Sunteți pe pagina 1din 7

Deși cel mai probabil nu se gândea la rezonanță magnetică funcțională atunci când a avansat în Meditatii

despre filozofia prima ideea că mintea și corpul uman sunt două entități calitativ diferite, care pot exista
independent una de cealaltă, formulând astfel așa numitul dualism carterzian, René Descartes explora una
dintre dilemele centrale ale întrebărilor referitoare la natura umană. Deși preferată de mulți filosofi de-a
lungul secolelor, ideea că mintea sau sufletul funcționează independent de creier prezintă o serioasă
problemă epistemologică. Preferat intuitiv și în psihologia de simț comun, dualismul nu a reușit niciodată
în secolele care au urmat să explice în mod credibil corelația perfectă dintre funcționarea creierului și minte,
observată atât în neurologie și neurochirurgie, cât și ulterior în neuroimagistica cognitivă. Cu alte cuvinte,
dualismul nu poate explica de ce, dacă mintea și creierul sunt două entități diferite, atunci când una dintre
ele este afectată, cealaltă manifestă modificări observabile în timp real. Cu toate acestea, dualismul, fie și
implicit, rămâne modul de autopercepție preferat de majoritatea populației, precum și de o serie de școli de
gândire din filosofie și psihologie.
Problema explorării creierului in vivo, fără a aștepta rezultatele necroptice ale unor studii de caz particulare,
este în continuare una complicată din cel puțin patru puncte de vedere.
1.creierul este greu accesibil anatomic și fiziologic, fiind singurul organ închis în spatele cutiei
craniene.
2.este greu accesibil farmacologic, fiind protejat de o barieră hemato-encefalică, nu toate substanțele
administrate unui pacient ajungând automat la creier.
3.este singurul organ care controlează direct conștiința și personalitatea umană, iar ca urmare, de-a
lungul secolelor, studiul și concluziile care se puteau trage despre funcționarea sa au fost constrânse
politic. În cazul particular al lui Descartes, faptul că pedeapsa cu moartea pentru blasfemie era
oricând posibilă pentru scrieri care nu conveneau ideologic Bisericii Catolice amintește că aparentele
concluzii filosofice sau științifice au fost deseori condiționate de presiuni politice sau socio-economice.
4.chiar și atunci când toate cele trei condiții de mai sus nu mai reprezintă impedimente, creierul
rămâne unul dintre cele mai complexe sisteme cunoscute vreodată umanității, datele obținute din
studierea lui fiind extrem de complicat de interpretat productiv.
Deși electroencefalografia exista încă din anii 20, aceasta era limitată la înregistrări restrânse din punct de
vedere spațial, având în vedere că putea face înregistrări electrofiziologice numai la nivelul scalpului. Abia
în anii ‘70 Tomografia computerizată și rezonanța magnetică nucleară au fost de asemenea descoperiri
monumentale în istoria neuroimagisticii, pentru care s-au câștigat mai multe premii Nobel, atât în medicină,
cât și în fizică, aceste metode erau mai relevante diagnosticului neurologic, fiind metode exclusiv de
investigație structurală (anatomică). Tomografia cu emisie de pozitron necesita iradierea pacienților cu
trasoare radioactive scumpe, așa că abia la începutul anilor 90, atunci când rezonanța magnetică nucleară a
putut fi adaptată pentru înregistrarea fluxului sangvin din creier în timp real, neuroimagistica a devenit
relevantă pentru psihologie. Deși a produs un entuziasm major atât în psihologia cognitivă, cât și în
psihiatrie, rezonanța magnetică nucleară funcțională s-a dovedit a avea limite metodologice evidente
imediat, apariția unor tipare de activitate hemodinamică fiind mai dificil de corelat cu activitatea
psihologică decât se sperase inițial.
Mara Mather, psiholog interesat de emoție și memori de la University of Southern California, explorează
alături de John Cacciopo, de la University of Chicago, unul dintre cei mai importanți psihologi sociali și
fondator al neuroștiinței sociale și de Nancy Kanwisher, neurobiolog la MIT, unul dintre cei mai prolifici
cercetători din neuroimagistica cognitivă, câteva din limitele și întrebările la care rezonanța magnetică
nucleară funcțională poate răspunde pentru psihologie.
Perspectives on Psychological Science

How fMRI Can Inform Cognitive Theories 8(1) 108­–113


© The Author(s) 2013
Reprints and permission:
sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav
DOI: 10.1177/1745691612469037
http://pps.sagepub.com

Mara Mather1, John T. Cacioppo2, and Nancy Kanwisher3


1
University of Southern California, 2University of Chicago, and 3Massachusetts Institute of Technology

Abstract
How can functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) advance cognitive theory? Some have argued that fMRI can do little
beyond localizing brain regions that carry out certain cognitive functions (and may not even be able to do that). However, in this
article, we argue that fMRI can inform theories of cognition by helping to answer at least four distinct kinds of questions.Which
mental functions are performed in brain regions specialized for just that function (and which are performed in more general-
purpose brain machinery)? When fMRI markers of a particular Mental Process X are found, is Mental Process X engaged when
people perform Task Y? How distinct are the representations of different stimulus classes? Do specific pairs of tasks engage
common or distinct processing mechanisms? Thus, fMRI data can be used to address theoretical debates that have nothing to
do with where in the brain a particular process is carried out.

Keywords
fMRI, neuroimaging, cognitive theory, cognition

The goal of cognitive psychology is to develop and test theo- below, localization findings have also been used in many cre-
ries about how the mind works. In this commentary, we ative ways to test other hypotheses about cognition.
address the question of how fMRI can be used to help psy-
chologists understand cognition. We start by putting forth our Question 2: Can markers of Mental Process X be found
own views: that fMRI can inform theories about cognition by during Task Y?
helping to answer at least four distinct questions.
From the perspective of some cognitive psychologists, the
Question 1: Which (if any) functions can be localized to focus of initial fMRI research on localization did not appear to
specific brain regions? provide information about how the mind worked (for a review,
see Shimamura, 2010). For instance, Uttal (2001) argues that,
Coltheart (2013, this issue) argues that, “we do not have “Even if we could associate precisely defined cognitive func-
any evidence showing that any particular form of brain activa- tions in particular areas of the brain (and this seems highly
tion is a sign that some particular type of cognitive operation unlikely), it would tell us very little if anything about how the
is being performed” (p. 100). The degree to which the brain is brain computes, represents, encodes, or instantiates psycho-
composed of modules that each carry out a specific aspect of logical processes” (Uttal, 2001, p. 217).
cognition or of components that each participate in many dif- But to say that neuroimaging answers only the “where”
ferent processes has been hotly debated for years (for a review, questions is to confuse the superficial format of raw neuroim-
see Kanwisher, 2010). However, some cortical regions aging data with the content of the questions those data can
respond selectively to certain categories of visual stimuli (for answer; Neuroimagers collecting fMRI data need no more
instance, the fusiform face area, the parahippocampal place restrict themselves to “where” questions than cognitive psy-
area [PPA], and the extrastriate body area; Downing, Chan, chologists measuring reaction times need limit themselves to
Peelen, Dodds, & Kanwisher, 2006). This category selectivity “when” questions.
bears directly on one of the basic tasks of cognitive psychol- Indeed, looking back over the past two decades of work
ogy, which is to come up with an inventory of dissociable using fMRI, one can see that an initial focus on brain mapping
mental processes. Thus, the finding that a given cortical provided a critical foundation for the field that allowed it to go
region is selectively engaged in a particular mental process
can be informative not because it tells us the location of that
Corresponding Author:
process (why would a psychologist care?), but because it sug- Mara Mather, University of Southern California, 3715 McClintock Ave, Los
gests that the brain, and hence the mind, contains specialized Angeles, CA 90089
mechanisms for that particular mental process. As reviewed E-mail: mara.mather@usc.edu

Downloaded from pps.sagepub.com at Scientific library of Moscow State University on January 4, 2014
fMRI and Cognitive Theories 109

beyond “where” questions to address “how” questions. To the & Tong, 2005), the movement direction in a field of dots
extent that highly specialized brain regions are discovered, (Kamitani & Tong, 2006), the semantic category of a word (T.
and their functional specialization well established,1 activity in M. Mitchell et al., 2004), the category of object (e.g., animals,
these regions can serve as markers for specific cognitive func- cars, planes), and in some cases even the exemplar of a cate-
tions, enabling us to ask whether and to what extent Mental gory (e.g., cows, frogs, turtles; Cichy, Chen, & Haynes, 2011).
Process X is engaged in Task Y. For example, by showing For instance, representations of scenes in the PPA (Epstein &
people a series of scenes and faces and asking them to remem- Kanwisher, 1998) have been shown to encode the layout of
ber one type of stimuli and ignore the other during a retention space in a scene (Kravitz, Peng, & Baker, 2011; Park, Brady,
interval, researchers tested the hypothesis that people suppress Greene, & Olivia, 2011), and to generalize across photographs
mental representations of distracting, to-be-ignored stimuli and line drawings of scenes (Walther, Chai, Caddigan, Beck,
(Gazzaley, Cooney, McEvoy, Knight, & D’Esposito, 2005) & Fei-Fei, 2011), whereas representations in the early visual
and that older adults show less suppression of the distracting cortex encode distance, and neither encode conceptual or
stimuli (Gazzaley, Cooney, Rissman, & D’Esposito, 2005). In semantic information about scenes (Kravitz et al., 2011). In
this study, activity in the fusiform face area (for faces) or the contrast, the lateral occipital cortex encodes information about
PPA (for scenes) was used as a signal of enhancement or sup- the content of scenes, such as whether it is an urban or natural
pression of processing that type of stimuli. setting (Park et al., 2011).
Another example comes from work testing the hypothesis Probing these types of representations can also address
that objects are the units of attentional selection rather than theoretical questions about the structure of cognitive pro-
locations or features (O’Craven, Downing, & Kanwisher, cesses. For instance, one study tested the hypothesis that infor-
1999). In O’Craven et al.’s study, each stimulus in a sequence mation in working memory is maintained by the same sensory
consisted of a face transparently superimposed on a house, regions that process those stimuli when they are first perceived
with either the face or the house moving. Participants had to (Serences, Ester, Vogel, & Awh, 2009). This study showed
monitor either repetitions in faces or houses or the direction of participants colored grating patterns and asked them to either
motion. Attending to one attribute of an object (e.g., the motion remember the color or the grating orientation over a 10-s
of a house) enhanced activity not only in the region special- delay. When participants were trying to remember the color,
ized for that attribute (e.g., the medial temporal and medial multivariate pattern analyses were able to classify the color
superior temporal cortex for motion) but also in the region but not the orientation of the stimulus being maintained based
specialized for its other attribute (e.g., the PPA for houses) on activity in primary visual cortex during the delay period. In
compared against the other object’s attributes. These results contrast, when participants were trying to remember the orien-
provide evidence for object-based attention and argue against tation, the orientation could be classified but the color could
locations or features being the unit of selection. not. These results suggest that the sustained stimulus-specific
patterns in the primary visual cortex reflect active mainte-
Question 3: How distinct are the representations of dif- nance in working memory. These and other fMRI data chal-
ferent stimuli or tasks? lenge models that assume that working memory requires
dedicated buffers or storage sites (for a review, see D’Esposito,
One of the central tasks of cognitive psychology is the 2007).
characterization of mental representations. The crux of the
characterization of a mental representation is the specification Question 4: Do two Tasks X and Y engage common or
of its invariant and equivalence classes: Which entities are distinct processing mechanisms?
treated the same, and which are treated differently? A repre-
sentation common to two different viewpoints of an object is A fourth way that fMRI can inform cognition does not
an invariant representation of object shape, whereas a repre- require any commitment to, or prior finding of, strong func-
sentation that is common to the word “dog” and a picture of a tional specificity of a particular region of the brain. Specifi-
dog is an abstract semantic representation. This is the funda- cally, fMRI provides a natural way to ask one of the classic
mental logic behind priming methods in cognitive psychology questions of cognitive psychology: Do two Tasks X and Y
and looking-time methods in cognitive development research. engage common or distinct processing mechanisms? If con-
fMRI has two methods that follow the same basic logic, ducted properly, experiments showing overlapping brain acti-
enabling us to characterize neural representations in particular vation for the two tasks, with appropriate control conditions
brain regions by asking which stimuli are treated as different and within individual subjects, can provide evidence for com-
and which are treated the same: fMRI adaptation (Grill-Spec- mon mechanisms. For example, one study found common
tor & Malach, 2001) and fMRI multivariate pattern analysis brain regions engaged across diverse forms of visual attention
(Haxby, 2012; Norman, Polyn, Detre, & Haxby, 2006). (Wojciulik & Kanwisher, 1999), suggesting that these diverse
Multivariate pattern analysis is sensitive enough to decode attentional phenomena have more in common than their name.
differences in the visual stimuli being viewed, such as the ori- Conversely, other studies have shown that distinct mecha-
entation of a striped pattern (Haynes & Rees, 2005; Kamitani nisms are engaged in high-level language processing but not in

Downloaded from pps.sagepub.com at Scientific library of Moscow State University on January 4, 2014
110 Mather et al.

deductive logic (Monti, Parsons, & Osherson, 2009), algebra 2011 in eight journals found that most (89%) of the studies
(Monti, Parsons, & Osherson, 2012), or other cognitive phe- aimed to localize cognitive processes whereas 11% aimed to
nomena including music (Fedorenko, Behr, & Kanwisher, test a theory of cognition (Tressoldi, Sella, Coltheart, &
2011; Fedorenko, McDermott, Norman-Haignere, & Kan- Umilta, 2012). Tressoldi et al. argued that, of those studies that
wisher, in press), thus demonstrating powerful dissociations aimed to test a cognitive theory, around half committed the
between language and (many aspects of) thought. Another consistency fallacy (Mole & Klein, 2010) by (a) claiming that
example comes from studies testing the hypothesis that there their results supported some theory because the results and
is a unified attentional bottleneck involved in both perception theory were consistent without (b) providing evidence that the
and decision making (Jiang & Kanwisher, 2003; Tombu et al., study could have yielded a pattern of data that would have
2011). These studies found that the same brain regions showed opposed that theory. Based on these metrics, only a small set
“bottleneck” properties during a perceptual encoding task and of fMRI studies of cognition test cognitive theories.
during a speeded response decision task; these findings are Does this low hit rate mean that fMRI has properties that
inconsistent with task switching accounts that posit indepen- make it less likely to be able to inform cognitive theories than
dent substrates for encoding and response selection. behavioral data? For instance, Uttal (2001) argues that behav-
Another question that has been tackled by examining the iorism approaches are better suited for the study of psychologi-
similarity of brain activation patterns across two conditions is cal processes than are neuroimaging approaches: “One other
whether honesty results from the absence of temptation or general goal of this book has been to champion the resurrection
from the active resistance of temptation. Individuals who were of an underappreciated, yet scientifically sounder, approach to
given the opportunity to cheat but were honest showed no the study of psychological processes—behaviorism” (p. 206).
greater activity in brain regions associated with behavior con- So how does the cognitive theory track record of fMRI stack
trol than did those who were in a control condition with no up against that of behavioral methods? Although, to our
opportunity to cheat (or any differences in activity in any other knowledge, no one has attempted this type of comparison, the
brain regions, even at a low threshold), whereas those who case can be made that resolving controversies between theo-
were dishonest showed significantly more activity in brain ries in cognitive psychology is surprisingly difficult regardless
regions associated with cognitive control (Greene & Paxton, of the methods used (Greenwald, 2012). Greenwald reviewed
2009). The similarity of brain activation patterns among those 13 examples of prominent controversies in cognitive and
who were honest and those with no opportunity to cheat argues social psychology from the 1950s through the early 1980s and
against the hypothesis that honesty results from the active found that only one was clearly resolved. Interestingly, it was
resistance of temptation—at least in the context of the task not resolved by behavioral methods but by neuroimaging
used in that study. (Ganis, Keenan, Kosslyn, & Pascual-Leone, 2000; Kosslyn,
The observation that two tasks that have been thought of as Digirolamo, Thompson, & Alpert, 1998).
distinct engage common processing mechanisms can also gen-
erate new theoretical predictions. For instance, fMRI research
that directly compared activity while imagining the future to What is Needed for fMRI Research to
activity while remembering the past has revealed that these Inform Cognitive Theory?
processes engage the same neural networks (Buckner & Car- In their article in this special section, Wixted and Mickes
roll, 2007; Schacter & Addis, 2007; Szpunar, Watson, & (2013, this issue) state that “fMRI can inform cognitive theo-
McDermott, 2007). This surprising finding led to the novel ries that make predictions about patterns of activity in the
hypothesis that older adults, who have impaired function in brain” (p. 104). The implication, as made explicit by Coltheart,
the neural networks involved in remembering past events, is that cognitive theories that do not make predictions about the
should also show impairments in mentally simulating the results of functional neuroimaging experiments cannot be
future. Subsequent research revealed that, indeed, older adults informed by the results of neuroimaging experiments. We
generate fewer distinct details when simulating the future and argue that, to the contrary, results from fMRI studies can be
that this deficit is correlated with their relational memory abil- used to help resolve theoretical debates about cognition even
ities and with how many distinct details they generate when when the theories involved make no predictions about the
remembering the past (Addis, Wong, & Schacter, 2008). brain regions involved. An example described above is the
fMRI study testing the hypothesis that objects, rather than
locations or features, are the units of attentional selection
How Effectively Has fMRI Contributed to (O’Craven et al., 1999). In that study, the fMRI results were
Cognitive Theory? able to distinguish between processing of two different objects
So far, we have outlined four ways in which fMRI provides superimposed in the same location and their features (in this
tools that can be used to address theoretical debates about cog- case, motion). The specific brain regions involved in process-
nition. But how effectively have these tools been used? As ing each type of object and the motion were not relevant for
mentioned by Coltheart in this issue, a survey of fMRI studies testing the theory, but knowledge about these regions allowed
investigating cognitive functions published between 2007 and the researchers to decode which type of information was being

Downloaded from pps.sagepub.com at Scientific library of Moscow State University on January 4, 2014
fMRI and Cognitive Theories 111

processed. As in this example, researchers have been using the underlying psychological processes. Doing so constitutes an
decoding aspects of fMRI in many creative ways to test expansion of the purview of psychological science beyond a
research questions that themselves have little direct connection science of behavior, and beyond a science of the mind, to
to the brain. For instance, do older adults show more impair- include a science of the brain (Cacioppo & Decety, 2009).
ment in reflective selective attention than in perceptual selec-
tive attention (K. J. Mitchell, Johnson, Higgins, & Johnson,
2010)? Does a deficit in processing multiple stimuli at once Concluding Comments
contribute to older adults’ binding deficits (Chee et al., 2006)? In the 20 years since the first publication using fMRI, there has
Coltheart argues that cognitive systems need to be defined been an explosion of interest in this method and many have
first before neuroimaging data are collected and that cognition employed it to investigate questions about cognition. In this
thus informs neuroimaging (rather than being informed by commentary, we outlined four ways in which we believe that
neuroimaging). However, rarely do or should researchers in fMRI results can inform our understanding of cognition. First,
any area of science lock in its definitions and then just collect it can answer questions about which functions can be localized
data while insisting that those definitions remain rigidly fixed to specific brain regions, questions that are of critical interest
in place. Rather, interesting experimental work alters our for those examining issues related to the modularity of the
understanding of the very phenomena we set out to explore. brain (e.g., Blumstein, 2013, this issue; Cabeza & Moscovitch,
Coltheart’s argument says not that cognition cannot be 2013, this issue; Chiao & Immordino-Yang, 2013, this issue).
informed by the brain, but rather that it should not allow itself Second, fMRI data can be used as markers of particular mental
to be. But why not let our ideas about cognition be shaped in processes, allowing insight into what processes are being
part by neuroimaging data? For instance, as described above, engaged during different tasks. Third, fMRI can answer ques-
having discovered that imagining the future activates the same tions about exactly what information is represented in each
neural networks as remembering the past, researchers who region of the brain. Such data can be used to address theoreti-
knew that those neural networks were impaired in older adults cal questions about the nature of memory reactivation (e.g.,
were able to generate a new prediction about behavior and Levy & Wagner, 2013, this issue) and working memory (e.g.,
indeed demonstrated that older adults imagine the future less Reuter-Lorenz, 2013, this issue) as well as basic questions
vividly than younger adults do (Addis et al., 2008). about the structure of cognitive processes (e.g., Serences et al.,
In sum, we disagree with Coltheart that imaging can only 2009). Fourth, fMRI can answer questions about whether two
inform cognitive theories when we can assume that “Cogni- tasks engage common or distinct processing mechanisms. This
tive Process C is implemented in Brain Region X and nowhere strategy can provide important evidence to address theoretical
else in the brain, and Brain Region X subserves Cognitive Pro- questions about the nature of tasks (e.g., Rugg & Thompson-
cess C and no other cognitive process” (p. 101). Instead, as Schill, 2013, this issue) and how functional circuitry reorga-
outlined above, there are many ways that imaging can inform nizes with age (e.g., Park & McDonough, 2013, this issue).
cognition without meeting this high bar. Of course, powerful as it is, fMRI is impotent to answer
some questions. First, fMRI can never address the causal role
of a particular brain region in a particular task, though show-
The Importance of Having Cognitive ing correlations between fMRI signals and behavior help
Theories Inform Neuroimaging Research somewhat. Definitive answers to questions of causal role thus
We began by acknowledging the goal of cognitive psychology require other methods such as transcranial magnetic stimula-
as developing and testing theories about how the mind works. tion, electrical brain stimulation, and studies of patients with
However, this is not the only worthwhile goal. With the advent brain damage. Second, fMRI for the most part does not have
of neuroimaging techniques, cognitive psychologists (and psy- the necessary temporal resolution to reveal the workings of
chological scientists more generally) have also begun to thought, the component stages of which generally proceed on
advance the goal of developing and testing theories about how the scale of tens or hundreds of milliseconds, not seconds. Pre-
the brain works (Cacioppo & Decety, 2009). As evidence, cise timing information from the human brain is available
Wixted and Mickes (2013) note that many fMRI studies rely from event-related potentials and magnetoencephalography,
on a cognitive theory to interpret their results, even when they intracranial recordings, and transcranial magnetic stimulation.
are not testing the theory. Psychological theory is critically Third, even with high-resolution fMRI and even with sophisti-
important to understanding the human brain and also in design- cated pattern analysis methods, each voxel pools neural activ-
ing experiments that differentiate different cognitive processes. ity over hundreds of thousands of neurons, so the signal we
Given the complexity of the human brain, progress in under- can see with fMRI is a drastically subsampled version of the
standing its functional organization and structure depends on actual language in which neurons talk to each other. This
sophisticated theoretical specifications of the psychological means that we cannot tell whether the same neurons are
representations and processes that differentiate two or more involved even when activity looks the same across multiple
comparison conditions. Psychological scientists, therefore, are conditions. Finally, like other neuroscience methods, even the
well positioned to lead the search for brain mechanisms most astonishing demonstration of a specific neural

Downloaded from pps.sagepub.com at Scientific library of Moscow State University on January 4, 2014
112 Mather et al.

representation in a given region of the brain leaves open the Epstein, R., & Kanwisher, N. (1998). A cortical representation of the
question of whether that representation was computed locally local visual environment. Nature, 392, 598–601.
in the region where it is observed or whether instead that infor- Fedorenko, E., Behr, M. K., & Kanwisher, N. (2011). Functional
mation was inherited from an earlier stage of processing. The specificity for high-level linguistic processing in the human
best approach to answering questions about cognition there- brain. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA,
fore is a synergistic combination of behavioral and neuroimag- 108, 16428–16433.
ing methods, richly complemented by the wide array of other Fedorenko, E., McDermott, J. H., Norman-Haignere, S., & Kan-
methods in cognitive neuroscience. wisher, N. (in press). Sensitivity to musical structure in the
human brain. Journal of Neurophysiology.
Declaration of Conflicting Interests Ganis, G., Keenan, J. P., Kosslyn, S. M., & Pascual-Leone, A. (2000).
The authors declared that they had no conflicts of interest with Transcranial magnetic stimulation of primary motor cortex affects
respect to their authorship or the publication of this article. mental rotation. Cerebral Cortex, 10, 175–180.
Gazzaley, A., Cooney, J. W., McEvoy, K., Knight, R. T., & D’Esposito,
Note M. (2005). Top-down enhancement and suppression of the mag-
1.  Poldrack has correctly criticized reverse inference, in which men- nitude and speed of neural activity. Journal of Cognitive Neuro-
tal processes are inferred from the location of fMRI responses science, 17, 507–517.
(Poldrack, 2006). Note however that for the few cases of brain Gazzaley, A., Cooney, J. W., Rissman, J., & D’Esposito, M. (2005).
regions with very specific functions, and for which that specificity is
Top-down suppression deficit underlies working memory impair-
widely replicated, these regions can indeed support solid reverse
ment in normal aging. Nature Neuroscience, 8, 1298–1300.
inferences.
Greene, J. D., & Paxton, J. M. (2009). Patterns of neural activity asso-
References ciated with honest and dishonest moral decisions. Proceedings of
the National Academy of Sciences, USA, 106, 12506–12511.
Addis, D. R., Wong, A. T., & Schacter, D. L. (2008). Age-related Greenwald, A. G. (2012). There is nothing so theoretical as a good
changes in the episodic simulation of future events. Psychologi- method. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 7, 99–108.
cal Science, 19, 33–41. Grill-Spector, K., & Malach, R. (2001). fMR-adaptation: A tool for
Blumstein, S. E., & Amso, D. (2013). Dynamic functional organi- studying the functional properties of human cortical neurons.
zation of language: Insights from functional neuroimaging. Per- Acta Psychologica, 107, 293–321.
spectives on Psychological Science, 8, 44–48. Haxby, J. V. (2012). Multivariate pattern analysis of fMRI: The early
Buckner, R. L., & Carroll, D. C. (2007). Self-projection and the brain. beginnings. NeuroImage, 62, 852–855.
Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 11, 49–57. Haynes, J.-D., & Rees, G. (2005). Predicting the orientation of invis-
Cabeza, R., & Moscovitch, M. (2013). Memory systems, process- ible stimuli from activity in human primary visual cortex. Nature
ing modes, and components: Functional neuroimaging evidence. Neuroscience, 8, 686–691.
Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8, 49–55. Jiang, Y. H., & Kanwisher, N. (2003). Common neural mechanisms
Cacioppo, J. T., & Decety, J. (2009). What are the brain mechanisms for response selection and perceptual processing. Journal of Cog-
on which psychological processes are based? Perspectives on nitive Neuroscience, 15, 1095–1110.
Psychological Science, 4, 10–18. Kamitani, Y., & Tong, F. (2005). Decoding the visual and subjec-
Chee, M. W. L., Goh, J. O. S., Venkatraman, V., Tan, J. C., Gutchess, tive contents of the human brain. Nature Neuroscience, 8, 679–
A., Sutton, B., . . . Park, D. (2006). Age-related changes in object 685.
processing and contextual binding revealed using fMRI adapta- Kamitani, Y., & Tong, F. (2006). Decoding seen and attended motion
tion. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 18, 495–507. directions from activity in the human visual cortex. Current Biol-
Chiao, J. Y., & Immordino-Yang, M. H. (2013). Modularity and the ogy, 16, 1096–1102.
cultural mind: Contributions of cultural neuroscience to cognitive Kanwisher, N. (2010). Functional specificity in the human brain:
theory. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8, 56–61. A window into the functional architecture of the mind. Proceed-
Cichy, R. M., Chen, Y., & Haynes, J.-D. (2011). Encoding the identity ings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, 107, 11163–
and location of objects in human LOC. NeuroImage, 54, 2297– 11170.
2307. Kosslyn, S. M., Digirolamo, G. J., Thompson, W. L., & Alpert, N. M.
Coltheart, M. (2013). How can functional neuroimaging inform (1998). Mental rotation of objects versus hands: Neural mecha-
cognitive theories? Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8, nisms revealed by positron emission tomography. Psychophysiol-
98–103. ogy, 35, 151–161.
D’Esposito, M. (2007). From cognitive to neural models of working Kravitz, D. J., Peng, C. S., & Baker, C. I. (2011). Real-world scene
memory. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Bio- representations in high-level visual cortex: It’s the spaces more
logical Sciences, 362, 761–772. than the places. Journal of Neuroscience, 31, 7322–7333.
Downing, P. E., Chan, A. W. Y., Peelen, M. V., Dodds, C. M., & Kan- Levy, B. J., & Wagner, A. D. (2013). Measuring memory reactiva-
wisher, N. (2006). Domain specificity in visual cortex. Cerebral tion with functional MRI: Implications for psychological theory.
Cortex, 16, 1453–1461. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8, 72–78.

Downloaded from pps.sagepub.com at Scientific library of Moscow State University on January 4, 2014
fMRI and Cognitive Theories 113

Mitchell, K. J., Johnson, M. R., Higgins, J. A., & Johnson, M. K. Rugg, M. D., & Thompson-Schill, S. L. (2013). Moving forward with
(2010). Age differences in brain activity during perceptual versus fMRI data. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8, 84–87.
reflective attention. NeuroReport, 21, 293–297. Schacter, D. L., & Addis, D. R. (2007). The cognitive neuroscience
Mitchell, T. M., Hutchinson, R., Niculescu, R. S., Pereira, F., Wang, of constructive memory: Remembering the past and imagining
X., Just, M., & Newman, S. (2004). Learning to decode cognitive the future. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B:
states from brain images. Machine Learning, 57, 145–175. Biological Sciences, 362, 773–786.
Mole, C., & Klein, C. (2010). Confirmation, refutation and the evi- Serences, J. T., Ester, E. F., Vogel, E. K., & Awh, E. (2009). Stimulus-
dence in fMRI. In S. J. Hanson & M. Bunzl (Eds.), Foundational specific delay activity in human primary visual cortex. Psycho-
issues in human brain mapping (pp. 99–112). Cambridge, MA: logical Science, 20, 207–214.
MIT Press. Shimamura, A. P. (2010). Bridging psychological and biological sci-
Monti, M. M., Parsons, L. M., & Osherson, D. N. (2009). The bound- ence: The good, bad, and ugly. Perspectives on Psychological
aries of language and thought in deductive inference. Proceedings Science, 5, 772–775.
of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, 106, 12554–12559. Szpunar, K. K., Watson, J. M., & McDermott, K. B. (2007). Neural
Monti, M. M., Parsons, L. M., & Osherson, D. N. (2012). Thought substrates of envisioning the future. Proceedings of the National
beyond language: Neural dissociation of algebra and natural lan- Academy of Sciences, USA, 104, 642–647.
guage. Psychological Science, 23, 914–922. Tombu, M. N., Asplund, C. L., Dux, P. E., Godwin, D., Martin, J.
Norman, K. A., Polyn, S. M., Detre, G. J., & Haxby, J. V. (2006). W., & Marois, R. (2011). A unified attentional bottleneck in the
Beyond mind-reading: Multi-voxel pattern analysis of fMRI data. human brain. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences,
Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10, 424–430. USA, 108, 13426–13431.
O’Craven, K. M., Downing, P. E., & Kanwisher, N. (1999). fMRI Tressoldi, P. E., Sella, F., Coltheart, M., & Umilta, C. (2012). Using
evidence for objects as the units of attentional selection. Nature, functional neuroimaging to test theories of cognition: A selec-
401, 584–587. tive survey of studies from 2007 to 2011 as a contribution to the
Park, S., Brady, T. F., Greene, M. R., & Oliva, A. (2011). Disentan- decade of the mind initiative. Cortex: A Journal Devoted to the
gling scene content from spatial boundary: Complementary roles Study of the Nervous System and Behavior, 48, 1247–1250.
for the parahippocampal place area and lateral occipital complex Uttal, W. R. (2001). The new phrenology: The limits of localizing
in representing real-world scenes. Journal of Neuroscience, 31, cognitive processes in the brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
1333–1340. Walther, D. B., Chai, B., Caddigan, E., Beck, D. M., & Fei-Fei, L.
Park, D. C., & McDonough, I. M. (2013). The dynamic aging mind: (2011). Simple line drawings suffice for functional MRI decod-
Revelations from functional neuroimaging research. Perspectives ing of natural scene categories. Proceedings of the National
on Psychological Science, 8, 62–67. Academy of Sciences, USA, 108, 9661–9666.
Poldrack, R. A. (2006). Can cognitive processes be inferred from Wixted, J. T., & Mickes, L. (2013). On the relationship between fMRI
neuroimaging data? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10, 59–63. and theories of cognition: The arrow points in both directions.
Reuter-Lorenz, P. A. (2013). Aging and cognitive neuroimaging: Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8, 104–107.
A fertile union. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8, Wojciulik, E., & Kanwisher, N. (1999). The generality of parietal
68–71. involvement in visual attention. Neuron, 23, 747–764.

Downloaded from pps.sagepub.com at Scientific library of Moscow State University on January 4, 2014

S-ar putea să vă placă și