurt/M.:
Bourdieu, Pierre, Distinction: A Social Critique 0/theJudgment o/Taste (Cambridge,
Suhrkanlp,
MA: Harvard University Press, 1984).
Makropoulous, Michael, Theorie der Massenkultur (Munkh: Wilhelm Fink, 2.008).
Bovenschen, Silvia, Über-Empfindlichkeit. Spielformen der Idiosynkrasie [Hypersen­
Menke, Christoph, 'Die Disziplin der Ästhetik. Eine Lektiire von Überwachen und
sitivity: Variations ofIdiosyncrasy] (Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 2.000).
Strafen' [The Discipline ofAesthetics: A Reading of Discipline andPunishmentJ
Bröckling, Ulrich, 'Über Kreativität. Ein Brainstorming' [On Creativity: Brainstorm­
in Gertrud Koch, Sylvia Sasse and Ludger Schwarte, eds, Kunst als Strafe. Zur
ing] in Christoph Menke andJuliane Rebentisch, eds, Kreation und Depres­
Asthetik der Disziplinierung (Munich: Wilhelm Fink. 2.003), 109-2.1.
sion Kreation und Depression. Freiheit im gegenwärtigen Kapitalismus (Berlin:
- - , 'Subjekt, Subjektivität: in Karlheinz Barck et al., eds, Ästhetische Grundbe­
Kadmos, 2.OH), 149-70.
griffe. Historisches Wörterbuch in sieben Bänden V (Stuttgart and Weimar:
de Man, Paul,Die Ideologie desAsthetischen, ed. by Christoph Menke (Frankfurt /M.:
Metzler, 2.003), 734-87.
- - , 'Zweierlei Übung: Zum Verhältnis von sozialer Disziplinierung und ästhetischer
Deleuze, Gilles, 'Post-scriprum sur les societes de controle' [Postscript on the Socie­
Existenz' [Two Kinds ofExercise: On che Reladonship between Socia! Disciplina­
des of Control], 1
don and Aesthetic Existence], in Axd Honneth and Martin Saar, eds, MichelFou­
ePostScriptum.html> accessed 3January 2.014; German trans. as Gilles ucu::uzc,
cault: Zwischenbilanz einer Rezeption (Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 2003), 2.83-99.
'Postskriptum über die Kontrollgesellschaften: in Unterhandlungen. If}72-If}f}0
'Aporien der kulturellen Moderne', in Hauke Brunkhorst, Regina Kreide and
(Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 1993),2.54-62..
Cristina eds, Habermas-Handbuch (Stuttgart: Metzler, 2.009), 2.05-14.
Dubos, Jean-Baptiste, R4flexions critiques sur la poesie et sur la peinture II [Critical
- - , Kraft. Ein Grundbegriffästhetischer Anthropologie (Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp,
ReRections on Poetry and Painting] (Genf: Slamne Reprints, 1967).
2.008); Eng. trans. as Force: A Fundamental Concept 0/Aesthetic Anthropology
Eagleton, Terry, The Ideology 0/the Aesthetic (Oxford: Wiley, 1990).
(New York: Fordham University Press,
202.
CHRISTOPH MENKI!

"
Rebentisch, Juliane, Die Kunst der Freiheit. Zur Dialektik demokratischer Existtm~
KAM SHAPIRO
(The Art of Freedom - On the Dialectics of Democratic Existence] (Berlinl ".

Suhrkamp 2012.).
ir.
·.·I.
Reckwitz, Andreas, 'Vom KÜflstlermythos zur Normalisierung kreativer Prozesse, Biopolitical Reflections: Cognitive, Aesthetic :~
Der Beitrag des Kunstfelds zur Genese des Kreativsubjekts' (From Artist Myth r~
and Reflexive Mappings of Global Economies rfl
to the Normalization of Creative Processes: The Contribution of the Field of 'il
11
Art to the Genesis of the Creative Subject], in Christoph Menke andJulianc 11

Rebentisch, eds, Kreation undDepression. Freiheit imgegenwärtigen Kapitalismus


(Berlin: Kadmos, 2.ou), 98-1I7.
Sennett, Richard, The Corrosion ofCharacter: The Personal Consequences ofW'ork in
the New Capitalism (New York: Nonon, 199 8). We have associated new materialism with renewed attention to the dense
Thomä, Dieter, ~sthetische Freiheit zwischen Kreativität und Exstase. Überlegungen causes and eEfects ofglobal political economy and thus with questions of
zum Spannungsfeld zwischen Ästhetik und Ökonomik' (Aesthetic Freedolll social justice for embodied individuals.
11I
between Creativity and Ecstasy: Thoughts on the Held ofTension between - DIANA COOLE AND SAMANTHA FROST
Aesthetics and Economics], in Christoph Menke andJuliane Rebentisch, eds,
Kreation und Depression Kreation und Depression. Freiheit im gegenwärtigen It is not a question of eEfacing what can be fclt, but of multiplying the
Kapitalismus (Berlin: Kadmos, 2011), 89-97. powers ofproducing what can be fclt and making them intersect.
- JACQUES RANCIERE

Maps to me are tricl<y and insidious, and they've always fascinated mc.
- MARK BRADFORD

In this essay I reflect on FredricJameson's suggestion that 'an aesthetk of


cognitive mapping (ofsodal processes ] is an integral part of any sodalist
political project' in light of recent theories ofembodied cognition. I first
explore mappings of sodal processes in connection with popular media
accounts of the global economy ofcoltan (a metal used in consumer elec­
tronics). I then consider possibilities for a reflexive orientation to the pro­
cesses shaping such mappings. That is, I consider what happens when we try
to map the political economy ofour embodied and mediated perceptions
of political economies. Reflexive mapping of this kind leads quicldy to a
series oflimits and paradoxes. However, I argue that an encounter with
such limits comprises an important component of a materialist politics.
Moreover, I find encounters of this kind are also staged in popular media.
Insofar as this is the case, I condude, such media can contribute to what

S-ar putea să vă placă și