Sunteți pe pagina 1din 285

Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F.

Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

RETHINKING NEOLIBERALISM

This book is a collection of essays from a two-year-long faculty seminar on


neoliberalism at Hunter College, CUNY. Various presenters contributed chapters,
some examining particular theoretical issues and others more empirical in orienta-
tion, focusing on politics, policymaking, and issues of governance. An organizing
theme for the collection is that neoliberalism is a hegemonic governing ethic
regimenting subordinate populations into a market-centered society. For decades
now, neoliberalism has been ascendant as the default logic that prioritizes using
economic rationality for all major decisions, in all sectors of society, at the
collective level of state policymaking as well as the personal level of individual
choice making. Neoliberalism promotes a market-centered society and disciplines
people to be compliant in adhering to its strictures, incentivizing market-
consistent behavior, and punishing people when they fail to comply. The chapters
in this volume were in most cases completed before Donald Trump became the
US President, with some commentators arguing that his victory represents a
repudiation of neoliberalism as a regime of governance. Others have argued that
Trump personally embodies a neoliberal approach to governing. Regardless, the
analyses collected in this volume are likely to endure in relevance beyond his
presidency. For now, neoliberalism remains a flashpoint for political contestation.
The essays collected in this volume interrogate neoliberalism critically and therefore
provide resources for resisting its ongoing hegemony.
This collection of papers is from an impressive group of scholars. They provide
important insights on neoliberalism as an ideology and as a practice. Key themes
in the various chapters include:

 Theoretical debates vital for understanding the origins of neoliberalism as an


ideology
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

 The relationship between neoliberalism, the state, and civil society


 Neoliberalism and the use of social policy to discipline citizens
 Urban policy and how neoliberalism reshapes urban governance
 What it will take politically to get beyond neoliberalism

Written in a consistently clear and accessible style, Rethinking Neoliberalism


offers new and important insights and analyses for understanding neoliberalism, its
origins, its philosophical and ethical orientations, and its influence on politics,
policymaking, and governance today.

Sanford F. Schram teaches at Hunter College, CUNY where he is Professor of


Political Science and Faculty Associate at the Roosevelt House Public Policy
Institute. He also teaches at the CUNY Graduate Center. His published books
include Words of Welfare: The Poverty of Social Science and the Social Science of Poverty
(1995) and Disciplining the Poor: Neoliberal Paternalism and the Persistent Power of
Race (2011) – co-authored with Joe Soss and Richard Fording. Both books won
the Michael Harrington Award from the American Political Science Association.
His latest book is The Return to Ordinary Capitalism: Neoliberalism, Precarity, Occupy
(Oxford University Press, 2015). Schram is the 2012 recipient of the Charles
McCoy Career Achievement Award from the Caucus for a New Political
Science.

Marianna Pavlovskaya is a Professor of Geography at Hunter College and


CUNY Graduate Center. She has an MA in Geography from Moscow State
University and a PhD in Geography from Clark University. Her major fields
include urban geography, feminist geography, and critical GIS (Geographic
Information Science). Her current research examines neoliberalism and the pro-
duction of economic difference in post-Soviet Russia, the role of the census,
statistics, and geo-spatial data in constitution of the social body, the relationship
between gender, class, and work-related migration, and the emergence of the
solidarity economy in the United States. Her work has appeared in the Annals of
the American Association of Geographers, Geoforum, Europe-Asia Studies, Environment
and Planning A, Cartographica, Urban Geography, and many edited volumes. She has
worked on international research projects with colleagues from Norway, Uganda,
and Russia.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

RETHINKING
NEOLIBERALISM
Resisting the Disciplinary Regime

Edited by Sanford F. Schram and


Marianna Pavlovskaya
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

First published 2017


by Routledge
711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017
and by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business
© 2017 Taylor & Francis
The right of Sanford F. Schram and Marianna Pavlovskaya to be identified as
the authors of the editorial material, and of the authors for their individual
chapters, has been asserted in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the
Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or
utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now
known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any
information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the
publishers.
Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered
trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent
to infringe.
Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data
[CIP data]

ISBN: 978-1-138-73595-8 (hbk)


ISBN: 978-1-138-73596-5 (pbk)
ISBN: 978-1-315-18623-8 (ebk)

Typeset in Bembo
by Taylor & Francis Books
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

CONTENTS

List of Illustrations vii


List of Contributors viii
Introduction: Rethinking Neoliberalism: Resisting the Disciplinary Regime xiii
Sanford F. Schram and Marianna Pavlovskaya

PART I
Theorizing Neoliberalism: The Individual, the Subject,
and the Power of the State 1
1 Nothing Personal 3
Jodi Dean
2 The Secret Life of Neoliberal Subjectivity 23
Mitchell Dean
3 Foucault’s Three Ways of Decentering the State 41
Kaspar Villadsen

PART II
Reconstructing the Individual via Social Policy 61
4 Investing in Social Subjects: The European Turn to Social
Investment as the Human Capital Theory of Social Citizenship 63
Bettina Leibetseder
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

5 Ontologies of Poverty in Russia and Duplicities of


Neoliberalism 84
Marianna Pavlovskaya
6 Neoliberalism Viewed from the Bottom Up: A Qualitative
Longitudinal Study of Benefit Claimants’ Experiences of the
Unemployment System 104
Sophie Danneris
7 Neoliberal Talk: The Routinized Structures of Document-
Focused Social Worker–Client Discourse 119
Maureen T. Matarese and Dorte Caswell

PART III
The Neoliberal Disciplinary Regime: Policing Indentured
Citizens 139
8 Criminal Justice Predation and Neoliberal Governance 141
Joshua Page and Joe Soss
9 Neoliberalism and Police Reform 162
Leonard Feldman

PART IV
Urban Governance: At Home and Abroad 179
10 Neoliberalizing Detroit 181
Jamie Peck and Heather Whiteside
11 Political Dissent in Amman, Jordan: Neoliberal Geographies of
Protest and Policing 199
Jillian Schwedler

PART V
Forward: Working Through Neoliberalism 215
12 The Knight’s Move: Social Policy Change in an Age of
Consolidated Power 217
Sanford Schram
13 Neoliberalism: Towards A Critical Counter-Conduct 238
Barbara Cruikshank

Index 258
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

ILLUSTRATIONS

Figures
5.1 Income inequality in Russia, 1990–2015 91
5.2 Poverty rate and unemployment rate in Russia, 1992–2015 92
5.3 Income per capita, MSL (minimum subsistence level),
MMW (minimum monthly wage), and unemployment
benefit limits, 2005–2014 95
10.1 Federal funding for cities … and for Detroit 189

Tables
4.1 Social Investment Subjects 76
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

CONTRIBUTORS

Dorte Caswell is Associate Professor, Head of Section at the Department of


Sociology and Social Work, Aalborg University (Copenhagen Campus) and Head
of SAB (Social Work at the Frontline of Social and Employment Policy) at Aalborg
University, Denmark. Her current research is focused on an interest in bridging
political science and sociological approaches in understanding social work practice.
Research interests include welfare state developments, especially organizational
and professional aspects of this, as well as understanding the implications for the
most vulnerable clients. The research is informed by a theoretical perspective
paying attention to the translation of policy in interaction at the frontline of
the welfare state in meetings between clients and professionals. See http://
personprofil.aau.dk/117637 for more information.

Barbara Cruikshank is Associate Professor of Political Science at the University


of Massachusetts, Amherst. She is the author of The Will to Empower: Democratic
Citizens and Other Subjects (Cornell UP, 1999) and of a forthcoming book titled,
Machiavellian Optimism: Cultivating and Sustaining the Spirit for Political Life as an
Endless Struggle. She serves on the editorial boards of Foucault Studies and Polity.

Sophie Danneris teaches at Aalborg University in Denmark, Department of


Sociology and Social Work, where she is a Post Doc, with a PhD in Social Science.
Her special interest fields are social policy and labor market research with a focus on
vulnerable clients, and the methodological development of qualitative research. Her
published work includes “Ready to Work (Yet)? Unemployment Trajectories
among Vulnerable Welfare Recipients” and “One Size Doesn’t Fit All: Diversifying
Research on Active Labor Market Policies” as well as several publications in Danish
and contributions to books within the fields of sociology and social work.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

List of Contributors ix

Jodi Dean is the Donald R. Harter ’39 Professor of Humanities and Social
Sciences at Hobart and William Smith Colleges in Geneva, NY. She is the author
or editor of twelve books, including Democracy and Other Neoliberal Fantasies
(Duke, 2009), Blog Theory (Polity, 2010), The Communist Horizon (Verso, 2010),
and Crowds and Party (Verso, 2016).

Mitchell Dean is Professor of Public Governance at the Copenhagen Business


School. He has held Chairs of Sociology at the University of Newcastle and
Macquarie University, where he also was Dean of Society, Culture, Media and
Philosophy from 2002 to 2009. He is author of seven books, including
Governmentality: Power and Rule in Modern Society (Sage, 1999/2010), Critical and
Effective Histories: Foucault’s Methods and Historical Sociology (Routledge, 1994), and
The Signature of Power: Sovereignty, Governmentality and Biopolitics (Sage, 2013).
Stanford University Press has published his most recent book, co-authored
with Kaspar Villadsen, State Phobia and Civil Society: The Political Legacy of
Michel Foucault in 2016. He also edited, with Barry Hindess, Governing
Australia: Studies in Contemporary Rationalities of Government (Cambridge University
Press, 1998), the first national work of “governmentality studies.” His work
stands at the nexus between political and historical sociology and political
theory and philosophy.

Leonard Feldman is Associate Professor of Political Science at Hunter College


and the Graduate Center, CUNY. His research is focused in contemporary political
theory and public law, with an interest generally in the relationship between legal
order and executive, police, and popular powers. He is the author of Citizens
Without Shelter: Homelessness, Democracy and Political Exclusion (Cornell, 2004). He
is currently the Associate Editor for Political Theory of Polity. His work has
appeared or is forthcoming in Political Theory, Law, Culture and the Humanities,
Polity, Theory & Event and many edited volumes. Prior to CUNY he was a
Mellon Foundation post-doctoral fellow at Grinnell College, and an assistant and
an associate professor at the University of Oregon. From 2007 to 2008 he was a
member of the Institute for Advanced Study in Princeton.

Bettina Leibetseder is Assistant Professor at the Department of Politics and


Social Policy of the Johannes Kepler University in Linz, Austria. Her work
covers social policy in comparative perspective, especially aspects of minimum
income schemes and gender. Bettina was Fulbright-Botstiber Visiting Professor of
Austrian-American Studies at Hunter College, Department of Politics in spring
2015. Recent publications include an article on territorial fragmentation of welfare
in Austria (Journal of Social Policy), the impact of functional and territorial sub-
sidiarity on welfare in European countries (International Journal of Social Welfare)
and an analysis of the policy instruments embedded in the European Social
Investment Package (Comparative European Politics).
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

x List of Contributors

Maureen T. Matarese, an Associate Professor of Academic Literacy and Linguistics


at BMCC, City University of New York, specializes in the analysis of institu-
tional, practitioner–client interaction in social work and education. She examines
how bureaucratic, neoliberal policies surface in face-to-face, street-level organi-
zational communication. She has published in Discourse Processes, the Journal of
Applied Linguistics and Professional Practice, and the British Journal of Social Work, and is a
co-editor of and co-contributor to the book Analysing Social Work Communication:
Discourse in Practice, published through Routledge (2014). She is a member of the
DANASWAC network of researchers in discourse and narrative analysis in social
work and counseling, and she is the Vice President (and current acting President)
of the International Linguistic Association.

Joshua Page is an Associate Professor of Sociology and Law at the University of


Minnesota. He is the author of The Toughest Beat: Politics, Punishment, and the
Prison Officer Unions in California (Oxford, 2011) and Breaking the Pendulum: The
Long Struggle over Criminal Justice (Oxford, 2017). He’s currently studying the bail
bond industry and, with Joe Soss, writing a book titled Criminal Debts: Predatory
Governance and the Remaking of American Citizenship (Chicago). He can be contacted
at page@umn.edu.

Marianna Pavlovskaya is a Professor of Geography at Hunter College and


CUNY Graduate Center. She has an MA in Geography from Moscow State
University and a PhD in Geography from Clark University. Her major fields
include urban geography, feminist geography, and critical GIS (Geographic
Information Science). Her current research examines neoliberalism and the pro-
duction of economic difference in post-Soviet Russia, the role of the census,
statistics, and geo-spatial data in constitution of the social body, the relationship
between gender, class, and work-related migration, and the emergence of the
solidarity economy in the United States. Her work has appeared in the Annals of
the American Association of Geographers, Geoforum, Europe-Asia Studies, Environment
and Planning A, Cartographica, Urban Geography, and many edited volumes. She has
worked on international research projects with colleagues from Norway, Uganda,
and Russia.

Jamie Peck is Canada Research Chair in Urban & Regional Political Economy
and Professor of Geography at the University of British Columbia, Canada. With
long-term research interests in urban restructuring, geographical political economy,
labor studies, the politics of policy formation and mobility, and economic geo-
graphy, his current research is focused on the financial restructuring of US cities,
the politics of contingent labor, and the political economy of neoliberalization.
Recent books include Offshore: Exploring the Worlds of Global Outsourcing (Oxford,
2017); Fast Policy: Experimental Statecraft at the Thresholds of Neoliberalism (Minnesota,
2015, with Nik Theodore); Constructions of Neoliberal Reason (Oxford, 2010); and
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

List of Contributors xi

the Wiley-Blackwell Companion to Economic Geography (Wiley, 2012, co-edited


with Trevor Barnes and Eric Sheppard). A Fellow of the Royal Society of
Canada, and previously the holder of Guggenheim and Harkness fellowships,
Peck is the Editor-in-Chief of the Environment and Planning series of journals.

Sanford Schram teaches at Hunter College, CUNY where he is Professor of


Political Science and Faculty Associate at the Roosevelt House Public Policy
Institute. He also teaches at the CUNY Graduate Center. His published books
include Words of Welfare: The Poverty of Social Science and the Social Science of Poverty
(1995) and Disciplining the Poor: Neoliberal Paternalism and the Persistent Power of
Race (2011) – co-authored with Joe Soss and Richard Fording. Both books won
the Michael Harrington Award from the American Political Science Association.
His latest book is The Return to Ordinary Capitalism: Neoliberalism, Precarity, Occupy
(Oxford University Press, 2015). Schram is the 2012 recipient of the Charles
McCoy Career Achievement Award from the Caucus for a New Political
Science.

Dr Jillian Schwedler is Professor of Political Science at the City University of


New York’s Hunter College and the Graduate Center, and Nonresident Senior
Fellow of the Rafiq Hariri Center for the Middle East at the Atlantic Council.
She is a member of the Board of Directors and the Editorial Committee of the
Middle East Research and Information Project (MERIP), publishers of the quar-
terly Middle East Report. Dr Schwedler’s books include the award-winning Faith in
Moderation: Islamist Parties in Jordan and Yemen (Cambridge, 2006) and (with Laleh
Khalili) Policing and Prisons in the Middle East (Columbia, 2010). Her articles have
appeared in World Politics, Comparative Politics, Middle East Policy, Middle East Report,
Journal of Democracy, and Social Movement Studies, among many others. Her research
has received support from the National Science Foundation, the United States
Institute of Peace, the Fulbright Scholars Program, the American Institute for
Yemen Studies, and the Social Science Research Council, among others.

Joe Soss is the inaugural Cowles Chair for the Study of Public Service at the
University of Minnesota, where he holds faculty positions in the Hubert H.
Humphrey School of Public Affairs, the Department of Political Science, and the
Department of Sociology. His research and teaching explore the interplay of
democratic politics, societal inequalities, and public policy. He is particularly
interested in the political sources and consequences of policies that govern social
marginality and shape life conditions for socially marginal groups. His books include
Disciplining the Poor: Neoliberal Paternalism and the Persistent Power of Race (2011) and
Unwanted Claims: The Politics of Participation in the U.S. Welfare System (2000). In
addition to his scholarship, Soss has been named to the University of Minnesota’s
Academy of Distinguished Teachers and, as a musician, recently released an album,
The Sound of Sweet Ruin. He can be contacted at jbsoss@umn.edu.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

xii List of Contributors

Kaspar Villadsen is a Professor at the Department of Management, Politics and


Philosophy, Copenhagen Business School. Villadsen is doing research on the
concept of the state and civil society in Michel Foucault’s authorship. He has
published Statephobia and Civil Society: The Political Legacy of Michel Foucault
(Stanford University Press, 2016, with Mitchell Dean). He is also the author of
Power and Welfare: Understanding Citizens’ Encounters with State Welfare (Routledge,
2013, with Nanna Mik-Meyer). Villadsen’s work has appeared in journals such as
Economy and Society, Theory, Culture and Society, Body and Society, and New Political
Science.

Heather Whiteside is Assistant Professor of Political Science at the University of


Waterloo and Fellow at the Balsillie School of International Affairs, Canada. Her
research and publications center on the political economy of privatization, finan-
cialization, and fiscal austerity. She has published articles in journals such as
Economic Geography, Studies in Political Economy, and Health Sociology Review, and
her books include About Canada: Public-Private Partnerships (Fernwood, 2016), and
Purchase for Profit: Public-Private Partnerships and Canada’s Public Health Care System
(University of Toronto Press, 2015). She is currently a co-investigator on two
multi-year Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada grants
investigating varieties of austerity and alternatives to austerity. She is a co-editor
of the journal Studies in Political Economy.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

INTRODUCTION
Rethinking Neoliberalism: Resisting the
Disciplinary Regime

Sanford F. Schram and Marianna Pavlovskaya

This book is a collection of essays about neoliberalism as the governing ethic of


our time. The focus is on neoliberalism’s disciplinary regime that seeks to regiment
subordinate populations into a market-centered society. Neoliberalism has been
ascendant for some time as the default logic that prioritizes using market logic for
making the critical decisions across all spheres of society, at the collective level of
state policymaking as well as the personal level of individual choice-making
(Schram 2015). Neoliberalism promotes a market-centered society and disciplines
people to be compliant in adhering to its strictures, incentivizing market consistent
behavior, and punishing people when they fail to comply. Already controversial,
neoliberalism came under intense scrutiny as it had not before with the surprising
election of Donald Trump as President of the United States. When Trump won,
some commentators noted that he had run as an outsider against the Washington
Establishment that had favored neoliberal approaches to governing, and his victory
signaled a repudiation of the neoliberal orientation that had for several decades
dominated national politics (Fraser, 2017; Klein, 2016; and Lynch, 2016).
To be sure, Trump’s election was already controversial in other many ways.
Perhaps most disturbing was the role played by racism, xenophobia, and sexism
that evidently helped propel his candidacy to victory. Trump’s candidacy was also
profoundly provocative because he cut such a controversial profile as an outsider
with no real qualifications for governing the country. He lacked both govern-
mental experience and rudimentary knowledge of policy. He seemed to be
extremely temperamental and talked in over-simplified and emotional terms. He
proved to be a pathological liar, especially about things that made him less great
than his constant boasting claimed. He made the controversial claim that as a
successful businessman he could apply his business skills once in office to undo
failed policies. He would make the USA a winner on the world stage in both
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

xiv Introduction

foreign and economic policy. He would as his slogan claimed “Make America
Great Again” which many of his white nationalist supporters could interpret as
“Make America White Again.” His calls to crack down on illegal immigration,
ban Muslims from the Middle East, and other xenophobic policy proposals suggested
that that might have been what he actually meant. There was a lot to not like. In
fact, Trump ultimately lost the popular vote to his opponent Hillary Clinton by
almost 3 million votes but won the Electoral College by outpolling her ever so
slightly in the three Rust-Belt states of Michigan, Pennsylvania, and Wisconsin
where deindustrialization turned some voters against Clinton toward Trump,
perhaps if only out of desperation for change in economic policy in particular.
Irrespective of how unconventional a candidate Trump was, once in office his
cabinet appointments and early policy positions suggested not the end of neoli-
beralism but its continuation and even perhaps its intensification. As president,
Trump stayed loyal to the corporate class and hired wealthy supporters to head key
agencies that often were poised to dismantle. He took a pronounced big business
approach to rolling out his administration. He continued to tout the idea that busi-
nessmen like himself knew best how to govern. In his autocratic style, he claimed
only he could save us. He said he would be the people’s voice. Yet his demagoguery
was founded on claiming to be a man of the people while acting on behalf of the
corporate class to actually intensify the neoliberal approach to governing that the
people had voted against. He was proving to be a master in playing those contra-
dictions to his political advantage. He claimed he would end policies that served the
interests of what he had characterized in the campaign as a global corporate class,
while now he emphasized that he would remove barriers to corporate profit-taking.
His was at best a faux populism, consistent with the right-wing demagogues in
Europe who were seeking to impose autocratic rule on their countries as a way of
addressing their social and economic problems (Müller, 2016).
The political context not only in the USA but across the globe had in fact
made it possible for Trump to exploit people’s frustrations with existing neoliberal
approaches that worked largely for a privileged few. In the USA, both major
political parties had failed to stand up for ordinary Americans while global economic
change was wreaking havoc for middle Americans for several decades. The frustra-
tion cut across all groups of people other than the wealthy who seemed to be the
only winners in the economic shift that had been going on since the 1970s. But
Trump appealed most successfully to whites who thought that the eight years of
the presidency of Barack Obama, the country’s first black president, meant their
concerns were being ignored in a changing political economy that featured
inclusion of women and minorities but not displaced white workers. Many of
these people were not happy with the Republicans who championed integration
into a global economy without social protections for those left to the wayside.
But the Democratic Party was not much better. The Party looked to have
betrayed white workers by focusing only on amending neoliberal policies with an
identify politics that sought inclusion for out-groups, women, and racial and
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Introduction xv

sexual minorities but left economic change off the table as a non-issue not meriting
serious discussion. Bernie Sanders had tried to redress this but his failed candidacy
now served only to remind people how the Democrats ended up being propo-
nents of a “progressive neoliberalism” that simply put a smiling face of racial and
gender inclusion on the economic transformation (Fraser, 2017).
People who had struggled to maintain their standard of living post the Great
Recession were among those vulnerable to being seduced by Trump’s bombastic
lying about what he would do to “drain the swamp” of Washington and bring
back prosperity to middle America (Edsall, 2017). Some people were attracted to
his bellicose approach to foreign threats whether it was illegal immigration that
was allegedly taking away jobs from American citizens or the radical Islamic terrorists
who periodically were killing people in the Middle East, Europe, and in the
USA. Trump said he was just the vessel of a social movement, that he heard what
people wanted and he promised to give it to them. But like most demagogues his
understanding of “the people” was self-serving (Müller, 2016).
Trump ran hard, even violently, against Clinton, accusing her of crimes, using
her gender to shame her as weak and identify her as part of the Washington
Establishment (or Cartel, as one of Trump’s defeated Republican opponents for
the nomination called it). Hillary was too inside-the-beltway. She was a proponent
of the dreaded neoliberalism (if the “progressive” version that added multiculturalism
to the mix in ways that seemed more aimed at rationalizing the elite-dominated
status quo than actually producing progressive change for most people). Yet, by
the time Trump got around to picking his cabinet, it was clear he was transparently
telling the public one thing but was never intending to “drain the swamp,” and
his policy initiatives were now all of a sudden strikingly and explicitly neoliberal
on any number of fronts across the policy spectrum, from charter schools, to
privatizing Social Security and Medicare, to tax cuts for the rich, to enforcing
personal responsibility on the poor to be market compliant actors who overcame
their adversity by being successful in the deregulated economy. Neoliberalism was
not evidently ever in retreat and now it appears to be ever ascendant.
How could it be otherwise? Trump embodied neoliberalism, he lived and
breathed the idea that government should be run like a business by a businessman
just like himself. He believed in blurring boundaries including and now especially
between the market and the state. Trump refused to relinquish his business
holdings while president, forcing the issue into the courts, his wife hawked her
jewelry line on the White House webpage the very first day of his presidency and
Trump insisted on making the taxpayers pay the Trump Organization (his own
personally owned company) for security for his wife and son to continue living in
Trump Tower and not the White House (Honig, 2017). Trump insisted he
would govern by making better business deals with other countries and interna-
tional institutions and actors. In fact, he treated all government decision-making
as if it were a form of business deal-making. He was marketizing the state in real
time and in an iterative fashion, day by day, or even at some moments it seemed
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

xvi Introduction

hour by hour. His initial actions as president showed he saw governing strictly
through the lens of his best-selling book The Art of the Deal. If this is not
neoliberalism, it is not clear what is.
Neoliberalism in fact has been variously defined but arguably it is first and
foremost about making market logic hegemonic as the touchstone for decision-
making, personal and collective, in all spheres of life including the public sector
and the managing of state operations (Schram, 2015). It is significantly about
blurring the boundaries between the market and the state, bringing in market
actors to reorganize the state along market lines, marketizing state operations to
run consistent with market logic and to make those public policies and programs
more specifically directed to buttress rather than countering markets by getting
people as clients or citizens more generally to be more market compliant. While
Keynesian liberal economics relied on the state to counter markets and mitigate
their worst effects, especially on the least advantaged in society, neoliberalism saw
the state as buttressing markets to enable them to become more profitable in a
globalizing world (Krinsky, 2008). If that is neoliberalism, Trump embodied it
like no president before.
People may have voted against Clinton for her stubborn commitment to the
neoliberalism of her husband, the former President Bill Clinton, the champion of
a finding a “Third Way” between left and right (as his friend Tony Blair in
England did) to work within the existing structure of consolidated power by
being a “New Democrat.” Hillary did promise to make neoliberalism work for
ordinary people even if it had failed them in the past. She epitomized though at
best that limited effort of “progressive neoliberalism” (Fraser, 2017). Yet, Trump
quickly turned out to be much more a neoliberal than Clinton ever imagined,
especially since he ran against her progressive version of neoliberalism and its
commitments to multiculturalism. She may have cravenly fallen into sticking with
Clintonian neoliberalism as its own desperate if moderate, Third Way, New
Democrat approach to squeezing benefits from the prevailing power structure for
Middle America. But Trump more fulsomely lived and breathed a cutthroat
neoliberalism, perhaps even thoughtlessly, or even somatically, as if it were the
only way to act in the world.
Trump’s ascendancy is very much associated with the rise of far-right, nativistic
demagogues in Europe and Asia, all seemingly reacting to neoliberal policies that
promote globalization, immigration, and multiculturalism while leaving native
workers more economically vulnerable (Müller, 2016). His friendship with Russian
President Vladimir Putin showed Trump was attracted to leaders who ruled
autocratically. Some of the more demagogic leaders of these movements are more
explicitly fascistic in their orientation and many take an autocratic approach to
governing. Some say Trump is a fascist, but neoliberalism has strong affinities
with fascism, especially in using state disciplinary power on subordinate classes so
that they will be market compliant in ways that serve corporate interests
(Chaudhary and Chappe, 2016). The long wave of structural change from the
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Introduction xvii

1970s until Trump’s election has concentrated wealth and power at the top and
elites have used that shift to re-make the state to run consistent with market
principles to benefit those who dominate the market system (Schram, 2015). The
autocrats might run against neoliberalism but end up ruling consistent with it.
With Trump as president, we can see now clearly that neoliberalism has not
gone away and is not likely to any time soon. It remains hegemonic as the largely
unstated public policy orientation of our time. While much has been written
about neoliberalism as ideology and as a public policy orientation, much more
remains to be said and needs to be said in an age of Trump where the president
embodies that ideology and orientation without perhaps even knowing it and
without ever saying its name or defending its perspective.
In fact, neoliberalism, it turns out, is more of an implicit orientation to governing
than a full-blown, explicit ideology. It is more the zeitgeist for making decisions in a
market-centered society (Schram, 2015). Whereas President Richard Nixon said we
are all Keynesians now, it goes without saying that today we are all neoliberals,
increasingly under pressure to make key life decisions, publicly and privately,
collectively as well as individually, according to market logic. It remains the case
that in today’s neoliberal society, people are expected to become entrepreneurs of
the self who can take full responsibility for our personal choices. In this way, we
enact what has come to be called “neoliberal governmentality” (Foucault, 2008).
Trump is that neoliberal man-child who instinctively acts in a neoliberal fashion,
now as president, performing his incessant and highly insecure market-centered
approach to his own life and applying it to his public decision-making.
Trump therefore is part of something larger. Nancy Pelosi, the leader of the
Democrats in the US House of Representatives, affirmed that after the 2016
election when she responded to a question about doing more to appeal to dis-
enchanted young voters: “We’re capitalists and that’s just the way it is” (Seipel,
2017). Neoliberalism is today’s most significant manifestation of the capitalism
Pelosi says reigns supreme. Therefore, this volume’s important intellectual
resources can have profound pertinence to the politics of our time. The essays in
this volume were in most cases completed before Trump was elected and do not
specifically address his policy proposals. Yet, their relevance is likely to endure
beyond a Trump presidency. Neoliberalism remains hegemonic irrespective of
what happens to his incendiary approach to governing. Both parties remain
focused on proposing neoliberal approaches to addressing social and economic
issues at home and issues of economic development and political stability abroad.
Each chapter makes an important contribution to the growing literature on
neoliberalism, especially as it relates to social policy, and most especially regarding
the self-making processes enacted by neoliberalism via social policy. The volume
brings together a diverse set of essays that examine both the theory and the
practice of neoliberalism in this regard. The essays use theory to interrogate neo-
liberalism critically and therefore can provide resources for political resistance in an
age of neoliberalism.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

xviii Introduction

The lessons for thinking critically about neoliberalism today come from a wide
range of sources. The chapters are authored by an interdisciplinary group of
scholars from political science, sociology, geography, social work, and related fields.
Included in this diverse group are scholars from the United States and Europe, who
offer theoretical and empirical accounts of the rolling out of neoliberalism as a
policy regime in different parts of the world.
The chapters range across issues of theory and practice, but have a keen focus
on how neoliberalism puts in place a disciplinary regime for managing sub-
ordinate populations. The beginning chapters provide a theoretical context for
thinking about neoliberalism as promoting a highly individualizing form of
population management. The next set of chapters considers the ways in which
neoliberalism has relied on social policy to discipline citizens as particular types of
compliant subjects within subordinated populations. This is followed by a section
that includes two chapters on the role of policing in disciplining individuals of
these most often racialized, subordinated populations. Next are three chapters on
urban policy and how neoliberalism reshapes urban governance to focus on issues
of disciplining the subordinated to be complaint, economically as well as socially
and politically. The final set of chapters asks what it will take politically to get
beyond neoliberalism.

The Origin
These chapters did not come to us randomly but originated in a two-year-long
faculty seminar on neoliberalism at Hunter College, CUNY, where we worked
to bring the best people to talk about their specific research efforts on neoliber-
alism. The seminar was an ongoing event of significant scholarly attention at
Hunter. It started in the fall of 2014 when a select group of Hunter College
faculty and CUNY doctoral students began meeting to present their work on and
discuss neoliberalism as the influential ideological orientation it had become in
theory and practice in the USA and across the globe. To further this process of
reflection and discussion, the faculty decided to invite additional scholars who had
written on the topic to make presentations.
The seminar presentations took place from the fall of 2014 through the spring
of 2016 and included scholars from a widening geographic network: Mimi
Abramovitz, Leonard Feldman, Marianna Pavlovskaya, Sanford Schram, and Jillian
Schwedler, from Hunter College; David Harvey, Ruthie Gilmore, and Cindi
Katz from the CUNY Graduate Center; Nancy Fraser, from New School for
Social Research; Bernard Harcourt, Columbia University; Jodi Dean, Hobart and
William Smith Colleges; Lester Spence, Johns Hopkins University; Carolyn
Fraker and Joe Soss, University of Minnesota; Barbara Cruikshank, University of
Massachusetts; Jamie Peck, University of British Columbia; Mitchell Dean and
Kaspar Villadsen, Copenhagen Business School; Sophie Danneris, Aalborg Uni-
versity in Denmark; Maureen Matarese and Dorte Caswell, presenting together
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Introduction xix

from Borough of Manhattan Community College and Aalborg University,


Copenhagen, respectively; François Ewald, French Technological Academy and
Columbia University Center for Contemporary Critical Thought; Bettina
Leibetseder, Johannes Kepler University, Linz, Austria; Katherine Gibson, Western
Sydney University, Australia; and Guy Feldman, Tel Aviv University.
This volume reflects some the best presentations of our seminar. It adds sig-
nificantly to the literature on neoliberalism. While there is a burgeoning literature
on neoliberalism, there is a dearth of books that bring theoretical analysis to bear
on concrete social policy issues. There are fewer that provide a comparative
analysis such as we offer in this book, with chapters on the EU, Denmark, Jordan,
Russia, the USA, and elsewhere. Our great group of seminar presenters provide
the opportunity to offer this more international and comparative perspective. The
essays included here also provide a good mix of theoretical and policy-related
analyses of neoliberalism that are specifically focused on neoliberalism’s dis-
ciplinary regime for regimenting subordinate populations into a market-centered
society.
While a variety of work by prominent scholars informs the scholarship showcased
here, a few jump out as most significant. The volume reflects the long shadow
Michel Foucault (2008) has cast over the study of what he calls “neoliberal govern-
mentality,” where the state is marketized in order to get subordinate populations to
be market compliant. Foucault is at the center of a number of chapters in this
volume. A very critical, recent work that draws heavily from Foucault but also
re-works and extends his thinking is that of Wendy Brown (2015). Almost as
influential is Philip Mirowski (2014). Other chapters draw from a wide variety of
sources including from several of the seminar participants whose work is not
included in this volume but who made significant contributions to the seminar.
Prominent among these are David Harvey (2007) and Bernard Harcourt (2012).
Also, key contributor to the existing literature Jamie Peck (2011) has a co-authored
chapter in this volume. A common theme in these writings is that neoliberalism is
not mere market fundamentalism that emphasizes liberating markets from state
control. Instead, neoliberalism involves centrally re-orienting the state to use
its coercive power to discipline people to be market compliant in furtherance of
creating a more thorough, robust market-centered society, where market logic
reigns supreme over all decision-making across all social spheres and at all levels,
personal and political, individual and collective.
Drawing on these and other sources and this orientation toward understanding
neoliberalism, our contributors offer a rich set of essays that can help understand
the challenges for resisting the neoliberal disciplinary regime in an age of Trump.
We say this in particular since Trump’s neoliberalism is likely to be extremely
harsh for those on the bottom of the socio-economic order. It is all the more
pertinent then that a prominent unifying theme to the included essays is the
relationship of neoliberalism to social welfare and related public policies that affect
people’s opportunities to thrive socially and economically.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

xx Introduction

The Chapters that Follow


The chapters that follow are organized into sections. The first section lays theoretical
groundwork on the issue of neoliberalism to social policy. Jodi Dean provides a
theoretically rich examination of how the left has failed to come to grips with the
individualization that neoliberalism enacts on public discourse today. Her chapter,
entitled “Nothing Personal,” takes up what she sees as neoliberalism’s anti-political
assault on collectivity. She looks at shifts in “commanded individuality” from the
1970s to the present, highlighting the political, economic, social, and cultural
challenges on the individual as she becomes “the overburdened remainder of
dismantled institutions and solidarities – the survivor.” Revisiting Christopher
Lasch’s The Culture of Narcissism (1996), Dean notes that it underscored incisively
the ways capitalist processes simultaneously promote the individual as the primary
unit of capitalism and unravel the institutions of solidaristic support on which this
unit depends. She puts later sociologists in conversation with Lasch to extend the
implications of Lasch’s account. The chapter concludes by examining the effects
of neoliberalism’s individuation for the left. Dean provides an incisive critique of
the fragmentation of a collective perspective under the weight of reasserted
capitalist class power. She draws on Elias Canetti’s (1984) work on crowds to
introduce the power of the many as a productive response to the demands for
individuality. Dean emphasizes that her chapter aims to dislodge from left thinking
the individualism that serves as an impasse to left politics.
Mitchell Dean’s chapter follows in direct relationship to Jodi Dean’s analysis. In
“The Secret Life of Neoliberal Subjectivity,” Dean addresses both Michel Foucault’s
contribution to the current debate on neoliberalism, together with its legacy in
governmentality studies, and the intellectual-historical context of his own
engagement with it in the later part of the 1970s. The chapter examines Foucault’s
view of liberalism and neoliberalism as sharing an orientation toward the “art of
government” as manifested in post-war Europe and the United States. In parti-
cular, Dean notes how neoliberalism operated within such political movements as
the French “Second Left” of the 1970s. Dean uses this historiography to critically
examine the still contested legacy of Foucault in what has come to be called
“governmentality studies.” Dean concludes:

Foucault can seem insightful and prescient about neoliberalism because he


would come to share so many of its premises: the impossibility of a science of
the human that does not intensify domination, the economy – not the public,
or the state – as the generator and manifestation of truth, at least for liberal or
even modern governance, and the occlusion of the question of inequality.
Foucault both acutely diagnosed and to some extent could be said to have
participated in what amounted to a counter-revolution in public policy.

The last of the three chapters in this first theoretically oriented section of the
book is by Kaspar Villadsen: “Foucault’s Three Ways of Decentering the State.”
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Introduction xxi

This chapter extends Dean’s analysis to think how Foucault’s evolution enables us
to think about power, politics, and policy in an age of neoliberalism. Villadsen
explains how Foucault reached a “decentered position on the state.” For Villadsen,
the later Foucault reflected his evolution away from state-centered political
analyses to the point that Foucault seemed to conclude that neoliberalism would
allow greater space for difference and individual self-formation. Villadsen con-
cludes that Foucault’s theorizing, while not without problems, ends up being
prismatic in ways that can help study and challenge power in a neoliberal era.
Building on the theoretical investigations of the first section, the second section
of the book includes chapters organized around the role of social policy in con-
structing individuals as compliant citizens. Chapter 4, “Investing in Social Sub-
jects: The European Turn to Social Investment as the Human Capital Theory of
Social Citizenship,” by Bettina Leibetseder examines critically the self-making
involved in what is called the EU’s “Social Investment Package.” The EU’s
Social Investment strategy places the newer conceit of social investment on equal
footing with the established idea of social protection. Leibetseder notes that critics
of the scheme argue that social investment over-invests in an economic governing
rationality that threatens established understandings of social citizenship (and its
welfare state protections) as grounded in solidarity as a basis for binding citizens
and societies together, especially in the emerging and fragile European Community.
Theoretically, the social investment perspective could actually help perpetuate
commitments to social citizenship, even as it endorses a human capital approach
and redistributive aims concomitantly. Leibetseder argues that this remains possi-
ble due to the EU’s “polysemic” notion of social investment; however, it may
instead advance neoliberal approaches to social welfare that would limit redis-
tribution to the poor. Analyzing EU policy documents, Leibetseder finds four
types of subject formation variously affected by the EU’s social investment
approach. Not only do the unemployed face an activation regime, but also the
young and old, sick and healthy, are targeted in neoliberalizing individuating
ways. Leibetseder concludes that the European Commission’s Social Investment
Package moves human capital theory into mainstream European social policy and
with less than positive implications for sustaining a commitment to an inclusionary,
solidaristic social citizenship.
The issue of targeting populations is extended in Chapter 5, “Ontologies of
Poverty in Russia and Duplicities of Neoliberalism,” by Marianna Pavlovskaya.
For Foucault, neoliberal governmentality centrally involved the state creating
populations and then getting people to populate these as compliant members of
particular groupings, all in the service of stabilizing the social order. Pavlovskaya
notes that in contrast to the Soviet past, when differences in material wealth were
relatively limited, the post-Soviet transformation has produced a dramatically
polarized society with a large impoverished population including working poor.
Consequently, Russia has to develop from scratch new metrics and policies to
deal with this emerging population that is a result of regime change at the state
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

xxii Introduction

level. This chapter examines how these metrics of poverty have evolved in ways
that both normalize and obscure the extent of poverty produced by the twenty-
five years of the arduous transition from state socialism to free-market capitalism
and in the end reinforce this large population. During this transformation, the
Soviet system of universal welfare, arguably the most complete and comprehen-
sive in the world, was radically transformed as well, through regulations largely
guided by neoliberal ideologies adopted by the Russian state. The authorities
implemented a shift to means-tested and targeted welfare provisioning following
Western societies who built their welfare systems under capitalism over decades.
The chapter concludes by comparing unemployment benefits in Russia with
those in the United States (a common reference point for Russians) in order to
highlight the deleterious effects of neoliberal reform creating and normalizing the
poor as an distinct population. Pavlovskaya suggests that, given its growing
influence on the world stage, the Russian neoliberal regime that the state has
rapidly and successfully built, and continues to support with an increasingly con-
solidated authority, may indeed set the development path for the rest of the
world unless we learn to resist and divert this trajectory.
Chapter 6, “Neoliberalism Viewed from the Bottom Up: A Qualitative
Longitudinal Study of Benefit Claimants’ Experiences of the Unemployment
System,” by Sophie Danneris, drills down more concretely into the neoliberalizing
effects of the unemployment system in Denmark. Arguing that it is pivotal to look
at neoliberal policy from the bottom up, this chapter explores the lived experiences
of program participants. Through a qualitative longitudinal study on the effects of
recent welfare reforms in Denmark, Danneris explores how neoliberalism is
experienced from the viewpoint of the people subject to it on a daily basis. She
focuses on vulnerable long-term unemployed benefit claimants. Through an
in-depth analysis of client interviews, Danneris highlights how clients are coping
by adjusting to the new rules, and in the last instance working as best they can to
make the system work for them personally. Thus, by looking at policy through
the eyes of the people who are directly affected by the new regime, the chapter
offers an “everyday world” perspective to the analysis of how active labor market
reforms involve self-making and re-making. In the process, the study reveals a
multitude of hidden dimensions to the way neoliberalism manifests itself in the
daily life of the unemployed.
Chapter 7, “Neoliberal Talk: The Routinized Structures of Document-Focused
Social Worker–Client Discourse,” by Maureen Matarese and Dorte Caswell drills
down even further to examine how the interactions between social workers and
clients involve issues of self-making. This chapter uses conversation analysis to
examine this issue. Analyzing naturally occurring data from social work interac-
tions in a homeless shelter, the authors argue that combining a bottom-up, street
level bureaucracy perspective with a conversation analytical approach enables us
to discover new aspects of form-related interaction. The analysis shows how
standardization, routinization, time, and documentation function in concert to
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Introduction xxiii

accomplish social work goals that end up consciously or not having good as well
as bad implications for client self-understandings.
The third section brings together two chapters that examine issues of governance
via population management when the subordinated are constructed as a deviant,
racialized other. In Chapter 8, “Criminal Justice Predation and Neoliberal Govern-
ance,” Joshua Page and Joe Soss examine how the racialized US state system
systematically operates not just to discipline but also to exploit. They focus on the
predatory practices associated with the carceral regime today that end up making
subordinated blacks vulnerable to becoming indentured citizens. Here the state is
the flip side of the social citizenship state that accords people social protections.
Instead, for those who do not meet the threshold conditions for inclusion in the
social citizenship state, often because they are poor, non-white, and sequestered
in marginal neighborhoods, the state is more Janus-faced and operates to dis-
cipline more than to uplift. But it goes further to exploit their subordination to
serve the state’s need to sustain itself financially. We see this most especially
through the operations of the criminal justice system (though it is by no means
limited to that). Page and Soss note that this was forcefully brought before the
American public in 2015, when the US Department of Justice (DOJ) concluded
in a detailed report in response to the shooting of Michael Brown by police
officer Darren Wilson that the city of Ferguson, Missouri had been operating a
“predatory system of government.” Police officers were acting as street-level
enforcers for a program – aggressively promoted by city officials – in which fines
and fees were used to extract resources from poor communities of color and deliver
them to municipal coffers. Page and Soss argue that what the DOJ discovered in
Ferguson should not be seen as anomalous, either in relation to US history or
governance in contemporary America. They highlight how the predatory state
relies on “targeted mechanisms of resource extraction, organized by race, class,
and gender,” and deployed in specific communities, relying at times on private
actors. They argue that “the neoliberal era of governance has been marked by a
resurgence and transformation of state predation on poor communities of color.”
They conclude that neoliberalism will be misunderstood if we fail to develop a
theoretical and empirical account of its distinctive predatory forms and the new
model of the resulting form of “indentured citizenship” it is constructing.
In Chapter 9, “Neoliberalism and Police Reform,” Leonard Feldman pursues
the issues of neoliberal criminal justice further by examining how quantitative
performance measurement and surveillance combine to be redeployed in the
service of police reform. Relying on Bernard Harcourt (2012) and others, Feldman
describes how neoliberalism as a political form involves the development of parti-
cular technologies of measurement and observation. He considers two specific
reforms: (1) DOJ investigations of police departments to establish evidence of
unconstitutional, illegal conduct; and (2) policy-violating uses of force through a
CompStat-like approach to quantitative performance measurement. He turns to
the debate about how police body cameras redeploy contemporary surveillance
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

xxiv Introduction

technologies in the service of making state actors accountable. In arguing that


neoliberal governance technologies play a role in police reform efforts, Feldman
recognizes the well-documented role of neoliberal policies in facilitating or pro-
ducing the intensified policing of urban space and the refocusing of punitive and
carceral mechanisms on subjects who fail to self-regulate according to market
norms. But he supplements that picture with an account of how neoliberal govern-
ance logics can become attached to different political projects. In conclusion, he
considers the limitations of such redeployed neoliberal technologies by arguing
that, even as they promise to restrict excess police violence, they “enframe” it in
an administrative logic that prevents consideration of broader questions of the
legitimacy of police use of force.
The fourth section of the book turns to the urban scene as the site for the most
intensified forms of neoliberal disciplining of the subordinated. In ways reminiscent
of David Harvey’s analysis of New York City (2007), in Chapter 10, “Neoliber-
alizing Detroit,” Jamie Peck and Heather Whiteside provide a critical study of
Detroit as a test case for a domesticated form of neoliberal structural adjustment in
the United States. They note that Detroit was one of the first cities to “entre-
preneurialize” after the early 1970s, as a largely defensive response to economic
decline, white flight, and state withdrawal. Detroit has since experienced its own
version of corporate failure, having declared the largest municipal bankruptcy in
US history. The authors diagnose that the city has been subjected to a “politically
steered and racially targeted process of financialized restructuring,” based on a
neoliberal model of technocratic governance, and involving court-administered
municipal downsizing and public asset stripping. They explain that Detroit is now
being repurposed, in leaner form, for new markets. “In the wake of the Wall
Street crash of 2008, Detroit has become a strategic target in an evolving regime
of austerity urbanism, with important implications for cities near and far, as well
as for emergent modalities of market rule.”
In Chapter 11, “Political Dissent in Amman, Jordan: Neoliberal Geographies
of Protest and Policing,” Jillian Schwedler turns the analysis of neoliberalism
toward the regulation of street protest (which became a staple of resisting Trump’s
policies). Schwedler notes that in the case of the city of Amman, its dramatic
expansion over the past thirty years led to its population more than doubling
through growth of the indigenous population being supplemented by an influx of
two new waves of refugees (from Iran and now Syria). King Abdullah II, who
gained the throne in 1999, has sought to address the growing economic disparities
of the city with neoliberal reforms, notably developing a foreign real estate
market, attracting foreign finance services, and implementing incremental austerity
programs. The result has been a dramatic altering of the locations and repurposing
of public space, with attendant effects on the ability to mobilize politically,
especially for public demonstrations and street protests. Schwedler notes that with
the shifting of the city’s built environment in the course of advancing neoliberal
projects, the visibility and availability of public spaces in which citizens can protest
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Introduction xxv

has been significantly reduced. In other words, this chapter examines the changing
geography of the city through the lens of political protests. It utilizes original field
research to illustrate how the neoliberalization of the city – or, what turns out to
be half of the city, to be precise – has a profound depoliticizing effect, rendering
some protests invisible as it eliminates the spaces previously available for enacting
protest.
The final section of the book includes two chapters about responding to the
challenges of neoliberalism. Both offer heterodox responses that transgress the
convention of a left–right continuum. In Chapter 12, “The Knight’s Move:
Social Change in an Age of Consolidated Power,” Sanford Schram discusses the
challenges for getting meaningful social policy change in an age of neoliberalism
where power is increasingly concentrated among market actors in highly unequal
ways and only incremental policy change is likely. Using the neoliberalization of
social welfare policy in the USA as his main example, Schram goes on to suggest
that the key to progressive policy change is trying to figure out how to make
incremental changes that lay the basis for more dramatic transformation which
helps us get beyond the limitations of existing power relationships. This is not a
“progressive neoliberalism” that seeks to rationalize the existing neoliberal policy
regime (Fraser, 2017). Instead, it is a “radical incrementalism” that looks to
identify which incremental changes have radical potential to lay the basis for
eventually getting beyond the neoliberal disciplinary regime. The chapter suggests
how we can build on such incremental changes to rework power relationships and
begin the process of creating more inclusive, solidaristic, and equitable policies
that address fundamental problems rather than papering over them and rationa-
lizing them. The contentious example of Obamacare is put forward as a site for
thinking about radical incrementalism even as it faces its greatest threat of repeal
in the first moments of the Trump administration.
The last chapter in the book, Chapter 13, ”Neoliberalism: Towards a Critical
Counter-Conduct” is by Barbara Cruikshank. It extends the consideration of
how to respond to neoliberalism as hegemonic and does so by returning to the
insights of Michel Foucault. Cruikshank asks, as did Foucault, why we tend to
only focus on neoliberalism as always an instrument of subjection. Cruikshank
argues that that sort of critical conduct – in activist and academic alike – too often
remains under the spell of what Foucault called the “repressive hypothesis” and the
questionable presumption that freedom and knowledge – in this case movements
against and critical studies of neoliberalism – are external to power. Cruikshank
thoughtfully suggests such a presumption mistakenly unifies neoliberalism as an
object of resistance and essentializes it as self-evidently real, stable, and bad,
thereby closing off the door to contingent forces of change. For these reasons,
Cruikshank says, critical conduct under the spell of a neoliberal repressive
hypothesis has become an obstacle to the kind of critical thought and action
much needed in the current era. This kind of intransigent stance leads to the
devaluation and disparagement of ongoing struggles that are deemed insufficiently
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

xxvi Introduction

critical of neoliberalism. Cruikshank uses examples of current movements challen-


ging neoliberalism from within as models for a more politically effective “critical”
counter-conduct.
Cruikshank’s analysis is profoundly protean in a number of ways that make for
a fitting last chapter of this book. For instance, it opens the door to considering
other voices to move beyond the so-called “capitalocentrism,” that is, the tendency
to examine capitalism as a homogeneous economy while disregarding the sig-
nificance of the ongoing non-capitalist economic practices that over time could
prove to be critical to constructing “post-capitalist” politics (Gibson-Graham
2006; Roelvink et al., 2015).
In conclusion, these chapters reflect a diverse set of voices, examining issues
both theoretical and empirical. They share a focus on neoliberalism, especially as
manifested in social policy and how those policies work to target subordinated
populations for discipline. They provide resources for countering neoliberalism in
the current era. While we may have thought the age of neoliberalism was fading
away, it seems ever more ascendant, making these essays profoundly politically
pertinent.
The current political climate is undoubtedly challenging and those seeking to
resist the perpetuation of a neoliberal system of subordination need all the help
they can get. But it is important to keep in mind that opportunities for political
resistance are still available. It is important to remember, for instance, that
Trump’s victory does not mean that American society as a whole has endorsed his
faux populism and cutthroat neoliberalism. The speed at which protests greeted
his ascendancy has indicated otherwise. The opposition comes from a variety of
sources, opposing his racism, sexism, and class politics that reinforce some of the
most oppressive dimensions of how neoliberalism gets enacted through state
policy today. Even without Trump, neoliberalism’s grip on policy is not likely to
be loosened without ongoing active resistance to the disciplinary regime. Critical
analyses of neoliberalism, therefore, will continue to be relevant to the ongoing
struggles. Our hope is that readers will find important political insights in these
essays, especially for combating neoliberalism as the defining way to govern
still today.

References
Brown, W. (2015). Undoing the Demos: Neoliberalism’s Stealth Revolution. Cambridge: Zone
Books.
Edsall, T. (2017). The Peculiar Populism of Donald Trump. New York Times, February 2.
Retrieved from: www.nytimes.com/2017/02/02/opinion/the-peculiar-populism-
of-donald-trump.html?ribbon-ad-idx=3&rref=opinion&module=Ribbon&version=con
text&region=Header&action=click&contentCollection=Opinion&pgtype=article
Chaudhary, A. and Chappe, R. (2016). The Supermanagerial Reich. Los Angeles Review of
Books, November 7. Retrieved from: https://lareviewofbooks.org/article/the-superma
nagerial-reich/
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Introduction xxvii

Foucault, M. (2008). The Birth of Biopolitics: Lectures at the Collège de France 1978–1979.
London: Palgrave.
Fraser, N. (2017). The End of Progressive Neoliberalism. Dissent, January 2. Retrieved
from: www.dissentmagazine.org/online_articles/progressive-neoliberalism-reactionary-
populism-nancy-fraser.
Gibson-Graham, J. K. (2006). A Postcapitalist Politics. 1st edition. Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press.
Harcourt, B. (2012). The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order
(Reprint edition). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Harvey, D. (2007). A Brief History of Neoliberalism. New York: Oxford University Press.
Honig, B. (2017). The President’s House Is Empty. Boston Review, January 17. Retrieved
from: http://bostonreview.net/politics/bonnie-honig-president%E2%80%99s-house-
empty
Klein, N. (2016). It Was the Democrats’ Embrace of Neoliberalism that Won It for
Trump. The Guardian, November 9. Retrieved January 30, 2017, from: www.thegua
rdian.com/commentisfree/2016/nov/09/rise-of-the-davos-class-sealed-americas-fate
Krinsky, J. (2008). Free Labor: Workfare and the Contested Language of Neoliberalism. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Lynch, C. (2016). Neoliberalism’s Epic Fail: The Reaction to Hillary Clinton’s Loss
Exposed the Impotent Elitism of Liberalism. Salon, November 19. Retrieved January
30, 2017, from: www.salon.com/2016/11/19/neoliberalisms-epic-fail-the-reaction-to-
hillary-clintons-loss-exposed-the-impotent-elitism-of-liberalism/
Mirowski, P. (2014). Never Let a Serious Crisis Go to Waste: How Neoliberalism Survived the
Financial Meltdown. London: Verso Books.
Müller, J-W. (2016). What is Populism?Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
Peck, J. (2011). Constructions of Neoliberal Reason. London: Oxford University Press.
Roelvink, G., St. Martin, K., and Gibson-Graham, J. K. (Eds.) (2015). Making Other
Worlds Possible: Performing Diverse Economies. Minneapolis: University Of Minnesota
Press.
Schram, S. F. (2015). The Return of Ordinary Capitalism: Neoliberalism, Precarity, Occupy.
New York: Oxford University Press.
Seipel, B. (2017). Pelosi Town Hall Question on Capitalism Wasn’t Planned: Report.
The Hill, February 2. Retrieved from: http://thehill.com/blogs/blog-briefing-room/news/
317639-pelosi-town-hall-question-on-capitalism-wasnt-planned-report
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

PART I

Theorizing Neoliberalism
The Individual, the Subject, and the Power
of the State
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

1
NOTHING PERSONAL
Jodi Dean

The era of communicative capitalism is an era of commanded individuality. The


command circulates in varying modes. Each is told, repeatedly, that she is unique
and encouraged to cultivate this uniqueness. We learn to insist on and enjoy our
difference, intensifying processes of self-individuation. No one else is like us (like
me). The “do-it-yourself” injunction is so unceasing that “taking care of oneself”
appears as politically significant instead of as a symptom of collective failure – we
let the social safety net unravel – and economic contraction – in a viciously
competitive job market we have no choice but to work on ourselves, constantly,
just to keep up. Required to find out, decide, and express it all ourselves, we
construe political collectivity as nostalgia for the impossible solidarities of a different
era. The second-wave feminist idea that the “personal is political” has become
twisted into the presumption that the political is personal: how does this affect me?
Individualism has not always been so intense and unmitigated. As Jefferson
Cowie (2010) details in his history of the United States in the 1970s, “reformed
and diversified individualisms” undermined class-based approaches to economic
rights over the course of the decade.1 This chapter takes up the assault on collectivity.
Looking at shifts in commanded individuality from the 1970s to the present, I
highlight the enormous strains placed on the individual as it becomes the over-
burdened remainder of dismantled institutions and solidarities – the survivor. I
revisit Christopher Lasch’s The Culture of Narcissism (1979), marking the ways
capitalist processes simultaneously promote the individual as the primary unit of
capitalism and unravel the institutions of solidaristic support on which this unit
depends. Putting later sociologists in conversation with Lasch, I draw out the
limits of Lasch’s account. Even as Lasch’s descriptions of celebrity culture, com-
petition, and consumerism still resonate, individualism is today less an indication
of narcissism than it is of psychosis. The chapter continues by considering a left
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

4 Jodi Dean

example of the off-loading of responsibility onto the individual: the debate over
the “new times” that took place at the end of the 1980s. Against the background
of the sociologists’ conversation, the emphases on individual responsibility and
identity in this debate appear as what they in fact were: the fragmentation of a
collective perspective under the weight of reasserted capitalist class power. The
last sections of the chapter begin an inversion that will be more fully developed in
Chapter 2. They find possibilities of collectivity in the ruptures of the fragile
individual form. With help from Elias Canetti’s (1984) indispensable study of
crowds, I introduce the power of the many and the relief it provides from the
unbearable demand for individuality. This chapter aims to dislodge from left
thinking the individualism that serves as an impasse to left politics.
Two commercials illustrate the celebration of personal uniqueness characteristic
of communicative capitalism. Both are for soft drinks. Both, in different ways,
engage the limits conditioning the very individuality that they command.
On January 9, 2012, Dr Pepper announced a new advertising campaign,
“Always One of a Kind.” The campaign’s first commercial features hundreds of
people in red T-shirts with white lettering converging in a crowd to march down
streets and through a park. The T-shirts have slogans like “I’m One of a Kind,”
“I’m a Cougar,” “I’m a Fighter,” and “I’m a Pepper” (one of Dr Pepper’s earlier
slogans). The accompanying music is a cover of the 1968 Sammy Davis, Jr. hit,
“I’ve Gotta Be Me.” According to the press release accompanying the campaign’s
launch, the red T-shirt wearers are Dr Pepper fans “proudly showing off their
own original expressions on T-shirts describing what makes them unique and
different from the rest of the crowd.”2 In the optimistic words of the company’s
director of marketing, the campaign “should serve as a catalyst for expressing
originality and being authentically you.” Dr Pepper also offered fans the
“opportunity to express their originality by ordering their own ‘Always One of a
Kind’ t-shirts on DrPepper.com.”
Putting aside the designation of customers as “fans,” the targeted demographic
appears to be people who want to express their uniqueness. The commercial hails
them as individuals, inviting them to identify with particular slogans and identities.
Within Dr Pepper’s commercial imaginary, going to the streets isn’t collective
rage; it’s individual self-expression, an opportunity to assert one’s individuality
and stand out. Crowds are that against which individuals define themselves. The
Dr Pepper Brand, in this imaginary, is a natural continuation of primary urges
to establish unique identities, a helpful, vital supplement for the crucial task of
distinguishing oneself from others.
The commercial’s presumption that people need support in expressing their
originality – an authenticity catalyst of the kind a T-shirt might provide – gives it
an ironic inflection. Augmented through the retro turn to Sammy Davis, Jr., the
irony of expressing one’s authenticity via a branded soft drink invites another
identificatory twist: are you like the crowd of those who really think that
Dr Pepper T-shirts make you unique, or does your capacity to get the joke, to
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Nothing Personal 5

recognize that originality necessarily exceeds any branded media image, make you
different from, even superior to, the rest of the crowd? The fact that some of the
slogans are reappropriations of offensive labels – “cougar” and “mamma’s boy,”
for instance – opens up this alternative. The wearers of these shirts are unique in
their strength, confident enough to assert the labels, to own them. Thus, a further
irony: their courage is amplified by the crowd. The energy of the commercial, its
feel, comes less from what’s written on the T-shirts (the majority of which can’t
be read) than from the sea of red that carries people along. The celebration of
difference and creativity comes from the enthusiasm of a crowd where people
march shoulder to shoulder, pumping their fists and taking confidence in their
collectivity. Even as collectivity as a trope is coopted into the service of amplify-
ing individual courage, the fact of, the need for, this amplification cuts through the
individualist message as it acknowledges the power of the crowd.
Coca-Cola’s “Share a Coke” campaign likewise takes individuality as its theme,
targeting a demographic the company presents as preoccupied with the assertion
of personal uniqueness.
“For teens and Millennials, personalization is not a fad, it’s a way of life,”
explains the press release announcing the campaign. “It’s about self-expression,
individual storytelling and staying connected with friends” (Moye 2014). Launched
in Australia in 2011 and expanded into some fifty additional countries, the cam-
paign alters the Coke iconography by replacing the Coke logo with personal
names. It encourages young consumers to find cans and bottles with the names of
themselves and their friends, photograph them, and share them online.
In the campaign, personal names take the place of the brand. Consumers aren’t
called on to show their individuality by wearing the brand. The brand comes to
them, taking on their individual identities, letting individuals see themselves in it.
The icon becomes abstract enough to carry individual identities while nonetheless
transcending them. The appeal of the campaign arises not just from the personal
name but from the personal name in the place of the known and popular. The
social media dimension of the campaign testifies to the continuation of the place
of the brand. The Coke icon is still there, now riding on and circulating through
individual uploads of personal self-expression, less viral marketing than free product
placement in the intimate moments of everyday life.
When the left echoes injunctions to individuality, when we emphasize unique
perspectives and personal experiences, we function as vehicles for communicative
capitalist ideology. “Left” becomes nothing but a name on a bottle, the shape of
which is determined for us and which relies on us for its circulation. Making
individual difference the basis of our politics, we fail to distinguish between
communicative capitalism and emancipatory egalitarian politics. Even worse, we
strengthen the ideology that impedes the cultivation of politically powerful
collectivities. To call on people to ground their politics in the personal experi-
ences that differentiate them from others is to reinforce capitalist dynamics of
individuation. Offering the fantasy of customizable politics, such a call says: look
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

6 Jodi Dean

at yourself from the specific position and interests given to you by capitalism and
do what you want. In so doing, it pushes away from the collectivity on which left
politics depends.

Individualism without Individuals


The injunction to individuality is so ubiquitous that it’s easy to forget its histories
and modulations (Seigel 2005). The research of sociologists such as Christopher
Lasch, Richard Sennett, Jennifer M. Silva, and Carrie M. Lane treads a path
through this history as it attends to the pathologies accompanying capitalist processes
of individuation. As I detail below, key sites along this path – rugged individual,
corporate gamesman, flexible temp worker, and sole survivor – open up the ways
economic turmoil, changes in the structure of authority, and the loss of self-
sufficiency give a tenuous quality to personal identity. The shifts from one site to
another demonstrate moreover how the competitive pressures of capitalist pro-
cesses become increasingly displaced onto and concentrated in the individual. The
forces enjoining individuation undermine it. The more the individual, that fictitious
subject of capitalism, is glorified, the more strained and impossible it becomes.
Lasch’s influential book The Culture of Narcissism: American Life in An Age of
Diminishing Expectations presents an individualism that has self-destructed.
Appearing in 1979, the book highlights the rise of a therapeutic sensibility. The
economic man of the nineteenth century “has given way to the psychological
man of our times – the final product of bourgeois individualism” (Lasch 1979,
p. xvi). For Lasch, the preoccupations with self, authenticity, and personal growth
that became prevalent over the course of the 1970s are symptomatic of an indi-
vidualism collapsing in on itself as commanded individuality struggles to realize
the ever-increasing expectations coming to burden it.
Lasch describes his critique of the therapeutic individual as “radical,” even as he
shares conservative concerns with the weakening of the family and the rise of
dependency. This overlap is worth noting. Not only does it point toward an
increasing convergence among critics of the basic institutions of the welfare state,
but it also indexes the common object of their concern: the fragile individual.
The difference between Lasch’s analysis and the conservative critique of welfare
liberalism consists in their targets. Where conservatives attack the bureaucracy of
the welfare state, Lasch attacks the bureaucracy of the corporation. He expands
this attack into a full assault on the broader impact of corporate culture on
American life. Lasch’s innovation stems from his diagnosis of the “me decade’s”
preoccupation with psychic health as a symptom of the more fundamental
intellectual and political bankruptcy of welfare state capitalism’s liberal pater-
nalism. The end of the individual in narcissistic hedonism and aggression is the
outgrowth of capitalism, inclusive of and exacerbated by the liberal welfare state.
Capitalism’s own injunctions to individuality overburden and undermine the
individual form.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Nothing Personal 7

Locating changes in the individual in the context of political and economic


change, Lasch contrasts the narcissistic personality of the twentieth century with
the rugged individual of the nineteenth century. His vision of the nineteenth-
century American psyche (clearly an ideological figure or organizing motif) comes
from the settler colonialism of the frontier. The pioneer fights to tame the West,
to subdue nature, and eliminate the native threat. This fight requires an attendant
internal battle: domination over more immediate appetites and impulses. Lasch
writes:

Through compulsive industry and relentless sexual repression, nineteenth-


century US Americans achieved a fragile triumph over the id. The violence
they turned against the Indians and against nature originated not in unrest-
rained impulse but in the white Anglo-Saxon superego, which feared the
wildness of the West because it objectified the wildness within each
individual.
(p. 10)

He continues, “Capital accumulation in its own right sublimated appetite and


subordinated the pursuit of self-interest to the service of future generations.” The
frontier American is egoistic and brutal, this brutality tied to a self-constraint on
behalf of civilized community. Violence is channeled, put to internal as well as
external use.
Lasch positions the corporation as the twentieth-century parallel to the frontier.
In contrast to the fierce and rugged pioneers fighting for survival, seventies
Americans are stuck in a boring, ordered, and banal society. Because the struggle
for success has replaced the struggle to survive, they have lost the capacity to
desire. Nonetheless US Americans in the seventies seethe with an inner rage that
bureaucratic society and its injunction to cheerful getting along prevents them
from expressing the violent forces of the id, now lacking an outlet.
Lasch uses the “executive” as a figure for twentieth-century narcissism. Unlike
the “organization man” associated with mid-century American anxiety about
conformism, Lasch’s executive is the bureaucratic “gamesman.” Seeking compe-
titive advantage, the gamesman wants to get ahead of everyone else. He values
quickness and mobility. He construes power in terms of momentum. He replaces
craftsmanship with socials skills that involve seducing, humiliating, and manip-
ulating others. The gamesman doesn’t interiorize rules as socially valid norms; he
experiences both work and personal relations as power struggles. Bureaucratic
emphases on rules and cooperation couple with personal exceptionalism – rules
don’t apply to me. The gamesman thus looks for ways to exploit conventions for
his own benefit. “Activities ostensibly undertaken purely for enjoyment often
have the real object of doing others in” (p. 66). A friendly demeanor, an air of
compassion, and an open, participatory approach to decision-making all conceal a
power game that the majority will lose.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

8 Jodi Dean

The sense that a game is being played extends beyond the corporation. The
lower orders, Lasch writes:

internalize a grandiose idea of the opportunities open to all, together with an


inflated opinion of their own capacities. If the lowly man resents those more
highly placed, it is only because he suspects them of grandly violating the
regulations of the game, as he would like to do himself if he dared. It never
occurs to him to insist on a new set of rules.
(p. 186)

The “lowly man” acquiesces uneasily to expectations of friendly cooperation,


suppressing dissatisfaction into a growing emptiness.
Lasch’s psychoanalytic explanation for the rise of the narcissistic personality
highlights changes in the paternal function. Unlike the materially self-sufficient
frontier family, the family in the second half of the twentieth century depends on
help and advice from experts. Whether as medical and therapeutic child-rearing
guidance or educational and juridical intervention in the domestic sphere,
expertise dislodges symbolic patriarchal authority. This dislodging continues
broader patterns associated with industrial development, more specifically with
the separation of production and reproduction, the distancing of children from
labor, and the diminution of opportunities for fathers to teach the technical skills
associated with their work directly to their children. The father’s absence
“encourages the development of a harsh and punitive superego based largely on
archaic images of the parents, fused with grandiose self-images” (p. 178). The
child doesn’t identify with parents; it introjects them, holding itself up to idea-
lized standards and punishing itself for failing to achieve them. Put in Lacanian
terms, the change in the paternal function is a decline in authority such that the
symbolic law can no longer provide a site of relief from superegoic demands
(Žižek 1999, pp. 322–334).
The decline of symbolic authority in liberal therapeutic society induces cultural
narcissism. Welfare capitalism’s bureaucratic rationality replaces the previous era’s
hierarchy with administrators, technicians, and experts. The struggle to succeed
within the confines of the corporate bureaucratic game takes the place of survival
under frontier conditions. Rather than having symbolic authority, experts and
administrators have knowledge. This knowledge is generally contestable and
provisional: experts disagree; what a bureaucrat knows may not be useful. The
culture of technocratic expertise and management absolves individuals of
responsibility, making everyone a victim of sickness or circumstance. More
broadly, narcissistic culture infantilizes by promoting dependence on the patern-
alist bureaucracies of welfare liberalism (corporation and state) and at the same
time encouraging the pursuit of pleasure. The narcissistic person admires the
strong and rich – celebrities – for their independence, their capacity to do and
have whatever they want. Mass media encourages the fascination with celebrity,
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Nothing Personal 9

amplifying the narcissist’s tendency to divide society into two groups: winners
and losers, the great and the crowd. Self-fulfillment and hedonism are celebrated,
yet unsatisfying and, increasingly, unattainable. In response, people absorb them-
selves in a search for authenticity, their skepticism toward the falsity of mass culture’s
manufactured illusions manifesting as an ironic detachment that further distances
them from meaningful connections with others.
What Lasch diagnoses as pathological or secondary narcissism is a reactive
individuality that accompanies changes in capitalist society associated with mass
production and consumption. When consumption is a way of life, work need not
be meaningful, fair, or morally necessary (as a previous generation held). Instead,
the purpose of work is acquisition. Consumption solves all problems, fills all
needs. Rather than postponing pleasure, consumerism enjoins gratification now.
The concomitant growth in management and proliferation of technicians, experts,
and knowledge professionals presents “new forms of capitalist control, which
established themselves first in the factory and then spread throughout society”
(p. 235). Having lost its role in production, the family is stripped of its role in
reproduction as its social tasks either become matters in need of expert intervention
or reducible to problems solved by the right commodities. The effect of these
developments is a realization of the logic of capitalism such that “the pursuit
of self-interest, formerly identified with the rational pursuit of gain and the
accumulation of wealth, has become a search for pleasure and psychic survival”
(p. 69). The result, which Lasch says was already foreseen by the Marquis de
Sade, is the reduction of people to objects. Each person is to be used for the
enjoyment of another: “pure individualism thus issues in the most radical repu-
diation of individuality” (p. 70). The culture of narcissism erodes the individual it
ostensibly celebrates.
In sum, Lasch links changes in the individual form to changes in capitalism.
The shift from the rugged individual of the frontier to the gamesman of the
corporation is economic and psychic. As the struggle to survive becomes a drive to
consume, the self-reliance of the frontier morphs into dependence on corporate and
state bureaucracy. Frustrated individuals narcissistically strain against their traps,
identifying with celebrities and searching for authenticity. They want to be
unique, exceptional. The rules don’t apply to them, so they need not abide by
them. They can focus on themselves, their own well-being, using others as means
to achieve it.
A quarter of a century later, Richard Sennett (2006) suggests that deepening
inequality and economic insecurity have further changed the contemporary
individual. Where Lasch highlights the bureaucratic corporation for its cultivation
of gamesmanship and dependency, Sennett considers the so-called “new economy”
of temporary workers, technology workers, and entrepreneurs (before and after
the bursting of the dot-com bubble). These workers aren’t dependent on
bureaucracy. They aren’t locked into the banal security of the corporation and its
internal machinations. Their lives and work are unstable, without guarantees,
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

10 Jodi Dean

precarious. They lack a narrative for adulthood. Many work on short-term contracts.
Companies want to be flexible – and to avoid providing health insurance and
pensions. The critique of dependency has become itself an interiorized norm.
Whether a firm employs the winner-take-all dynamic of internal markets, relies
on subcontractors and temporary labor, or uses consultants and a revolving door
of executives, primary business values are autonomy and self-direction. Workers
worry about keeping their skills up-to-date, having the potential to learn new tasks
quickly and cultivating easily transferable capacities such as “problem-solving.”
Surprising, though, is the resonance of Sennett’s account with Lasch’s. One
might expect the enforced self-reliance of the new economy to induce a sense
of purpose and direction along the lines of the rugged individualism of the
frontier. Instead, Sennett’s sociological investigations into late capitalism suggest
a self oriented toward the short term, focused on potential, and capable of
jettisoning the past. This echoes Lasch’s highlighting of immediacy, flexibility,
and a break with historical continuity. Like Lasch, Sennett emphasizes the
separation of power from authority, the diminution of trust, and the growth of
anxiety. But where Lasch presents the pressure confronting the individual as an
effect of a corporate culture that breeds gamesmanship and dependence, Sennett
attributes the problem to the loss of corporate culture and the unmooring of
individuals from the intelligible patterns of everyday life that results. The
corporation no longer provides a stabilizing point of reference for the narrative of
working life.
Lasch of course observes that the Protestant work ethic eroded decades ago.
Sennett, however, links its disciplinary effects to the corporate structuring of life
patterns (even for those working outside the corporation).
On the one hand, insofar as he attends to a certain loss, Sennett signals the
decline of the symbolic that subtends Lasch’s analysis of the change in paternal
authority. With the vantage of two more decades, Sennett detects that this
change is a loss. He analyzes this loss in terms of meaning and language: the
absence of a place from which to narrate one’s life. On the other hand, because
Sennett concretizes this loss as a loss of narrative rather than of symbolic authority,
he overlooks the real changes to the individual form that Lasch already diagnosed.
Sennett wants to shore up the individual. Lasch recognizes the form’s obsoles-
cence. By emphasizing the missing narrative of adulthood, Sennett thus covers
over the more fundamental disruption at the level of the symbolic.
For Sennett, the new economy has an upside. It allows for the emergence of
new personal qualities such as “repudiation of dependence, development of one’s
potential ability, the capacity to transcend possessiveness” (p. 182). Accentuating
the bright side of the post-welfare state technologized economy, Sennett tries to
redeem the project of the New Left, making its critique of bureaucracy, cult of
individuality, and celebration of emotional authenticity into not simply vanishing
mediators of communicative capitalism but real achievements to be continued.
He packages his recommendations for this continuation as the cultural values that
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Nothing Personal 11

individual workers require to sustain themselves in the fast-paced and volatile


economy: narrative, usefulness, and craftsmanship.
Sennett’s advocacy of a “cultural anchor” for an economy he recognizes as
productive of extreme inequality and social instability puts Lasch’s critique of
monopoly capitalism in stark relief: Lasch’s rejection of capitalism really is radical.
Jennifer M. Silva (2013) draws out an alternative to Sennett’s emphasis on a
missing narrative of adulthood. The narrative isn’t missing. The narrative has
changed, morphing into a more extreme version of the therapeutic self Lasch
already identified in the collapse of its material and symbolic supports. What
matters in the twenty-first century is individuation itself. “In a time when suf-
fering is plentiful and work and family unreliable,” Silva writes, competent
adulthood is defined “not in terms of traditional markers like financial inde-
pendence, a career, or a marriage, but rather in terms of psychic development:
achieving sobriety, overcoming addiction, fighting a mental illness, or simply
not becoming one’s parents” (p. 125). Silva’s alternative account of the pressures
on contemporary adults draws from her ethnographic study of working class
adults in Massachusetts and Virginia. Her interviewees emphasize self-reliance,
making it on their own. They can’t rely on experts or institutions. Other people
are likely to fail or betray them. Individualism preserves and protects their own
best thing, the only thing they can rely on, themselves. Their repudiation of
dependence is a reaction to the loss of dependable others. Rather than
an achievement, independence is a fetish barely holding together the fragile
individual form.
Silva’s account of a transition to adulthood marked not by “entry into social
groups and institutions but rather the explicit rejection of them” provides a
poignant rejoinder to Sennett (p. 84). One man tells Silva that “the hardest part
about being an adult is finding a real fucking job” (p. 98). People aren’t lacking a
narrative for adulthood. Capitalism presents adulthood as an individual project. For
the young working people Silva interviewed, individualism equals dignity. They
tell heroic tales of self-sufficiency, turning inward as they manage feelings of
betrayal, accept flexibility and flux, and buttress their sense of being utterly alone.
Although the dependencies of the welfare state and corporate bureaucracy that
Lasch associates with the therapeutic sensibility have been dismantled and
replaced by a harsher, more competitive capitalism, therapeutic language remains
the vocabulary through which to account for individual success and failure.
Instead of the jettisoning of the past that Lasch and Sennett observe, Silva’s
subjects embrace the past as they narrate the challenges they have had to overcome
in order to realize their authentic selves. Understood in terms of familial and
personal experiences, the past provides an open field of explanations for hardship,
failure, and the diminution of what they see as success. Unlike Lasch’s empty
narcissists, Silva’s young adults have lives of inner purpose – surviving on their own
in a context where the odds are against them. They struggle with illness and battle
with addiction. They overcome dysfunctional families and past relationships. The
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

12 Jodi Dean

fight to survive is the key feature of an identity imagined as dignified and heroic
because it has to produce itself by itself.
Silva’s young adults point to an imaginary identity beyond the rugged indivi-
dualist and the narcissistic gamesman: the survivor. Unlike the symbolic identity
of institutions (the place from which one sees oneself as acting), imaginary identity
is the image one adopts of oneself. Since so many of Silva’s informants feel they
have had to do it all by themselves, in contexts of poverty and diminishing
opportunity, they take the fact of their survival as the morally significant fact:
making it on one’s own is what bestows dignity. Some of the white survivors
Silva interviews resent “socialists” like US President Barack Obama for trying to
take away their last best thing, the special something that is all they have left,
namely, the dignity they have because they are completely self-reliant. The
black survivors, too, narrate their experiences in individual rather than collective
terms. They, too, seek to hold on to the only person they can count on –
themselves. Betrayed by schools, the labor market, and the government, Silva’s
working class informants in general feel “completely alone, responsible for their
own fates and dependent on outside help at their peril.” For them, surviving
means internalizing the painful lesson that “being an adult means trusting no
one but yourself” (p. 9).
What Sennett lauded as a repudiation of dependence appears in Silva’s account
as a deep skepticism of solidarity. Reliance on other people requires acknowl-
edging one’s insufficiency as an individual, one’s inability to survive alone. The
hostility to the needy expressed by some of Silva informants suggests a defense
against their own need. Hostility lets them displace their need onto others and
thereby shore up a fragile and impossible individuality. Having learned that they
can’t rely on anyone, these young working class adults try to numb their sense of
betrayal by affirming the worst cultural scripts of individualism, personal respon-
sibility, and self-reliance, hardening themselves to the world around them. Their
hostility to various forms of government intervention, particularly affirmative
action, makes them ideal supports for neoliberal capitalism. Incidentally, those of
us who write and circulate critical exposés – stories of governmental corruption,
university failure, and corporate malfeasance – may not be helping our cause. We
may be affirming what some in the working class already know to be true: they
are being betrayed.
Likewise countering Sennett’s happy rendering of the repudiation of depen-
dence, Carrie M. Lane’s (2011) research on white-collar technology workers in
Dallas situates the emphasis on individual responsibility in the context of wide-scale
layoffs and unemployment. Insecurity is a primary feature of the lives of these
tech workers. Most alternate through contract positions of varying duration,
unemployment, and self-employment.3 Lane notes how the technology workers
she interviewed embrace a “career management” ideology that casts “insecurity as
an empowering alternative to dependence on a single employer” (p. 13). They
construe loyalty as a thing of the past: since everyone is a victim of economic
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Nothing Personal 13

forces beyond their control, neither companies nor employees owe each other
anything. Owners and workers both want to make money however they can. No
one should expect a company to provide employment security or opportunities
for professional development. Such an expectation indicates a childish attitude of
dependence. According to one executive, “To give my employees job security
would be to disempower them and relieve them of the responsibility that they
need to feel for their own success” (p. 51). Laid-off and job-seeking tech workers
adopt the corresponding individualist mindset: success comes from doing “whatever
it takes” to get by, get through, get that next job.
The survivor is a compelling identity under conditions of extreme competition
and inequality. It validates surviving by any means necessary. Survival is its own
reward. Setbacks and lapses are new challenges, ultimately greater proof of one’s
survival skills. Popular culture provides a wide array of survivors to emulate (as
well as examples of those who have been unable to get themselves together):
from Katniss in The Hunger Games, to the winners of uncountable reality televi-
sion competitions, to games like Day Z and Fallout, to victims of illness or crime.
Emotions of anger, suspicion, and defensiveness are justified – one can rely only
on oneself – and potentially useful as the psychic weapons that can help maintain
an impossible individuality.
The survivor is a figure not for a culture of narcissism but for a psychotic culture.
If narcissistic culture is characterized by the dislodging of symbolic authority,
psychotic culture is characterized by its foreclosure (see Dean 2009). In brief,
Lacan (1997) defines psychosis in terms of the foreclosure of the Name-of-the-
Father or master signifier. That the master signifier is foreclosed means that it does
not stabilize meaning; the signifying chain lacks an anchor that can hold it together.
The generalized loss of symbolic power impacts the subject such that he feels this
now-missing authority to be all the closer, more powerful, and intrusive. In a
psychotic culture, then, mistrust is pervasive, all-consuming. Each confronts
power directly and alone.
To compensate for the missing symbolic authority, the psychotic turns to the
imaginary. He positions himself in relation to a “captivating image,” perhaps of
one whom he hates, admires, or fears. This imaginary other would then be a rival
to defeat or destroy. The psychotic may try to mimic those around him, parti-
cularly as he grapples with intense fear and aggression. And he may also become
captivated by an image of himself. Here the psychotic imagines himself not as
anyone or anything in particular: I am my own worst enemy. What matters is
persistence, survival, for its own sake.
Whether rendered as caring for oneself or looking out for number one, the
captivating image of the individual enjoins its own maintenance. For all their
emphases on self-reliance, Silva’s interviewees nonetheless want to be recognized.
They want someone else to hear their stories, validate what they’ve accom-
plished. Communicative capitalism supplies the necessary infrastructure, the
crowd of many who might view, like, or share.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

14 Jodi Dean

The Pressure Is Killing Me


The intensification of capitalism amplifies pressures on and for the individual.
These pressures are political: the individual is called on to express her opinion, speak
for herself, get involved. She is told that she, all by herself, can make a difference. Her
responses to ubiquitous demands for feedback take the place of collective action,
rendered as either impossible or too repressive to constitute a real alternative. The
pressures on the individual are also economic: even in the absence of significant
social mobility, the individual is offered up as the most significant determinant of
success or failure. In competitive labor markets, attracting buyers for one’s labor
power is a challenge. One has to distinguish oneself to get hired or, for some of
us, to maintain the fantasy of something like a fair competition (it would be horrible
to think that all that debt was for nothing). No wonder that communicative capit-
alism enjoins us to uniqueness: we are the product we make of ourselves. At the
same time, specialization supports marketeers’ interests in ever more granular
access to customers, police efforts to locate and track, and capital’s concern with
preventing people from coalescing in common struggle. Identification is inseparable
from surveillance, personalization absorbed in commerce. Capitalism’s injunction
to individuate is the most powerful weapon in its arsenal.
The pressures are also psychological, as we have already seen. Franco Berardi
(2009) highlights the “conquest of internal space, the interior world, the life of
the mind” endemic to communicative capitalism. Informational intensification
and temporal acceleration saturate our attention to “pathological levels.” Berardi
associates panic, aggressiveness, depression, and fear with this saturation. He finds
symptoms of it in waves of suicide, escalating Viagra use among those with no
time for affection, tenderness, and sexual preliminaries, “millions of boxes of
Prozac sold every month, the epidemic of attention deficit disorders among
youngsters, the diffusion of drugs like Ritalin to school children, and the
spreading epidemic of panic” (Berardi, p. 82). People respond to overload with
drugs and technology, trying to do more, be more, keep up and on top, but the
pressure is relentless. The more they do, the more they are expected to do.
Swamped under the overproduction of signs, the human receiver is overloaded to
the point of breakdown.
I agree with much of Berardi’s description, but I want to suggest an alternative
approach to the psychopathologies he observes. Drugs, depression, ADHD, and
panic are not merely pathologies. They are also defenses. The real pathology is
the individual form itself. Drugs attempt to maintain it, keep it going. The individual
is pathological in the sense that it is incompatible with its setting, incapable of
responding to the pressures it encounters without pain, sacrifice, or violence
(psychoanalysis stems from this insight, hence the primacy of castration). The
problem of contemporary subjectivity arises not from the extremes of a capitalism
that has merged with the most fundamental components of communicativity. It’s
not that the saturated, intensified, and unbearably competitive circuits of
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Nothing Personal 15

communicative capitalism are making us depressed, anxious, autistic, and dis-


tracted and that we need to find ways to preserve and protect our fragile indi-
vidualities. Depression, anxiety, autism, and hyperactivity signal the breakdown of
a form that has always itself been a problem, a mobilization of processes of indi-
viduation and interiorization in a reflexive inward turn that breaks connections
and weakens collective strength. The individual form is not under threat. It is the
threat. And now it’s weakening.
In Alone Together: Why We Expect More from Technology and Less from Each
Other, Sherry Turkle (2011) documents some of the ways social media provide
relief from individualist expectations. To be sure, she does not describe her findings
in terms of such relief. Rather than construing the individual form as a problem,
she presents it as a vulnerability in need of protection. So she echoes dominant
injunctions to individuality. Nonetheless, her explorations of “networked life and
its effects on intimacy and solitude, on identity and privacy” open up paths she
doesn’t follow, paths to collectivity (p. 169).
Reporting on her interviews with teenagers, Turkle describes young people
waiting for connection, fearful of abandonment, and dependent on immediate
responses from others even to have feelings. For example, seventeen-year-old
Claudia has happy feelings as soon as she starts to text. Unlike a previous
generation that might call someone to talk about feelings, when Claudia wants to
have a feeling, she sends a text (p. 176). Turkle reports the anxieties people
express about face-to-face interactions as well as about expectations associated
with the telephone, that is to say, about speaking to another person in real time.
The multitasking inseparable from contemporary communication, the fact that
people may be texting and talking simultaneously, looking at something else while
ostensibly listening to their interlocutor, implants an uncertainty as to whether
another is even paying attention. Combined with pressures for immediate
response and the knowledge that the “internet never forgets” (most of us are
unable to eliminate all traces of our digital identities after they’ve been uploaded,
archived, and shared), our new intimacy with technology, Turkle demonstrates,
is affecting the kinds of selves we become. We experience solitude, privacy,
connection, and others differently from how we did before.
For Turkle, these new experiences are pathological. Drawing from Erik Erikson’s
work on personal identity, she argues that networked technologies inhibit the
kind of separation necessary for maturation. Parents are always in reach, available,
even if they are not actually present but themselves overworked, distracted, and
overextended. Young people do not learn how to be alone, how to reflect on
their emotions in private. Fragile and dependent, they fail to develop the sense of
who they are that they need to have “before” they “forge successful life part-
nerships” (p. 175). Rather than inner-directed and autonomous (Turkle refers to
David Riesman), the culture of mobile phones and instant messaging has raised
other-directedness “to a higher power” (p. 167). The expectation of constant
connectivity eliminates opportunities for solitude even as people are “increasingly
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

16 Jodi Dean

insecure, isolated, and lonely” (p. 157). Turkle concludes, “Loneliness is failed
solitude. To experience solitude, you must be able to summon yourself by
yourself; otherwise you will only know how to be lonely” (p. 288).
If we do not give normative priority to the individual as the proper or exclusive
form of subjectivity, we can read the evidence Turkle offers differently. We can
read it as an indication that a political form of separation and enclosure is changing,
mutating, becoming something else. Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri (2000)
follow Gilles Deleuze in describing this change as the passage from disciplinary
society to the society of control. They point out how disciplinary logics worked
primarily within the institutions of civil society to produce individuated subjects.
By the end of the twentieth century, disciplining and mediating institutions – the
nuclear family, the school, the union, and the church – were in crisis (Lasch’s
cultural narcissism is one diagnosis of this crisis). The spaces, logics, practices, and
norms previously coalescing into social and economic institutions broke down
and apart. In some instances, the release of an institutional logic from its spatial
constraints gave it all the more force; in other instances, the opposite occurred.
Thus, Hardt and Negri argue that pervasive institutional dissolution has been
accompanied by an “indeterminacy of the form of the subjectivities produced”
(p. 197). Hardt and Negri conclude that the bourgeois individual – the citizen-
subject of an autonomous political sphere, the disciplined subject of civil society,
the liberal subject willing to vote in public and then return home to his private
domesticity – can no longer serve as a presupposition of theory or action. They
suggest that in its place, we find fluid, hybrid, and mobile subjectivities who are
undisciplined, who have not internalized specific norms and constraints, and who
can now only be controlled.
Hardt and Negri are right to point to the changes in the settings that produced
the bourgeois individual. Yet they underplay the emergent ferocity of com-
manded individuality. Their fluid, hybrid, and mobile subjectivities appear as loci
of freedom, as if their singularity were a natural property rather than itself
enjoined, inscribed, and technologically generated in the service of capitalism. As
the decline of discipline weakened individuating structures, new technologically
mediated techniques of individuation took their place. An easy example (one
prominent in Turkle’s discussion) is the adoption of mobile phones as personal
communication devices for kids. Enabling parents to keep track from a distance,
phones fill in for the direct supervision and contact that has diminished in the
wake of increasing work demands on parents, particularly mothers. Additional
such techniques and technologies of individuation include competition in inten-
sified labor markets as they induce a marketing relation to oneself; targeted
advertisements that urge consumers to differentiate and specify themselves;
locative technologies associated with mobile phones and GPS; cookies and other
data-gathering techniques associated with transactions on the internet; political
injunctions to personal participation; and, in the USA, a rights-based political
culture focused on personal identity, harm, and exclusion as opposed to common,
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Nothing Personal 17

collective, and systemic injustice – within this culture, systemic problems such as
exploitation in the workplace and amplified personal indebtedness are treated as
the effects of individual choices, preferences, and luck. The fluidity that Hardt and
Negri observe, then, is accompanied by the technologies and practices of com-
manded individuality. The result is that the expectation of unique individuality
exerts demands that are as constant and unyielding as they are impossible to meet.
That the young people Turkle interviewed express anxieties associated with
autonomy and connection is not surprising. They are enjoined to individuality,
told each individual is selfsame, self-creating, self-responsible: one is born alone
and one dies alone; you can rely on no one but yourself. Yet the technologies
that further individuation – smartphone, tablet, laptop – and the platforms that
encourage it – Twitter, Facebook, Instagram, Tumblr – provide at the same time
an escape from and alternative to individuation: connection to others, collectivity.

Crowds
Turkle thinks that people’s aversion to talking on the phone (as opposed to
texting) and conversing face-to-face reflects their need for filters, for ways to
handle sensory and information overload. They reflect, she suggests, not only a
longing for solitude but also the way that in a stimulation and simulation culture
we have become cyborgs (p. 209). Elias Canetti (1984) suggests an alternative
interpretation: we may be coming to prefer the crowd, the presence of many that
opens us to collectivity and relieves us of anxiety. One-on-one conversations may
feel too constraining insofar as they enclose us back in an individual form. Rather
than part of a group, of many, we are just ourselves.
If this is plausible, then we have an alternative way to think about preoccupa-
tions with numbers of friends, followers, blog hits, shares, and retweets. They do
not indicate personal achievement or popularity. They mark our absorption in the
crowd, how densely we are enmeshed in it. So, to be clear, we can think of these
counts in the individualist terms given us by capital. We can also recognize them
as something else, as markers of belonging to something larger than oneself. In
this latter sense, they reassure us that we are not unique but common.
For Canetti (1996), the relief we feel in a crowd is paradoxical. It arises from a
fear of others, a feeling that others are threatening, which “reverses into its
opposite” in the crowd. In a discussion with Adorno, he explains that he believes
that people like to become a crowd because of “the relief they feel at the reversal
of the feeling of being touched” (p. 185). From this vantage point, the craving for
dopamine Turkle describes seems more like the relief we may feel when we shake
off the fears associated with individuation – isolation, exposure, vulnerability.
One might object that Canetti’s crowd is physical and the networked crowd is
virtual. This objection is absolutely right and compelling – part of the power of
the occupations of Tahrir Square, Syntagma Square, and the Occupy movement’s
multiple parks and sites came from the force of bodies out of doors in
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

18 Jodi Dean

collectivities authorized by neither capital nor the state. But this is not the end of
the story. Most crowd theorists attend to physical and virtual crowds. They draw
out “crowd” as a verb, as dynamics, and as affects that traverse and constitute
collectivity. Canetti himself describes invisible crowds of the dead and spermatozoa.
Gustave Le Bon’s (1896) influential (albeit notoriously reactionary) work on
crowds treats the crowd primarily as a psychological concept. Le Bon goes so
far as to claim enigmatically that “crowds, doubtless, are always unconscious,
but this very unconsciousness is perhaps one of the secrets of their strength” (p. 6).
Furthermore, technologies of presencing have developed so as to make our
mediated interactions feel all the more present and intense. We are interacting
with others, not just screens. When we register trending hashtags and multi-
shared stories, we experience the force of many. In social media, the many flow
across our screens, waves of images and expressions of feeling with effects that
accumulate, resonate, and consolidate into patterns irreducible to any particular
position or utterance. Canetti (1992) notes “how gladly one falls prey to the
crowd” (p. 148). The crowd, virtual and physical, moves and intoxicates. Canetti
(1982) writes:

you were lost, you forgot yourself, you felt tremendously remote and yet
fulfilled; whatever you felt, you didn’t feel it for yourself; it was the most
selfless thing you knew; and since selfishness was shown, talked, and threatened
on all sides, you needed this experience of thunderous unselfishness like the
blast of the trumpet at the Last Judgment.
(p. 94)

The experience of flow that overwhelms the conscious experience of self that
Turkle finds so threatening, then, might also be understood as a breaking out
of the illusion that the individual is and can be a subject of action (rather than a
form of enclosure and containment) and a giving-over to a crowd.

We’ve Got to Be We
The crumbling of capitalist realism – the shaking off of Margaret Thatcher’s
destructive mantra that “there is no alternative” to unfettered capitalist competition –
has led to mainstream acknowledgement that capitalism is a system that takes
from the many and gives to the few (Fisher 2009). Today no one denies the fact
that some always lose in the capitalist economy. The system produces losers –
the unemployed, the homeless, the indebted, the conned, the wiped out, the
abandoned, the sacrificed. It runs on debt, foreclosure, expropriation, eviction,
dispossession, destruction – these are just other words for privatization. But then
what? Ever since the left started looking at itself and the world in terms of indi-
vidual specificity and the efficiency of markets, it has seemed easier to imagine the
end of capitalism than it is to imagine an organized left.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Nothing Personal 19

Some find collectivity to be undesirable because of its opposition to individual


responsibility and freedom. Rejecting the communisms of Badiou as well as
Hardt and Negri, Vanessa Lemm (2011) warns, “in both these trends, the process
of subjectivation tends to dissolve the individual into a ‘multitude’ or a ‘cause’
that is supra-individual and that, far from assuming responsibility for one’s freedom,
demands that one surrender it” (p. 96). Lemm offers a Nietzschean “counterforce
to the radical egalitarianism” of the communists, emphasizing how Nietzsche’s
“aristocratic conception of culture” relies on “cultivating the responsibility of
singular individuals.” Others position collectivity as undesirable by insinuating
that collectivity has to be imposed; any collective employs a state logic. Banu
Bargu’s (2011) bold deployment of Max Stirner’s egoist view of liberation as an
individual project of self-valorization best exemplifies this view: to realize their
own uniqueness and potential, egoists “should direct their efforts not only against
the state, but against any collectivity and collective project” (pp. 114–115).
In the place of an undesirable collectivity, left realism offers up diversity, plurality,
and multiplicity. To this end, Eugene Holland (2011) wants to create a “multiplicity
of multiplicities.” Jimmy Casas Klausen and James Martel (2011) likewise encou-
rage expressions of human diversity and view thriving political and economic
associations as those that are adaptable, contingent, and multiple. And Andrew
Koch (2011) claims that anarchism is the “only justifiable political stance” because
of its defense of the infinite pluralism of individuated meaning (p. 38). Such views
proceed as if such multiplicity were primarily ontological, rather than also stimulated
by capitalism for its benefit and preservation. They also underplay state interest in
plurality, particularly the fragmentations that hinder collective opposition and the
individuations that facilitate targeting, isolation, and control.
Left realism’s second premise is that collectivity is impossible. We are so different,
so singularized in our experiences and ambitions, so invested in the primacy of
one set of tactics over another that we can’t cohere in common struggle. At best
we can find momentary affinities and provisional coalitions. Politics should thus
involve cultivating our own unique point of view – or the point of view of our
sect, tribe, or locale – rather than trying to organize these views into something
like a strategy. Left realism implies that coming together itself should be exposed
as a fantasy covering over a hidden Hobbesian impulse to transcendence, a myth
some use to manipulate others into fighting for their interests.
A further variation on the premise of impossibility is that fundamental changes
in the world economy preclude collectivity (Clover and Benanav 2014). Rather
than concentrating workers in centralized locations, contemporary capitalism dis-
perses them across the globe. It relies on long supply chains and global capital,
using complexity to dissolve sites of accountability. Workers in ever more sectors
of the capitalist economy are thus isolated, immiserated, and politically dis-
organized. To be sure, immiseration and political disorganization also characterize
the early decades of revolutionary socialism. Karl Marx, Friedrich Engels, and
Rosa Luxemburg all emphasize how competition means that workers tend to
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

20 Jodi Dean

remain isolated, lack solidarity, and take a long time to unite. This is why unions
and parties have to be created and why creating them is a struggle. Left realism’s
one-sided emphasis on the objective dimension of our present capitalist setting
fails to acknowledge the subjective dimension of perspective, organization, and
will: our perspective is part of the setting it sees. This subjective dimension has
always been crucial to the Marxist tradition. The communist response to isolation
is not to let the reality that produces individualism determine our political hor-
izon. Instead, it is to build solidarity.
The assumptions that collectivity is both undesirable and impossible derive
from an even more insidious assumption of left realism: that politics involves the
individual. Manuel Castells (2012), for example, treats as a key cultural transforma-
tion “the emergence of a new set of values defined as individuation and autonomy,
rising from the social movements of the 1970s, and permeating throughout
society in the following decades with increasing intensity” (p. 230). Exactly how
politics involves the individual varies – no one speaks for me but me; the personal is
political; if I can’t dance, I don’t want to be part of your revolution. But the premise
remains the same: a left politics has to encourage and express the multiplicity of
individual projects. Individuals have to choose and decide – even as the left fails to
provide something anyone could actually choose. Leaders, vanguards, and parties are
modes of politics for a time not our own, we are told. They are remnants of a
political-economic assemblage that has already crumbled (Gilbert, 2014).
Left realism feels realistic to some because it resonates with the prevailing ethos
of late neoliberalism that tells us to do it ourselves, stay local and small, and trust
no one because they will only betray us. It affirms capitalism’s insistence on
immediacy and flexibility and the state’s replacement of long-term planning and
social services by crisis management and triage. Left realism is good on spontaneous
outrage. But it fails to organize itself in a way that can do something with this
outrage. Disorganized, it remains unable to use crises to build and take power
much less construct more equitable and less crisis-prone social and economic
arrangements.
The realism in which the Left has been immersed in the neoliberal decades has
meant that even when we are fully conscious of the deep inequity of the system
in which we find ourselves, we confirm and conform to the dominant ideology:
turn inward, enclave, emphasize the singular and momentary. Sometimes we
don’t feel like we can do anything about it (maybe we have too much work to
do already). Or we find ourselves participating in individuated, localized, or
communicatively mediated activities without momentum, duration, or a capacity
for political memory. Or we presume that we have to focus on ourselves, start
with ourselves and thereby redirect political struggle back into ourselves. In a
brutal, competitive, and atomized society, psychic well-being is so difficult that
success on this front can feel like a significant accomplishment. Trying to do
it themselves, people are immiserated and proletarianized and confront this
immiseration and proletarianization alone.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Nothing Personal 21

This chapter has sought to dismantle the assumption of the political primacy of
the individual that binds left politics to the dominant capitalist imaginary and that
prevents us from seeing the concentration of politics onto the individual as
symptomatic of left defeat. Rather than a locus for creativity, difference, agency,
and responsibility, the individual is the overburdened remainder of dismantled
institutions and solidarities. Commanded individuality obscures individual inca-
pacity even as it amplifies the contradictions barely congealed in the individual
form. At the same time, these commands and incapacities attest to another force,
the power of collectivity that manifests in crowds.

Notes
1 Throughout this chapter, I blur together individualism, individuality, and individuation,
treating them as component aspects of capitalist society’s requirement for and production
of individuals.
2 Product release: “Dr Pepper Celebrates Its Legacy Of Originality With The Launch Of
The New ‘Always One Of A Kind’ Advertising Campaign,” news.drpeppersnap-
plegroup.com, January 9, 2012.
3 Lane’s subjects were men and women, in their twenties through sixties, from different
racial and ethnic backgrounds – African American, Asian American, Latino, Indian,
Pakistani, Chinese, and Japanese. Most, however, were white men between the ages of
thirty and fifty.

References
Bargu, B. (2011). Max Stirner, Postanarchy avant la lettre. In J. Klausen and J. Martel
(Eds.) “How Not to Be Governed”: Readings and Interpretations from a Critical Anarchist Left.
Lanham, MD: Lexington Press.
Berardi, F. (2009). Precarious Rhapsody. London: Minor Compositions.
Bernes, J. (2013). Logistics, Counterlogistics, and the Communist Prospect. Endnotes, 3
(September). Retrieved from: https://endnotes.org.uk/issues/3/en/jasper-bernes-logis
tics-counterlogistics-and-the-communist-prospect
Canetti, E. (1982). The Torch in My Ear, trans. Joachim Neugroschel. New York: Farrar,
Straus and Giroux.
Canetti, E. (1984). Crowds and Power, trans. C. Stewart. New York: Farrar, Straus, and
Giroux.
Canetti, E. (1992). Crowds and Power. London: Penguin Books.
Canetti, E. (1996). Discussion with Theodor W. Adorno. Thesis Eleven, 45, 1–15.
Castells, M. (2012). Networks of Outrage and Hope: Social Movements in the Internet Age.
Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.
Clover, J. and Benanav, A. (2014). Can Dialectics Break BRICS? South Atlantic Quarterly,
113, 743–759.
Cowie, J. (2010). Stayin’ Alive: The 1970s and the Last Days of the Working Class. New
York: The New Press.
Dean, J. (2009). Democracy and Other Neoliberal Fantasies: Communicative Capitalism and Left
Politics. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Fisher, M. (2009). Capitalist Realism. London: Zero Books.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

22 Jodi Dean

Gilbert, J. (2014). Common Ground: Democracy and Collectivity in an Age of Individualism.


London: Pluto Press.
Hardt, M. and Negri, A. (2000). Empire. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Holland, E. (2011). Nomad Citizenship. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Klausen, J. and Martel, J. (2011). Introduction. In J. Klausen and J. Martel (Eds.), “How
Not to Be Governed”: Readings and Interpretations from a Critical Anarchist Left. Lanham,
MD: Lexington Press.
Koch, A. (2011). Poststructuralism and the Epistemological Basis of Anarchism. In
D. Rousselle and S. Evren (Eds.), Post-Anarchism: A Reader. New York: Pluto Press.
Lacan, J. (1997). The Psychoses: 1955–1956, Seminar III, ed. Jacques-Alain Miller, trans.
Russel Grigg. New York: Norton.
Lane, C. (2011). A Company of One. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Lasch, C. (1979). The Culture of Narcissism. New York: Norton.
Le Bon, G. (1896). The Crowd: A Study of the Popular Mind. Kitchener, ON: Baroche
Books.
Lemm, V. (2011). Nietzsche, Aristocratism and Non-Domination. In J. Klausen and J. Martel
(Eds.), “How Not to Be Governed”: Readings and Interpretations from a Critical Anarchist Left.
Lanham, MD: Lexington Press.
Moye, J. (2014). Summer of Sharing: “Share a Coke” Campaign Rolls Out in the U.S.,
June 10. Retrieved from: coca- colacompany.com
Sennett, R. (2006). The Culture of the New Capitalism. New Haven, CT: Yale University
Press.
Seigel, J. (2005). The Idea of the Self: Thought and Experience in Western Europe Since the
Seventeenth Century. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Silva, J. (2013). Coming Up Short: Working-Class Adulthood in an Age of Uncertainty. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Turkle, S. (2011). Alone Together: Why We Expect More from Technology and Less from Each
Other. New York: Basic Books.
Žižek, S. (1999). The Ticklish Subject. London: Verso.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

2
THE SECRET LIFE OF NEOLIBERAL
SUBJECTIVITY

Mitchell Dean

Neoliberalism has been called a “rascal concept – promiscuously pervasive, yet


inconsistently defined, empirically imprecise and frequently contested” (Brenner,
Peck, and Theodore 2010, p. 182). While the term is usually employed as a critical
tool, those who are its supposed agents do not accept the epithet and (at least
since the mid-1950s) prefer instead to regard themselves as classical liberals in the
tradition of Adam Smith (Mirowski 2009, p. 427; Dean 2014b, p. 154). In general,
and in its most explicit form, it refers to a kind of “economic theology” (Agamben
2011) consisting of a faith in the providential order of the free-market economy
and individual economic freedom and self-government – but to stop there would
be very misleading, as Michel Foucault’s work (2008) would point out. While it is
often attributed to the Chicago School of the mid-twentieth century, particularly
in Europe, many Americans use the term “liberal” to denote the progressive side of
politics, supporting enhanced freedoms of individual lifestyle and, to some extent, a
level of federal governmental intervention in the provision of healthcare, education,
and social welfare. With the administration of President Obama, and in particular
Hillary Clinton’s 2016 presidential election campaign, however, it often seemed
that the Democratic Party sought to reconcile these two kinds of liberalism: a
political liberalism offering a rights-based progressive “identity politics” of diversity
and an economic liberalism that would be a pro-corporate, pro-financial capital,
version of free-trade globalism.
Some are more used to the term “neo-conservative” to describe a certain
recent form of the New Right, at least since the administration of President
George W. Bush. Here, we find the advocacy and implementation, often
through executive orders, of enhanced security mechanisms such as intensified
surveillance of populations, stronger border controls, the use of detention camps,
extra-territorial “black sites,” “enhanced interrogation techniques” (more
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

24 Mitchell Dean

commonly referred to as torture) and extra-juridical killings in the treatment of


enemies. All this hardly seems consistent with the rosy end-of-history gospel of
global free-trade and prosperity. Indeed, neoliberalism often seems to refer to
quite contrary things: the principle that the state should be rolled back in the
name of individual freedom coexists with the mistrust concerning whether many
individuals are capable or responsible enough to use that freedom and a con-
tinuum of paternalist, authoritarian, and coercive treatment of the latter. If this is
the case, the new Trump administration may not be a case of a rascal concept
going full “loony tune.” Rather than a fundamental departure from a neoliberal
paradigm it could be approached as a nationalist and protectionist inflection and
intensification of it: at the same time de-regulatory and protectionist toward the
national economy, further marketizing healthcare, insurance, and social provision,
while re-enforcing borders and (further) restricting immigration, reviving the
hyper-security state, and working through executive order rather than legislation.
But rather than announce yet another death of neoliberalism, it might be better
to think of recent developments as a kind of national neoliberalism.
More broadly, there are the “roll back” and “roll out” phases or dimensions of
neoliberalism, as Jamie Peck (2010a, pp. 21–25) puts it, not to mention the
simple rolling on – or rolling with. As Philip Mirowski (2009, 2013) has pointed
out, the claim of the vanity of human knowledge in the face of the market as the
great information-processor seems to except those who advance that truth,
including much of the economics profession. While justifying itself as preventing
the slippery slope to totalitarianism, neoliberalism has often found itself preferring
liberalism to democracy, a “liberal dictator” to an anti-liberal demos, as F. A.
Hayek (1981) did during the Pinochet regime in Chile. At the onset of the
financial crisis of the 2000s, it called for bank bailouts and quasi-nationalizations
of certain industries deemed “too big to fail.” In fact, some have spoken of a
“zombie neoliberalism” that lives on in an undead form after its much proclaimed
death as that crisis unfolded (Peck 2010b). In the course of that crisis, it appeared
both to lose its legitimacy and gain a source of renewal. While initially a marginal
political ideology, it has become so embedded in governmental practices, every-
day politics, and culture, and perhaps even our subjectivities that it has proved
very difficult to resist and redirect. Even allowing for its contingent appearance
and operation, once established it follows uneven forms of development with
particular path dependencies, feeding on the roiling crises it seems to provoke
(Brenner, Peck, and Theodore 2010).
For those working with Foucault and particularly his work on govern-
mentality, there are some additional complications. Taking some sustenance from
Foucault, a group of scholars in the United Kingdom and Australia produced a
literature on what might be called “neoliberal governmentality” or, rather less
pointedly, “advanced liberal rule” (Rose 1996), by the end of the twentieth
century, although the latter term seemed often to depoliticize neoliberalism,
systematically downplaying its authoritarian side and its rootedness in robust
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

The Secret Life of Neoliberal Subjectivity 25

intellectual-political movements and action taken to appropriate political sover-


eignty. Nevertheless, we did this without much of Foucault’s work on the topic
being either published or widely available. Hence, our work was exciting as a
conceptual and analytical invention provoked by Foucault rather than a fidelity to
his text. In any case our main objective was not the scholastic interpretation of
Foucault’s texts but the development of an analytical perspective – an “analytics
of government” as I called it at the time (Dean 1999, pp. 20–27) – that could be
applied successfully to many different spheres of governing, from education,
indigenous issues, bureaucracy, auditing, and accounting to the reform of welfare-
state measures. While the initial heyday of this now much cited literature was the
1990s, the lectures Foucault delivered in the 1970s on governmentality and
neoliberalism would only become widely available after the initial development of
what Michel Sennelart later dubbed “governmentality studies” (2007, p. 390) – in
French in 2004 and English in 2007. In fact his lectures on neoliberalism, The
Birth of Biopolitics, would appear in English in the fateful year 2008. As a result
destiny has tied these lectures, which were concluded a month prior to the elec-
tion of the Thatcher government in the UK and almost two years before the
Reagan administration took office in the USA, to a wholly different context.
That was the worst economic crisis in the North Atlantic world since the Great
Depression and the subsequent revaluation of the legacy of neoliberalism and
its poster girl and boy. If the crisis was good for some businesses – predatory
moneylenders, debt collection and insolvency firms, private employment service
providers engaged by governments, to name some – it was also propitious for
academics trading or hoping to trade in Foucault’s analysis of neoliberalism,
themselves under the pressures of a university system they felt was also
“neo-liberalizing.”
A further complication is that these very lectures are made available under the
general editorship of his former student and assistant François Ewald, thus making
him perhaps Foucault’s most influential follower. The apparent irony here is that
Ewald, in his work with the employers’ association, Medef, would promote what
Maurizio Lazzarato describes as the “policies and mechanisms for … reconstructing
society according to neoliberal principles” that were first revealed to him in
Foucault’s very lectures of 1979 (2009, p. 110). While the case of Ewald as a
neoliberal has been raised for some time in Parisian circles by Lazzarato, Antonio
Negri (2001), and Jacques Donzelot (Donzelot and Gordon 2008, p. 55), among
others, the question of Foucault’s own critical but positive appreciation of aspects
of neoliberalism has been put on the agenda by none other than Ewald himself.
Ewald suggested in 2012 in conversation with the Chicago economist, Gary
Becker, that Foucault had offered an “apology of neoliberalism” (Becker, Ewald
and Harcourt 2012, p. 4; Dean 2014a) – a suggestion he seems to have sought
more recently to retract (Ewald 2016). One very small lineament of our present is
that this topic of Foucault’s possibly affirmative reading of neoliberalism has now
become a matter for public debate, following the publication of two books
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

26 Mitchell Dean

endorsing this view in French, one embracing it as the way forward for the Left
(Lagasnerie 2012), the other suspecting Foucault of undermining the Left’s core
commitments to health and social rights (Zamora 2014b; see Hansen 2015). The
Foucault blogosphere would be lit up by an interview with the editor of
the latter book, the then PhD student Daniel Zamora, in Jacobin (Zamora 2014a).
In 2015, this debate reached the pages of the Los Angeles Review of Books
(Steinmetz-Jenkins and Arnold 2015) under the title “Searching for Foucault in
an Age of Inequality” and continues with the revised English version of Zamora’s
book (Zamora and Behrent 2016) and commentaries on it in History and Theory,
among other places.
Despite all this Foucault is still, at least in the United States, imagined as an
unadorned radical. On the day of the inauguration of Donald Trump, anthro-
pologists held “read-ins” of the final lecture of Society Must Be Defended (Foucault
2003; Jaschik 2017). Whether or not this amounts to one of those “facile gestures”
that Foucault himself warned against, this practice perhaps raises the question of
Foucault’s relation to our political present. After this lecture, Foucault had a year
on sabbatical that cemented his relationship with the United States. On his return
to the lectern in 1978, his concern was no longer with the inscription of a genocidal
racism in the modern state in the combination of biopolitics and sovereignty
but with a new framework of power, “governmentality,” and the genealogy of
liberalism or the liberal arts of government that would culminate in a discussion
of the variants of neoliberalism. Is it possible, I want to ask, that Foucault dis-
covered or foreshadowed the possibility of a form of politics that would incor-
porate neoliberal technologies of government and would be highly influential on
the Left over the last three or even four decades, but which has left those
democracies vulnerable to the type of nationalist neoliberalism and acclamatory
populism we witness today?
To do this, I shall leave the question of the empirical adequacy of his genealogy
of liberalism aside for another time. I want to ask instead, what is the distinctive
contribution of Foucault’s approach to neoliberalism, and by those who followed
him? And what are the strengths and limits of this work on neoliberal govern-
mentality today, in the wake of crisis, heightened inequality, and populist insur-
gence, and, in Europe, reborn nationalism, continuing austerity, massive youth
unemployment, and economic stagnation? In answer to the first question, I shall
argue that there are several strengths we can build on in Foucault’s work on
neoliberalism: first, his intellectual-historical approach to it; second, his view of
neoliberalism as an art of government; and third, his focus on its critical ethos. At
the heart of my way into the more critical assessment is a fourth theme found in
much of the secondary literature, that Foucault acutely posed the problem of the
production of neoliberal subjectivity. The focus on questions of subjectivity and
the problematic of subjection/subjectification takes us to the heart of the current
problem for the Left: that its support of contestation against the (often welfare
state) institutions and forms of social scientific knowledge as the major forms of
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

The Secret Life of Neoliberal Subjectivity 27

domination since the 1970s brought it into a critical alignment with the libertarian
dimension of neoliberalism and rendered it relatively useless in preventing the
authoritarian populist rise.

Foucault, Governmentality, and Neoliberalism


To start with the obvious, Foucault’s analysis alerts us to the plurality of forms of
neoliberalism, their emergence within but movement across particular national
borders and temporal contexts. Foucault demonstrates the worth of an intellectual-
historical and even biographical study of the variants of neoliberalism and their
key figures, which he himself recognizes as something of a departure from his
usual methods (2008, p. 10). This brings neoliberalism down to earth as something
that is identifiable and study-able, as something that is more plural, contingent,
and historically rooted than a narrative of neo-liberalization might indicate.
With the publication of excellent intellectual-historical studies of neoliberalism
such as those found in Mirowski and Plehwe’s The Road from Mont Pèlerin (2009)
and Jamie Peck’s Constructions of Neoliberal Reason (2010a), this point might seem
redundant. But if we allow Foucault the status of a thinker of the Left, which I
think he remained (see below), this project was almost unique at the time of his
lectures. On the other side of the Channel, there was Andrew Gamble’s (1979)
paper in The Socialist Register in 1979. But what is interesting is that despite
Laclau and Mouffe’s 1985 recognition (2001) that neoliberalism was a “new
hegemonic project,” there was little Left engagement with the sources of this
project. This was despite the fact, as Foucault’s lectures (2008) would report, that
such a project had become a practical doctrine of government from the very
beginning of the Federal Republic of Germany, that is, some almost forty years
before. For Foucault this neglect was due to mistaking neoliberalism as a mere
revival of classical liberalism or simply another ideology of market capitalism. The
Left, still in thrall to something like a base-superstructure model of ideology, was
not able to grasp neoliberalism “in its singularity” (Foucault 2008, p. 130). As
Foucault put it: “Neo-liberalism is not Adam Smith; neo-liberalism is not a
market society. Neo-liberalism is not the Gulag on the insidious scale of Capitalism”
(2008, p. 131).
In paying serious attention to the intellectual-historical sources of neoliberalism,
Foucault anticipates those who would regard neoliberalism as a “thought collective”
(Mirowski 2009, p. 428), that is, as I understand it, as an empirically and histori-
cally identifiable group of thinkers pursuing a common project and ambition but
within a certain space of conversation and dissension. As the contributors to The
Road from Mont Pèlerin have shown, the neoliberal thought collective proved to
be one of the most successful, if not the most successful, political movements of
the second half of the twentieth century in the influence, capture, and appro-
priation of the powers of national states and other governmental organizations
(above and below the nation state).
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

28 Mitchell Dean

Yet almost contrary to this careful intellectual-historical method, with its


emphasis on plurality and historical contingency of the various strands of the
neoliberal thought collective, is another of Foucault’s bold masterstrokes, the
identification of neoliberalism – and indeed classical liberalism – as an “art of
government,” something he announces at the very beginning of The Birth of
Biopolitics (2008, pp. 1–2). Citing Benjamin Franklin’s notion of “frugal govern-
ment” (2008, pp. 322, 319), Foucault defines liberalism as neither philosophy nor
ideology but as an art of government animated by the suspicion that one always
governs too much – or, as Barry Hindess and I argued, that the state is doing too
much of the governing (Dean and Hindess 1998, pp. 3–7). This general frame-
work allows him to distinguish between classical economic liberalism and the
varieties of neoliberalism. Whereas classical liberalism seeks the limitation of the
state in the face of the necessary and natural processes of the economy, neoli-
beralism will either seek to found the legitimacy of the state on the market, as the
Ordoliberals would in post-Nazi Germany, or to extend the market and its
rationality to all forms of social existence and to test and evaluate every single act
of government, as in the case of American neoliberalism. But to regard neoli-
beralism as an art of government is to shift the frame decisively from the theory of
ideology to the practical orientation of neoliberalism as a form of govern-
mentality. To put this in other words, neoliberalism is a form of statecraft. What is
important about this move is that it displaces the tendency to view neoliberalism
as something merely super-structural in relation to the capitalist economy and
forces us to look at it as a practical and technical exercise concerned with
governing states. Neoliberalism is not simply a philosophy of freedom and the
market that happens to have implications for governing states. It is all about
governing states – or about governing states and other organizations. It is a
doctrine, or set of doctrines, concerned with a practice centered first and foremost
on the exercise of political sovereignty (Foucault 2008, p. 3).
In a recent paper, I have used these two insights – neoliberalism as a thought
collective and as an art of government – to arrive at a particular way of characterizing
neoliberalism (Dean 2014b). In the first instance, neoliberalism as thought collective
conducts a form of what Max Weber called “politically oriented action”: that is,
action which “aims to exert influence on the government of a political organi-
zation; especially at the appropriation, redistribution or allocation of the powers
of government” (1978, p. 55). Its target is the control of the exercise of their
powers by states and other organizations, from school boards to political parties,
universities, and international government organizations. Rather than applying
the term “neoliberal” to a form of state, I prefer to suggest that neoliberalism is
most appropriately described as a way of governing the state and a way of governing
by the state. Against the anti-statism of much current political thought, it is
necessary to distinguish between “regime” and “state” (Du Gay and Scott 2010)
and view neoliberalism as a regime of government of and by the state. In this way,
we can protect ourselves from the dangers of an analytical anti-statism.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

The Secret Life of Neoliberal Subjectivity 29

There are many other more general and specific aspects of Foucault’s lectures
on neoliberalism one could focus on to define the distinctiveness of his con-
tribution. A further set I want to mention contains issues Foucault raises about the
critical ethos of neoliberalism. Here we find that at least one part of his orientation
to neoliberalism is the identification of what it criticizes or, to put it even more
bluntly, what it problematizes. These problematizations are of course national-
context dependent – the Ordoliberals (Foucault 2008, pp. 107–108) oppose ideas
of national economy derived from Friedrich List in the 1840s, Bismarkian state
socialism, and the wartime planned economy, for example, while Hayek displays
a particular animus towards the New Deal and the programs of Beveridge in
England (Foucault 2008, p. 110). The American school opposes both the latter
and the economic and social programs of the postwar federal administrations in
the United States, particularly Democratic ones (Foucault 2008, p. 217). However,
their common enemies are even more interesting – especially the economics and
policy prescriptions of John Maynard Keynes. This approach to neoliberalism
underlines its political nature and the relations of antagonism that animated it,
against all those who would reduce its concerns to economic, technical, or even
ethical ones. It also indicates that liberalism and neoliberalism vary according to
context that has among its conditions of existence, the targets of their critique.
The three points I have derived from Foucault emphasize the political character
of neoliberalism as a diverse movement or network with no doubt differences of
opinion but united by common aims and enemies seeking to institute a particular
“regime of government” in various organizations above and below the state but
most particularly in national states and their agencies. The fourth proposition
concerning the distinctiveness of Foucault’s contribution concerns the production
of neoliberal subjectivity. This is where Foucault’s view, and his legacy, becomes
quite confused and confusing, and where, if we were to follow him too closely,
we might end up fighting the battles of a previous war.
If one consults contemporary books on neoliberalism, whether they are sym-
pathetic to Foucault, such as Dardot and Laval’s The New Way of the World (2013)
or more critical, such as Philip Mirowski’s Never Let a Serious Crisis Go to Waste
(2013) and Maurizio Lazzarato’s The Making of Indebted Man (2012), they all
concur that one of the strengths of Foucault’s work on neoliberalism is that he
concerned himself with the production of neoliberal subjectivity. Dardot and
Laval devote a chapter to “Manufacturing the Neoliberal Subject” (2013, ch. 9),
while Mirowski writes of an “everyday neoliberalism” that takes its cue from his
appraisal of Foucault’s view of neoliberal identify (2013, pp. 89f.). Mirowski
(2013, pp. 95–96) even allows that Foucault “got there first” with regard to key
propositions about this neoliberal subjectivity, including the fragmentation of
identity attendant upon the neoliberal version of the self, the indefinite extension
of the entrepreneurial regime of the self to all aspects of life, the relationship of
the entrepreneurial self to risk, and the general malleability of the self. My reservation
here is that while Foucault elsewhere described his general project as one
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

30 Mitchell Dean

concerned with the ways in which the subject is produced, there are only two
sets of indications about the theme of neoliberalism and subjectivity in The Birth
of Biopolitics, which we will summarize in a moment. Nonetheless, I take Mirowski’s
point that many critical thinkers – whether Marxist or otherwise – want to portray
neoliberalism as something more than a deployment of class power and use
Foucault to specify “the chains of causality stretching form the executive com-
mittee of the capitalist class to the shopper at Wal-Mart” (2013, p. 99). Foucault
presents a sophisticated take on how neoliberal governmentality reaches into the
very “relation of self to self,” of every individual as worker, consumer, and just
about any other social identity they might find themselves inhabiting. Let’s look
more closely at this.

Foucault on Neoliberal Subjectivity


The problem of neoliberal subjectivity does not appear until half way through the
ninth lecture of The Birth of Biopolitics, which is also the first lecture concerning
American neoliberalism. Even here it does not constitute the main topic, which is
simply an exposition of the central components of American neoliberalism and
the difference between it and Ordoliberalism. It is introduced in the discussion of
the theory of human capital, associated with Theodore Schultz, Jacob Mincer, and
Gary Becker, and first emerges in the account of the worker’s relation to work.
Foucault contrasts the treatment of labor in Marx and the human capital theorists.
In Marx, abstract labor (or “labor power”) is a result of the logic of capital and of
its historical reality; for American neoliberalism this abstraction is not a product of
capitalist production but of the economic theory that has been constructed upon
it (Foucault 2008, p. 221). The latter “adopts the task of analyzing the form of
human behavior and the internal rationality of this human behavior” (Foucault
2008, p. 223). In other words, it takes the viewpoint of the worker in economic
theory rather than regarding labor as simply one of the variables that enters into
production. Foucault concludes that these American neoliberals “for the first
time, ensure that the worker is not present in the economic analysis as an object –
the object of supply and demand in the form of labor power – but as an active
economic subject” (2008, p. 223).
It is at this point that Foucault announces that American neoliberalism undertakes
a new approach to the economic subject. Homo œconomicus is no longer “a partner
of exchange” explicable in terms of “the theory of utility based on the problematic
of needs” (Foucault 2008, p. 225). Rather homo œconomicus is “an entrepreneur,
an entrepreneur of himself” (Foucault 2008, p. 226). This means that whether we
approach them as producers or consumers, economic subjects should be regarded as
their own capital, which is the source of both their own income and satisfaction.
Even consumption must be regarded as an activity and consuming individuals are
producers of their own satisfaction. What is crucial to remember here is that this
is a supposition of economic theory not a concrete technology of government
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

The Secret Life of Neoliberal Subjectivity 31

such as the disciplinary practices and forms of knowledge that “subjectify” the
individual as criminal, homosexual, and so on.
Foucault then goes on to show the breakdown of human capital into innate
and acquired elements. With respect to the former, he suggestively argues that
even the genetic makeup of individuals and its manipulation will come to be
regarded as a component of human capital. After discussing the augmentation of
the acquired elements of human capital through education, parenting, maternal
care, family life, migration, and mobility, he concludes that all these aspects of
human life can enter into economic analysis “as behavior in terms of individual
enterprise, of enterprise of oneself with investments and incomes” (Foucault
2008, p. 230). In this lecture then the entirety of Foucault’s analysis of neoliberal
subjectivity concerns the implication of human capital theory. The lecture con-
cludes with an analysis of the implications of this for problems of economic
growth and development, but there remains no discussion of the strategies and
programs that might seek to enhance human capital nor technologies that work
on what he would later call “the relation of self to self.”
But, as we shall see, it is not the absence of technologies of creating subjects
that makes neoliberal interventions de-subjectifying.
At the beginning of the next, second lecture on American neoliberalism Foucault
returns to Ordoliberalism in order to contrast it with the American use of the
market economy to decipher all aspects of non-market relations. In the course of a
discussion of the promotion of small and medium size enterprises in Ordoliberal
social policy (Gesellschaftpolitik) he again raises the question of the generalization of
the enterprise to all aspects of “the individuals’ life itself – with his relationships to
private property … family, household, insurance, and retirement” (Foucault 2008,
p. 241). The individual becomes “a permanent and multiple enterprise.”
Again, Foucault’s principal concern is not with the formation of neoliberal
subjectivity but with the contrast between Ordoliberalism and American neoli-
beralism. On the one side, there is the “economic-ethical ambiguity” of Ordoli-
beralism with its idea of a “society for the market and a society against the
market, a society oriented towards the market and a society that compensates for
the effects of the market in the realm of value and existence” (Foucault 2008,
pp. 241, 242). On the other, this ambiguity will be resolved by the radical nature
of American neoliberalism that seeks an “unlimited generalization of the form of
the market” and uses the economic form of the market as “a principle of decipher-
ment of social relationships and individual behavior” (Foucault, 2008, p. 243).
Insofar as Foucault is concerned with something like a neoliberal subjectivity, it
is as but one feature of the broader generalization of economic rationality he
finds, to varying extent, in the texts of the different schools of neoliberalism. It is
a second-order form of the observation of human behavior, not a first-order
description of a new kind of subject. And, we might add, it is a form of
observation with potentially “liberatory” aspects, particularly from forms of
subjectification – at least for Foucault.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

32 Mitchell Dean

Foucault finishes this lecture by discussing the question of crime and punish-
ment. This part of the lecture is crucial because it makes clear what he derives
from American neoliberalism. It also shows that what is at stake is not so much a
form of neoliberal subjectification but the potential of de-subjectification.
Here, Foucault argues that penal reformers such as Jeremy Bentham and Cesare
Beccaria advanced a notion of homo penalis that is a kind of correlate of homo
œconomicus in so far as the objective of their reform is “to find the least costly and
most effective form of obtaining punishment and the elimination of conducts
deemed harmful for society” (2008, p. 249). However the search for this ideal
legal framework has the “paradoxical effect” that it opens the possibility of a
subjectification of the offender. Penalty and law have meaning not only as punish-
ment of an act but also as a treatment of “an individual, an offender who must be
punished, corrected and made to serve as a possible example to other offenders”
(Foucault 2008, p. 249). In the course of the nineteenth century, and under the
effect of multiple and reciprocal problematizations of the different social sciences,
homo penalis gives ways to homo criminalis. The idea of the criminal is thereby
born: someone who through their innate makeup or environment, through their
deviation from a norm, their membership of a population or a class, their social
deviance or psychopathology, embodies a certain identity. There is thus “an
inflation of forms and bodies of knowledge, of discourse, a multiplication of
authorities and decision-making elements, and the parasitic invasion of the sentence
in the name of the law and the norm” (Foucault 2008, p. 250). Foucault con-
cludes, almost as an afterthought, that “[a]nyway, this is how I would see things
were I to adopt a neo-liberal perspective on this evolution” (2008, p. 250).
Nevertheless such a perspective bears a strong resemblance to the emergence of
the epistemological-juridical complex of the power to punish addressed in Discipline
and Punish (1977, p. 23).
There is nothing like this in the neoliberal approach to the entrepreneurial
subject for Foucault – no bodies of knowledge, no new authorities, no forms of
normalization. According to Foucault, the genius of the human capital approach
to crime and punishment is precisely that it forgoes the translation of economic
theory into an ideal legal-institutional form. The source of the problem is that by
invoking the principle of utility, Bentham and Beccaria had thought they had
found a justification for the exercise of authority by the state. Indeed one might
say, utility is a principle of “veridiction” or truth-production by the state, some-
thing Foucault’s approach to liberalism rules with its privilege of the market as the
site of veridiction for liberal governing. Becker, by contrast to the eighteenth-
century reformers, will keep to a purely economic analysis in which crime is
simply that which makes the individual run the risk of penalty. By adopting the
point of view of the person who commits the crime, Becker moves to the side of
the individual subject in a manner that evades the determinations of subjectivity
found in psychopathology or criminal anthropology. Foucault argues that con-
sidering the subject as homo œconomicus neither means that the whole subject
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

The Secret Life of Neoliberal Subjectivity 33

becomes homo œconomicus, nor is it based on an anthropological theory of the


subject. It simply means that “economic behavior is the grid of intelligibility that
one will adopt on the behavior of the new individual … power gets a hold of
him to the extent, and only to the extent, that he is homo œconomicus” (Foucault
2008, p. 252).
This neoliberal de-subjectification of the idea of the criminal leads Foucault to
draw some larger implications regarding the forms of power he had been pursuing
in the previous decade: sovereignty, discipline, and biopolitics. Because of his
supposition that power is omnipresent, Foucault’s problematic is not one that
seeks a freedom from all sorts of power but rather an alternative to particular kinds
of power and regulation. At the end of the lecture in question, Foucault finds in
American neoliberalism a rather precisely defined alternative to the other kinds of
power and regulation he had analyzed:

you can see that what appears on the horizon of this kind of analysis is not at
all the idea of a project of an exhaustively disciplinary society in which the
legal network hemming in individuals is taken over and extended internally
by, let’s say, normative mechanisms. Nor is it a society in which the
mechanism of general normalization and the exclusion of those who cannot
be normalized is needed.
(2008, p. 259)

This statement directly addresses the governing of crime, but not just that. It can
be read in terms of the movement of Foucault’s thought through forms of power.
What is envisaged by American neoliberalism then is a form of regulation that is
not one of a sovereign power exercised through law, or of disciplinary society with
its norms, or even of the general normalization of a biopolitics of the population. It
is not one of the major forms of regulation discussed by Foucault prior to these
lectures on governmentality in 1979 and nor is it the framework of biopolitics
still attributed to the 1979 lecture course (no doubt due to its rather misleading
title). Rather it is a new program and vision:

On the horizon of this analysis we see instead the image, idea, or theme-
program of a society in which there is an optimization of systems of difference,
in which the field is left open to fluctuating processes, in which minority
individuals and practices are tolerated, in which action is brought to bear on
the rules of the game rather than on the players, and finally in which there is
an environmental type of intervention instead of the internal subjugation of
individuals [de l’assujettisement interne des individus].
(Foucault 2008, pp. 259–260; 2004, p. 265)

It would be mistaken to suggest that Foucault does not have reservations about
the project of the manipulation of choice through environmental interventions of
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

34 Mitchell Dean

the behavioral type – as he indicates at the beginning of the next lecture (Foucault
2008, p. 271). Yet these would seem simply to be the costs – in his language, the
“dangers” – of a form of neoliberal regulation that he finds has certain benefits – or
“potentials.” Chief among these potentials is that regulation no longer entails the
internal “subjectification” (assujettisement) of the individual. We need to attend to
the French phrase translated in English as “of the internal subjugation of individuals.”
Assujettisement has a specific dual meaning in Foucault’s thought: it is not only
subjection in the sense of “submission to” or “subjugation” but also entails the
fabrication or production of subjectivity. This dual meaning is underlined by the
adjective “internal” that emphasizes not the mere external forms of subjugation
(as the equivalent of domination) but the internal forms of subjugation as “sub-
jectification,” as the fabrication of subjectivity through relations of power and
knowledge. Thus Foucault here distinguishes the neoliberal program from those
forms of power and knowledge such as discipline and the human and social sciences
that subjugate individuals through the production of subjectivity, that is through
tying individuals to the truth of their identity, for example the occasional criminal,
the recidivist, the dangerous individual, the invert, and so on. For Foucault in this
passage neoliberalism does not subjectify in this sense. In doing so, it opens up the
space for tolerating minority individuals and practices and optimizing systems of
differences.
This conclusion is an astonishing one. Michael Behrent (2016, p. 53) suggests it
shows how far Foucault had come from Discipline and Punish with its fore-
shadowing of a society of normalization. I would add that it marks an astonishing
end – even a telos – to Foucault’s thinking of power over the previous decade. He
now foresees a “way out” of the struggle against the “forms of subjection … the
submission of subjectivity” he identified as the central concern of his own epoch
in his essay, “The Subject and Power” (1982, p. 782) – with the help of this
neoliberal rationality, logic, and future imaginary. It is mistaken to think that
Foucault offers us an account of neoliberal subjectivity. What he thinks that
neoliberalism offers us instead is a way out of subjectification, a way out of the
double bind that ties the production of who we are to our domination, the
making of subjectivity to subjugation.
I realize this reading cuts against the grain of much Foucault scholarship but, at
least in this one respect, that scholarship is haunted by a phantasm that simply is
not supported by the text. While Foucault is not entirely clear, and his thought
has a continuing experimental character and often takes on chameleon colors, the
main thrust of his analysis here is that viewing of the self as an enterprise and the
generalization of this entrepreneurial self is not a new form of subjectification,
equivalent to the subjectivity produced by the individualizing and normalizing
knowledges of the disciplines and related sciences. Rather it is a way of theorizing
and thinking about the subject that does not view subjects from the outside as
something to be managed, classified, and divided, but from their own point of
view, and makes minimal assumptions about their nature, for example Becker’s
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

The Secret Life of Neoliberal Subjectivity 35

assumption of the non-randomness of the individual subject’s reaction to changes


in its environment (Foucault 2008, p. 269). While power can never be entirely
limited, and from the viewpoint of the social sciences this way of viewing individuals
is reductive, it does cast aside the straightjacketed subjects of the disciplinary and
normalizing powers he had fought against, allows difference, and tolerates minority
groups.

Some Implications
Foucault of course was not entirely uncritical of American neoliberalism. Nor
would it be correct to say that he became a card-carrying member of the Neoliberal
Thought Collective. Yet there is no doubt that these are crucial and almost secret
passages in his work: textual passages and intellectual passageways. In this sense,
his conclusions regarding neoliberal regulation can be read as a kind of exclamation
point on ten years of concept formation and analyses of relations of power. It is
also possible that Ewald, and Andrew Dilts (2011), are correct in viewing the
encounter with human capital theory as a passageway to the later texts on sub-
jectivity and ancient practices of the self. The flipside of neoliberalism’s imaginary
of a form of regulation without subjectification is the idea of a domain in which
individuals form their own subjectivity by technologies of the self with or without
the help of others.
What are the political and the policy implications that should concern us here?
The work of Michael Behrent (2010, 2016) has demonstrated the close association
between Foucault and the so-called Second Left in France at the time of these
lectures. The Second Left was a faction of socialists and unionists that sought a
new approach to socialist politics based on the decomposition and distribution of
the state into voluntary associations according to the principle of self-management,
autogestion. Their principal concern was to free the Socialist Party, forever the
bridesmaid on the verge of forming government for the first time, from “social
statism.” Foucault participated in their conferences and mobilizations and praised
the work of their major theorist, Pierre Rosanvallon. Indeed in the Course
Summary of The Birth of Biopolitics, Foucault credits Rosanvallon with the dis-
covery of liberalism as critique of government against the market as a site of truth
production or “veridiction” (2008, p. 320). The Second Left would have shared
Foucault’s incredible – and unargued for – claim that there is no “autonomous
socialist governmentality” (2008, p. 92) and that the only alternatives were to
latch onto a liberal or police-state governmentality. Hardly, one might say, much
of a choice! While of course it is difficult to identify Foucault’s politics, he shows
an affinity with a kind of “libertarian Left” that is both willing to engage in anti-
statism and anti-institutionalism as very much part of France’s anti-totalitarian
moment of the 1970s and willing to experiment with neoliberal technologies of
government. In some ways he can be viewed as anticipating, and participating in,
early experiments on the French Left that will have more enduring manifestations
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

36 Mitchell Dean

in the Anglophone world in the idea of the Third Way in British Labour politics
and President Clinton’s administration. While this political formation for a time
seemed like the only possible position of the institutional Left in its struggle to
take government, the recent rise of nationalism and acclamatory populism suggests
its two flaws. First, the focus on a politics of identity and subjectivity, and the
local struggles that accompany them, left an opening for populist movements
with large segments of the working class with little sympathy for those concerns.
Moreover, second, it is precisely the latter whose standard of living and basis of
subsistence in the labor market has been substantially eroded with the fostering of
neoliberal trade policies and the growth of inequality. It is perhaps no longer
possible to prefer Foucault’s specific and partial transformations in the fields
of subjectivity (1984, pp. 46–47) to questions of inequality and the struggles
concerning the state.
Finally, consider the implications for public policy. In an interview for a
Second Left collection in 1983, Foucault diagnoses the current problem of social
security as one of “facing economic obstacles that are only too familiar,” as being
limited against the “political, economic and social rationality of modern societies”
and having the “perverse effects” of “an increasing rigidity of certain mechanisms”
and “a growth of dependence” (Foucault 1988, p. 160). This dependence arises
not from marginalization, as it historically had, but from integration in the social
security system itself (Foucault 1988, p. 162). His answers to these problems are
framed in terms of a “way of life” and deploy the language of “lifestyles” (Foucault
1988, pp. 164–165). They seek a “social security that opens the way to a richer,
more numerous, more diverse, and more flexible relation with oneself and one’s
environment,” that guarantees a “real autonomy” (Foucault 1988, p. 161). To
combat welfare dependency, Foucault also suggests “a process of decentralization”
that would lead to a closer relation between users of services and “decision-making
centers” (1988, p. 165). In short, the structural economic problems of the fiscal
crisis of the welfare state were to be met with new forms of relations to oneself and
the decomposition of the state. He stops short of advocating marketization here but
he concludes the welfare system should become a “vast experimental field” and
that the “whole institutional complex, at present very fragile, will probably have to
undergo a restructuring from top to bottom” (Foucault 1988, p. 166). In this same
interview, as Zamora points out (2016, pp. 74–75; Foucault 1988, pp. 169), he
rejects “the right to health” in terms closely related to free-market arguments
against universal health care. Because of the technical growth of medicine and the
demand for health, Foucault argues (1988, p. 169), “it is not possible to lay down
objectively a theoretical, practical threshold, valid for all, on the basis of which it
might be said that health needs are entirely and definitively satisfied.” This, again,
reminds us of the implications of these arguments for a present in which the
faltering attempts at universal coverage in the United States are being abandoned.
These few remarks, consonant with the orientation of the Second Left (and not
altogether alien to what became Ewald’s practice in the 1990s), give us a clue to
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

The Secret Life of Neoliberal Subjectivity 37

what his planned book on the art of government and socialist politics might look
like. They also have a certain familiarity for those of us who have taken more than
a passing interest in the so-called “reform” of welfare states in the name of com-
batting their self-produced dependency in recent decades and the inflationary
tendencies of demands on them.
Let us say that the countercultural and political movements of the sixties and
early seventies placed the question of subjectivity – the “politics of experience,”
as R. D. Laing called it – on the agenda in a time of relative prosperity. With the
crisis of the 1970s neoliberalism would appropriate themes around individual
freedom, empowerment, and the potentiality of the forces of civil society against
the state. Influential sections of the institutional and party Left would seek, just as
Foucault predicted, to appropriate and experiment with elements, rationalities,
and technologies from neoliberalism, particularly in regard to the welfare state.
What emerged over the ensuing period was the flooding of social policy and the
welfare state by the neoliberal use of self-technologies, so that the entrepreneurial
subject indeed became the elusive goal of many neoliberal social and economic
programs, contrary to Foucault’s analysis, and we have witnessed an idolatry of
the narcissistic individual – from the Me Generation of the 1980s to the “selfies”
of day – in popular culture to the point that the ultimate one occupies the White
House itself. While the latter subject has indeed occupied a key space in our
public culture during this time a more subterranean movement, called by some
“neoliberal paternalism” (Soss, Fording, and Schram 2011), has sought to nudge,
hector, shame, discipline, and coerce the victims of structural inequality, class and
race, into adopting certain forms of subjectivity manifested by their betters and
thought to be necessary to contemporary social and economic life. Foucault’s
lectures on neoliberalism and comments on the welfare state belong to this crucial
hinge-moment in recent political culture. In this sense there is a Faustian pact
here: Foucault can seem insightful and prescient about neoliberalism because he
would come to share so many of its premises: the impossibility of a science of
the human that does not intensify domination, the economy – not the public, or
the state – as the generator and manifestation of truth, at least for liberal or even
modern governance, and the occlusion of the question of inequality. Foucault
both acutely diagnosed and to some extent could be said to have participated in
what amounted to a counter-revolution in public policy.
As the Los Angeles Review of Books has argued in respect of this case, our task is
to think for ourselves rather than criticizing intellectuals of the past for our con-
temporary problems, or believing that they held a magic bullet to solve them.
Nevertheless Foucault’s work has been massively influential in the contemporary
social sciences – and in that part that continues to imagine itself as critical – at the
same time in which those sciences have proved largely acquiescent in the face of
this neoliberal counter-revolution. Since 1980, the institutional Left – what used
to be called “social democracy” – has been one of the main agents of this counter-
revolution and allowed itself to become identified with it. This has facilitated the
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

38 Mitchell Dean

current reconfiguration of the conservative right that can extend the everyday,
embedded, and routinized form of neoliberalism with its focus on competition
and its low-tax, de-regulatory ethos, at the same time as it mobilizes popular
movements against global trade agreements, action on global environmental
problems, and the possibility of the movement of subjugated peoples on our planet.

References
Agamben, G. (2011). The Kingdom and the Glory: For a Theological Genealogy of Economy and
Government, trans. L. Chiesa with M. Mandarini. Stanford, CA: Stanford University
Press.
Becker, G., Ewald, F., and Harcourt, B. (2012). Becker on Ewald on Foucault on
Becker: American Neoliberalism and Michel Foucault’s 1979 “Birth of Biopolitics” Lectures. Institute
for Law and Economics Working Paper No. 614. Chicago: University of Chicago Law
School.
Behrent, M. C. (2010). Accidents Happen: François Ewald, the “Antirevolutionary
Foucault,” and the Intellectual Politics of the French Welfare State . Journal of Modern
History, 82(3), 585–624.
Behrent, M. C. (2016). Liberalism without Humanism: Michel Foucault and the Free-Market
Creed. In D. Zamora and M. Behrent (Eds.), Foucault and Neoliberalism (pp. 24–62).
Cambridge: Polity.
Brenner, N., Peck, J., and Theodore, N. (2010). Variegated Neoliberalization:
Geographies, Modalities, Pathways. Global Networks, 10, 182–222.
Dardot, P. and Laval, C. (2013). The New Way of the World: On Neoliberal Society, trans.
G. Elliot. London: Verso.
Dean, M. (1999). Governmentality: Power and Rule in Modern Society. London: Sage.
Dean, M. (2014a). Michel Foucault’s “Apology” for Neoliberalism . Journal of
Political Power, 7(3), 433–442.
Dean, M. (2014b). Rethinking Neoliberalism. Journal of Sociology, 50(2), 150–163.
Dean, M. and Hindess, B. (1998). Introduction: Government, Liberalism, Society. In M. Dean
and B. Hindess (Eds.), Governing Australia: Studies in Contemporary Rationalities of Government.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
de Lagasnerie, Geoffroy (2012). La Dernière Leçon de Michel Foucault: Sur le Néolibéralisme, la
Théorie et la Politique. Paris: Fayard.
Dilts, A. (2011). From “Entrepreneur of the Self” to “Care of the Self”: Neo-liberal
Governmentality and Foucault’s Ethics. Foucault Studies, 12, 130–146.
Donzelot, J. and Gordon, C. (2008). Governing Liberal Societies: The Foucault Effect in
the English-speaking World. Foucault Studies, 5, 48–62.
Du Gay, P. and Scott, A. (2010). State Transformation or Regime Shift? Sociologica, 2.
Retrieved from: www.sociologica.mulino.it/journal/issue/index/Issue/Journal:ISSUE:10
Ewald, F. (2016). François Ewald on Foucault and Neoliberalism. January 24. Retrieved
from: http://blogs.law.columbia.edu/foucault1313/2016/01/24/ewaldneoliberalism/
Foucault, M. (1977). Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison, trans. A. Sheridan.
London: Allen Lane.
Foucault, M. (1982). The Subject and Power. Critical Inquiry, 8(4), 777–795.
Foucault, M. (1984). What is Enlightenment? In P. Rabinow (Ed.), The Foucault Reader
(pp. 32–50). London: Penguin.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

The Secret Life of Neoliberal Subjectivity 39

Foucault, M. (1988). Social Security. In L. Kritzman (Ed.), Politics, Philosophy, Culture:


Interviews and Other Writings 1977–84 (pp. 159–177). New York: Routledge.
Foucault, M. (2003). “Society Must be Defended”: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1975–1976,
trans. D. Macey. New York: Picador.
Foucault, M. (2004). Naissance de la Biopolitique: Cours au Collège de France, 1978–1979.
Paris: Gallimard Seuil.
Foucault, M. (2008). The Birth of Biopolitics: Lectures at the Collège de France 1978–1979,
trans. G. Burchell. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Gamble, A. (1979). Free Economy and the Strong State. The Socialist Register, 16, 1–25.
Goldschmidt, Niels and Rauchenschwandtner, Hermann (2007). The Philosophy of the Social
Market Economy: Michel Foucault’s Analysis of “Ordoliberalism”. Freiburg Discussion Papers on
Constitutional Economics, 07/4. Freiburg: Walter Eucken Institute.
Hansen, M. P. (2015). Foucault’s Flirt? Neoliberalism, the Left and the Welfare State.
Foucault Studies, 20, 291–306.
Hayek, F. A. (1981). Interview, El Mercurio. April 12. Retrieved from: www.fahayek.org/
Jaschik, S. (2017). Anthropologists and Other Scholars Plan Read-in of
Michel Foucault to Protest Inauguration of Donald Trump. Inside Higher Ed, January 16.
Retrieved from: www.insidehighered.com/
Laclau, E. and Mouffe, C. (2001). Hegemony and Socialist Strategy: Towards a Radical Democratic
Politics. London: Verso.
Lazzarato, M. (2009). Neoliberalism in Action: Inequality, Insecurity and the Reconstitution
of the Social. Theory, Culture and Society, 29(6), 109–133.
Lazzarato, M. (2012). The Making of Indebted Man: An Essay on the Neoliberal Condition,
trans. J. D. Jordan. Los Angeles: Semiotext(e).
Mirowski, P. (2009). Postface: Defining Neoliberalism. InP. MirowskiandD. Plehwe
(Eds.), The Road from Mont Pèlerin: The Making of the Neoliberal Thought Collective
(pp. 417–455). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Mirowski, P. (2013). Never Let a Serious Crisis Go to Waste: How Neoliberalism Survived the
Financial Meltdown. London: Verso.
Mirowski, P. and Plehwe, D. (Eds.) The Road from Mont Pèlerin. The Making of the
Neoliberal Thought Collective. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
Negri, A. (2001). Interview. Le Monde. October 3. Retrieved from: libcom.org/library/
interview-le-monde-negri/
Peck, J. (2010a). Constructions of Neoliberal Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Peck, J. (2010b). Zombie Neoliberalism and the Ambidextrous State. Theoretical Criminol-
ogy, 14(1), 1–7.
Rose, N. (1996). Governing “Advanced” Liberal Democracies. In A. Barry, T. Osborne,
and N. Rose (Eds.), Foucault and Political Reason: Liberalism, Neo-Liberalism and Rational-
ities of Government (pp. 37–64). London: UCL Press.
Sennelart, M. (2007). Course Context. In M. Foucault, Security, Territory,
Population: Lectures at the Collège de France 1977–1978 (pp. 369–401). London: Palgrave
Macmillan.
Soss, J., Fording, R. C., and Schram, S. F. (2011). Disciplining the Poor: Neoliberal Paternalism
and the Persistent Power of Race. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Steinmetz-Jenkins, D. and Arnold, A. (2015). Searching for Foucault in an Age of
Inequality. Los Angeles Review of Books. Retrieved from: https://lareviewofbooks.org/
Weber, M. (1978). Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretative Sociology, 2
vols. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

40 Mitchell Dean

Zamora, D. (2014a). Can We Criticize Foucault? Jacobin. Retrieved from: www.jacobinmag.


com/2014/12/foucault-interview/
Zamora, D. (Ed.) (2014b). Critiquer Foucault: Les Années 1980 et la Tentation
Néolibérale. Brussels: Éditions Aden.
Zamora, D. (2016). Foucault, the Excluded and the Neoliberal Erosion of the State. In
D. Zamora and M. Behrent (Eds.), Foucault and Neoliberalism (pp. 63–84). Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Zamora, D. and Behrent, M. (Eds.) (2016). Foucault and Neoliberalism. Cambridge Polity.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

3
FOUCAULT’S THREE WAYS OF
DECENTERING THE STATE

Kaspar Villadsen

Currently, we witness certain tendencies to valorize society over the state. In


relation to the collapse of the former communist states in Eastern Europe and
authoritarian regimes in Northern Africa and the Middle East, there were hopes
for democracy arising from below. In several cases, however, ethnic and religious
conflicts have displayed the dark side of a civil society “freed from” the state.
Across welfare states from New Zealand to Canada, universal social services provided
by the state have been increasingly dismantled as governments reduce funding,
tighten eligibility criteria, and delegate service provision to market agents and
voluntary associations. Within social science, intellectual streams like governance
theory, governmentality studies, and Actor Network Theory dissolve the unity of
the state. Instead, it is argued that the state should be viewed as “decentered” or
decomposed into transient policy networks and global circulations, hence pro-
blematizing the idea of centralized political sovereignty exercised over a territory.
All of this would seem to imply a diminishing importance of the state. Con-
versely, however, we have recently witnessed the irruption of nationalism across
Europe, the closing of borders around national territories, and the proclamation
of protectionism in the USA, all of which puts back the state – and state-centered
governance – at the center of the political and intellectual agenda.
It is well known that Michel Foucault challenged the centrality of the state.
Instead, he advanced a view of the state as decentered: “I must do without a
theory of the state, as one can and must forego an indigestible meal” (2008,
pp. 76–77). Foucault further declared: “The state has no heart, as we well know,
but not just in the sense that it has no feelings, either good or bad, but it has no
heart in the sense that it has no interior” (Foucault 2008, p. 90). Given Foucault’s
continuous influence over new generations of social science scholars who study
problems of the state, and related issues such as territoriality, borders, social policy,
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

42 Kaspar Villadsen

and welfare services it is pertinent to evaluate the legacy of his writings on the
state. At the outset it should be noted that Foucault’s approach is neither a history
of the state nor is it a sociology of the state and its institutions. Instead, he
recovers from the historical archive different frameworks, “the reflexive prisms,”
or the grids of intelligibility, though which something called “the state” appears.
Foucault does not undertake these investigations from a mere historical interest.
On several occasions, he mentions that he wishes to “test” the potentials of a
particular perspective on the state. This aspiration is evident in his 1976 lecture
series, where Foucault wanted to test to what extent politics could be conceived
as war by other means (2003), or to be more precise, the question to which
insights could be achieved by analyzing state formation and the preservation of
the state as resulting from struggles between social groups. Foucault’s experi-
mental approach to analyzing the state could be said, then, to follow this
explorative question: What if we imagine that the state rests upon perpetual social
struggle? Or, as he would ask in 1978, what would happen if we imagine the
state as pervaded by contradictory governmental rationalities? It is by excavating a
body of historical texts, confronting the reader with a particular reflexive prism,
that Foucault shows us the potential of a particular framework of analysis. It is this
analytical testing that I wish to foreground in this chapter.
In this context, I am neither interested in reifying the idea of Foucault’s
“decentered state” nor in discussing the historical accuracy of Foucault’s analyses
regarding the state. The question is instead which resources Foucault’s evolving
thought on the state offers for contemporary analysis of urgent political issues.
The following sections examine the three main routes by which Foucault in the
1970s reached his famous “decentered” approach to the state. I suggest that
through these routes Foucault excavates distinct analytical frameworks, and I dis-
cuss them in light of contemporary issues. In particular, I consider the question of
how Foucault’s political thought can be used to study the relationship between
the state, civil society, and contemporary neoliberalism. The issues discussed
include first, the resurrection of European populism and its connection to eco-
nomic reforms, second, the EU’s reaction to the “refugee crisis,” and, third, the
rise of Occupy Wall St. and the Tea Party movements in the USA.

First Decentering: The State Rests Upon Social Struggle


(B)eneath the formal facade of the State, there were other forces and … they were
precisely not forces of the State, but the forces of a particular group with its own
history, its own relationship with the past, its own victories, its own blood, and its
own relations of domination.
(Foucault 2003, p. 224)

The problem of the state’s pretentions to universality has been a key question
ever since the emergence of the modern state in Western Europe in the
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Foucault: Decentering the State 43

seventeenth century and remained urgent with the coming of constitutional


democracy. A longstanding problem is how the state can safeguard universal
norms while at the same time being responsive to particular individuals with
specific needs and demands. In political theory, it has been acknowledged that
any universal claim inscribed into the state’s laws and institutions will always,
inevitably, emanate from particular groups and their values. The 1976 lecture
series, Society Must be Defended (2003), is where Foucault most directly addresses
the problem of how the state may represent the totality – that is, reflect the
multiplicity of heterogeneous groups and identities. However, Foucault follows a
route that disallows any support of the state as the unrivalled instrument necessary
to end centuries of confessional conflicts and safeguard against social and ethnic
rivalries. Instead, in the 1976 lectures, Foucault presented the social body as a site
of perpetual struggles for dominance. In this context, the state does not at all
appear as the safeguard against these struggles but rather as the vehicle and
crystallization of them.
This is the first decentering of the state that Foucault would perform during
the late 1970s. In Society Must be Defended, Foucault (2003) breaks down the idea
of a unified state sovereignty by presenting a version of society as traversed by
perpetual social rivalries. These lectures have been commented upon by a range
of scholars, offering quite diverse readings (Pasquino 1993; Marks 2000; Badiou
2012; Karlsen and Villadsen 2015; Dean and Villadsen 2016). Here, I focus on
how Foucault argues for a fundamental transition in the legitimation of territorial
sovereignty. The fundamental shift is from the absolute monarch’s sovereignty to
the precarious construction of “the people” under democratized sovereignty.
To frame the whole lecture series Foucault performs a, for him, typical narrative
move: He describes a radical discursive break which he subsequently complicates,
demonstrating its porosity and contingency. This happens by way of a counter-
positioning of Hobbes and Clausewitz as emblematic for two competing
discourses on politics and state-formation. Leaving aside whether Foucault’s
interpretation of Hobbes was correct (Pasquino 1993), we notice that Hobbes is
type-cast as emblematic of the centrist-juridical model that Foucault seeks to
move beyond: “We have to study power outside the model of Leviathan, outside
the field delineated by juridical sovereignty and the institutions of the State”
(Foucault 2003, p. 34). On Foucault’s account, the Hobbesian model of sovereignty
established as break in political discourse which was both temporal and spatial.
Implicit in this model was the relegation of war to a pre-modern, barbarian past
or to the outside of the civilized territories of the modern West: “Increasingly,
wars, the practices of war, and the institutions of war tended to exist, so to
speak, only on the frontiers, on the outer limits of the great State units” (Foucault
2003, p. 48).
Foucault then advances his key proposition: There is a continuation of war
within a society that has allegedly been pacified. Foucault makes this point by
exploring two historical sources, namely “race-war” historians and the modern
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

44 Kaspar Villadsen

medical sciences with their normalizing effects. The first textual source centers on
the premise that any universalizing erection of the state’s legal and constitutional
order is inevitably based on a singular project originating from a particular group,
a people or a “race.” Foucault aligns himself with seventeenth century race-war
writers who approached state-formation as a question of writing-up victorious
narratives of the people and nation. Notably, in this textual archive, “race” does
not designate a specific ethnicity, but rather figures in discursive battles for
mobilizing one social group against another in struggles over territorial control.
Foucault thus finds a discursive resource, a kind of “counter-history” that tears
society apart. Race war discourse comprises a range of very diverse writers,
including the Puritans, the Levellers, and the Diggers in England, and it is
represented by reactionary French aristocrats who fought against the monarchy.
Foucault also forges a link to later supporters of biological racism and state
eugenics appearing in the late ninetenth century.
The significance of this discourse is that it undermines the constitution of the
state by rendering its universalism the outcome of contingent struggles and
impossible totalizations. The race-war writers also resonate with Foucault’s
Nietzschean view of history as perpetual struggle for dominance (Marks 2000). In
his essay on Nietzsche, Foucault thus wrote: “humanity installs each of its violences
in a system of rules and thus proceeds from domination to domination” (Foucault
1981, p. 85). Race-war discourse disrupts the idea of history as progressing
towards a pacified universality. There is no claim for a truthful, non-partisan
writing of history here. Instead, the historian is “a subject who is fighting a war”
(Foucault 2003, p. 54). Hence, the race-war writers are recognized to be in
absolute partisanship, writing against defined adversaries.
Across Foucault’s authorship, one finds several analyses that potentially undermine
the foundations of the modern, constitutional state as a guarantor of liberal rights,
the system of representation, and civic peace (Foucault 2000a, 2000b). This
undermining can be related to Foucault’s rather fundamental distrust in the social
body to be safeguarded – the state (Gordon 1996). Society appears, on Foucault’s
account, to be fundamentally pervaded by relations of domination, suspicions,
exclusions, denunciations, and mutual surveillance. The unity of “the people” is
rendered as an immanent field of perpetual and multiple force relations that seem
to disallow being constituted as a legitimate subject of democratic politics.

Austerity, “Populism,” and the Greek Crisis


The theme of “race-war discourse” opens up the study of the formation of statehood
around notions of national identity, the people, race, blood, and rightful inheri-
tance (Dean and Villadsen 2016, pp. 67 ff.). This is certainly an urgent issue in
our present. Across Europe, right-wing populism has gained influence demanding
the suspension of universal rights in their quest to control or expel individuals
who allegedly threaten the state’s unity from inside. We have witnessed the rise
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Foucault: Decentering the State 45

of nationalist parties in countries like the Netherlands (Wilders), France (Le


Pen), Denmark (“The Danish People’s Party”), and Austria (Haider). In the last
decades, we have also seen an upsurge of ethnic nationalism and bloody religious
persecution in the former Yugoslavia, in Ukraine, in parts of Africa, and in the
Middle East. One may also observe a continuation or resurgence of “populist”
political regimes, particularly in Latin America, including Venezuela, Argentina,
Equador, and Bolivia. In the USA, the situation is very different, yet the Occupy
movement, the Tea Party, and Donald Trump have all been designated
“populist.”
If we focus on the European context, we may relate the recent rise of populism
to neoliberal reforms implemented in certain countries that have drastically
reduced expenditures on health and welfare. Greece and Spain, in particular, have
witnessed the re-emergence of social issues such as general poverty, rapidly rising
youth unemployment, and an increasing amount of indebted and even homeless
families. These reforms that rest on neoliberal principles have triggered increasing
popular discontent and given rise to massive protests – at times addressed to
national governments, at other times addressing the”troika” of the European
Central Bank, the European Union, and the International Monetary Fund. We
have witnessed the discursive construction of two camps, that is, “the people”
suffering under severe austerity and “the establishment” consisting of domestic
elites and the EU institutions. As in the race-war discourse studied by Foucault,
we see competing narratives of the historical process leading to the crisis, just as
we see irreconcilable representations of who constitute legitimate political actors,
and who are represented as irresponsibly populist.
Let us briefly consider the Greek government-debt crisis, which was also
termed “the Greek Depression.” It is well known that an agreement was reached
on October 27, 2011 in which extensive austerity measures where requested by
the European Central Bank, the EU leaders, and the International Monetary
Fund in return for a bailout. From 2010 to 2016, the Greek government under-
took twelve rounds of tax increases, implemented cuts in public spending, and
major welfare reforms. Between 2008 and 2012, the Greek GDP diminished by
20 percent, and youth unemployment reached as high as 60 percent. These
effects triggered sustained public discontent, evident in the Indignant Citizens
Movement, and nationwide protests centered on issues like pension cuts and
youth unemployment. The EU-group and IMF represented the Greek problem
as one about returning to normality and securing the (otherwise) successful EU-
collaboration by taking “unavoidable measures.” In the discourse formulated by
Greeks in opposition to the austerity measures, the Eurogroup and IMF allegedly
performed a drastic shift towards Greece from the encouragement to spend to an
“overnight declaration” of the Greek debt as irresponsible and unsustainable
(Stavrakakis 2015, p. 276).
The anti-austerity and anti-EU elite-discourse can be reconstructed along the
following lines: In late 2009, upon a global economic crisis, the Greeks were
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

46 Kaspar Villadsen

suddenly faced by the declaration of their debt as unsustainable and disruptive of


the whole EU project. The Greeks were unjustly denounced as unproductive
“over-spenders,” a behavior contrasting with sound European values. The poli-
cies that were enforced upon the Greek government resulted in an economic and
social situation which no population should be subjected to. According to a
prolific critic, Yannis Stavrakakis, this was a “gigantic disciplining operation – a
huge experiment in violent downward social mobility and neoliberal adjustment
and restructuring” (Stavrakakis 2013, p. 315). Greece was in effect faced with an
alliance between the European economic elite and a technocratic EU system that
had no regard for common people’s suffering. This alliance relied on the “there is
no alternative” doctrine which was only challenged by the Syria party who
allegedly voiced the real interest of the Greek people:

Syriza promised to restore their dignity and represent their interests against
the Greek and European establishment, thus breaking the omertà that sur-
rounded the “success story” of the Eurozone, which had been declaring the
end of the crisis and a return to “normality.”

However, returning to normality in fact implied “the normalisation of the effects


of the crisis, a perpetual continuation of crisis within other means” (Stavrakakis
2015, p. 277). The anti-austerity discourse would point out factors, or failures, for
which the Greeks were not responsible, since they were in fact inherent to the
EU-construction or resulting from the recession of the global economy. We
notice that this anti-austerity discourse constructs a defined enemy, presents a
distinct historical narrative, and holds the promise of bringing dignity back to the
Greek people as they regain control of their country and destiny.
By contrast, the “administrative” discourse represented the Greek crisis in
what at first glance would appear to be more neutral or non-antagonistic (eco-
nomic) terms. It emphasized that the Greek crisis was caused by structural
weaknesses in the Greek economy, and that the gravity of government deficits
had remained unexposed by the data previously released by the Greek govern-
ment. At the center of this discourse was that the Greek government had
requested bailout loans in 2010, 2012, and 2015 from the Euro-group, the
International Monetary Fund, and the European Central Bank, and that it in
2011 agreed to a 50 percent “haircut” on debt owed to private banks. The
austerity measures were presented as something akin to a surgical operation
performed on Europe’s “sick man”: “We can clearly observe the operation of a
medical metaphor: the crisis is declared a serious illness, the result of an inherent
social pathology; ‘contagion’ or ‘contamination’.” (Stavrakakis 2013, p. 315).
The Greek illness, it was hypothesized, might spread to other European states
with comparable government debts and structural problems such as Italy, Spain,
or France. Despite this fear, the “administrative” discourse had no recognition
of any possible economic failures or systemic faults at the level of the EU.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Foucault: Decentering the State 47

Placed in the very foreground were innate pathologies of the Greek nation such
as irresponsibility and immorality. This construction made it possible to place
the fault of unemployment and indebtedness on the Greeks themselves in a
process of stigmatization or shaming.
A pertinent perspective on this construction of pathology and stigma can be
found in Foucault’s Society Must be Defended and his rendering of biopolitics
(2003, pp. 61–63). There, Foucault argues that the advent of modern biopolitics
understood as a strategy for optimizing the vitality of the living population
implied the attempt to control, normalize, and persecute elements within the
population that threatened it from the inside. In modern societies, sovereign
intervention can precisely be justified when such threats to the population are
detected, and the Greek pathology could indeed be viewed as such a deleterious
element. The Greek crisis proves the point that in liberal times, authoritative
interventions can take place with the justification of a “disease of the will,” the
detection of a pathology in which the will-power is no longer in charge of an
individual or a group (Valverde 1996). The logic of sovereign intervention is
hence not to suppress the individuals governed but to bring them back to rational
self-government. This discourse in effect represents the Greeks as a collective
subject without rational self-control and responsibility, but the latter can be
reinstalled by neoliberal management of the country’s economy and public
spending. Voices that contest this cure are depicted as enemies of Europe: “(W)
hoever diverges from the dominant neoliberal administration of the crisis is
immediately discredited and denounced as an enemy of European values” (Stav-
rakakis 2015, p. 275). Notably then, while the Eurozone institutions purport
“technocratic” solutions and rely upon economic calculation this is certainly still a
discourse partaking in a battle. This is perhaps most clearly evident in the use of
the negative term “populist” about the Syriza party and its supporters, which
delegitimizes contestation of the neoliberal narrative, its demands, and the social
order that it defends. Just as in the “populist,” anti-austerity discourse, we see the
construction of history, an enemy to be defeated, a rightful victory, and a just
juridical-economic order to be achieved.
These are merely tentative analyses that would require further development.
The race-war perspective offers a critical lens through which other, similar dis-
cursive political battles could be studied, for instance in Spain around Podemos or
in Poland and its right-wing populism (Shields 2012). There are, however, certain
limitations to this framework for studying politics and statehood which Foucault
excavates in 1976. Insofar as this perspective assumes that social positions and
interests are constituted not outside, but inside discursive practices, we cannot
speak of identifiable material interests, on the basis of which we can advance
critique (Dean and Villadsen 2016, p. 80). Hence, taken to its logical conclusion,
this framework can only address the persuasive force that particular discourses
may possess which we can analytically deconstruct but not substantially criticize
or reject.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

48 Kaspar Villadsen

Second Decentering: A Gamut of Secular, Administrative


Rationalities
In reality you have a series of complex edifices in which, of course, the techniques
themselves change and are perfected, or anyway become more complicated, but in
which above all changes the dominant characteristic, or more exactly, the system of
correlation between juridico-legal mechanisms, disciplinary mechanisms, and
mechanisms of security.
(Foucault 2007, p. 22)

Foucault’s second decentering of the state occurs in his 1978 lecture series,
Security, Territory, Population (Foucault 2007). There, he argues that the discovery
of “the living population” was a decisive event in the history of Western political
thought and government. Foucault describes how in the seventeenth and eighteenth
centuries a new episteme emerged for reflecting upon political rule, one shared
by a diverse range of thinkers, including physiocrats, demographers, hygienists,
and political economists. Common to these streams of thought was their departure
from the cosmological world-view of what, in short, may be termed “princely
rule.” Schematically, superseding the doctrine of a divine providence, the object
of political government became a living population which possessed inherent
mechanisms and regularities that should be studied empirically. I wish to give
attention to one analytical potential which these lectures offer. Instead of the
ultimate premise of sovereign rule in God’s providence, Foucault describes
the emergence of several competing governmental rationalities. This situation
renders problems of governance indeterminate and complex in a way that is very
recognizable from our present viewpoint.
At the start of the 1978 lectures, Foucault introduces three governmental
rationalities or “major technologies of power”: “law,” “discipline,” and “security”
(Foucault 2007, pp. 5–24). Reading eighteenth century texts about town planning,
Foucault then describes how these governmental rationalities offer very different
lenses for turning phenomena like theft or illness into objects of calculation and
intervention. Law, discipline, and security each constitute distinct lenses to such
an extent that stealing or illness come to appear as fundamentally different objects.
The legal rationality institutes “a binary division between the permitted and the
prohibited, and a coupling, comprising the code, between a type of prohibited
action and a type of punishment” (2007, p. 5). In the gaze of discipline, we see “a
series of adjacent, detective, medical, and psychological techniques appear which
fall within the domain of surveillance, diagnosis, and the possible transformation
of individuals” (2007, p. 5). Finally, security calculations take as their object the
living population, that is, the regularities by which populations procreate, pro-
duce, consume, migrate, and so on. The security rationality appears as the most
modern of the three governmental rationalities. The fundamental aim is to foster
and strengthen the self-regulating capacities of the population, insofar as security
targets the population as both “object and subject” (Foucault 2007, p. 11).
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Foucault: Decentering the State 49

Law seeks to reinstate an order that has been violated, whereas discipline strives
to prevent the unwanted from happening by normalizing bodies and actions.
Hence, in its fundamental form, law targets the totality of subjects who inhabit a
given territory. It is prohibitive and operates the binary distinction of the allowed
versus the forbidden. In contrast to this binary of legal/illegal, security instead
“establishes an average considered as optimal on the one hand, and, on the other,
a bandwidth of the acceptable that must not be exceeded” (Foucault 2007, p. 6).
Security also diverges from disciplinary normalization, since security starts from
the reality as given and entails the more tempered aspiration of optimizing the
processes already operative in this reality:

This given will not be reconstructed to arrive at a point of perfection, as in a


disciplinary town. It is simply a matter of maximizing the positive elements,
for which one provides the best possible circulation, and of minimizing what
is risky and inconvenient, like theft and disease, while knowing that they will
never be completely suppressed.
(Foucault 2007, p. 19)

Foucault then moves on to risk a broad generalization, stating that the emble-
matic object of legal rationality is a territory, discipline works upon bodies, and
security relates to the totality of the living population (2007, p. 11). The major
governmental rationalities do not appear historically in a sequential order: “There
is not a series of successive elements, the appearance of the new causing the earlier
ones to disappear” (2007, p. 8). Importantly, then, instead of outlining irre-
trievable breaks from one epoch or rationality to another, Foucault emphasized
the co-existence and dynamic interplay between governmental rationalities.
Accordingly, he wishes to study gradual transformations in “the system of correlation
between juridico-legal mechanisms, disciplinary mechanisms, and mechanisms of
security” (Foucault 2007, p. 22). This analytical framework offers a very fruitful
perspective for analyzing modern problems of political governance, foregrounding
the interplay, reverberations, and frictions between several co-existing govern-
mental rationalities (2007, pp. 6–24). Compared to Foucault’s previous study of
“disciplinary society,” he opened up more complex descriptions of mobile and
heterogeneous configurations of state power.
Clearly, Foucault’s explorations in 1978 took part in his attempt to challenge
the idea of the state as unified and static by retracing the genesis of our modern
governmental rationalities and displaying their distinct modalities of knowledge:

We should not be looking for some sort of sovereignty from which powers
spring, but showing how the various operators of domination support one
another, relate to one another, at how they converge and reinforce one
another in some cases, and negate or strive to annul one another in other cases.
(Foucault 2003, p. 45)
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

50 Kaspar Villadsen

Notably, this emphasis on multiple forms of governmental rationalities extends to


Foucault’s general Nietzschean conception of history as perpetual struggle
between divergent forces (Bussolini 2010, p. 88). The plurality of rationalities
renders social space fractured by different imperatives, at times reinforcing and
assimilating, at other times undermining and contradicting one another. Foucault’s
second decentering of the state leaves ample space for studying indeterminacy and
dynamic repercussions in regard to governmental problems that have become
indeterminate.

Refugees, Migrants, and the EU


I suggest that this framework can be put to use to understand the EU’s difficulties
in regard to how to regulate border-crossers in the shape of migrants and refugees.
This is a problem that situates itself in a fundamental paradox characteristic of
twenty-first century European welfare states which emerged as both capitalist-
expansive and territorially enclosed entities (Lessenich 2011). The thorny questions
of how to react to migrations are shaped by the fundamental contradiction
between, on the one hand, the capitalist logic of free circulation and, on the
other hand, the national-territorial order of inclusion and granting of social rights
via citizenship. At the EU level, one finds problems that reflect the deep-seated
tension between supranational mobility and the perpetuation of national borders.
This tension may elucidate why concrete problems of how to regulate migration
are so hard to determine and manage within the EU-collaboration.
Historically, the EU was established principally as a structure that would facilitate
trade, particularly by securing greater mobility of goods, capital, and labor. This
key objective of facilitating the effective functioning of the EU’s internal market
could, in Foucauldian terms, be understood as a security problem, insofar as the
EU’s creation of an internal market is comparable to a “milieu,” that is “a space in
which a series of uncertain elements unfold” (Foucault 2007, p. 20). Yet, the
citizens of EU member countries are still mainly assigned fundamental rights
according to a political-legal rationality of inclusion which is territorially delimited
(Lessenich 2011, p. 307). Accordingly, it would appear as if the EU’s regulatory
practices in relation to cross-border mobility are overdetermined by the legal
rationality premised on sovereign territoriality and security rationality which
centers on mobility and circulation.
However, the recent attempts to arrest the streams of people on the move
already before they reach the outer EU borders and to channel those who do
reach EU countries and distribute them in a planned fashion could be viewed as
guided by a disciplinary rationality. Hence, Foucault said about discipline that “it
arrests or regulates movements; it clears up confusion; it dissipates compact
groupings of individuals wandering about the country in unpredictable ways;
it establishes calculated distributions” (1977, p. 218). The disciplinary strategy rests
on the hope of being able to plan, guide, control, and arrest the individuals who
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Foucault: Decentering the State 51

are on the move. By contrast, the rationality of security entails a different set of
reflections and solutions, since it inserts phenomena (crime, grain production, or
moving individuals) into a series of probable events. Relevant for present con-
cerns in the EU to secure “good” supranational circulation, Foucault argued in
regard to early modern town planning: “(T)he concern of government became
that of making cities open to wider circulations, freed from their earlier spatial,
juridical, administrative and economic enclosure” (Baerenholdt 2013, p. 24).
Upholding territorial enclosures would be viewed as detrimental to the imperative
of allowing free circulations.
The interplay and shifts between the rationalities of law, discipline, and security
may help understanding the difficulties at the EU level in responding with a
common voice and in a consistent manner. For instance, this perspective could
make intelligible why migrant workers are today often conceived as a threat by
national governments who increasingly base their policies on the protection of
national boundaries and restricted access to social rights and permanent residency.
Stricter military and police measures are put in place to deter, control, arrest, isolate,
and survey border-crossers at the exterior EU border and at borders of member
states. These measures could be understood as guided by legal and disciplinary
rationalities, often contradicting the aspirations of security. Instruments like “fast-
mover,” Green Card arrangements, and schemes for attracting specific types of
skilled labor can be viewed as solutions resonating with a security rationality, that
is, as techniques for “securing” beneficial transnational circulation. The field of
regulation of migration and border-crossing in all its diverse manifestations is
characterized by rapid technical inventions. It is also marked by contradictions
and paradoxes which could be further analyzed as arising from the intersections of
the rationalities of law, discipline, and security which pervade the EU.
This analytical perspective can challenge what has been termed “the meta-
physics of the border” (De Genova 2013, p. 255), since it displays that neither the
exterior EU borders nor the national borders of member states are simply tangible
demarcations. Instead, these borders appear in their contingency, continually the
object of controversy and redefinitions. We begin to recognize that a sovereign-
territorial border is not the same as a disciplinary border, which again is not the
same as a security border. Hereby, the apparent fixity of the border is pro-
blematized, and instead we may speak of unstable practices of “bordering.” On
this perspective, the EU regulation of migrants straddles between the govern-
mental logics of law, disciplinarity, and security. Such a perspective on European
discussions of refugee management could also elucidate why refugees can simul-
taneously appear as vulnerable and criminalized, be spoken about as a resource and
a threat. Finally, it would be pertinent to explore how sovereign measures tend to
become routinized and embedded in administrative and bureaucratic (disciplinary)
systems. Indeed, the debates about how to deal with refugees and migrants at the
EU borders often emphasize the importance of avoiding excessive military and
police violence against vulnerable civilians displaced by catastrophes. At the same
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

52 Kaspar Villadsen

time, bordering practices are enframed in an administrative logic that makes dif-
ficult more serious discussion of the legitimacy of violent militarized deterrence
and police measures.

Third Decentering: The Infinite State and Political Eschatology


The state is at once that which exists, but which does not yet exist enough.
(Foucault 2008, p. 4)

In his 1979 lectures, Foucault performs a third decentering of the state (2008).
Methodologically, he does so by presenting the state as not a universal but as a
“transactional reality.” In terms of historical material, Foucault explores different
variants of liberal and neoliberal thought with a focus on how they conceive of
the state’s role vis-à-vis society.
Foucault begins by stating his general approach which avoids basing analyses of
historical processes on pre-given “universals” such as sexuality, the economy, civil
society, or the state (Foucault 2008, pp. 2–3). We must reject the assumption of
the state as a universal, Foucault argues, viewing it as if it were a primary reality
existent prior to social and historical events. Instead we must view the state as a
historical “singularity” which emerged at a particular moment and develops in
response to particular problems.
Perhaps, the 1979 lectures is the place where Foucault most effectually decenters
the state through conceptual innovation. He invented the category “transactional
reality” to designate “things that do not exist, and yet which are in reality and
follow a regime of truth” (2008, p. 20). Instead of assigning a substantial quality
to sexuality, the economy, civil society, or the state, Foucault foregrounded
practices organized around that “something” which is supposed to exist (2008,
p. 3). By this move, Foucault seeks to escape the choice between idealism (the
state as a mere abstraction) and realism (particular institutions constituting the
state). Instead, he takes as a starting point that the notion of the state is embedded
in a series of real practices from which it cannot be isolated, a whole “set-up”
which comprises laws, actions, and words (Veyne 2010, p. 31). Like madness and
sexuality, the state can be viewed as a transactional reality which does not “exist
in-itself,” but which saturates real practices that are organized in relation to it
(Villadsen 2016, p. 9).
As a transactional reality, the state is subject to a permanent critical reflection
regarding its role, its functions, and its limits. This is because the state became
inserted into a particular regime of truth, which we may broadly term modern
political economy, according to which questions of the state’s functions, proper
size, its limits, and so on are deliberated. Hence, Foucault describes how political
economists, from the eighteenth century onwards, began to subordinate the
exercise of state governance to a permanent test with reference to society’s self-
regulatory mechanisms: “I think that fundamentally it was political economy that
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Foucault: Decentering the State 53

made it possible to ensure the self-limitation of governmental reason” (Foucault


2008, p. 13). Henceforth, there will be a permanent testing of the government of
the state, which means that the state becomes an infinite project, a mobile object.
Hence, Foucault says: “The state is nothing else but the effect, the profile, the
mobile shape of a perpetual statification (étatisation) or statifications, in the sense
of incessant transactions which modify, or move, or drastically change” (Foucault
2008, p. 77). In 1978, Foucault similarly suggested that in contrast to historical
teleology, we now live in an infinite political time that is “not temporally
oriented toward a final unity” (Foucault 2007, p. 379). This is what could be
termed an “indefinite governmentality.” It rests on the belief that the state will
always be there, residing in a system of infinite inter-state competition. There
would henceforth be a governmentality “with no foreseeable term or final aim”
(2007, p. 342). This is a kind of liberal governmentality in which contestations of
government may lead to incremental changes, but in which grand ideas of a
completely different social order are excluded.
Some critics argue that Foucault’s analyses in 1979 depict the neo-liberal social
order as more flexible and open, and that he implicitly endorses it as preferable
compared to state-centered political ideologies (Behrent 2009; Dean and Villadsen
2016). Alain Badiou counts Foucault among those intellectuals who always caution
against the twentieth century’s major political projects for creating a “new man,”
and who risk effectively supporting the technical and “apolitical” biopolitics of the
twenty-first century, a purely economic-administrative protection of life (Badiou
2007, pp. 8–9). Notwithstanding their horrific outcomes, the grand political and
humanistic projects of the twentieth century were at least “passionate” and genu-
inely political, insofar as they represented man’s aspiration to transcend himself and
create a new society. By comparison, the current political order is “depoliticized”
which entails “the disappearance of the political,” a situation in which diverse
political demands are embraced as long as they do not fundamentally contest the
dominant neoliberal economic order (Swyngedouw 2014, p. 123). Instead of con-
testation between substantially divergent political ideologies, we now live in a state
of “managed democracy” characterized by conservative, technocratic solutions.
It should be noted, however, that Foucault presents an alternative to this liberal
governmental order. At the end of the 1979 lectures, he counter-positions
modern, liberal governmentality with what he terms statist and national politics
that invoke political eschatology. Conventionally, eschatology designates the
theological study of the dramatic end of the world and its rebirth in a perfected
form, usually according to a divine plan or a pre-designed history (Villadsen 2016,
pp. 14–15). Foucault speaks of a “lingering rationality” which comprises political
ideologies that invoke a truth which will reveal itself in the course of history. He
mentions Marxism, which invokes “a rationality of history progressively mani-
festing itself as truth” (2008, p. 313). Hence, the conception of time is pivotal.
Crucially, political eschatology asserts the coming of a final time, when a new
world or society will be realized. By promising the irruption of the existing order
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

54 Kaspar Villadsen

political eschatology is a forceful political discourse that “corresponds” to the


infinity state-reason and liberal governmentality. On Foucault’s account, eschato-
logical beliefs constituted one of the counter-conducts which developed in relation
to the Christian pastorate. With the emergence of state reason in the seventeenth
century eschatological themes were excluded from political discourse. But escha-
tological thinking was reactivated to contest the “indefinite time” of modern
governmentality. In its modern forms, political eschatology designates quasi-religious
political ideas of a perfect social order that interrupts the present or is awaiting its
realization in the final culmination of history.
Modern political eschatology would be found among extreme and utopian
political movements which adhered to the hope of the coming of a new human
world. These movements were premised on the hope for a day when the state
would transform into a united, non-antagonistic community; a specter that
included communitarian theologians, libertarians, utopian socialists, and later on
Stalinism, Fascism, and National Socialism. For the purpose of contemporary
political analysis, Foucault’s notion of “political eschatology” can be used to
analyze movements that promise a dramatic break with the emergence of a new
order; one that unifies state and society. Whereas liberal governmentality assumes
a permanent split between state and civil society and the economy, eschatological
ideologies dream of a unification of state and society (Villadsen 2016, p. 13).
Eschatological visions may be articulated by diverse forms of political action
against existent governmental structures. Particularly relevant for the present dis-
cussion, the dramatic idiom of eschatology offers a potentially disruptive weapon
in the face of technocratic “post-politics.”
The emergence in recent years of radical and utopian political movements
could possibly be analyzed through the lens of political eschatology. It has been
suggested that the Occupy movement was a reaction to a situation of depoliti-
cization and the monopolization of power by the economic and political elite in
contemporary liberal-capitalist society. Occupy succeeded in instituting a
moment of re-politicization by entirely rejecting the system of representation
and by refraining from formulating demands that could be accommodated
within the existing political structure. Hence, Occupy never mobilized around
something like a defined political program. Instead the movement articulated
broad notions of equality and revived democracy in the face of political-
economic inequality. The proclamation of equality, universal solidarity, and the
insurrection of a whole new form of politics gave the Occupy movement an
eschatological tenor.

Occupy succeeded in a kind of re-politicization exactly by way of its inclu-


sive and open character. OWS and related movements invoke a decidedly
universalizing logic. Although they would admit to constitute a minority in
number, they nevertheless claim to speak for “everyone,” for “the majority,”
or giving voice to “the 99%.” Evident here is a strive to transcend the
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Foucault: Decentering the State 55

particularism of the local issues of poverty, debts, home evictions and labour
struggles and insert them in an overall political spectacle.
(Turner and Villadsen 2016, p. 162)

There was something distinctly non-pragmatic, unnegotiable, and utopian


about the messages communicated by the Occupy movement. It articulated the
belief that it was better to achieve nothing at all than succumb to the pragmatism
of achieving something small within the existent structure. Occupy staged a dramatic
spectacle in opposition to pragmatic politics. Occupy’s attempt to disrupt the
political ontology of representation could be seen as an intervention with eschato-
logical connotations, insofar as it carried the message that the liberal-capitalist
order as we know it will henceforth be impossible. It promised, as it were, to halt
the infinite governmentality of liberal constitutionalism and ushered a new world.

A democratic government derives its just power from the people, but cor-
porations do not seek consent to extract wealth from the people and the
Earth; … no true democracy is attainable when the process is determined by
economic power. We come to you at a time when corporations, which
place profit over people, self-interest over justice, and oppression over
equality, run our governments.
(Occupy Wall Street General Assembly cited in Creech 2014, p. 466)

Occupy managed to unite and intensify popular protests against a world where
corporate capital corrupts and misuses the state apparatus, suppressing the expres-
sion of popular will. Banks and big corporations were posited as the absolute
antitheses of collectivist, democratic politics. Often the movement used public
displays and images of poverty, discrimination, and police brutality, transmitted
through social media technology, in order to “dramatize key issues in a given
society” (Kellner cited in Creech 2014, p. 463). It was a staged battle between the
forces of good and evil. The two-headed monster of abusive corporate capital and
the undemocratic political elite was confronted with the mass of protestors united
merely in the axiomatic demand for equality.
At another part of the political spectrum, the Tea Party movement, which
reached its peak in 2008–2010, similarly demanded a fundamentally different
political order. It attacked “big governance” and made reference to an original
(lost) America based on the wise doctrines of the founding fathers. Broadly similar
to Occupy, the Tea Party managed to generate mass support, it articulated utopian
visions some of which displayed quasi-theological and eschatological themes, and
it often connected to evangelical movements or congregations (Turner and Villadsen
2016, p. 166). In both cases, “the people” served as an empty signifier for mass
mobilization. However, the Tea Party rallied around an anti-government message,
requested tax-cuts, and claimed to represent the “small people” of suburban and rural
America. Its reactionary and conservative components can be seen in its attempts “to
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

56 Kaspar Villadsen

defend and retain traditional identities and statuses based on race, patriarchy and
hetero-normativity that have been under assault by late modern ‘network society’”
(Langman 2012, p. 469). The Tea Party can thus be viewed, at least in part, as a
reaction to the dissolution of cultural certainties and the sweeping process of
globalization.
In the Tea Party’s ideology, society is imagined as an almost mythical space,
that is, the original white, rural, and Christian America, which regrettably has
been distorted and needs regeneration. Of course this vision was invoked variously
across the different parts of the Tea Party movement. Christian conservatives
found in the Tea Party a confirmation of their longstanding convictions about the
theological signification of the founding of the American constitution and of
American exceptionalism. On their view, the juridical-theological foundation of
the “real” America has been perverted by politicians, bureaucracy, and the cultural
decay of big cities: “Indeed, there has been a long tradition in which the con-
servative, ‘idyllic’ countryside where people are more ‘authentic’ and ‘virtuous’
has counterpoised the nefarious cosmopolitan city with its toleration of diversity,
sophistication, and above all, decadence and sites of transgression” (Langman
2012, p. 473).
Political movements guided by Christian conservatism in the USA are intriguing
since they typically praise an original, natural, God-ordained (but now lost) social
order. This idea of the loss of “real America” makes possible the claim that the
movement is in a sense non-partisan, insofar as it simply aspires to reinstate the
founding fathers’ intentions and the ordained plan, also articulated as American
exceptionalism. Notably, the Tea Party’s vision of recovery of lost America is
connected with a particular set of fiscal and economic policies, evident in Tea
Party members’ calls for a severe reduction of the US federal budget deficit by
reducing government spending and lowering taxes. This ideological construct is
hence premised on “a consistent set of identifications that link the founders – and
the particular forms of fiscal and moral probity they are understood to exemplify –
with contemporary tea party conservatism” (Wilson and Burack 2012, p. 182).
The claim of defending the original constitution also justifies the representation of
political opponents as violators of the constitution. This is the case, for instance,
with President Obama whose socialist aspirations allegedly disrupt the very con-
stitution: “Mr. Obama’s problem is that the Constitution of the United States
stands in his way” (Wilson and Burack 2012, p. 48). In brief, then, the Tea
Party’s political eschatology revolves around the rebirth of God’s America.
Future work could use the notion of political eschatology to expand our
vocabulary for analyzing the formation of political identities. In particular, it
could help rendering current left- and right-wing populist movements and their
ideologies intelligible. The notion points to the totalizing and populist character
of movements that rely on eschatological visions which promise to annul the
permanent contestation of pluralistic politics and institute a new, non-antagonistic
society. However, political eschatology can rally both egalitarian movements and
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Foucault: Decentering the State 57

radical right movements. It may also constitute a potent critical weapon for
forming radical political subjectivities in the face of an economic-administrative
order premised on the “there is no alternative” ideology. When social groups
suffering from austerity are stigmatized as irrational and resistance is blocked
insofar as they are segregated as being individually responsible for their mis-
fortune, eschatological visions may unify people in a common vision that spurs
the kind of genuine politics that Badiou hopes for. In brief, political eschatology
must be analyzed as a flexible and polyvalent discursive resource.

Conclusion
Readers of Foucault have routinely stated that he turned the analytical focus away
from the state. Some have argued that his numerous statements on the state are
ambiguous and fail to constitute a coherent position. In this chapter, however, I
share Steven Sawyer’s aspiration to read Foucault’s ambivalences towards the state
positively as a resource (2015, p. 140). At a moment where many social scientists
shy away from theorizing and studying the state, a non-coherent approach which
offers different analytical frameworks for exploring the state and state-centered
politics may be very timely. This chapter has explored three ways of approaching
the state. In the first, the state was wedded to narratives of the nation or the
people. This helped us to elucidate how the Greek nation was constructed in
forceful narratives of what constitutes “the people,” their history, and their
rightful future. In the second approach, the state was decentered into adminis-
trative rationalities in which the state and state-action appear entirely differently as
a solution to mundane problems. The EU’s present difficulties with handling
migration served as a window for considering how contemporary (supranational
and national) governance straddles between several incongruous rationalities.
Third, we explored Foucault’s diagnosis of the modern state as embedded in an
“infinite governmentality,” and we discussed how political eschatology in the
preset context may constitute a disruptive force of political agency. Assuming that
the state is neither a specific structure, nor an inherently “cold” or “warm”
monster, means that the state can unfold in a plethora of ways. Foucault’s think-
ing on the state is certainly not coherent, neither is it without shortcomings. But I
hope that this chapter indicates some less acknowledged potentials for exploring
current issues of state, civil society, and neoliberalism.

References
Baerenholdt, J. O. (2013). Governmobility: The Powers of Mobility. Mobilities, 8(1), 20–34.
Badiou, A. (2007). The Century. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Badiou, A. (2012). The Adventure of French Philosophy. New York: Verso.
Behrent, M. C. (2009). Liberalism without Humanism: Michel Foucault and the Free-market
Creed, 1976–1979. Modern Intellectual History, 6(3), 539–568.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

58 Kaspar Villadsen

Biebricher, T. and Vogelmann, F. (2012) Governmentality and State Theory: Reinventing


the Reinvented Wheel? Theory & Event, 15(3), 1–18.
Bussolini, J. (2010). What is a Dispositive? Foucault Studies, 10, 85–107.
Cohen, J. and Arato, A. (1992). Civil Society and Political Theory. London: MIT Press.
Creech, B. (2014). Digital Representation and Occupy Wall Street’s Challenge to Political
Subjectivity. Convergence: The International Journal of Research into New Media Technologies,
20(4), 461–477.
Dean, M. and Villadsen, K. (2016). State Phobia and Civil Society: The Political Legacy of
Michel Foucault. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
De Genova, N. (2013). Spectacles of Migrant “Illegality”: The Scene of Exclusion, the
Obscene of Inclusion. Ethnic and Racial Studies, 36(7), 1180–1198.
Foucault, M. (1977). Discipline and Punish. New York: Penguin.
Foucault, M. (1980). Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings. New York:
Pantheon.
Foucault, M. (1981). Nietzsche, Genealogy, History. In P. Rabinow (Ed.) The Foucault
Reader. New York: Penguin.
Foucault, M. (2000a). Lives of Infamous Men. In Power: Essential Works of Foucault, 1954–1984,
Vol. 3. London: Penguin Books.
Foucault, M. (2000b). Truth and Juridical Forms. In Power: Essential Works of Foucault,
1954–1984, Vol. 3. London: Penguin Books.
Foucault, M. (2003). Society Must Be Defended: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1975–76.
New York: Picador.
Foucault, M. (2007). Security, Territory, Population: Lectures at the Collège de France 1977–78.
New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Foucault, M. (2008). The Birth of Biopolitics: Lectures at the Collège de France 1978–1979.
London: Palgrave.
Gordon, C. (1996). Foucault in Britain. In A. Barry, T. Osborne, and N. Rose (Eds.),
Foucault and Political Reason: Liberalism, Neo-Liberalism and Rationalities of Government.
London: UCL Press.
Karlsen, M. P. and Villadsen, K. (2015). Foucault, Maoism, Genealogy: The Influence of
Political Militancy in Michel Foucaul’'s Thought. New Political Science, 37, 91–117.
Langman, L. (2012). Cycles of Contention: The Rise and Fall of the Tea Party. Critical
Sociology, 38(4), 469–494.
Lessenich, S. (2011). Constructing the Socialized Self. Mobilization and Control in the
“Active Society”. In Ulrich Bröckling, Susanne Krasmann, and Thomas Lemke (Eds.),
Governmentality: Current Issues and Future Challenges. New York: Routledge.
Marks, J. (2000). Foucault, Franks, Gauls: “Il faut défendre la société”: The 1976 Lectures
at the Collège de France. Theory Culture Society, 17(5), 127–147.
Pasquino, P. (1993). Political Theory of War and Peace: Foucault and the History of
Modern Political Theory. Economy and Society, 22(1), 77–88.
Sawyer, S. W. (2015). Foucault and the State. The Tocqueville Review/La revue Tocqueville,
36(1), 135–164.
Shields, S. (2012). Opposing Neoliberalism? Poland’s Renewed Populism and Post-communist
Transition. Third World Quarterly, 33(2), 359–381.
Stavrakakis, Y. (2013). Dispatches from the Greek Lab: Metaphors, Strategies and Debt in
the European Crisis. Psychoanalysis, Culture & Society, 18(3), 313–324.
Stavrakakis, Y. (2015). Populism in Power: Syriza’s Challenge to Europe. Juncture, 21(4),
273–280.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Foucault: Decentering the State 59

Swyngedouw, E. (2014). Where is the Political? Insurgent Mobilisations and the Incipient
“Return of the Political”. Space and Polity, 18(2), 122–136.
Turner, B. S. and Villadsen, K. (2016). Counter Movements and Space: The Settlement,
Occupy Wall Street and the Tea Party. In H-J. Sander, K. Villadsen, and T. Wyller
(Eds.), The Spaces of Others – Heterotopic Spaces. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.
Valverde, M. (1996). “Despotism” and Ethical Liberal Governance. Economy and Society, 25(3),
357–372.
Veyne, P. (2010). Foucault: His Thought, His Character. Cambridge: Polity.
Villadsen, K. (2016). Michel Foucault and the Forces of Civil Society. Theory, Culture &
Society, 33(3), 3–26.
Wilson, A. R. and Burack, C. (2012). “Where Liberty Reigns and God is Supreme”: The
Christian Right and the Tea Party Movement. New Political Science, 34(2), 172–190.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

PART II

Reconstructing the Individual


via Social Policy
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

4
INVESTING IN SOCIAL SUBJECTS
The European Turn to Social Investment as the
Human Capital Theory of Social Citizenship

Bettina Leibetseder

Under the Belgian presidency of the Council of the European Union, the idea of
a social investment perspective was initially stipulated in 2001. Frank Vanden-
broucke (2002) presented the new concept as a way to promote “sustainable
social justice” in the field of social policy. The discursive establishment of a productive
notion was to guide member states to transform their welfare states.1
Social investment was also introduced to politically buoy the European social
model (Hemerijck 2002; Vandenbroucke 2002). This model, as Tony Judt identified
(2005, p. 748), “binds Europeans together” and creates a source of solidarity. It
has been disputed whether the model upholds strong systems of social protection
for all (Vaughan-Whitehead 2015).
Politically, social investment served the purposes of facilitating European inte-
gration and enabling new avenues of solidarity in an age of neoliberalism in
which market-based approaches to social inclusion are gaining favor. Nonetheless,
such a shift inevitably raises the question of whether social investment undermines
the inclusionary commitments of a social protection approach. In that respect,
social investment may alter policies that promote what theorists call social
citizenship, whereby the state compensates those who are left out or left behind
by market practices.
In the first decade of the twenty-first century, social investment faced three
challenges: First, three enlargement rounds2 led to a more heterogeneous landscape
of welfare states, creating new cleavages (Copeland 2012; Kvist 2004). Second,
European and national elections have favored conservative and far right wing and/
or Eurosceptic parties (Szcerbiak and Taggart 2008), in which the latter opposes the
European integration and the former is less supportive of social issues at the Eur-
opean level. Third, the economic crisis has threatened the sustainability of many
welfare states and national and European (social) cohesion (Streeck 2012).
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

64 Bettina Leibetseder

Under these less-than-favorable political and economic circumstances, the


European Commission (EC) has introduced the social investment idea. After
consultation with stakeholders, panels of experts, and political negotiations, the
EC issued its Social Investment Package in 2013 to promote human capital
investment as a new goal of social policy in addition to social protection and
economic stabilization (EC 2013a). The EU defines social investment as
“strengthening people’s current and future capacities” (2013a, p. 3).
Although proponents claim that refocusing on social investment assists in
maintaining social protection schemes and solidarity (Hemerijck 2013; Morel,
Palier, and Palme 2012a; Palier, Vandenbroucke, and Hemerijck 2011; Van
Kersbergen and Hemerijck 2012), its critics argue that such a focus cultivates
social inequality and dismantles social citizenship (Beckfield 2012; Bothfeld and
Rouault 2015; Cantillon 2011; Deeming and Smyth 2015; Jenson 2009; Pinte-
lon, Cantillon, Van den Bosch, and Whelan 2013; Saraceno 2015). Some voices
even state that social investment encourages neoliberal reforms (Barbier 2012).
Neoliberalism, on the one hand, promotes free markets, privatization, and
competition, leading to retrenchment policies and greater income inequality
(Harvey 2010; Peck 2013). Conversely, neoliberalism manifests an economically
driven rationality for individuals, societies, and states alike (Dean 2014b; Schram
2015). Wendy Brown (2015, p. 32) defines neoliberalism as “an order of nor-
mative reason that, when it becomes ascendant, takes shape as a governing
rationality extending a specific formulation of economic values, practices, and
metrics to every dimension of human life.”
Such economic government rationality may be proposed by social investment
thinking, which in turn can challenge current assumptions of social citizenship
and alter the goals of social policy. In welfare states, this social investment think-
ing can even introduce a rationality that re-forms the citizen subjects on the
grounds of potential rates of return on (social) investment.
In this chapter, I assert the changing rationality that portrays the social investment
subject in the EC’s documents on the Social Investment Package. However, the
documents do not define a singular subject. Moreover, each report problematizes
diverse aspects, proposes unique instruments, and deploys different normative reasons
and shapes, with the ultimate aim of achieving a distinct ideal subject.
The focus on multiple subjects rather than a single one emphasizes the
empirical variety which lacks in many studies portraying only one type (Brady
2014; Mckee 2009; Whitworth 2016). Furthermore, the plurality acknowledges
that social investment subjects cannot be set up in a societal vacuum because “the
residues of pre-existing social formations will never be entirely erased or rendered
inert” (Peck 2013, p. 154). Therefore, how economic belief systems for governing
human lives reshape conceptions of social citizenship for diverse groups is ripe for
substantial debate.
Because the social investment perspective spans numerous documents with
diverse target groups, I compare the varied expectations about the citizen that
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Investing in Social Subjects 65

needs to be shaped. First, I outline Michel Foucault’s ideas on human capital


theory and then connect these to social investment strategy and social citizenship.
I then frame the analytical grid that assists in delineating the proposed practices
and deconstructing the social investment subjects, describing ontology, ascetics,
deontology, and teleology. Next, I present the results of the analysis. My discussion
pinpoints the term’s ambivalent subject formations in relation to social citizenship,
and my conclusion recapitulates the changing subjectivity.

Economic Government Rationality and Social Investment


In the following section, I present Foucault’s much-discussed thinking on human
capital and how neoliberalism encourages changes in our conceptions of sub-
jectivity. I then connect Foucault’s analysis of neoliberalism to the theoretical
foundations of the social investment strategy. Then, I formulate the questions for
the empirical analysis.
For Wendy Brown (2015), Foucault provides an incisive analysis of human
capital theory, and I too rely on Foucault. His analysis centers on how neoliberalism
offers the recurring notion of individuals as subjects for investment by the state in
the name of furthering economic growth. For individuals to be seen as worthy of
economic investment, they need to be disciplined to behave consistently with the
ideals of an economic actor, that is, as “Homo oeconomicus.” This conception of
the citizen/subject as worthy of economic investment redefines the political
agenda to shift to the background the issues of citizenship rights implied by liberal
democratic notions of social justice. To focus on making citizens into economic
subjects worthy of investment modifies the established understandings of the liberal-
democratic social contract among citizens and between them and the state
because today human beings are not perceived as intrinsically valuable but are
instead constructed and re-construct themselves as human capital.
Wendy Brown follows the considerations of Michel Foucault (2008, p. 219),
who refers to human capital theory as distinctive “American neoliberalism,” most
notably theorized by Gary Becker’s writing (1962). Foucault (2008, p. 219) desig-
nates idiosyncratic characteristics to this theoretical school of thought, the
“extension of economic analysis into a previously unexplored domain” and “the
possibility of giving a strictly economic interpretation.”
In this interpretation, labor is seen as capital that has to be developed and that
requires investment – as with machinery – “to improve human capital” and “to
preserve and employ it for as long as possible” (Foucault 2008, p. 230). Further-
more, Foucault observed new policy aims for the state. By introducing human
capital thinking, it is observed that “the economic policies of all the developed
countries, but also their social policies, as well as their cultural and educational
policies, [are] being orientated in these terms” (Foucault 2008, p. 231).
This shift in policies of Foucault’s alters the strategic use of power at the micro
level. Individuals are perceived as “manageable” in a systematic, predictable
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

66 Bettina Leibetseder

manner with the right (dis)incentives. One of the merits that Foucault perceives is
the reduction of punitive actions, an aspect that is foregrounded by Gary Becker
(in Becker, Ewald, and Harcourt 2012, p. 17), who attributed human capital
theory to “freeing up individuals” and to self-development after reading Foucault’s
critique. Such an angle pertains to a “soft” libertarian approach that primarily
engages in enabling individuals to make choices within behavioral constraints
(Whitworth 2016).
From this perspective, human capital theory manifests a world that “is not at all
the ideal or project of an exhaustively disciplinary society in which the legal
network hemming in individuals is taken over and extended internally by, let us
say, a normative mechanism” (Foucault 2008, p. 259). In contrast to Foucault’s
assumptions in the late 1970s, neoliberalism is now seen as establishing a strong
state with rigid regulative structures (Peck 2010; Schmidt and Thatcher 2013).
In the field of welfare, the punishing ideas of Lawrence M. Mead (1986), in
whose perspective the right work ethic has to be taught to the unemployed poor
and unconditional benefits curtailed, led to the ascendance of workfare regimes
(Peck 2010). For Soss, Fording, and Schram (2011, p. 27), the coalescence of
neoliberalism and paternalism marks a distinctive regime of neoliberal paternalism:
“[T]hey define a strong state-led effort to bring discipline to the lives of the poor
so that they can become competent actors who recognize and act on their
interests as freely choosing agents on the market.”3
In addition to extending governing instruments, human capital theory also
redefines the addressees of policy interventions based on their earning power.
Interventions, such as James Heckman’s proposals (Carneiro and Heckman 2003;
Heckman 2000), must be evaluated, and those that are most effective and offer
the best rate of return must be put forward. Therefore, Heckman (2000) advocates
education policies as a means of developing human capital; reducing economic
inequality; and achieving, especially, in the case of early childhood interventions,
greater equal opportunity.
Taken to its extreme, the welfare state would be re-envisioned as a system of
return on investment. Reconstructing citizens as human capital may defy con-
temporary perceptions of merit or redistribution in social protection schemes. To
date, traditional approaches of reciprocity and quid pro quo have translated into
greater support in cases of social risk (Ewald 1991). That is to say, by pursuing
pure investment logic, the assessment would recast the individual’s value in
terms of the expected rate of return. Those categorized as unworthy – that is, less
“cost-effective” – of investment would obtain minimum income support,
whereas those in the “deserving” group would have access to the services that
they need to boost their productivity.
Distinct from the market logic, T. H. Marshall (1972, pp. 18–19) argues that
“it is a fundamental principle of the welfare state that the market value of an
individual cannot be the measure of his [or her] right to welfare.” Marshall
defined social rights as part of citizenship; these rights vary and can provide
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Investing in Social Subjects 67

benefits from “the right to a modicum of economic welfare and security to the
right to share to the fuIl in the social heritage and to live the life of a civilized
being according to the standards prevailing in the society” (Marshall 1950, p. 11).
Although they aim to build a broad middle class, the rights can mark individual
minimums or averages and also extend from unemployment and old age to health
services and education. They also oblige the individual to work, although their
intention is to restrain market forces (Jenson 2009).
In a contemporary social policy, the notion of social investment dates to
Anthony Giddens’ (1998) proposal of a “Third Way” for New Labour. In his
opinion, “[g]overnment has an essential role to play in investing in the human
resources and infrastructure needed to develop an entrepreneurial culture” (1998,
p. 99). Human capital investment should be strengthened, to create a “redistribu-
tion of possibilities” (1998, p. 101) and replace, if possible, income maintenance.4
Social investment does not advance redistribution; for Giddens, economic
inequality may be acceptable when it fosters economic and employment growth.
Conversely, Esping-Andersen highlights the need for redistribution and strong
welfare states that maintain security and social justice as “a precondition for an
effective social investment strategy” (2002, p. 5, original emphasis). However, he also
argues that social policy spending has to be identified as more than consumption
alone and refers to human capital theory. Although traditional conceptions classify
social expenditures as pure unproductive consumption, these can also “yield a
dividend because they (make) citizens more productive” (Esping-Andersen 2002,
p. 9). It may not be always easy to distinguish between these two traits (Nolan
2013). However, in his view, social investments provide individual and social
benefits over the life course, especially in education and child care. Next to
higher fertility rates and women’s labor market participation, Esping-Andersen
(2015) stresses social mobility and equal opportunity in referring to James
Heckman.
In contemporary ideas on social investment, the goals of “[raising] the human
capital stock” and introducing “policies serving to make efficient use of human
capital” (Hemerijck and Vandenbroucke 2012, p. 205) are embedded. From a life
course perspective (Kvist 2015), the social investment approach seeks to prepare
individuals, families, and societies to adapt to various transformations and “enable
the creation of more and better jobs” (Morel, Palier, and Palme 2012b, p. 354).
To stimulate the economy, full employment, and social cohesion simulta-
neously, the investment perspective wants to re-channel welfare state resources to
address skill demand and to provide social security and social services that support
a more flexible labor market and raise overall employment rates. It promotes
social inclusion, the creation of high-quality employment, and equal opportunity
through human capital investment (Morel et al. 2012a, p. 12).
Social investment policies do not abolish income provisions, which “must
remain an important function of the welfare state that works as a necessary
complement to activation and which cannot be substituted by activation” (Morel
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

68 Bettina Leibetseder

et al. 2012b, p. 359). Although income security over the life course should be
preserved, social investment seeks to uphold social rights in reference to their
productive impact or economic efficiency (Morel et al. 2012a, p. 5). The per-
spective may preach sacrifice now, with “the focus being more on the life cycle
and on the future than on equality of outcomes in the present” (Morel et al.
2012a, p. 11).
Because the diverse accounts vary on what social investment should achieve,
the perspective constitutes a “polysemic” vessel (Jenson 2010): It is reinterpreted,
crossing the boundaries of academic and political arenas. Beyond traveling across
epistemic communities, the common-sense meaning helps to adapt the concept
and ties together diverse actors in the political sphere, who may translate it in any
number of ways.
For some, social investment emerges as an answer to classic neoliberal concepts
by which fiscal austerity and price stability dominate the macroeconomic agenda
and the welfare state is portrayed as redundant (Jenson 2010; Mahon 2013; Morel
et al. 2012a). From that perspective, social investment combines traits of human
capital investment and social protection beyond income relief for the poor
(Mahon 2013).
Social rights and redistribution may be challenged by the potential of eco-
nomically driven reclassification of citizens and the strict enforcement of work.
Pertaining to the theoretical debate, two questions arise for the empirical part.
First, the analysis has to explore extending the economic reclassification of the
subjects, in greater detail, to the soft and disciplining governing modes put
forward to alter citizens’ behavior. Second, the inquiry has to consider the impact
on redistribution, that is, whether or not the subjects are perceived as intrinsically
valuable and endowed with social rights.
The transformations, as indicated by the Commission’s SIP, reframe the con-
ception of citizens and may severely alter subjectivity. In the next section, I
briefly sketch the content of the European Union’s social investment policy
documents, which indicate multiple routes of self-formation, and the analytical
steps. Then, I depict the empirical analysis in greater depth.

Advocated Subjects of Social Investment


For the European Commission, social investment should complete and moder-
nize contemporary welfare states. Instead of a short-term perspective, welfare
states should engage in reforms that “have lasting impacts by offering economic
and social returns over time, notably in terms of employment prospects or
labour incomes” (EC 2013a, p. 3). Additionally, not only should social policy
intervene ex post, but individuals should be prepared to face uncertainties in
their lives ex ante. In more detail, a “systematic” adaptation should ensure a
preventative approach to financing and spending and enforce a life course
perspective in social policy.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Investing in Social Subjects 69

The EC has published numerous documents as part of the SIP; two papers set
the general framework and address diverse target groups (EC 2013a, 2013e).
Other documents single out specific policy fields and relate to distinct groups,
such as children (EC 2013b), the homeless (EC 2013d), the unemployed (EC
2013f), and persons with long-term care needs (EC 2013h) and health issues (EC
2013g).5
Analyzing these policy documents, I use a discursive approach (Rapley 2007)
because official papers provide unique material on how they portray subjects,
define problems, and achieve solutions (Sapsford and Jupp 2006). Drawing on a
Foucauldian method, I investigate how the diverse subjects are understood.
Analytically, the focus for each group lies on four linchpins determined by
Mitchel Dean (1995), which allows for a systematic review of the proposed
government practices for each target group: ontology, ascetics, deontology, and
teleology. First, ontology defines the subject who is to be governed or has to
govern him-/herself. It covers any form of problematization that is to be (self-)
governed, typically related to the unemployed, the sick, or the poor in social
policy. The focus shifts from the subject’s situation toward the circumstances, the
behavioral assumptions and effects of policy interventions (Dean 1995). Ontology
can address the wrongful or suboptimal choices of “rational” subjects who retire
too early, are out of work for too long, or suffer from ill health. Conversely,
ontology can portray a deviant subject who does not want to live up to responsibilities
(Whitworth 2016).
Second, the aspect of ascetics denotes the various techniques the documents
recommend for governing subjects (or having them self-govern). It specifies the
types of instruments needed to achieve individual normalization, for example,
client contracts or benefits adjustments, soft governance, or discipline (Dean
1995). Therefore, ascetics can propose an optimum of (dis)incentives to steer
individual choices or it can opt for disciplinary actions and coercion (Whitworth
2016).
Third, deontology specifies the role or position of the subject within the process,
that is, why, in moral or normative terms, one ought to partake in the mode of
subjectification. In relation, the position raises questions concerning rules and
norms (Dean 1995); for example, one governs oneself to fulfill potential as a
productive citizen, to develop human capital, and to strive for entrepreneurial
capacities.
Finally, teleology characterizes the subject who should be shaped. It addresses
understanding what the practices aim for and what vision of the subject the
practices aim to produce (Dean 1995); in that respect, the produced subject is, for
example, employed and active (Whitworth 2016). The telos also influences
notions of an active or disciplinary society.
For each of the four criteria, I coded the documents, and thus, they encompass
a distinct range in regard to the subject; for each document, I first marked the
text passages and then exported them into a word processing program that
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

70 Bettina Leibetseder

categorized the content into one of the four criteria I discuss above. I then
compared the exported passages and scanned the original document a second
time to increase consistency.
Based on these four traits of subject formation, I present the diverse target
groups. I start with the general document that outlines the Commission’s overall
perspective on social policy, followed by the documents that address children,
health and long-term care, homelessness, and unemployment. I subsequently
compare these diverse aspects and then discuss the findings.

Investing in Society
The policy document Towards Social Investment for Growth portrays the EC’s
overall envisioned policies (2013a). The paper describes a common line of argument
for all target groups and specific routes for distinct problems, which are then
outlined in greater depth in subsequent papers.
Broadly, the EC addresses the subjects as being “at risk.” In this perception,
social policy has to “cover the challenges faced at various stages of people’s lives”
(EC 2013a, p. 6). Specifically, the paper consistently mentions groups such as
children in poverty, young people, the long-term unemployed, the working
poor, women, the disabled, and migrants as facing hardships and not having the
necessary resilience to conquer these risks; these groups are not to blame for their
plights. However, the lack or inadequacy of services and benefits plays a decisive
role in creating these situations of social distress. Moreover, the labor market
accelerates segmenting processes and further intensifies inequalities.
Ontology stresses that current social policy does not adequately address the risks
people face over the life course. Out of this problematization, social investment
means “adapting integrated services, cash benefits, and assistance to the critical
moments in the life of a person, and preventing hardship from materializing later”
(EC 2013a, p. 13). Therefore, ascetics promotes investment in human capital and
protection, and human capital purposes to enhance people’s skills and enable
them to overcome situations of distress on their own or at least to mitigate the
negative effects.
The techniques aim at establishing people’s self-governing capacity. In contrast,
welfare states are still expected to provide adequate and accessible benefits and
services, which marks the traditional governance technique of social protection.
However, transformations are supposed to pinpoint “critical junctions” (EC
2013a, p. 8) in the life cycles of all groups and provide support that increases life
chances and independent living and “provide[s] an exit-strategy, so they should in
principle be temporary” (EC 2013a, p. 3). To limit the time of receiving benefits,
any support is expected to be conditional, with mandatory job searching, partici-
pation in training programs, or education; the degree of coercion is not stipulated,
and the restrictions and conditions are not limited to the unemployed but also
affect children and those in need of health and care services.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Investing in Social Subjects 71

Decisive appears to be the long-term economic impact of social policies; the


subject is subjugated to the public code of productivity. The moral code for
individuals is to realize or make the most of their potential (EC 2013a, p. 14), to
actively participate to the best of their abilities, and to confront life’s risks (EC
2013a, p. 3). Nevertheless, the right “to live a life in dignity” (EC 2013a, p. 7) is
still declared, which preserves human beings as entitled to social rights.
The telos, as implied in this document, is one that furthers active subjects,
although the active role of the subject is not limited to employment but also
entails participation in society. Next to the “active” subject, the “dependent” one
still exists. Any form of dependency links the subject to a wide array of interventions
that raise his/her human capital or at least want to ensure the greatest independence
from the welfare state, creating a “temporary dependent subject.”

Investing in Children
The policy document on children (EC 2013b) deviates in its scope from all other
papers, which concentrate on responsibilities. Instead of conditionality, this
document understands children as right-bearing citizens and integrates principles
and requirements laid down in the UN Convention on the Rights of the Child.
Children are understood as being more at risk of poverty or social exclusion
(EC 2013b, p. 2) than the general population. The ontological claim is that
experiencing poverty in childhood reduces school achievement, increases health
risks, and, overall, lowers life chances. Parts of the causes of children’s risk of poverty
are rooted in their parents’ employment status. The document puts forward the
strong link between parents’ participation in the labor market and children’s
living conditions (EC 2013b, p. 5). Consequently, two aspects are problematized:
first, the lack of equal opportunity for children who live in poverty and, second,
the inadequate labor market participation of parents.
The policy document states that investing in children should break the cycle of
disadvantage (EC 2013b, p. 2). Ascetically, a broad range of instruments covers care,
education, health, and social services. The tools aim to provide universal high-quality
services and early investments for all children but to specifically support those with
greater needs or who come from disadvantaged backgrounds. Furthermore, partici-
patory approaches cultivate engagement in society and decision making in that policy
makers should “consult [children] on relevant policy planning” (EC 2013b, p. 9).
Next to children, parents become a key focus, albeit in a fairly divergent
manner; all parents, but especially single ones, should be engaged in the labor
market, and hence, taxes and benefits are proposed to be redesigned to increase
employment rates for parents. However, any purposed conditionality or curtailment
intends not to punish children; punitive actions are set to “the child’s best interest”
(EC 2013b, p. 5).
In the deontological dimension, children are safeguarded, but they themselves
do not have specific moral obligations. The norm addresses the state and society,
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

72 Bettina Leibetseder

which are expected to enable children to live up to their full potential and con-
tribute to their resilience (EC 2013b, p. 2). The public’s obligation is to foster
equal opportunity and protect, a trajectory that should limit the adverse effects of
families of origin. The grounds for justification suggest an instrumental and ethical
argument. Instrumentally, investing in children should maintain economic
growth in the short and long terms, boosting the productivity of parents today
and of children in the future. Ethically, individuals’ life chances should be
increased and equalized irrespective of social background.
For parents, good parenthood and supportive family environments are relin-
quished and economic responsibility strengthened. “[W]hilst fully acknowledging
the importance of supporting families as primary carers” (EC 2013b, p. 4), parents’
subjectification is to work to lift their children out of poverty.
The paper intends to promote social justice and protection (EC 2013b, p. 1),
but the practices propose to shape children as citizens and prospective workers.
The telos creates a society of equal opportunity and reframes children as right-
bearing subjects independent of their families of origin. The parents are delimited
as workers and earners, eliminating the vision of caretaking within families.

Investing in Health and Long-Term Care


The documents on elder care and health (EC 2013g, 2013h) employ identical
thoughts on all four comparative aspects. The problematization puts forth the
rising need in care and health services due to sociodemographic changes. Moreover,
the escalating costs of health care threaten universal coverage of services, but
informal care provision is portrayed as declining because of the increase in female
employment. Thus, it is paramount “to find ways to limit growth in public
spending … while avoiding a rapidly widening gap between the need … and the
supply available” (EC 2013h, p. 16).
The papers also address users and employees. For users, the inaccessibility of
quality services increases the potential of social exclusion (EC 2013g, p. 2), and
employees in health and long-term care services suffer from poor working con-
ditions. As a result, society faces economic impairment because of ill health in the
working-age population and informal care lowers productivity (EC 2013g, p. 5;
2013h, p. 8).
Various techniques are employed to govern the subject: Improved employment
conditions and formalization of care are expected to support female labor market
participation and job retention (EC 2013g, p. 16; 2013h, p. 13). To counteract the
rising costs, prevention is singled out as the gold standard. Healthy, physically and
mentally active lifestyles are proposed, in particular, for disadvantaged groups (EC
2013g, p. 17).
These processes, though, shift responsibilities toward the individual. Within
health, patient empowerment aims to enable patients to live independently;
within long-term care, strategies are planned to foster users’ coping capabilities
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Investing in Social Subjects 73

given that “becoming dependent is influenced by a person’s perception of their


ability to manage despite functional limitations” (EC 2013g, p. 11).
The deontology of the two papers is never lucidly expressed; the opaque moral
understanding that drives the reform is phrased cautiously. Individuals are obliged
to maintain healthy lifestyles, avoid any risky behavior, and act preventatively. In
case of need, they are expected to regain the utmost independence from health
and care services. Deontologically, individuals strive for healthy, independent, and
productive lives.
Ideally, policies aim “to boost economic growth by improving the health status
of the population and enabling people to remain active and in better health for
longer” (EC 2013h, p. 7). The telos again validates an active subject, which
implies an independent, self-managing one, with extended employability. The
stipulated values of such a policy conversion anticipate the improved quality of
life for individuals from all social backgrounds and the sustainability of universal
health and long-term care services. Overall, the papers plan for a healthy and
productive society.

Investing in Housing
The document on homelessness (EC 2013d, p. 12) sets out from another angle.
In the beginning, it accentuates the engrained support against homelessness at the
European level. Then, it initiates with the remark that “(h)omelessness is an
extreme manifestation of poverty and social exclusion which reduces a person’s
productive potential and is a waste of human capital” (EC 2013d, p. 5).
The problem description first underscores the destructiveness of homelessness,
which affects health and reduces life expectancy and employability. Second, any
lack of affordable housing and inadequate preventative services leads to more
costly interventions at a later point. Third, the typical stage-based service
approach for homeless persons, whereby clients must first visit shelters and only
later move on to more permanent residences, is criticized for prolonging the
experience of homelessness (EC 2013d, p. 12).
Structural constraints are repeatedly stressed in this document. Homelessness is
rooted in a lack of affordable housing, regulations that favor landlords and mortgage
lenders, inadequate housing benefits, and the current construction of services for
homeless people. In the specific mode of problematization, subjects’ behavior is
mentioned as one factor (EC 2013d, p. 23), but is addressed to a lesser degree.
The problematization addresses the social and economic costs of homelessness
and the lack of social and political rights for clients. The techne of government
foremost encourages restructuring housing markets and social services for the
homeless; in detail, measures to prevent homelessness, such as low-cost housing
and revised eviction policies, are put forward. For the homeless, a rapid transition
into permanent housing should shorten negative experiences in shelters, minimizing
the human and social costs of homelessness (EC 2013d, pp. 23–26).
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

74 Bettina Leibetseder

The process of normalizing homeless individuals furthermore intends voice and


choice. Policies are supposed to aim at “(e)mpowering homeless people through
their participation in service delivery and relevant policy-making” (EC 2013d,
p. 30).
The subjectification of the homeless does not mark the target group itself. As
in the case of the children’s document, this policy document shifts the normative
obligations toward policy makers and implementers, who are expected to per-
ceive the homeless as rights-bearing citizens who are anticipated to have the same
access to basic goods and services.
The subject who should be shaped is a social and political citizen who obtains
status equality with people who have housing. First, the services propose to sub-
jugate users no longer than necessary; they ideally transform the clients into
tenants and bring them instantly into the ranks of “ordinary” people. Second, the
statements stipulate an active, political homeless citizen in social service delivery
and in the political process.

Investing in Work
The document on active inclusion for people outside the labor market (EC
2013f) presents a sequel to a previous EC recommendation paper (EC 2013e). It
outlines at great length the advantages of the then proposed strategies.
In the realm of work, inactivity is seen as a problem; any non-participation in
the labor market, not merely unemployment, is portrayed as “dormant human
capital” (EC 2013f, p. 8). The problematization, however, gives a more nuanced
perspective on the subject and widens the field; it refers to barriers to employment
and to poverty in and out of work.
The cause for inactivity is traced back to the institutional design of the welfare
state, which prevents job entry. Institutionally, employment is hampered by lack
of work enforcement, mediocre employment services, and the exclusion of certain
groups from services. So-called financial disincentives may obstruct the “labour
friendliness” (EC 2013f, p. 25) of the benefit system. High benefit withdrawal
rates may erect traps of inactivity (EC 2013f, p. 24), unemployment, low wages
(EC 2013f, p. 25), dependency, and, overall, poverty (EC 2013f, p. 10).
Too-generous benefits are asserted to hinder employment, and “inadequacy,
low coverage, and non-take-up of minimum income” and “in-work-poverty”
(EC 2013f, p. 3) are argued to lead to poverty. What is the suggested techne to
incentivize work for so-called dormant human capital without jeopardizing
minimum income provisions? On the individual level, the right to a benefit is
proposed to be tied to “the willingness to work and a minimum commitment to
seeking a job” (EC 2013f, p. 35). Rights and responsibilities are to be laid out in
individualized contracts that should consider personal circumstances, and these
contracts are supposed to follow a staircase approach that intensifies social services
over the duration of unemployment (EC 2013f, p. 35). Such agreements are
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Investing in Social Subjects 75

understood to empower clients, but they may provide reasons for imposing
sanction policies as well.
Profiling techniques are intended to advance effectiveness. For example, statics
is proposed to assist with the selection of the program, which is “expected to
have the largest effect in reducing the length of periods of unemployment for a
particular individual with given personal characteristics” (EC 2013f, p. 19). The
document even excludes some groups from services: “For instance, extensive
educational programmes could be made available only to young people who
are unemployed and do not have formal education” (EC 2013f, p. 13). Despite
the paper’s acknowledgement that longer training shows better outcomes in the
medium run (EC 2013f, p. 12), budgetary concerns limit the instruments, aiming to
“shorten the time a person needs to find a job, while cutting the cost of activation”
(EC 2013f, p. 13).
To ensure access to activating and enabling services, the document proposes
“one-stop shops” that merge job centers and social assistance offices. Less stig-
matizing, these single entry points are expected to boost labor market attachment,
“address the need of those least likely to get a job” (EC 2013f, p. 4), and ease the
access to a minimum income. High take-up rates of benefits are anticipated to
lower the poverty rate.
The policy paper proposes a set of instruments so that individuals may obtain a
minimum income without eroding incentives to take up work (EC 2013f, p. 37).
In addition to job search and training, the benefit levels are planned to adapt to
individual and household needs while avoiding traps of any kind. To circumvent
the inactivity, unemployment, low-wage, dependency, and poverty traps, the
benefit and tax systems are envisioned to contribute to “mak[ing] work pay” (EC
2013f, p. 8).
To incentivize work, any benefit should be set at the 40% median income, and
the minimum wages should be tied to the 60% median income, with both poverty
thresholds grounded in the European context; the gap between these two limits
intends to ensure that people choose work over benefits. Taking these suggestions,
per year, in Germany, the former group would obtain 7,900 Euro in benefits and
11,900 in low-wage work; in the United Kingdom, the groups would receive
8,200 and 12,400 Euro; in Sweden, 10,800 and 16,300 Euro; and in Greece,
3,100 and 4,600 Euro, all respectively.6
“Providing adequate, well-designed income support for those who need it,
while helping them back into jobs” (EC 2013f, p. 4) recapitulates the ascetics of
the social investment strategy. The deontology is not addressed in the document; the
moral argument for partaking in activation and in employment appears to be
taken for granted.
The formed subject ought to work, whenever and as quickly as possible. The
telos, nevertheless, does not inhibit provision and take-up of benefits and frames
out-of-work citizens as entitled to social support. In this ideal scheme, the sug-
gestions lead to two sets of subjects. First, the rational unemployed subjects
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

76 Bettina Leibetseder

should govern themselves and seek employment because the optimal design of
benefits incentivizes work over inactivity. Second, irrational subjects who do not
conduct themselves according to the system’s logic are bound to reposition
themselves as rational and self-governing subjects over time as services and
conditionality transform their behavior into either disadvantage or discipline.

Investment Subjects
Comparing these six documents (or five groups), the notion of an active, pro-
ductive subject flourishes (see Table 4.1). Not only do the unemployed face an

TABLE 4.1 Social Investment Subjects

Ontology Ascetics Deontology Teleology

Society At risk Benefits and services Make most of Active, life-


at critical moments their potential, risk-managing
right to live with subject,
dignity temporarily
dependent
subject
Children Intergenerational Equal opportunity State’s moral Children as
transmission of for children, obligation to citizens and
poverty, future employment for enable children’s upcoming
lack of human parents potential and working subjects
capital resilience, under the wings
parents’ norm to of state services,
earn to lift parents as
children out of working subjects
poverty
Health and Limited access to Benefits and services Uphold Healthy,
Long-Term health and that prolong labor independence independent,
Care long-term care market participation and health employable
services and independence subject
from services
Housing Manifestation of Restructuring State’s obligation Social and
poverty and housing markets, to create citizen political citizen
social exclusion social services, subject
voices, and choices
Work Dormant human Avoiding any – Working,
capital trap conditionality rational
(incentivized)
subject or
irrational
(disadvantaged,
disciplined)
subject
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Investing in Social Subjects 77

activation regime, but also the young and old, sick and healthy are targeted. The
proliferation of human capital thinking, however, problematizes, alters govern-
mental techniques, and redefines norms away from a singular subject. Although
social investment challenges social citizenship, it does not abolish social rights.
Children and the homeless have not been morally obliged to govern themselves
toward activity. Both are first and foremost right-bearing citizens, and it is the state’s
obligation to enact these subjects; all other subjects are morally obliged to make the
most of their potential, although they are still entitled to live lives with dignity.
The documents themselves do not clarify how much paternalism the member
states should establish. The paper on the unemployed distinguishes between an
optimized route for rational subjects and a disciplinary regime for non-complying
ones. In contrast, the recommendations for children stoop lower to sanctioning
the parents and put the child’s well-being and development first.
The degrees of coercion make explicit that the policy papers do not present a
uniform thinking. Another example depicts empowerment: Barbara Cruikshank
(1994) understands empowerment as an instrument of subjection, a way to work
upon the citizen. In all four cases, empowerment aims at clients’ independence
and self-governing, but the extent and direction vary. For the frail, empowerment
means regaining self-sufficiency so that they can manage their daily lives with less
or no help from services (EC 2013h, p. 17). Patient empowerment for people
with chronic illness signifies greater self-management of the condition in con-
sultation with health staff (EC 2013g, p. 13). The elderly and sick are depicted as
gaining the means to shape their everyday lives. In the case of self-management, a
new form of moral obligation that introduces “permanent activeness” may be
introduced (Fersch 2015).
The contracts with the job centers should empower the unemployed, with
rights and responsibilities defined on an individual basis (EC 2013f). In practice,
the unemployed should alter their behavior as outlined in the contracts, which
are designed to be more constraining and standardized than individualized and
empowering (Minas, Wright, and van Berkel 2012; van Berkel and Valkenburg
2007). In contrast, the homeless should be empowered politically (EC 2013d) and
are expected to obtain political strength.
Social investment thinking, as displayed in the documents, clearly aspires to
improve human capital and to employ it to the fullest. In doing so, the thinking
in the documents also redefines the worthiness of citizens according to rates of
return, which is exemplified in comparing the papers on children and the
unemployed. Evidently enunciated is the human capital development approach
for children and the young unemployed who have no formal education; here, the
expected individual and societal gains from longer and costly trainings are assessed
to be greater than those for the older or already educated workforce. Yet despite
this economic argument, both documents stress that policies are expected to
target the worst off as well, eliminating pre-existing inequalities and pushing for
equal opportunities.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

78 Bettina Leibetseder

Social investment’s potential to reposition social inclusion and equality, as


indicated by Jenson (2013) and Mahon (2013), is curtailed severely, at least in the
paper on work. On the one hand, the disciplinary approach promotes sanctions
and does not recapitulate the right to live in dignity. On the other hand, the soft-
governance approach optimizes the benefits levels to incentivize reentry and thus
proposes a rather low benefit.
Taking the optimization by labor market participation and emphasizing the
expected rates of return, these approaches may contradict the recommendation to
assist disadvantaged groups at a greater rate. Instead of social inclusion, such advice
may reinforce exclusionary tendencies and create a second tier of beneficiaries
who can only access limited benefits and mediocre services.
Social investment concentrates on equal opportunities for children, which in
the future should ensure both social justice and competition. The question
remains whether equal opportunity alone is decisive given that the policy docu-
ments highlight certain minimum income provisions that address poverty as well.
A pure neoliberal policy would resist any further interference in redistribution
(Plant 2010), whereas the social investment perspective goes beyond that: It
upholds social citizenship and is aware that merely equal opportunity may ruthlessly
mutilate social and democratic rights.
To facilitate enablement and redistribution concurrently, services hold a pivotal
position in the SIP. Many types of services may stimulate job creation and then
provide good job opportunities and raise overall productivity, especially as
women’s employment flourishes. Separate from the upswing in female labor
market participation, the services contribute to caring for children and the elderly
irrespective of social background.
Though the redistributive capacity of benefits and services may be cur-
tailed, using the example of merging social assistance and unemployment
services to a one-stop shop, the higher take-up and improved services for
social assistance recipients may be offset by modest support and less generous
compensation for unemployment beneficiaries. Correspondingly, flat-rate
universal or, more likely for the unemployed, targeted provisions may replace
other benefits and services that previously upheld an element of status security
and valued merit.
Not only might merit be replaced completely in the long run, but universal
services and benefits may also be perpetually examined to “increase the effec-
tiveness and efficiency of social policies” (EC 2013a, p. 3). Although this eco-
nomic belief system is deemed necessary to uphold social inclusion, it may
ultimately value social investment more than social rights. Because of the lack of
explicitly stated social rights in the documents, the challenges of the social
investment approach for social citizenship may be best analyzed in consideration
of the implementation in the European Union member states. Nevertheless, the
two recommended levels of income between those in and out of work might
indicate the proposed way forward.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Investing in Social Subjects 79

Conclusion
Theoretically, the social investment perspective may perpetuate social citizenship
by concomitantly endorsing a human capital approach and redistributive aims,
which caters to all societal groups and extends beyond employability. However,
social investment may also advance neoliberal policies; these policies may limit
redistribution to the poor and advance a human capital approach that values its
positive impact on labor market participation and economic growth.
The European Commission’s SIP backs an ambivalent adaptation of the social
investment perspective. It moves human capital theory into mainstream European
social policy and labels it more temptingly as “social investment,” and its pivotal
element is eliminating all kinds of traps so that people will incentivize work over
benefits. Additionally, education policies are expected to align children for early
entry into a competitive workforce but also foster equal opportunity. Moreover,
preventative and enabling policies are intended to further the independence and
employability of the general population, especially the elderly. Clearly, these
subjects should raise a dividend and lead more productive lives.
Expanding human capital theory, children, the elderly, and the general popula-
tion are addressed as social investment subjects, but the documents do not portray a
singular version: subjects are active and life-risk managing versus temporarily
dependent, citizens and future workers, working parents, healthy, independent,
and employable, social and political, rational, disciplined and disadvantaged.
For most subjects, soft-governing mechanisms prevail, although the unemployed
may face a disciplining, paternalistic approach; still, social services should provide
training for the disadvantaged unemployed. Despite all that, the policy papers
accentuate universal services and social rights, particularly for children and the
homeless. Such services may deliver indispensable resources for individuals to
participate in society.
Thus, the SIP not only carries forward a neoliberal agenda but still supports
and protects subjects accordingly. Ultimately, though, this notion of support may
depend on budgetary decisions more than on a belief that human beings are
intrinsically valuable, which may hamper a genuine European social model and
provide scarce, minimal social protection.

Notes
1 Owing to the multi-tier system, the European Union often introduces reform agendas
with the open method of coordination. Policy coordination should “softly” make
policy at the national level with comparisons, guidelines, benchmarks, expertise, and the
involvement of relevant stakeholders (Wallace and Reh 2015).
2 In 2004, Czech Republic, Estonia, Cyprus, Latvia, Lithuania, Hungary, Malta, Poland,
Slovakia, and Slovenia were added; in 2007, Bulgaria and Romania; and in 2013,
Croatia.
3 Moreover, whereas the shift is state led, private-sector institutions themselves apply
market logic. Private and public actors combine and competition rules are introduced,
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

80 Bettina Leibetseder

which fosters the need for permanent innovation, and then management and surveillance
tools are strengthened (Schram, Fording, and Soss 2011; Soss et al. 2011). .
4 Such a productivist notion of social policy has a long tradition in social science, as
Smyth and Deeming (2016) stress with the ideas of Myrdal in the 1930s and Tawney in
the 1960s.
5 Three policy documents were excluded from the analysis: One because it addresses legal
issues for social services (EC 2013c); another one outlines proceedings of the European
social funds (EC 2013i); and one only describes problematizations, which are then
repeated in all other documents, but it does not give notes on the other three aspects
(EC 2013e).
6 I made these calculations using EU-Survey on Income and Living Conditions, 2014 data.

References
Barbier, J.-C. (2012). Comment on Anton Hemerijck/2. Social Investment, a Problematic
Concept with an Ambiguous Past. Sociologica, 1, 1–11.
Becker, G. S. (1962). Investment in Human Capital: A Theoretical Analysis. Journal of
Political Economy, 70(S5), 9–49. doi: doi:10.1086/258724
Becker, G. S., Ewald, F., and Harcourt, B. E. (2012). Becker on Ewald on Foucault on Becker.
American Neoliberalism and Michel Foucault’s 1979 “Birth of Biopolitics” Lectures. Coase-Sandor
Institute for Law & Economics Working Paper (614).
Beckfield, J. (2012). Comment on Anton Hemerijck/3. More Europe, Not Less: Rever-
sing the Long, Slow Decline of the European Social Model. Sociologica, 1. doi:
doi:10.2383/36890
Bothfeld, S., and Rouault, S. (2015). Families Facing the Crisis: Is Social Investment a
Sustainable Social Policy Strategy? Social Politics: International Studies in Gender, State &
Society, 22(1), 60–85. doi: doi:10.1093/sp/jxu014
Brady, M. (2014). Ethnographies of Neoliberal Governmentalities: From the Neoliberal
Apparatus to Neoliberalism and Governmental Assemblages. Foucault Studies, 18, 11–33.
Brown, W. (2015). Undoing the Demos. Neoliberalism’s Stealth Revolution. New York: Zone
Books.
Cantillon, B. (2011). The Paradox of the Social Investment State: Growth, Employment
and Poverty in the Lisbon Era. Journal of European Social Policy, 21(5), 432–449. doi:
doi:10.1177/0958928711418856
Carneiro, P. M., and Heckman, J. J. (2003). Human Capital Policy. IZA. Discussion Paper (821).
Copeland, P. (2012). EU Enlargement, the Clash of Capitalisms and the European Social
Model. Comparative European Politics, 10(4), 476–504.
Cruikshank, B. (1994). The Will to Empower. Technologies of Citizenship and the War
on Poverty. Socialist Review, 23(4), 29–55.
Dean, M. (1995). Governing the Unemployed Self in an Active Society. Economy and
Society, 24(4), 559–583.
Dean, M. (2014a). Michel Foucault’s “Apology” for Neoliberalism. Journal of Political
Power, 7(3), 433–442. doi: doi:10.1080/2158379X.2014.967002
Dean, M. (2014b). Rethinking Neoliberalism. Journal of Sociology, 50(2), 150–163.
Deeming, C., and Smyth, P. (2015). Social Investment after Neoliberalism: Policy Paradigms
and Political Platforms. Journal of Social Policy, 44(2), 297–318.
Esping-Andersen, G. (2002). Towards the Good Society, Once Again? In G. Esping-
Andersen, D. Gallie, A. Hemerijck, and J. Myles (Eds.), Why We Need a New Welfare
State (pp. 1–25). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Investing in Social Subjects 81

Esping-Andersen, G. (2015). Welfare Regimes and Social Stratification. Journal of European


Social Policy, 25(1), 124–134. doi: doi:10.1177/0958928714556976
EC (2013a). Communication from the Commssion to the European Parliament, the Council, the
European Economic and Social Committee and the Committee of Regions: Towards
Social Investment for Growth and Cohesion – Including Implementing the European Social Fund
2014–2020. Brussels.
EC (2013b). Investing in Children: Breaking the Cycle of Disadvantage. Brussels.
EC (2013c). Social Investment Package Commission Staff Working Document: 3rd Biennal Report
on Social Services of General Interest. Brussels.
EC (2013d). Social Investment Package Commission Staff Working Document: Confronting
Homelessness in the European Union. Brussels.
EC (2013e). Social Investment Package Commission Staff Working Document: Evidence on
Demographic and Social Trends. Social Policies’ Contribution to Inclusion, Employment and the
Economy. Brussels.
EC (2013f). Social Investment Package Commission Staff Working Document: Follow-up on the
Implementation by the Member States of the 2008 European Commission Recommendation on
Active Inclusion of People Excluded from the Labour Market – Towards a Social Investment
Approach. Brussels.
EC (2013g). Social Investment Package Commission Staff Working Document: Investing in Health.
Brussels.
EC (2013h). Social Investment Package Commission Staff Working Document: Long-term Care in
Ageing Societies – Challenges and Policy Options. Brussels.
EC (2013i). Social Investment Package Commission Staff Working Document: Social Investment
through the European Social Fund. Brussels.
Ewald, F. (1991). Insurance and Risk. In G. Burchell, C. Gordon, and P. Miller (Eds.),
The Foucault Effect. Studies in Governmentality with Two Lectures By and an Interview With
Michel Foucault (pp. 197–210). Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Fersch, B. (2015). Expectations Towards Home Care Re-ablement in Danish Munici-
palities. International Journal of Sociology and Social Policy, 35(3/4), 126–140. doi:
doi:10.1108/IJSSP-06-2014-0045
Foucault, M. (2008). Birth of Biopolitics. Lectures at the College de France 1978–79. Basing-
stoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Giddens, A. (1998). The Third Way: The Renewal of Social Democracy. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Harvey, D. (2010). A Brief History of Neoliberalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Heckman, J. J. (2000). Policies to Foster Human Capital. Research in Economics, 54(1), 3–56.
Hemerijck, A. (2002). The Self-Transformation of the European Social Model(s). In G.
Esping-Andersen, D. Gallie, A. Hemerijck, and J. Myles (Eds.), Why We Need a New
Welfare State (pp. 174–213). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hemerijck, A. (2013). Changing Welfare States, 1st edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hemerijck, A., and Vandenbroucke, F. (2012). Social Investment and the Euro Crisis: The
Necessity of a Unifying Social Policy Concept. Intereconomics/Review of European Economic
Policy, 47(4), 200–206. doi: http://link.springer.com/journal/volumesAndIssues/10272
Jenson, J. (2009). Redesigning Citizenship Regimes after Neoliberalism. Moving Towards
Social Investment. In N. Morel, B. Palier, and J. Palme (Eds.), What Future for Social
Investment? Research Report (pp. 27–44). Stockholm: Institute for Futures Studies.
Jenson, J. (2010). Diffusing Ideas for After Neoliberalism: The Social Investment Perspec-
tive in Europe and Latin America. Global Social Policy, 10(1), 59–84. doi: doi:10.1177/
1468018109354813
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

82 Bettina Leibetseder

Jenson, J. (2013). Changing Perspectives on Social Citzenship: A Cross-time Comparison.


In A. Evers and A.-M. Guillemard (Eds.), Social Policy and Citizenship. The Changing
Landscape (pp. 57–79). New York: Oxford University Press.
Judt, T. (2005). Postwar – A History of Europe Since 1945. New York: The Penguin Press.
Kvist, J. (2004). Does EU Enlargement Start a Race to the Bottom? Strategic Interaction
among EU Member States in Social Policy. Journal of European Social Policy, 14(3), 301–318.
doi: doi:10.1177/0958928704044625
Kvist, J. (2015). A Framework for Social Investment Strategies: Integrating Generational,
Life Course and Gender Perspectives in the EU Social Investment Strategy. Comparative
European Politics, 13(1), 131–149. doi: doi:10.1057/cep.2014.45
Mahon, R. (2013). Social Investment According to the OECD/DELSA: A Discourse in
Making. Global Policy Volume, 2, 150–159.
Marshall, T. H. (1950). Citizenship and Social Class. And other Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Marshall, T. H. (1972). Value Problems of Welfare-Capitalism. Journal of Social Policy, 1(1),
15–32. doi: doi:10.1017/S0047279400002166
Mckee, K. (2009). Post-Foucauldian Governmentality: What Does it Offer Critical Social
Policy Analysis? Critical Social Policy, 29(3), 465–486. doi: doi:10.1177/
0261018309105180
Mead, L. M. (1986). Beyond Entitlement: The Social Obligations of Citizenship. New York:
The Free Press.
Minas, R., Wright, S., and van Berkel, R. (2012). Decentralization and Centralization:
Governing the Activation of Social Assistance Recipients in Europe. International Journal
of Sociology and Social Policy, 32(5/6), 286–298.
Morel, N., Palier, B., and Palme, J. (2012a). Beyond the Welfare State as We Knew It? In
N. Morel, B. Palier, and J. Palme (Eds.), Towards a Social Investment Welfare State?: Ideas,
Policies and Challenges (pp. 1–31). Bristol: Policy Press.
Morel, N., Palier, B., and Palme, J. (2012b). Social Investment: A Paradigm in Search of a
New Economic Model and Political Mobilisation. In N. Morel, B. Palier, and J. Palme
(Eds.), Towards a Social Investment Welfare State?: Ideas, Policies and Challenges (pp. 353–376).
Bristol: Policy Press.
Nolan, B. (2013). What Use is ‘Social Investment’? Journal of European Social Policy, 23(5),
459–468. doi: doi:10.1177/0958928713499177
Palier, B., Vandenbroucke, F., and Hemerijck, A. (2011). The EU Needs a Social Investment
Pact. OSE Paper Series. Opinion paper (May 5, 2011).
Peck, J. (2010). Construction of Neoliberal Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Peck, J. (2013). Explaining (with) Neoliberalism. Territory, Politics, Governance, 1(2), 132–157.
doi: doi:10.1080/21622671.2013.785365
Pintelon, O., Cantillon, B., Van den Bosch, K., and Whelan, C. T. (2013). The Social
Stratification of Social Risks: The Relevance of Class for Social Investment Strategies.
Journal of European Social Policy, 23(1), 52–67. doi: doi:10.1177/0958928712463156
Plant, R. (2010). The Neo-liberal State. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Rapley, T. (2007). Doing Conversation, Discourse and Document Analysis. London: Sage.
Sapsford, R., and Jupp, V. (2006). Data Collection and Analysis (2nd edn.). London:
Sage.
Saraceno, C. (2015). A Critical Look to the Social Investment Approach from a Gender
Perspective. Social Politics: International Studies in Gender, State & Society, 22(2), 257–269.
doi: doi:10.1093/sp/jxv008
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Investing in Social Subjects 83

Schmidt, V. A., and Thatcher, M. (2013). Theorizing Ideational Continuity: The Resilience of
Neo-liberal Ideas in Europe. In V. A. Schmidt and M. Thatcher (Eds.), Resilient Liberalism in
Europe’s Political Economy (pp. 1–52). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Schram, S. (2015). The Return of Ordinary Capitalism. Neoliberalism, Precarity, Occupy.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Schram, S., Fording, R. C., and Soss, J. (2011). Neoliberal Paternalism: Race and the New
Poverty Governance. In M.-K. Jung, E. Bonilla-Silva, and J. H. Costa Vargas (Eds.),
State of White Supremacy. Racism, Governance, and the U.S. (pp. 130–159). Palo Alto, CA:
Stanford University Press.
Smyth, P., and Deeming, C. (2016). The “Social Investment Perspective” in Social Policy:
A Longue Durée Perspective. Social Policy & Administration, 50(6), 673–690. doi:
doi:10.1111/spol.12255
Soss, J., Fording, R. C., and Schram, S. (2011). Disciplining the Poor: Neoliberal Paternalism
and the Persistent Power of Race. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Streeck, W. (2012). Gekaufte Zeit. Die vertagte Krise des demokratischen Kapitalismus. Berlin:
Suhrkamp.
Szcerbiak, A., and Taggart, P. (Eds.) (2008). Opposing Europe? The Comparative Party Politics
of Euroscepticism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
van Berkel, R., and Valkenburg, B. (Eds.) (2007). Making it Personal: Individualising Activation
Services in the EU. Bristol: Policy.
Van Kersbergen, K., and Hemerijck, A. (2012). Two Decades of Change in Europe: The
Emergence of the Social Investment State. Journal of Social Policy, 41(3), 475–492.
Vandenbroucke, F. (2002). Foreword: Sustainable Social Justice and “Open Co-ordination”
in Europe. In G. Esping-Andersen, D. Gallie, A. Hemerijck, and J. Myles (Eds.), Why We
Need a New Welfare State (pp. xiii–xxiv). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Vaughan-Whitehead, D. (2015). The European Social Model in Times of Crisis: An
Overview. In D. Vaughan-Whitehead (Ed.), The European Social Model in Crisis: Is
Europe Losing Its Soul? (pp. 1–65). Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing.
Wallace, H., and Reh, C. (2015). An Institutional Anatomy and Five Policy Modes. In H.
Wallace, M. A. Pollack, and A. R. Young (Eds.), Policy-Making in the European Union
(7th edn., pp. 72–114). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Whitworth, A. (2016). Neoliberal Paternalism and Paradoxical Subjects: Confusion and
Contradiction in UK Activation Policy. Critical Social Policy, 36(3), 412–431. doi:
doi:10.1177/0261018315624442
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

5
ONTOLOGIES OF POVERTY IN RUSSIA
AND DUPLICITIES OF
NEOLIBERALISM1

Marianna Pavlovskaya

There is no money for your pensions now. But you will somehow hang on. Best
wishes for high spirits and health to everyone!
Prime Minister Dmitry Medvedev to retired women of Crimea in May 2016

Thinking about poverty has particular significance for Russia as a post-Soviet


society. This is because the majority of the population was born during the Soviet
period when poverty did not exist and was not recognized as such in the form
that it is today. The notion of poverty was not unfamiliar to Soviet society but it
was separated from Soviet time and space: it existed in the past, under the Tsarist
regime, or outside of the Soviet Union, in the capitalist West. Relegating the
possibility of poverty to the past or to another location provided the Soviet
government with a way to deny its existence in any form within the Soviet
Union. This denial had both material and ideological foundations. On the one
hand, the Soviet state guaranteed minimal levels of social security and consump-
tion. On the other hand, the Soviet ideology of Marxism-Leninism firmly placed
poverty within non-socialist societies. Thus, even the theoretical possibility of
poverty under socialism was eliminated while it was considered common under
capitalism.
Consequently, when post-Soviet Russia radically reset its compass from socialism
to capitalism in 1991, poverty was no longer seen as a proximate impossibility.
Instead, its presence in Russia became accepted as a natural part of and an unavoid-
able price to pay for the advantages of a market economy. In contrast to the
Soviet past, when differences in material wealth were relatively limited, the post-
Soviet transformation produced a society with dramatic inequalities and a large
impoverished population. Russia, however, entirely lacking experience with
capitalism, was unprepared to address poverty at a societal level. Consequently,
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Ontologies of Poverty in Russia 85

Russian social scientists and the government had to develop from scratch metrics
and policies to manage this new population of the poor.
This chapter examines the ways in which Russia has used the new interna-
tional metrics of poverty designed by the ILO (International Labor Organization)
since it first introduced capitalism in 1991. My analysis shows that these metrics
measure the poor in a way that normalizes poverty. In particular, I show how the
metrics both affirm the presence of poverty and, at the same time, deny its actual
scope and extent. That is, they make poverty visible within society but also make
it appear limited and manageable despite its pervasiveness. Poverty in Russia does
not, however, appear exceptional when compared to the rest of the world;
indeed, it is within the “norm” by Western industrial standards. Yet, when
compared to the recent Soviet past, the very existence of poverty and its current
scale looks like a social catastrophe. The Russian government, however, can
avoid comparisons to the Soviet period because the ILO metrics have only been
applied since 1991. Measuring and understanding poverty (and non-poverty)
in Russia, then, is only possible within and relative to the post-Soviet period.
The Russian government first developed new poverty-related policies during
the post-Soviet period which coincided with the global turn toward neoliberal-
ism. Because of this timing, Russia adopted distinctly neoliberal versions of
Western social policies which foreground the role of markets and social discipline
to alleviate poverty. Had Russia moved towards capitalism in the middle of the
twentieth century, for example, it may have adopted more welfare-oriented
approaches to address poverty. Given the neoliberal climate of the late twentieth
century, Russia, with unprecedented speed, went from full welfare provision
under the Soviet system to a state of extreme wealth polarization, pervasive poverty,
and authoritarian governance, a state which also increasingly characterizes other
Western nations particularly the United States.
The Russian government, however, has a complex relationship with neoliberalism.
It clearly adopts neoliberal market-oriented and disciplinary logics yet uses the term
rhetorically to negatively characterize Western “liberal” values and policies
including those of the Obama administration, to which it counterpoises tradi-
tional Russian Orthodox values, a uniquely Russian path to development, and its
pride in a strong nationalistic state. Perhaps unsurprisingly, Putin’s government
was quick to celebrate the new Trump administration, trusting it will lead to a
reduction in US opposition to Russian geopolitical ambitions and the removal of
international sanctions against Russia. Neoliberal leaders easily find common
ground because they share ideologies of markets and strong state control.
The Russian people have, however, responded to economic deprivation,
poverty, and disciplinary policies as creatively as they responded to scarcity and
authoritarian control during the Soviet period. Under the surface of the formal
capitalist economy that generates vast inequalities and poverty, a whole realm of
economic practices exists which are driven by ethics of sharing, mutual support,
and collective survival, and which work to support livelihoods, people, and places
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

86 Marianna Pavlovskaya

on a daily basis. It is then worth seeing Russia as a realm of multiple economies in


transformation that can become, even under the most authoritarian and/or neo-
liberal rule, a site of economic possibility and solidarity (Roelvink et al. 2015;
Pavlovskaya 2004, 2013, 2015). While discussion of these practices is beyond the
scope of this essay, it is important to recognize their role in alleviating the poverty
produced by neoliberal capitalism and meager welfare support.
In the rest of the chapter I will first outline the importance of studying Russia
as a laboratory for the production of poverty under neoliberal capitalism. I will
then discuss the Soviet welfare system and its transformation since the 1990s and
the introduction of capitalism. I will then examine the extent of Russian poverty
visible in statistics and will show how the new metrics both normalize and hide
structural poverty. Underneath these internationally sanctioned metrics, a set of
meaninglessly related indicators work to misrepresent the level of deprivation and
therefore render Russian social policy, informed by these statistics, ineffectual, as
the case of unemployment benefits will demonstrate. In the conclusion, I reflect
on the implications of the Russian experience with poverty for other societies
similarly subject to neoliberalizing regimes and on the possibility of progressive
post-capitalist politics even under such conditions.

Russia as a Laboratory of Poverty for the Neoliberal Age


In his widely discussed book Capital in the Twenty-First Century, Thomas Piketty
only briefly mentions Russia despite his interest in the trajectory of capitalism and
the inequalities it produces. This is perhaps surprising given that Russia, like no
other country in the world, implemented, virtually overnight, a radical transfor-
mation from state socialism to capitalism, becoming the largest single territory of
capital accumulation once its public assets were privatized. Piketty is not alone in
paying little attention to this part of the world: liberal and critical researchers alike
turn their gaze away from Russia. For them, either Russia is an oligarchic and
authoritarian deviation from capitalism and therefore can tell us little about
capitalism per se or studying Russia is theoretically and politically uncomfortable
given its history of abandoning socialism. Most research on poverty focuses on
the, so called, First and Third worlds despite the establishment a quarter of a
century ago of an enormous “territory of poverty” (Roy and Crane 2015) in
Russia. As a result, the impoverished lives of millions of people do not register
within global assessments of poverty; they simply do not exist on the world map.
While some of the harshest outcomes of neoliberal trajectories are made invisible
when we ignore the case of Russia, so too is the degree to which such trajectories
and outcomes are not “natural” but are of our making. Prior to 1991, Soviet
Russia was a society where there was no legal provision for either private property
or unemployment for most of the twentieth century. As a result, capitalism
needed to be “built” out of whole cloth by state policies that closely followed the
prescriptions of the best neoliberal minds that the IMF could find (Offe 1994;
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Ontologies of Poverty in Russia 87

Sachs 1995; Aslund 2001). In this sense, it was “state of the art” neoliberalism, a
constructed social reality with nothing natural about it. Therefore, Russian genea-
logies of capitalism and poverty can be framed in the context of an explicit policy
effort which can open new ways of thinking about social change. In particular,
development, within Russia and beyond, might best be rethought as not following
a predetermined and inevitable path toward “the end of history” (Fukuyama 1989)
so that alternative futures may be imagined and politically articulated. Russia,
deliberately and decisively, changed its course twice in the twentieth century;
despite many undesirable outcomes, the case of Russia pushes us to see social
transformations and various economic futures as not only possible but as also
always ongoing, incomplete, and the result of a contested political process.
What place could be more intriguing for those who want to understand how
contemporary capitalism is constituted and maintained? What lessons could the rest
of the world learn from the Russian experience? In Russia the extremes of modern
capitalism are allowed to flourish without constraint; indeed, Russia might be the
already actualized neoliberal tomorrow of the West. As a real life laboratory of
large-scale economic marginalization and poverty, the Russian experience calls
for urgent efforts to better understand and resist neoliberalism, and work on alter-
native futures “here and now” (Gibson-Graham 1996, 2006; Gibson-Graham,
Cameron, and Healy, 2013; Pavlovskaya 2013, 2015).

Normalization of Poverty through Metrics


In Russia, it is clear that neoliberal reform results in widespread poverty which,
twenty-five years on, can no longer be rationalized as the “necessary and short
lived pain” of transition. Furthermore, Russia also provides us with a clear case of
how measuring and understanding poverty matters, how it allows for some policies
and not others, and how it works to reinforce inequalities even as it claims to
create knowledge for its alleviation. Like capitalism itself, modes of poverty
knowledge in Russia have been adopted/imposed from elsewhere. In particular,
Russian policy makers and scholars look to the West, international organizations
such as the ILO, and especially the United States, where poverty is understood as
a “normal” part of everyday life, for insights into how to know and address the
problem of poverty (Collier and Way 2004; Pavlovskaya 2015).
Policy makers and scholars who have accepted neoliberalism also accept, perhaps
reluctantly, the inevitability of the existence of poverty in Russia. Making poverty
acceptable more broadly, to the society that recently denied its existence, is not,
however, a trivial task. It required a complete rejection of Marxist state ideologies,
rationalities, and truths that the government and social scientists had produced for
decades during the Soviet era. These ideologies had to be replaced with new
truths emerging from neoliberal discourses that legitimize individualism, the right
to wealth accumulation, inherent inequality, and poverty as an unfortunate but
inevitable condition. Social and economic truths are, however, constructed by
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

88 Marianna Pavlovskaya

more than ideological shifts and dispositions; they are established and reinforced
through socio-technical practices and methodologies, not the least of which are
state sponsored categorizations and collections of data. Indeed, metrics of poverty
that conform to international standards (e.g. ILO and others) have played a
crucial role in the normalization of poverty because they produce a powerful
message that poverty is everywhere in the world and it is acceptable to have it
in Russia. These metrics, therefore, do not simply describe poverty, they pro-
duce the poor as a new subject and object of policy; they produce a social body
that neoliberalism can manage (Hannah 2001; Pavlovskaya and Bier 2012). The
relatively new introduction into Russia of not only neoliberal ideologies and
policies but also the practices and methodologies of state knowledge production
about capitalism (e.g. new categories and techniques for counting and measuring)
makes clear how ideology and metrics work together to maintain Russia’s
neoliberal trajectory.

Welfare and Poverty under State Socialism


In order to appreciate the degree of strain on social reproduction caused by the
removal of Soviet era welfare support, it is important to disentangle the advances
of state welfare per se from the Soviet authoritarian political system. Neoliberal
theorists, however, see welfare as dependency on state authority; they treat them
as two sides of the same coin. In their view, state welfare is necessarily joined
with political conformism while freedom can only exist under capitalism freed
from state intervention (Friedman 1951). Because Russian reformers thought in
this way too, they dismantled the Soviet welfare system insofar as it was under-
stood to be integral to the totalitarian state (Pavlovskaya 2015). Yet, totalitarian
regimes around the world such as Pinochet’s Chile, China, and now Russia have
aggressively promoted private markets; it is clear that the connection between
capitalism and democracy is contingent rather than necessary. Consequently,
neither do the welfare state and authoritarianism need to be theorized as two sides
of the same coin; their proximity could be seen as that of two coins put together in a
contingent manner. Starting from such an understanding, we can start to (re)imagine
post-capitalist (or non-capitalist) democracies with strong welfare support as
legitimate, desirable, and possible. In this regard, the experience of the Soviet
welfare system is invaluable for appreciating what a society can accomplish by
treating basic human needs as entitlements and rights instead of commodities.
Private property in the means of production did not exist under the Soviet
system and the state guaranteed jobs to all as a single employer; there was no
unemployment (in fact, avoiding work was treated as a problem). Wages and
pensions covered basic consumption needs while prices for food items, manu-
factured goods, cultural services, utilities, and transportation were low and fixed.
Such social goods as childcare, healthcare, housing, and education were provided
universally, free of charge, and disregarding the ability to pay. The quality and
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Ontologies of Poverty in Russia 89

availability of these goods and services obviously varied significantly across Soviet
space (they were especially lacking in rural areas, Zaslavsky 1982) but the point is
that their provision equalized income differentials and assured social mobility at
the large scale. Additionally, the system of the so-called l’goty provided benefits
(monetized and in kind) to specific population groups such as, for example, labor
veterans (those over twenty-five years in the labor force), war veterans, the
handicapped, and families with children.2 Seen as irrational, wasteful, and even
“exuberant” from the neoliberal point of view (Collier and Way 2004; Pavlovskaya
2015), the Soviet welfare system worked well for decades by equalizing social
differences without explicitly addressing them.
The former Soviet Union denied that poverty could exist within socialism on
theoretical grounds. In the 1930s, Stalin declared that the foundations of socialism
had been built and the social roots of poverty as well as other “bourgeois” societal
ills (such as exploitation, patriarchy, ethnic discrimination, class differences, and so
on) had been eliminated. As a result, statistical agencies did not gather statistics on
class differences until the 1950s–1960s (Rimashevskaya 2003). Nevertheless, the
Soviet government realized the need to address existing differences in material
well-being. Statisticians began collecting what was then classified information
about income and consumption levels, information that was only made available
to economists and sociologists charged with consulting with the government.
Because the term “poverty” was reserved for capitalism, Soviet scholars began
assessing what they called “low material security” (maloobespechennost’) of certain
groups from the overall population (e.g., families with several children, the
handicapped, or retirees). It was measured against the scientifically determined
“minimum subsistence budget” (Rimashevskaya 2003, p. 124). Assessment
focused on the availability of food and other everyday expenses but excluded the
universally provided free goods such as childcare, housing, healthcare, and
education.
Material security was also assessed relative to the wages that the government
fixed. Across the entire country, the government set the minimum wage to
exceed the minimum subsistence levels by a factor of 1.5 so that a working
adult could support a dependent. Low material security meant that income per
family member fell below the subsistence minimum. In the late Soviet, it was
estimated that 25–30% of families had low material security (Rimashevskaya
2003, p. 122).
While today some scholars argue that low material security under the Soviet
system was a form of poverty, it is clear that its nature and scope differed
significantly from poverty under capitalism. Importantly, it was not seen as a
function of not being able to earn adequate wages but that of having to support
non-working dependents (e.g., families with many young children) or not being
able to work because of disability or some other condition. Families with low
material security still had the same access to childcare, housing, healthcare, and
education as everyone else.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

90 Marianna Pavlovskaya

From Soviet to Neoliberal Capitalist Welfare


After 1991, private property became legal for the first time in over seventy years
which led to the rapid wholesale privatization of national assets and the closure of
many long-standing enterprises. Unemployment, now also legal, was rapidly rising,
and for those who remained employed, the liberalization of prices diminished
wages manifold. Furthermore, any remaining social guarantees, such as free health-
care, soon lost their meaning as a wide range of state services quickly disin-
tegrated. Finally, high prices for newly commodified versions of what had been
state provided services put them out of reach for the majority of the population.
The devastating effects of these changes on the Russian population quickly
became evident in many domains including a demographic crisis unprecedented
in peace time (Heleniak 1995; Eberstadt 2010). From the 1990s onward the
population of Russia has declined in absolute terms because high mortality rates
exceed drastically diminished birth rates while, at the same time, life expectancy
fell to its lowest level (for men it dropped in the mid-1990s to 56 years). In other
words, “building capitalism” cost Russia millions of premature deaths that critical
scholars in other contexts have attributed to the “death-dealing” nature of capitalism
that exposes people to economic, social, and physical violence (Gilmore 2007).
The violence of poverty inflicted on the Soviet people by “disaster capitalism”
(Klein 2008) included job loss, stress, crime and gun violence, deteriorated health,
collapse of the public healthcare system and other safety nets, and increased
self-destructive behavior and suicide rates.
Many of these problems have been ongoing since the mid-1990s and their
persistence over twenty-five years clearly suggests that they are inherent to neoliberal
capitalism rather than to social transformation per se.

Ontologies of Capitalist Poverty


The immediate, dramatic, and devastating effects of “shock therapy” and price
liberalization on the economic well-being of the Russian population are visible in
the new metrics of social differentiation, provided we compare them to the pre-
1991 society. In this case, in one year Russian society changed from one of the
most equal to one of the most unequal in the world.

Wealth and Income Polarization


Privatization of national assets has led to the exceptional concentration of wealth
that considerably exceeds US levels. In the US the infamous 1% hold 40% of per-
sonal assets but in Russia they hold 71% of personal assets and its top 5% own 81%
of all wealth (Zotin and Kvasha 2014). Because most people make a living by
earning their income, measures of income inequality are even more important. The
popular Gini coefficient, one of the new post-Soviet metrics, shows that income
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Ontologies of Poverty in Russia 91

FIGURE 5.1Income inequality in Russia, 1990–2015


Source: Author based on Rosstat data.

inequality (Figure 5.1) has grown from one of the world’s lowest (0.260 in 1991,
comparable to Scandinavian countries) to the world’s highest levels (already 0.407
by 1993 and 0.423 in 2007). Income inequality is worse than in the USA (Gini
coefficient around 0.411) and remains high whether the economy is doing poorly
(such as in the 1990s) or well (such as during high oil prices in the 2000s). In other
words, deep inequality has become a permanent feature of Russian society.
Other measures support the story told by the Gini coefficient. For example,
the income discrepancy between the top and bottom deciles (10% population
groups) was only fourfold in the last year of the Soviet period but jumped to
fifteen times as early as 1994 and reached seventeen times by 2015. For compar-
ison, decile ratios of ten or more are considered by many experts to be large
enough to generate social unrest (Garanenko 2007). Even in the USA, which
tolerates high levels of inequality (routine decile rations of ten–twelve), inequality
has become a major political concern as manifest in, among other things, the
Occupy Wall Street movement. In Russia, despite glaring economic inequality,
popular protests target corruption and election fraud rather than inequality.
In short, Russian capitalism led to a rapid, dramatic, and entrenched con-
centration of wealth and earning power in the hands of a few while the majority
of the population has not fared well and many live in poverty.

Rise of Poverty
The Russian liberal reformers of the 1990s, together with their IMF consultants
(who included then Harvard economist Jeffry Sachs), convinced politicians and
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

92 Marianna Pavlovskaya

the public that a program of shock therapy would be painful but short lived.
Once the wealth-generating capacities of capitalism were activated, all who were
willing to work hard would be able to make a living (Sachs 1995). Russian statistics,
however, show that the poverty created by capitalism quickly became widespread
and, in contrast to what the neoliberal theorists claimed, poverty – like economic
inequality – has become a structural condition of Russian society.
According to the Russian Statistics Agency (Rosstat), by 1992 over one-third
of the population or almost 50 million people were living in poverty (Figure 5.2).
While the poverty rate fluctuated in subsequent years, it never became negligible
and today it remains at roughly 15%. In other words, a condition of widespread
and long-term economic marginalization was established in a country that had no
prior experience with structural poverty.
Paradoxically, if we forget about the Soviet period when such poverty was
absent, the current poverty rate makes Russia look quite good. For example,
the policy makers can claim that poverty declined more than three times from
33.5% in 1992 to 11% in 2013 (Ovcharova et al. 2014) and, therefore, the new
capitalist system, given time, does lift people out of poverty. A similarly rosy
picture emerges when comparing Russia to other countries. Because they all
have poverty, capitalist Russia does not deviate from the standard social condi-
tion. Moreover, Russian scholars cite the World Bank definition of absolute
poverty as subsisting on or less than $1.25-–$2/day to conclude that the
“poverty level in Russia already in the middle of the 2000s was less than 0.0%”
(Ovcharova et al. 2014, p. 4). The statistics conceal the fact that it is
ludicrous for a nation with an advanced space program to compare itself to the

40

33.5
35
31.5 Unemployment rate, %
29
30 28.3 27.5 Poverty rate, %
24.7 24.6
22.4 23.3
25
22
20.7 20.3
20 17.6 17.8
15.2
13.3 13.4 13 12.5 12.7 15.1
15 13.3
12.6 10.7 10.8 11.2
11.8
10.58
9.5 9.7 8.98
10 8.1 7.88 8.21 7.76 8.3
7.12 7.05 7.35 6.5
6.2
5.2 5.9
6 5.46 5.5 5.2 5.5
5

0
1992
1993
1994
1995
1996
1997
1998
1999
2000
2001
2002
2003
2004
2005
2006
2007
2008
2009
2010
2011
2012
2013
2014
2015

FIGURE 5.2 Poverty rate and unemployment rate in Russia, 1992–2015


Source: Author based on Rosstat data.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Ontologies of Poverty in Russia 93

poorest nations of the world. Finally, a poverty level of 15% makes Russia,
which still considers the USA its primary rival, look good relative to the USA
where the rate is similar. In sum, poverty in Russia is no longer seen as an
exception, it is commonplace and it is within the statistical norm as demon-
strated by comparison with Russia’s peers and by a host of international
organizations.

Politics of Metrics of Poverty


When Russia began measuring poverty in 1992 using the ILO methodology,
researchers reviewed a variety of Western practices and settled on the
“absolute” definition of poverty, a measure which roughly paralleled Soviet
measures of low material security. In this case, people are poor if they do not
earn enough to afford the scientifically determined basic level of consumption:
the consumer basket, the monetary cost of which is called the minimum
subsistence level (MSL). The rate of poverty is measured as a percentage of
the population with a per capita income below the MSL. This key metric is
used for assessing the state of the economy, socio-economic well-being, and
social policy needs.
On the surface, these measures make perfect sense and make Russian data
internationally comparable. Yet, national surveys report that two-fifths of the
population self-identify as poor – a much larger share than the official poverty
rate of 15%.While survey measures are subjective, the differences between
them and the official statistics suggest that the latter may underestimate the
level of on-going economic marginalization. Moreover, the discrepancy is not
just a technical error. Because the consistent use of statistical categories
actively shapes the social body (Hannah 2001; St. Martin 2009; Pavlovskaya
and Bier 2012), Russian metrics of poverty are not innocent. They, in fact,
obscure the true scale at which neoliberal capitalism produces and reproduces
poverty.
While determining poverty rate appears straightforward, (e.g., percentage of
population with income below minimum subsistence level) it actually hinges on
three separate metrics which together inform social policy: the minimum sub-
sistence level (MSL), income per capita, and minimum wage. These metrics each
have the capacity to shift the poverty line, affect the overall size of the poor
population, and determine individual eligibility for social assistance.
To make social policy meaningful, the MSL should properly reflect the cost of
basic necessities so that a reasonable poverty line can be set. The minimum wage
should exceed the MSL so that working adults can earn enough to provide for
basic necessities. Households with per capita income below the subsistence
minimum (aka poverty line) would then be considered poor. The actual rela-
tionship between these indicators, however, tends to obscure more than they
clarify relative to the question of poverty.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

94 Marianna Pavlovskaya

The Secrets of the Minimum Subsistence Level (MSL)


The consumer basket and the corresponding MSL (Figure 5.3) are defined by the
federal government for three population groups (children, adults, and the elderly)
every three months. The consumer basket includes both food and non-food
items which are revised every five years to better reflect available products and
current prices. The consumer basket has regional equivalents because what is
essential varies from region to region as do prices.
The state can and often does directly alter the size of the impoverished popu-
lation by lowering or increasing the MSL threshold. The concern is that these
fluctuations affect eligibility for social assistance because they may throw into or
lift out of poverty millions of people at once. For example, in 2015 the increase
in MSL by 26%3 made the population below the poverty line larger by 3 million
while in 2016 the government inexplicably lowered the MSL despite the fact that
the cost of living and inflation were going up.
More importantly, however, the MSL has diverged from the cost of basic
needs since the very start of the capitalist period. At the end of the Soviet period,
it was set at 135 rubles and if the same value had been applied after the shock
therapy of 1992, 70–80% of population would be in poverty due to plummeting
income levels. Because capitalist social welfare policy is only meant to help rela-
tively small groups of people who are in need of temporary assistance, poverty at
the scale of the entire society could not be addressed (Rimashevskaya 2003,
p.123). Hoping that capitalism would soon start creating well-paying jobs and
solve this large scale problem, Yeltsin’s government decided to revise the MSL
down to 60 rubles (less than half of the previous amount) in order to redefine
poverty as the experience of only the very poorest and to bring the national
rate down to a more acceptable 33.5% (Rimashevskaya 2003, p. 124). This still
large but artificially lowered figure is now used as the starting point for analyzing
relative change in poverty over time. It obscures the overwhelming scale of
economic marginalization in those first years of the transition but it serves very
well to demonstrate the subsequent reduction of poverty.
Beyond alterations of the MSL, changes in its composition have also affected
the poverty rate.
For example, more than once, the government modified the ratio between the
cost of food and other items in the consumer basket (Rimashevskaya 2003,
p. 124; Ovcharova et al. 2014, pp. 6–8). The 2000 revision still excluded from
consideration costs for healthcare, education, and social services because it was
assumed that, as under the Soviet welfare system, these services were available at
the minimum level free of charge (Ovcharova et al. 2014, p.8). By that time and
further on, however, expenses for healthcare, education, utilities, and transportation
had all become a major cost.
Since 2013, only norms for basic food consumption (in kilos) are specified
while the cost of other goods and services in the consumer basket is simply set to
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Ontologies of Poverty in Russia 95

50% of the cost of food (Federal law, 2012) despite rapidly rising prices for non-
food items. Because the MSL value sets the poverty line, a proper assessment of
the basic subsistence needs provides a foundation for a sound social policy. The
way the MSL is currently determined underestimates, by a factor of 2.5 or even
3, the costs of basic necessities, which considerably reduces the size of the popu-
lation in poverty.

Elusive Per Capita Income


Determining the national or regional poverty rate involves calculating the share of
population that earns income below the MSL. The distribution of income
throughout the population is done based upon macro-economic tools. The sta-
tistical models calculate income per capita for the entire population (including
income earners, their dependents, etc.) and determine how many people fall into
the group with per capita income below the poverty line. The national per capita
income consistently climbs above the MSL which creates a sense of growing
affluence (Figure 5.3) and declining poverty (Figure 5.2). If we recall, however,

25000

20000

Unemployment benefit, min,


rubles
Unemployment benefit, max,
15000
rubles
MSL, rubles
Income per capita, rubles
MMW, rubles
10000

5000

0
2005 2006 2007 2008 2009 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015

FIGURE 5.3Income per capita, MSL (minimum subsistence level), MMW (minimum
monthly wage), and unemployment benefit limits, 2005–2014
Source: Author based on Rosstat data.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

96 Marianna Pavlovskaya

that the MSL should be three times higher, the poverty level and per capita
income would be very close to each other, showing a much larger poverty rate.
In addition, per capita income is statistically corrected to adjust for undeclared
income which increases the earnings by 20–30%. The income per capita is
corrected uniformly for all income groups although higher earning groups have
larger undeclared income. Per capita income on the bottom, therefore, is over-
estimated with the effect of again reducing the population below the poverty
threshold (Ovcharova et al. 2014).
Moreover, income per capita is calculated as an average value which obscures
the fact that income distribution is skewed with many low income earners at the
bottom and a small group of high income earners at the top. Scholars contend
that a median income (which is considerably lower than the average) better
reflects this distribution and would be more useful for determining the size of
population in poverty. In short, the macro-economic procedures that measure per
capita income also contribute to considerably underestimating the population in
poverty and the demand for social assistance.

The Non-Compliant Minimum Monthly Wage


The last metric vital to the calculation of poverty measures is the minimum
monthly wage (MMW). MMW has the status of law and serves to regulate wages
and calculate unemployment payments as well as taxes, fines, and other fees. By
Russian law, MMW should exceed the minimum subsistence level. During the
Soviet period, the minimum wage was indeed set at 1.5 of the MSL to assure that
a working adult could support a dependent in addition to herself (Rimashevskaya
2003, p. 122). Soon after 1992, however, MMW lost its ability to keep up with
growing living costs and quickly fell below the post-Soviet MSL (which itself was
already more than halved by reformers in the attempt to reduce the poverty rate).
Initially, the reformers thought that this inversion would be temporary but it
kept growing such that by 1999, for example, the minimum monthly wage
comprised just 11% of the MSL despite the fact that legally it had to exceed it
(Rimashevskaya 2003, p. 125).
The current MMW still remains considerably lower than the MSL (Figure 5.3).
The government declared that the two indicators should finally converge by the
end of 2017 but this remains to be seen because the powerful industrial lobby
opposes such attempts.
The point is that the government policy with regard to minimum wage, in
violation of the law has kept it below the subsistence minimum for the last
twenty-five years. This reversal of these legally set thresholds leads to systemically
suppressed wages and is particularly harmful for those with low income. This
situation clearly supports neoliberal economic policies that enable high levels of
exploitation of the working classes and entrenches them in poverty. At the same
time, the Russian government continues to regularly set its minimum monthly
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Ontologies of Poverty in Russia 97

wage and publish related statistics as if there is nothing wrong here. This very act
ironically signals that the government does not ignore labor regulation and complies
with the international expectations and requirements.
To sum up, the key metrics of poverty used in Russia – MSL, per capita
income, and MMW – relate to each other in such a way that they obscure the
true dimensions of economic marginalization. While their ability to effectively
inform social policy is limited at best, their continued use by the government, as
if they had meaning, makes the level of poverty in Russia appear both “normal”
and manageable.

Working People as the Poor


Finally, that poverty is chronic and structural rather than a temporary outcome of
the transition is supported by the prevalence of the working poor in Russia. As
others have noted (Hoynes et al. 2005), contrary to widely spread claims,
employment in the capitalist labor market does not necessarily provide a way out
of poverty. Since the introduction of capitalism in Russia, a large segment of
working people have lived in poverty. For example, those Soviet state employees
who were not immediately laid off continued to work for many years for drastically
devalued wages. This was especially true for many professional workers who were
amongst the first of a new class of working poor. Today, employees who work
within Putin’s government or in certain private companies do earn relatively
good wages, but other working people, including professionals, continue to earn
meager wages that trap them in poverty. Thus, the working poor, who today are
often young and educated, have become a permanent fixture of the Russian neo-
liberal economy. Moreover, their share among the poor has been growing and in
2013, for example, they made up an outstanding 63% of the poor population.
While some suggest that working people locked in poverty are specific to
Russian capitalism (Rimashevskaya 2003; Ovcharova et al. 2014), the growing
working poor population is becoming a worldwide trend. It is also present in the
USA. As a result of an ongoing shift to neoliberal post-industrial work regimes,
people work long hours at several jobs but cannot lift themselves out of poverty
because of low wages (Peck 1996; Beck 2000). In Russia, this situation developed
in the very first years of capitalism and, as suggested above, might foretell the
contours of a neoliberal future in which most jobs have no protections and wages
below the subsistence minimum are normalized.

Why Help the Unemployed?


That material comfort in Russia is not well related to jobs is suggested by Figure 5.2
in which poverty and the unemployment rates 1992 through 2015 are counter-
poised. If employment provided sufficient wages and job loss caused poverty,
then poverty and unemployment rates would vary somewhat together: low
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

98 Marianna Pavlovskaya

unemployment would coincide with low poverty and vice versa. The graph suggests,
however, that in Russia poverty and unemployment rates have been generally out of
sync and, indeed, have been most of the time opposite each other.
Liberal social assistance, however, presumes that job loss causes poverty and
employment lifts people out of it. It also presumes that capitalism generates eco-
nomic opportunities for the poor in the form of jobs that the poor are expected
to pursue. Welfare programs in the USA provide short-term unemployment
benefits and job placement services, such programs also require the unemployed
to look for jobs and, occasionally, get retrained. Moreover, unemployment
benefits must be less attractive than the most marginal employment in order to
encourage people to cycle back into the workforce as soon as possible.
To deal with the unemployment that appeared in Russia after 1991, the Russian
government adopted rules that are even more neoliberal in spirit than those in the
USA. In Russia support is provided for up to 24 months and during the first year
unemployment benefits initially constitute 75% of the last salary and slide to 45%
after a few months. These payments cannot, however, go beyond the minimum
and maximum limits set by the government. During the second year, the benefit
is set to the minimum level only. The set limits on the benefits, however, ensure
that they cannot support household needs. For example, in the mid-2000s the
maximum limit was still close to the minimum subsistence level but since then
the MSL continued to increase while the benefit limits have practically stayed the
same (Figure 5.3). Currently, the minimum level is set to only one-tenth of the
MSL (about $14 per month at the current exchange rate) while the maximum
is about half of the MSL (about $82 per month). If we recall that the MSL
underestimates the costs of living by a factor of 3, the monetary value of the
unemployment benefits virtually disappears.
It is hard to imagine how one would survive their unemployment without
relying on other sources of support from, for example, family, friends, and other
networks (Pavlovskaya 2015).

Moral Standing, Self-Discipline, and Desire to Work


In addition to negligible benefits, there are also strict requirements that the
registered unemployed must meet. They must show up for events and trainings,
re-register every ten days, and accept the second job offered in order to not be
bumped out of the system. A job is considered acceptable if the pay on offer is
above the subsistence minimum (or its fractions for part-time employment)
which, as we have seen, will not lift the unemployed out of poverty. To reduce
government payments, legislators aim to shorten the period of coverage, reduce
the size of payments, and limit eligibility to particular populations (e.g.,
exclude those who never worked). Furthermore, legislators attempt to insure that
recipients are only those demonstrating a high moral character and will to work
by, for example, requiring the registered unemployed to participate in
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Ontologies of Poverty in Russia 99

uncompensated public works projects near their place of residence (e.g., cleaning
streets, planting trees, etc.) (Mintrud 2016).
It is, perhaps, not surprising that only one-quarter of the estimated 4 million
people who are currently unemployed have registered with an employment
agency. This is similar to the current situation in the USA where those registered
to receive unemployment benefits fluctuate between 25% and 40% of the
unemployed, reaching an all-time low of 23% in 2014 (Delaney and Scheller
2015). While the need for support certainly remains high amongst the unem-
ployed, they are deterred from seeking assistance as neoliberal policies increase
targeting, means-testing, and other disciplinary measures (Soss et al. 2011; Schram
2015). Instead of providing compassionate government support to the poor and
the unemployed, neoliberal social policies in Russia, as in the USA, increasingly
marginalize them.

Invisible Economies of Cooperation


Nationalism and geopolitical confrontation are needed to divert attention from
low wages and poverty, especially when the government does not have a policy
response to the negative consequences of neoliberal capitalism, a system it not
only imposed but also continues to support. The government’s lack of response
was symbolically captured in a recent remark made by the prime minister.
Medvedev, during a recent visit to the Crimea, responded to a group of retired
women requesting an increase in their meager pensions by saying: “There is no
money for your pensions now. But you will somehow hang on. Best wishes for
high spirits and health to everyone!” Then he walked away (Gazeta.ru, 2016).
What do people do when the government abandons them even during times of
extreme hardship as in the case of elderly women trying to survive in the recently
annexed Crimea? Or when, as we have seen, the government not only ignores but
also actively obscures, via state metrological practices, the long-term marginalization
of what is likely a considerable majority of the Russian population?
Some studies suggest that with no formal jobs paying a living wage and no
meaningful social assistance, 14–25 million people have turned to the informal
economy, where formal capitalist and state institutions do not have the same
control over economic practices and where people can organize social reproduc-
tion on their own terms (Pavlovskaya 2015). The diverse economies (Gibson-
Graham 2006) they create often work to support livelihoods instead of profits in
the direst of the times. While much informal economic activity is undesirable
and likely to involve exploitation, also emerging are non-capitalist economic
practices that require cooperation, sharing, and mutual support; people build
alliances to survive and even manage to provide modest but comfortable con-
sumption levels for their families (Pavlovskaya 2015). This is not to say that the
informal economy as a whole should be celebrated, but in the face of persistent
large-scale poverty in Russia and lack of a viable social policy, people are
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

100 Marianna Pavlovskaya

finding creative ways to secure social reproduction and live well by participating
in distinctly non-capitalist practices.

Conclusions
The post-Soviet transformation produced a dramatically polarized society with a
large population of the poor. Since 1992, the poor have constituted between 33%
and 10% of the Russian population, or anywhere between 43 and 15 million
(Figure 5.1). Russia, along with capitalism itself, developed from scratch a set of
metrics and policies designed to address and manage this new segment of the
population. As a result, poverty in Russia is understood to be an unfortunate but
“normal” condition as in other developed capitalist countries. Official statistics,
academic policy reports and articles, as well as mass media have played an
important role in normalizing poverty as well as obscuring its extent and its
detrimental effects.
In this chapter, I have focused on those key metrics, suggested by other countries
and international organizations, that are used by the government to simultaneously
assess and, as I have shown, systematically obscure the depth and persistence of
poverty in Russia. A close examination of the most important measures of poverty
(e.g. minimum subsistence level or MSL, per capita income, and minimum monthly
wage or MMW) reveals their collective role in establishing the foundations for
government proclamations concerning the level of poverty and for government
intervention in poverty alleviation. In particular, we have seen how the MSL grossly
underestimates the cost of subsistence, how per capita income overestimates the
wages earned by the lowest income groups, and how the minimum monthly wage
has lingered below the subsistence minimum for a quarter of a century. Nevertheless,
these metrics are routinely used by policy makers, politicians, and bureaucrats to
provide evidence that the poverty rate is decreasing and that its level is within what
is considered “normal” in the West. At the same time, and since the advent of
capitalism in Russia, the population of the Russian poor has expanded to include
not only the unemployed, the retired, those with many dependents, and the
handicapped, but also working age, able bodied, and even many employed adults.
The Russian experience deserves more attention than it now receives from
critical scholars because it powerfully puts into relief, as in a laboratory setting, the
work needed to produce and maintain neoliberal capitalism. The case of Russia
disrupts the illusion of capitalism’s promise of prosperity for working people and
it exposes the everyday violence of neoliberalism produced by low wages,
precarious jobs, absent social mobility, and meager social assistance. Most Russians
do not dream of capitalist riches, they want secure livelihoods and meaningful
lives which they increasingly find only within non-capitalist spaces where diverse
economies of cooperation are emerging.
Finally, the Russian experience has profound implications for understanding
how neoliberalism works or might work in other national and international
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Ontologies of Poverty in Russia 101

contexts. It powerfully demonstrates what happens to a society that implements


capitalism via a strong state whose aim is to protect and enhance capital accu-
mulation. Russia has the unique advantage of still remembering the elaborate
social welfare of the Soviet period although this memory is being quickly erased.
This recent history makes it clear that socialized welfare is practically possible and
necessary. People in Russia and elsewhere must continually challenge the neo-
liberal state to provide the basic standards of well-being that they should see as
their right and not a market commodity.
The case of Russian neoliberal capitalism also makes clear that economies are
decidedly more contingent and constructed than commonly thought; while this
case demonstrates how a particular economic form can be adopted out of whole
cloth and imposed from the top down, it also reveals how maintaining any
economy requires a host of cooperating metrics and related technologies of
assessment. If policy effort can change a society from socialism to capitalism, it can
also change its social assistance systems in many other big and small ways,
including establishing sound welfare support. Meanwhile, the vast population of
the un- and under-employed, those who cannot survive on their state benefits or
formal wages, necessarily engage in economic activity that is, like themselves,
unacknowledged. In this sense, what the government misses and what we are called
to reveal is another economy out of which we might produce new post-capitalist
imaginaries that foreground collective ways to care.

Notes
1 Acknowledgements: Support for this work was partially provided by PSC-CUNY grants
65805 and 78704. Funding for the two year long faculty Seminar on Neoliberalism that
inspired this book and this chapter was provided by the Dean of Arts and Sciences at
Hunter College. I am thankful for the opportunity to get to know and work together
with Sandy Schram who was the major energetic force behind the seminar and the book
and whose work enriched my thinking about poverty in Russia. I am grateful, as always,
to Kevin St. Martin for his continued support and feedback on the draft of the paper.
2 Examples of l’goty included, for example, special food items for holidays, extra living
space, trips to health resorts, school meals, free public transportation, discounts on utilities
and medications, and so on.
3 MSL went up from 7688 rubles in the I quarter of 2014 to 9662 rubles in the I quarter
of 2015, or by 26%.

References
Aslund, A. (2001). Building Capitalism: The Transformation of the Former Soviet Bloc. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Beck, U. (2000). The Brave New World of Work. Cambridge: Polity.
Burawoy, M. (1997). Review Essay: The Soviet Descent into Capitalism. American Journal
of Sociology, 102(5), 1430.
Collier, S. J. (2011). Post-Soviet Social: Neoliberalism, Social Modernity, Biopolitics. Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

102 Marianna Pavlovskaya

Collier, S. J., and Way, L. (2004). Beyond the Deficit Model: Social Welfare in Post-
Soviet Georgia. Post-Soviet Affairs, 20(3), 258–284.
Delaney, A., and Scheller, A. (2015). A Lot Fewer Americans Get Unemployment Benefits
Than You Think. Huffington Post, March 13. Retrieved from: www.huffingtonpost.
com/2015/03/13/unemployment-benefits-rate_n_6832552.html
Eberstadt, N. (2010). Russia’s Peacetime Demographic Crisis: Dimensions, Causes, Impli-
cations. Retrieved February 2, 2017, from: www.nbr.org/publications/element.aspx?
id=446
Federal law (2012). Federal law, December 3, 2012, N 227-FZ “On national consumer
basket for Russian Federation.” Approved by State Duma on November 20, 2012.
Approved by Federation Council on November 28, 2012. In Russian: Федеральный
закëн ëт 3 декабря 2012 г. N 227-ФЗ “О пëтребительскëй кëрзине в целëм пë
Рëссийскëй Федерации” Принят Гëсударственнëй Думëй 20 нëября 2012 гëда
Одëбрен Сëветëм Федерации 28 нëября 2012 гëда
Fukuyama, F. (1989). The End of History? The National Interest, Summer, 3–18.
Friedman, Milton (1951). Neo-Liberalism and its Prospects. Farmland, February 17, 89–93.
Gazeta.ru (2016). Медведев на вëпрëс ë пенсиях в Крыму: денег нет, нë вы
держитесь. Retrieved February 3, 2017, from: www.gazeta.ru/business/news/2016/
05/24/n_8672513.shtml
Gibson-Graham, J. K. (1996). The End Of Capitalism (As We Knew It): A Feminist Critique
of Political Economy. New York: Guilford Press.
Gibson-Graham, J. K. (2006). A Postcapitalist Politics. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press.
Gibson-Graham, J. K., Cameron, J., and Healy, S. (2013). Take Back the Economy: An Ethical
Guide for Transforming Our Communities. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Gilmore, R. W. (2007). Golden Gulag: Prisons, Surplus, Crisis, and Opposition in Globalizing
California. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Garanenko, A. (2007). Terribly Rich. Izvestia, August 9. In Russian: Гараненкë, А.
Страшнë бëгатые. Известия, 9 августа. Retrieved April 3, 2017, from http://izvestia.
ru/news/327476
Hannah, M. G. (2001). Sampling and the Politics of Representation in US Census 2000.
Environment and Planning D: Society and Space, 19(5), 515–534. doi: doi:10.1068/d289
Harvey, D. (2007). A Brief History of Neoliberalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Heleniak, T. (1995). Economic Transition and Demographic Change in Russia, 1989–1995.
Post-Soviet Geography, 36(7), 446–458. doi: doi:10.1080/10605851.1995.10641002
Hoynes, H., Page, M., and Stevens, A. (2005). Poverty in America: Trends and Explanations
(Working Paper No. 11681). National Bureau of Economic Research. doi: doi:10.3386/
w11681
Klein, N. (2008). The Shock Doctrine: The Rise of Disaster Capitalism. New York: Picador.
Mintrud (2016) Минтруд выступил за ëтмену пëсëбий для хрëнических безрабëтных,
May 13. Retrieved January 31, 2017, from: https://informatio.ru/news/society/mintrud_
vystupil_za_otmenu_posobiy_dlya/
Offe, C. (1994). Capitalism by Democratic Design? Democratic Theory Facing the Triple
Transition in Central and Eastern Europe. In P. D. H.-J. Wagener (Ed.), The Political
Economy of Transformation (pp. 25–43). Heidelberg: Physica-Verlag HD. doi:
doi:10.1007/978-3-642-52404-2_2
Ovcharova, L. N., Biryukova, S. S., Popova, D. O., and Vardanyan, E. G. (2014). Level
and Profile of Poverty in Russia: From the 1990s until Today. Moscow: VShE. In Russian:
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Ontologies of Poverty in Russia 103

Овчарëва, Л.Н., Бирюкëва, С.С., Пëпëва, Д.О., Варданян, Е.Г. Урëвень и прëфиль
беднëсти в Рëссии: ëт 1990х дë наших дней. Мëсква: ВШЭ, 2014.
Pavlovskaya, M. (2004). Other Transitions: Multiple Economies of Moscow Households
in the 1990s. Annals of the Association of American Geographers, 94(2), 329–351.
Pavlovskaya, Marianna (2013). Between Neoliberalism and Difference: Multiple Practices
of Property in Post-Soviet Russia. Europe-Asia Studies, 65(7), 1295–1323. doi:
doi:10.1080/09668136.2013.822708.
Pavlovskaya, M. (2015). Post-Soviet Welfare and Multiple Economies of Households in
Moscow. In Gerda Roelvink, Kevin St Martin, and J. K. Gibson-Graham (Eds.), Making
Other Worlds Possible: Performing Diverse Economies (pp. 269–295). Minneapolis: Uni-
versity of Minnesota Press.
Pavlovskaya, M., and Bier, J. (2012). Mapping Census Data for Difference: Towards the
Heterogeneous Geographies of Arab American Communities of the New York
Metropolitan Area. Geoforum, 43(3), 483–496. doi: doi:10.1016/j.geoforum.2011.10.007
Peck, J. (1996). Work-Place: The Social Regulation of Labor Markets. New York: The Guilford
Press.
Piketty, Thomas (2014). Capital in the Twenty-First Century, trans. Arthur Goldhammer.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Rimashevskaya, N. (2003). People and Reforms: The Secrets of Survival. Moscow: ISEPN RAN
(Russian Academy of Sciences). In Russian: Римашевская, Н.М. Челëвек и рефëрмы:
Секреты выживания. Мëсква: ИСЭПН РАН, 2003.
Roelvink, G., Martin, K. S., and Gibson-Graham, J. K. (Eds.) (2015). Making Other Worlds
Possible: Performing Diverse Economies. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Roy, A., and Crane, E. S. (Eds.) (2015). Territories of Poverty: Rethinking North and South.
Athens: University of Georgia Press.
Sachs, J. D. (1995). Rynochnaya ekonomika i Rossia (Market economy and Russia), trans. from
English. Moscow: Ekonomika.
Schram, S. F. (2015). The Return of Ordinary Capitalism: Neoliberalism, Precarity, Occupy.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Soss, J., Fording, R. C., and Schram, S. F. (2011). Disciplining the Poor: Neoliberal Paternalism
and the Persistent Power of Race. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
St. Martin, K. (2009). Toward a Cartography of the Commons: Constituting the Political
and Economic Possibilities of Place. Professional Geographer, 61(4), 493–507. doi:
doi:10.1080/00330120903143482
Zaslavsky, V. (1982). The Neo-Stalinist State: Class Ethnicity & Consensus in Soviet Society.
Florence: Routledge.
Zotin, A. and Kvasha, M. (2014) All Sides of Inequality. Kommersant-Den/gi, 24(15). In
Russian: Зëтин, А. and Кваша, М. (2014, June 23). Все грани неравенства.
Кëммерсантъ Деньги, 24(15). Retrieved April 3, 2017, www.kommersant.ru/doc/
2485570
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

6
NEOLIBERALISM VIEWED FROM
THE BOTTOM UP
A Qualitative Longitudinal Study of
Benefit Claimants’ Experiences of the
Unemployment System

Sophie Danneris

Throughout the western world during the last few decades, substantial transfor-
mations have changed the nature of human services in general and of social policy
in particular. Neoliberal organizational reforms such as privatization, performance
management, and the economic streamlining of services have supported a
marketization of social service organizations; as a result, their most important task
today is to make dependent clients independent as quickly as possible. In this task,
standardization and disciplinary tools such as sanctions, financial penalties, and
controlling work processes have been the favorite management tools (Braedley
and Luxton 2010; Brown 2003; Schram and Silverman 2012; Schram 2015).
Embedded in this neoliberal orientation has been a personalization of the social
problems of the clients. This means that matters such as poor health and unem-
ployment, which had once been considered the shared responsibility of the state
and the citizen, are now first and foremost treated as personal problems of the
individual to be solved through rational individual choices (Schram 2015;
Caswell, Eskelinen, and Olesen 2011). Thus, the task of the state is to encourage
individuals to see themselves as personally responsible for managing their lives
and, using the most efficient tools, to discipline clients by making this a moral
responsibility. As Brown puts it, “The state attempts to construct prudent subjects
through policies that organize such prudence” (Brown 2003, p. 43). Extending
economic rationality to domains formerly dominated by non-economic values
enrolls clients in a neoliberal order that normatively constructs them as rational,
autonomous, and calculating creatures with the ability to provide for their own
needs (Brown 2003). This leaves individuals with full responsibility for their
situation, regardless of the circumstances that led to their applying for help –
for example a sick child, a severe accident, or unemployment. However, due to
their problems, vulnerable welfare claimants are rarely able to live up to this
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberalism Viewed from the Bottom Up 105

individual responsibility. This means that they fail as economic actors and moral
civic beings in the neoliberalized society and that they themselves must seek to
change this through individual efforts (Danneris and Nielsen forthcoming; Soss,
Fording, and Schram 2011). But how are they supposed to do this?
This chapter attempts to answer this question by gaining insight into how
neoliberalism works in local situations and thereby trying to trace the con-
sequences of neoliberalism as we shape policies in our day-to-day practices and
lived lives (Braedley and Luxton 2010, p. 20). Based on the understanding that
neoliberal policies and practices are not uniform and that their effects depend on
the context, the aim is to look at empirical accounts of neoliberalism as a policy
regime and explore the nuances in how neoliberalism affects the citizens who are
subject to it (Lipsky 2010; Brodkin 2013; Koivisto 2007). This means that the
purpose of this chapter is not to trace and discuss the historical and political nature of
neoliberal development. On the contrary, this study of unemployed and vulnerable
benefit claimants is first and foremost an empirical analysis that examines the
neoliberal welfare state from the standpoint of those who are the targets of state
intervention (Naples 1998; Patrick 2014). Thus, looking at policy through the
eyes of the people that it directly affects, this chapter applies an “everyday world”
perspective to the analysis of how neoliberal policies in general and active labor
market reforms in particular are implemented. In adopting this perspective, the
study reveals a multitude of hidden dimensions of the way in which neoliberalism
manifests itself in the daily life of the unemployed (Braedley and Luxton 2010;
Danneris 2016).
As has been documented by much research in the field, both theoretical and
empirical, the western world’s neoliberal misery appears fairly stark and hopeless.
However, an examination of how benefit claimants engage with the welfare state
in their daily practices reveals nuances, cracks, and non-simultaneities, which
challenge a narrow interpretation of the consequences of neoliberalism. These
cracks and conflicting real world tendencies indicate opportunities where light
shines through and potential pathways become evident.

The Danish Case


In Denmark as in the majority of western countries, neoliberalism has affected the
welfare model. The social policy profile of Denmark has undergone a substantial
transformation; although it is still defined as a universal welfare state (Larsen
2015), it is now widely recognized that the character of the Danish welfare
system is drastically changing. In the domain of employment, which is the subject
of this chapter, active labor market policies are developing from a human capital-
dominated policy approach towards a work-first policy approach (Goul Andersen
2013; Juul 2010a; Lødemel and Moreira 2014) that seeks the shortest possible
route to employment for benefit claimants (Høilund 2006; Juul 2010b; Trianta-
fillou 2012). This development finds expression more or less clearly in several
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

106 Sophie Danneris

recent labor market reforms and in ways of organizing the work related to
moving the unemployed from benefits into a permanent position in the labor
market. For example, the formal categories of work capability among unem-
ployed cash benefit claimants have been transformed step by step by political
reforms in recent decades. A brief glance at the four most recent reforms of work
capability categories will elucidate this.
From 2000 to 2014, there was a drastic change in the categorization of the
vulnerable unemployed and, accordingly, in the way this group of clients is por-
trayed in policies. In 2000, official guidelines from the Danish Directorate General
for Employment Placement (Arbejdsmarkedsstyrelsen 2000) clearly explained that
front line workers were to place cash benefit claimants in one of five groups,
ranging from clients with unemployment as their only problem to clients where
unemployment is the least of their problems. In 2004, in the slipstream of a
landmark labor market reform (“More people to work”), match-categories were
introduced in Danish social policy as a new system of classification. Unlike the
former categories, which had focused on the problems of the claimant, match-
categories measured the instantaneous distance between the benefit claimant on the
one hand and the labor market on the other (Socialministeriet 2001). The basic
idea was to view the unemployed with an optimistic neoliberal understanding of
the individual’s resources, assuming that “everyone is capable” (Bang 2002).
Thus, the point was to look at the resources and possibilities of the benefit
claimants rather than their problems and challenges, and to perceive all unemployed
individuals as subjects with the ability/capacity to move towards the labor market
(Bang 2002), while recognizing their individual pace and the fact that some were
closer to the goal than others (Arbejdsmarkedsstyrelsen 2004). With the five
match-categories, employment potential was brought to the forefront of job-
readiness evaluation, and the claimant was placed in one of five categories ranging
from Match 1 (immediate labor market match) to Match 5 (no labor market
match).
In 2010, the system of classification was reformed once again, and the number
of match categories was reduced from five to three. In this reformed system, the
category containing the claimants with the poorest possibilities was renamed so that
“no labor market match” became “temporarily passive.” Again, the argument for this
change was to be found in a fundamentally positive neoliberal view of human
beings, stating that no one is without resources and that everyone has labor market
potential and the responsibility to exploit this potential (Arbejdsmarkedsstyrelsen
2010a, 2010b).
In 2014, as an important part of the most recent major reform of the Danish
cash benefit system, the categories were redefined once more. The concept of
match categories was abandoned to pave the way for a new form of classification
named “Categories of readiness” (Aftaletekst 2013; Beskæftigelsesministeriet
2013). Since then, all cash benefit claimants have been perceived as ready, and
categorization has become a process of assessing the sort of activity for which the
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberalism Viewed from the Bottom Up 107

claimant is ready. Once again, the number of categories was reduced, so only two
major groups of cash benefit claimants now exist: “job ready” and “activity ready.”
These remarkable changes over the past fifteen years in the categorization of
the most vulnerable Danish benefit claimants clearly reflect the neoliberalization
of the welfare system; they moved from being initially defined as “suffering from
heavy social and/or physical problems” to having “no match with the labor
market” to “temporarily passive,” and finally to their current definition as “ready
for activity,” where they are described as those who, “with some help and possibly
through a long process/program can be ready for the labor market” (Danneris
and Nielsen forthcoming).1 However, given these substantial and continuous
changes, it is remarkable that the group of benefit claimants has not changed
correspondingly in numbers or definition. They remain a highly differentiated
group of unemployed people with a variety of problems, including poor physical
health, mental diseases, social problems, and a lack of the competencies needed
for participation in the labor market. If the group of benefit claimants has not
changed, we can conclude that the changes in the categorization system reflect a
new construction of the “relationship” between the individual and the welfare
state. Instead of building a welfare system and implementing policies related to
changes in the group of clients in need of social services, these changes in the
categorization of clients have primarily acted as a political and administrative way
of making the citizens fit into the neoliberal understanding of benefit claimants and of
how they should behave.

Research Approach
In this chapter, I draw on the findings of a qualitative longitudinal study of
twenty-five Danish welfare claimants’ unemployment trajectories. With the purpose
of capturing the complexities and nuances in the encounters between the
unemployed and the neoliberal policies to which they are subject, the aim of this
methodological approach was to access the claimants’ own reality and under-
standings of the encounters and how their lives progressed through time (Grinyer
and Thomas 2012). The qualitative longitudinal research has allowed me to
accompany a group of clients as their lives and their relations with the Jobcenter
unfolded, and this has provided an exceptional opportunity to explore the pro-
cesses and dynamics of change as well as the complex interplay of structure and
individual agency (Elder 2011; Neale and Flowerdew 2003; Patrick 2014; Verd
and López 2011).
Over a two-year period (2013–2015) and in five irregular empirical waves, data
was collected intensively from repeated interviews and observations of each claimant’s
unemployment trajectory (Danneris 2016). The approach to data collection was
holistic (Holstein and Gubrium 2003), and contact took various forms, including
hour-long biographical and follow-up interviews, observations of meetings
with social work professionals, phone interviews, and informal conversations.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

108 Sophie Danneris

Furthermore, the duration, number, and location of meetings varied (for instance,
at the Jobcenter, in the claimant’s home, or at activation sites). In total, the
empirical material consists of eighty-five individual interviews and thirteen
observations.2
All twenty-five claimants included in the study were formally categorized as
“activity ready,” which, as described above, indicates that they were assessed as
having severe problems besides unemployment. Apart from this commonality, the
claimants were highly diverse; they had a multitude of physical and mental health
issues, family or social issues such as substance abuse or homelessness, low levels (if
any) of education, and minimal or unstable work experience. While a few had
only one specific problem (for example a physical problem due to a back injury),
most had complex issues pertaining to several problems.3
All of the twenty-five claimants were in the range 30–59 years of age, and
twelve were men. During the data collection period, they lived in different parts
of Denmark, in cities and in small villages. Some lived in their own houses, while
others lived in rentals, in caravans, or in the living room of a friend’s apartment.
Only four of the claimants lived with their spouse, while the rest lived alone or
were single parents. Two claimants managed to find jobs during the period and
were still employed in the summer of 2015 (Danneris 2016).
In the analysis that follows, the focus will be on the claimants’ narratives about
their unemployment trajectories. This bottom-up perspective allows attention to
the nuances and variations in how individuals meet the state and tackle the
meeting in their everyday encounters. In this regard, it is important to note that
taking the clients’ experiences as the point of departure does not mean that other
factors such as the organizational context or the views of street-level professionals
are irrelevant to the attempt to understand the relationship between citizens and
the state. Neither does it mean that the clients’ experiences can be treated as
witnesses of the truth about the consequences of neoliberalism. However, it is the
underlying assumption of this analysis that benefit claimants have important and
unique knowledge through their individual experiences, that this knowledge is
relevant, and that it is necessary to gain access to it if we are to obtain a fuller
picture of how neoliberalism has affected the welfare system.

Analysis
Through an in-depth analysis of each of the twenty-five claimants’ unemployment
trajectories, I identified four different coping strategies adopted by the clients
in their encounters with the neoliberal welfare system: resignation, action,
adjustment, or resistance. The choice of strategies was not related to the individual
but changed through time, depending on where the claimant was located in his
or her unemployment trajectory. This means that throughout the two years of
data collection, the same claimant made use of several or all of the four coping
strategies, according to his or her current situation, type of problem, and relation
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberalism Viewed from the Bottom Up 109

to the employment system and so on. In the analysis below, I will elaborate on
each of the four coping strategies by using a main case that exemplifies the strategy
in question. In varying forms and at different points in time, the analytical patterns
were identified across all twenty-five claimants’ trajectories, but for the sake of
illustration they will be exemplified through the four stories in the following
analysis. Thus, the four cases are neither the “most different” nor representative of
a general truth; they are examples from the full sample of unique stories of
encounters between benefit claimants and the neoliberal welfare state.

Resignation
The first coping strategy found in the data is resignation, which is characterized
by the claimants as a stage during their unemployment trajectory when they have
given up their attempts to live up to the current norms proscribing how they
should behave. They find themselves in a directionless parallel world and have
found that their options for acting on their current situation have been depleted,
thus leaving them in a state of resignation. An example of a benefit claimant
drawing on this strategy is David. David is in his early thirties and has been
unemployed for about four years due to a bipolar disorder and ADHD. He
receives stabilizing medication and sedatives, and he spends most of his time alone
in his apartment playing games on the computer. David has been provided with
several different types of social services. He has a mentor, an at-home supporter
who helps him with everyday tasks like cleaning the kitchen and buying groceries,
and a social worker at the Jobcenter. In addition, he has an advisor in the criminal
system to make sure that he meets the conditions of his parole, a psychologist,
and a psychiatrist with whom he meets on a regular basis.
For the last year, David has participated in two different in-job-training programs
for a few hours a week. Here, his work readiness (the number of hours he would
be able to work, taking his problems into consideration) has been described and
assessed by social work professionals, leading to their final decision on his future
in the labor market:

D: Now I have been thrown into something that they call a resource
program instead of just being on cash benefits, because they can’t figure out
what to do with me.
I: What does a resource program consist of?
D: Nothing. No, because they can’t really find out what … because I am
too young to get a disability pension, they say. So the resource program just
consists of the same stuff that I have already been doing so far.
I: What do you think of this?
D: I think it is a bit ridiculous, ehm, they can’t figure out what to do with
me. And then they just put me on a resource program, and then they have
an excuse for placing me there for the next 3.5 years.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

110 Sophie Danneris

As David describes in this interview excerpt, the Jobcenter has reached no real
decision so far. He does not fit into the available categories because he is too
young to be granted a disability pension but at the same time has problems that
are too severe for them to find a place for him in the labor market. This short
extract from David’s narrative exemplifies one out of many situations in the data
where the lived life of benefit claimants and the policies targeting them do not
match each other. Active labor market policies are based on the understanding
that everybody has work potential and that it is the citizen’s own responsibility to
exploit this potential. In David’s case, however, this proves quite difficult. First, as
can be assumed from the number of professionals involved in his life, David’s
disabilities mean that he is not capable of taking on the expected responsibility.
He is in need of help every day of the week.
Second, David actually wants to work and contribute to society, but he does
not fit into the definition of what characterizes the neoliberal worker; he cannot
take any available job, needs substantial support, and will always rely on the
government for assistance if he is to participate in the labor market. This means
that he does not fit into any of the categories available in the system, which can
only define him as either ready for an activity or so disabled that there is no other
solution than a disability pension. After several years of trying to change his
situation, this has left David in a state of resignation:

D: It is just like they have put me on a shelf and then I can stay there for a
while.
I: How long has this been going on?
D: It started two–three months ago and will continue for the next three
years. I have threatened them by saying that I will just go out and find a job,
but then I will lose all my financial support for medication and stuff. So I feel
kind of tied up in a way. … It is kind of like when you have fought for a
long time, it is like they counteract you.
I: So you used to fight more?
D: Yes. But now I have sort of given up.

At this stage in his unemployment trajectory, David is frustrated about the lack of
willingness in the system to make a decision about his future, and he now finds
himself shelved with no immediate prospect of being removed or any possibility
of changing the situation himself. He has no other option than to accept his
inability to match the neoliberal understanding of the good citizen and consequently
his inability to change the current situation. He has given up.

Action
A different story unfolds in other parts of the data, both at earlier points in
David’s trajectory and in stages of the other benefit claimants’ trajectories. Here
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberalism Viewed from the Bottom Up 111

the clients make use of an active coping strategy; instead of giving up, they use
their available resources to work through their situation and change for the
better. An example of this is Harry’s story. Harry is in his mid-thirties and is a
part-time father with a daughter. As a former drug addict, he has lived a turbulent
life, and he has struggled with an ADHD diagnosis and negative experiences from
school. However, he managed to complete a formal education as a butcher in his
late twenties. Five years ago, Harry applied for sickness benefits after a stressful
period at work. After the maximum two years on sickness benefits, Harry applied
for social benefits because he still felt unable to work.4
Like David, Harry has found himself in stages in his unemployment trajectory
where he felt like giving up and just leaving his situation up to whatever social
work professional was assigned to his case. However, the last time I met Harry,
he had applied a different coping strategy:

When I got the chance at the butcher’s shop where I am now, … having
been there for a month or so, I was just doing the dishes, and I am a skilled
butcher. I was looking out the window thinking: “Are you standing here
doing the dishes for free, in order to maybe get a job at some point?” and
then I started thinking that the tasks I was given were a bit more random. It
didn’t quite seem they needed me. So at that point I said to my boss: “Listen,
this is not working. It looks too much like every other in-job-training pro-
gram I have attended. I just work for free. It has nothing to do with you, but
I just want a real job.” And then I quit down there. Ehm, and then I con-
tacted my consultant at the Jobcenter. … And then I said to him: “Okay,
from now on, if you are going to find an in-job-placement for me, it has to
be because they are looking to hire someone.” Otherwise it doesn’t make
sense to me. I am 100 percent determined about that.

As this short narrative demonstrates, Harry has expressed his dissatisfaction with
the system and refused to submit to it, but instead of applying David’s coping
strategy, Harry has decided to work through the system. He accepts the fact that
he has to participate in another in-job-training program in order for the Jobcenter
to assess his work ability and the number of hours a week he will be able to work
before he can get out and apply for a permanent position. However, he defines
his conditions for the job consultant. He will not accept enrolment in yet another
program with no prospect of a real job after finishing the program; instead, he
tells his job consultant that if he is to play by the rules of the system, it must be in
a way that makes sense to him. Thus, Harry adopts an action strategy by accepting
the rationale behind the system but insisting that it must be applied on his terms.
Harry’s use of this strategy produces the effect he hoped for. The job consultant
accepts Harry’s terms and soon finds a placement with a boss who has agreed to
hire Harry if he shows up and does his job satisfactorily every day for three
months. According to Harry, this has made an important difference to him:
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

112 Sophie Danneris

I: What difference does it make that there is light at the end of the tunnel
now?
H: Well, this is exactly what I have always sought. This, that now I have a
way. I have the opportunity to do something actively myself to move for-
ward. And that is finally what I have at hand now, so I’ll just catch it with
both hands.
I: Yes.
H: Well, this is the first time in many years that I have had the opportunity
to move forward.
I: As opposed to earlier when you have felt stuck?
H: But that is how it’s been. Well, I haven’t been able to do anything
active to move forward.

In Harry’s case as well as in other trajectories in the data, claimants actually want
to participate and become the good citizens that the neoliberal view praises.
However, the system has built a wall of processes and procedures that target the
unwilling, “bad,” or non-responsive neoliberal client, which actually makes it
difficult to be the good client demanded by the system. Furthermore, the rigid
system processes encourage the job consultant to accommodate demands for
registration as proof of development instead of meeting Harry’s demands. On
several occasions, Harry has tried to take responsibility for his own situation and
gone out looking for employment, but he has encountered a system with rules
and narrow procedures that the claimant must follow before being able to take a
job. As this example illustrates, benefit claimants need substantial resources to be
good neoliberal citizens, or, as Harry puts it, “It takes a lot of effort and resources
to be sick and dependent on the system.”

Adjustment
The third coping strategy identified in the data is adjustment. This strategy
corresponds to a stage in the claimants’ unemployment trajectory where they feel
insecure about what is happening and what is supposed to happen and where they
experience their situation as frozen with them unable to see their options to change
it. Susan presents an example of a benefit claimant using adjustment as her coping
strategy. She is in her mid-forties and lives in a two-bedroom apartment with the
younger of her two daughters. She is a trained and qualified home assistant but has
a very unstable work history comprising various unskilled jobs, educational failures,
and several periods on benefits. Nine years ago, Susan became pregnant with her
youngest daughter. At the same time, she started suffering from severe back pain
while trying to deal with personal problems (divorce, her mother’s cancer, and her
eldest daughter’s depression), and she has not been employed since then.
At one point in her trajectory, Susan finds herself in a situation where the non-
transparency in the system regarding the decisions and actions to be taken in her
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberalism Viewed from the Bottom Up 113

case leaves her agency dependent on the social work professional in charge of her
case. Susan feels as if her life has been put on hold:

My birthday is coming up soon; it won’t be long before I turn fifty and then
I just wonder what I will spend the rest of my life doing, you know? As long
as you don’t have a clear assessment … I just want to figure out where I can
work for the rest of my time, right? There are still things in life that I want
to do with my daughter. But as long as I don’t have any assessment about
where I am in my life, I find it very difficult to find some long-term goals.
So I’ll just wait till tomorrow.

At this stage in her trajectory, Susan has been left so paralyzed that she just waits,
adjusts to the condition of not knowing, and lets the institution take over. When
Susan has tried to take the initiative to do something, she has found herself being
slowed down or completely put on hold due to various circumstances. One of
the reasons, Susan explains, is the continuous replacement of the social work
professional responsible for her case:

Since [name of former social worker] quit it has just been a constant stream
of different social workers, and then you have to start over every single
time – as opposed to having one that you are attached to and can more or
less finish it. I know, as many people tell me, that it is impossible because
they are moved around. But as for me, I just feel that it is very tiresome. I
feel that there will never be an end to this. If I get a new one, she might
look at things differently than the others and then I have to start over again
and again. They might be close to something, where you think that now
something is going to happen, and then I get a new social worker again. This
is probably the worst thing about not getting on with it and just being on
cash benefits. It is that you don’t feel safe and can’t tell … and don’t even
feel that you can trust anyone. Actually I kind of put my life in other people’s
hands and hope that they can help me. Of course I have to help myself, but
in the situation I am in right now, I think that, well, yes, I’ll try the best I
can to figure it out. Right now I just don’t bother anymore. This is where I am
now, so they can just do whatever they want with me.

Susan acknowledges that new social workers are inevitable, but when it happens
several times it has a great impact on her ability to act and change her situation.
Now Susan has moved from progress toward the labor market to a locked situation
where each new shift in social worker moves her further away from a job. In the
above quote, she refers directly to the neoliberal discourse when she says “of
course I have to help myself,” but she finds it very hard to do so when the
institution appears fragmented and becomes a barrier to her progress. In this stage
of her trajectory, Susan wants to give up; even though she tries her best,
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

114 Sophie Danneris

she encounters institutional factors that significantly constrain her situation. As


opposed to earlier stages in her trajectory, she has come to a point where she just
adjusts to the institution, takes no action herself, and leaves the future up to
whatever social worker is currently responsible for her case.

Resistance
During their unemployment trajectories, several of the claimants represented in
the data make use of what I would describe as a resistance strategy in trying to cope
with the consequences of being part of a neoliberal welfare system. Resistance as a
coping strategy is characterized by narratives about the system acting as an oppo-
nent that always challenges and questions the situation and (lack of) resources of the
client. André’s story is an example. He is in his mid-fifties and lives alone in a
small apartment. He is divorced and has three adult children. He has been
working since he was 14 years old, first as an unskilled worker and then for many
years as a truck driver. Eight years ago, André was involved in two work-related
accidents only a few months apart: first, he drove off a cliff in his truck and
second, a hoist broke as he was unloading groceries off a truck. In both cases, his
back was severely injured and, since then, he has not been able to re-enter the
labor market. In the first four years after the accidents, André was eligible for
sickness benefits. However, despite no significant changes in his health situation,
he received notification from the Jobcenter three years ago that he was categorized
as ready for activation and thus no longer eligible except for substantially lower
cash benefits. As a consequence of his re-categorization from sick to “activation
ready,” André had to participate in several in-job training programs to assess his
work ability in different fields.
In André’s view, he has contributed to society for thirty years, paid his taxes,
and been a good citizen, and now, when he is dependent on help from the
system, he feels badly treated and neglected while his problems are not recognized
or not taken seriously:

They keep saying all the time that “you have to do this and you have to try
this and if you … I think you have so many resources.” I am just about to …
I lose my temper when they say resources. I am about to throw up over that
word. I had a lot of resources once. They are not going to fucking sit there
and say that because I have been a blacksmith and because I have been a
lifeguard and have worked in my parents’ business and have been a truck
driver that I have resources. I had some resources once; now I’m broken,
now I have no resources left. And in both my mood and my mind, I am
completely devoid of resources. Sometimes I don’t even have the resources
to enter the shower. It is true! It sounds silly. But it is fucking true. I
have home assistance every Friday. They keep on talking about resources. I
can’t sleep.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberalism Viewed from the Bottom Up 115

At this point in his trajectory, André has no resources due to his injuries and feels
provoked by the neoliberal resource-orientation shaping the Jobcenter’s approach
to his situation:

I can’t figure it out, not at all. Back in the old days, well now I say old days –
it was about fifteen, ten or fifteen years ago – well then you got a disability
pension if you were injured as much as I am. But now you have to work
even though you are injured. Who the fuck decided that? If you know what
I mean? And even if you don’t. And it is not, it is not like the government
says. Then they [social workers] say, when you have been at the Jobcenter
talking to this young social worker, then she says: “It is the government’s
fault.” But which government? I have been fucking sick during three different
government periods, and now the fourth is about to begin.

Like David’s extract, André’s example demonstrates patterns in the data reflecting
a mismatch between reality as perceived by the client and the neoliberal under-
standing of the individual citizen which emphasizes how everyone is capable and
has resources to be realized in the labor market for the benefit of (not least) the
client. In fact, André explicitly states how the resource focus directly leads to
systematic neglect of his severe problems. Unlike David, André resists succumbing
to neoliberal views. However, the result of his coping strategy is similar to the
result of David’s. Even though André fights back and refuses to participate in the
“neoliberal circus,” he is still dependent on it for help and thus must play by
the neoliberal rules to receive his benefits.

Concluding Remarks
This chapter has explored findings from a qualitative longitudinal study of the
unemployment trajectories of twenty-five vulnerable welfare claimants, focusing
on their coping strategies in their day-to-day encounters with the neoliberal
welfare state. As the analysis shows, the consequences of being part of the neoliberal
welfare system are not uniform but can take several different forms, depending on
factors such as the individual client’s situation, available resources, and health.
David’s, Harry’s, Susan’s, and André’s trajectories are unique, but the patterns of
difference between neoliberal policy and lived experience found in the twenty-
five individual trajectories exhibit similarities through time. From this analysis it
can be concluded that the lived experience of some of the most vulnerable
unemployed citizens is neither reflected in univocal neoliberal catchphrases stating
that “everybody is capable” nor in the political rhetoric that portrays unemployed
citizens as resourceful clients able to take responsibility for their own situation.
What seems to be needed is a language that, amongst other things, allows
recognition of the ambiguities in the trajectories of the long-term unemployed
and acknowledgement of the severe problems faced by some claimants. This
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

116 Sophie Danneris

chapter demonstrates how longitudinal qualitative accounts of the experiences of


welfare claimants can be activated in order to critically investigate the relationship
between the perceptions embedded in neoliberal policy and the perceptions of
those it most directly affects.

Notes
1 Translation of description from a Danish municipality: www.aarhus.dk/sitecore/con
tent/Subsites/JobcenterAarhus/Home/Borgere/Uddannelseshjaelp/Aktivitetsparat.aspx?
sc_lang=da
2 The national authority of data management has approved collection and management of
data – and each client has consented to participation, been given full anonymity as well as
the opportunity to withdraw from the study at any time during the data collection period.
3 Several issues, for example the extent of the informants’ problems and the longitudinal
design, raise central ethical questions besides general ethical guidelines like anonymity
and so on. For example the implications of maintaining the researcher–informant rela-
tionship throughout two years and how to deal with the special type of knowledge
gained by following informants through time. These and other ethical issues have been
critically reflected upon elsewhere (Danneris 2016).
4 This reflects Danish legislation on sickness benefits in 2013, which was changed with a
new reform in January 2014 that removed the two-year limitation.

References
Aftaletekst (2013). Aftale om en reform af kontanthjælpssystemet – flere i uddannelse og job.
Copenhagen: Beskæftigelsesministeriet.
Arbejdsmarkedsstyrelsen (The National Labor Market Authority) (2000). Vejledning om
ændrede rådigheds- og sanktionsregler. Copenhagen: Arbejdsmarkedsstyrelsen.
Arbejdsmarkedsstyrelsen (2004). På kanten af arbejdsmarkedet. Copenhagen:
Arbejdsmarkedsstyrelsen.
Arbejdsmarkedsstyrelsen (2010a). Notat. Ny matchmodel – hvorfor og hvordan. Copenhagen:
Arbejdsmarkedsstyrelsen.
Arbejdsmarkedsstyrelsen (2010b). Ny matchmodel. Sådan og derfor. Copenhagen:
Arbejdsmarkedsstyrelsen.
Bang, J. (2002). Arbejdsevnemetode: En teoretisk og praktisk indføring. Copenhagen: Nyt Juridisk
Forlag.
Beskæftigelsesministeriet (Ministry of Employment) (2013). Alle kan gøre nytte – Udspil til en
kontanthjælpsreform. Copenhagen: Beskæftigelsesministeriet.
Braedley, S. and Luxton, M. (2010). Competing Philosophies: Neoliberalism and
Challenges of Everyday Life. In M. Luxton and S. Braedley (Eds.), Neoliberalism and
Everyday Life. Montreal: McGill Queen University Press.
Brodkin, E. Z. (2013). Street-Level Organizations and the Welfare State. In E. Z. Brodkin
and G. Marston (Eds.), Work and the Welfare State: Street-level Organizations and Workfare
Politics. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.
Brown, W. (2003). Neo-Liberalism and the End of Liberal Democracy. Theory & Event, 7(1).
doi: doi:10.1353/tae.2003.0020
Caswell, D., Eskelinen, L., and Olesen, S. P. (2011). Identity Work and Client Resistance
Underneath the Canopy of Active Employment Policy. Qualitative Social Work, 12(1),
8–23. doi: doi:1473325011413629
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberalism Viewed from the Bottom Up 117

Danneris, S. (2016). Ready to Work (Yet)? Unemployment Trajectories among Vulner-


able Welfare Recipients. Qualitative Social Work. doi: doi:10.1177/1473325016672916
Danneris, S. and Nielsen, M. H. (forthcoming). Bringing the Client Back in – A Com-
parison between Government Rhetoric on “Job Readiness” and Experiences of the
Unemployed. Social Policy & Administration.
Elder, G. H. (2011). Life Course: Sociological Aspects. In N. J. Smelser and B. Baltes
(Eds.), International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioural Science. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Goul Andersen, J. (2013). Medborgerskab under pres. In J. Guldager and M. Skytte (Eds.),
Socialt arbejde – Teorier og perspektiver. Aalborg: Akademisk Forlag.
Grinyer, A. and Thomas, C. (2012). The Value of Interviewing on Multiple Occasions or
Longitudinally. In J. F. Gubrium, J. A. Holstein, K. McKinney, and A. Marvasti (Eds.),
The Sage Handbook of Interview Research: The Complexity of the Craft (2nd edn.). Thousand
Oaks, CA: SAGE Publications.
Høgsbro, K. (2012). Social Policy and Self-Help in Denmark: A Foucauldian Perspective.
International Journal of Self Help and Self Care, 6, 43–64.
Høilund, P. (2006), Social Retfærdighed: Udkast til en Retslære for Socialt Arbejde. Copenhagen:
Jurist-og Økonomforbundets Forlag.
Holstein, J. A. and Gubrium, J. F. (2003). Inside Interviewing: New Lenses, New Concerns.
Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE Publications.
Juul, S. (2010a). Solidaritet – Anerkendelse, Retfærdighed og god Dømmekraft: En Kritisk analyse
af Barrierer for Sammenhængskraft i Velfærdssamfundet. Copenhagen: Hans Reitzel.
Juul, Søren. (2010b). Solidarity and Social Cohesion in Late Modernity: A Question of
Recognition, Justice and Judgement in Situation. European Journal of Social Theory, 13,
253–269.
Koivisto, J. (2007). What Evidence Base? Steps towards the Relational Evaluation of Social
Interventions. Evidence and Policy: A Journal of Research, Debate and Practice, 3(4), 527–537.
Larsen, C. (2015). Universalisme og befolkningens opfattelse af “de fattige” og “de
arbejdsløse” [Universalism and the citizens’ view on “the poor” and “the unemployed”].
In C. Larsen and J. Andersen (Eds.) Den universelle velfærdsstat. Funktionsmåde, folkelig
opbakning og forandring (pp. 119–130). Copenhagen: Saxo.
Lipsky, M. (2010). Street-level Bureaucracy: Dilemmas of the Individual in Public Services. New
York: Russel Sage Foundation.
Lødemel, I. and Moreira, A. (Eds.). (2014). Activation or Workfare? Governance and the Neo-liberal
Convergence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Naples, Nancy A. (1998). Bringing Everyday Life to Policy Analysis: The Case of White
Rural Women Negotiating College and Welfare. Journal of Poverty: Innovations on Social,
Political & Economic Inequalities, 2, 23–53.
Neale, B. and Flowerdew, J. (2003). Time, Texture and Childhood: The Contours of
Longitudinal Qualitative Research. International Journal of Social Research Methodology, 6,
189–199.
Patrick, R. (2014), Working on Welfare: Findings from a Qualitative Longitudinal Study
into the Lived Experiences of Welfare Reform in the UK. Journal of Social Policy, 43,
705–725.
Schram, S. F. (2015). The Return of Ordinary Capitalism: Neoliberalism, Precarity, Occupy.
New York: Oxford University Press.
Schram, S. F. and Silverman, B. (2012). The End of Social Work: Neoliberalizing Social
Policy Implementation. Critical Policy Studies, 6, 128–145.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

118 Sophie Danneris

Socialministeriet (2001). Arbejdsevnemetode. Metode til beskrivelse, udvikling og forbedring af


arbejdsevne. Copenhagen: Socialministeriet.
Soss, J., Fording, R. C., and Schram, S. F. (2011). Disciplining the Poor. Neoliberal Paternalism
and the Persistent Power of Race. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Triantafillou, P. (2012). Decentralization as the Exercise of Power and Autonomy: The
Case of Danish Employment Policy. Journal of Political Power, 5, 55–71.
Verd, J. M. and López, A. M. (2011). The Rewards of a Qualitative Approach to Life-
Course Research. The Example of Effects of Social Protection Policies on Career Paths.
Forum: Qualitative Social Research, 12(3). Available from: www.qualitative-research.net/
index.php/fqs/article/view/1753
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

7
NEOLIBERAL TALK
The Routinized Structures of Document-Focused
Social Worker–Client Discourse

Maureen T. Matarese and Dorte Caswell

Routinization has increasingly become a way for front-line practitioners to make


unwieldy caseloads manageable (Lipsky 2010 [1980]). A common tension in
modern day social work, the tension between responsiveness and standardization
(Hjörne, Juhila, and van Nijnatten 2010), in part surfaces through the use of
routines that standardize practice, some argue, at the expense of more personal,
individualized service (Abramovitz and Zelnick 2015). While routines are an
enduring part of bureaucratic practice in general (Lipsky 2010 [1980]), the advent
of neoliberal ideology and its attendant institutional manifestations (New Public
Management and New Managerialism) has forced routines to do double duty
(White, Hall, and Peckover 2008). Thus, they persist in helping practitioners
manage heavy caseloads, while also integrating a business purpose to routine
work. Routine documents still record client information but also serve to measure
performance and ensure accountability. Book contributor Jamie Peck (2010) has
suggested that “the ontology of neoliberalism” involves “an evolving web of
relays, routines, and relations” (p. 34).
Soss, Fording, and Schram (2011) have found that the business model is alive
and well in the organizational culture of Florida’s Welfare Transition program,
observed in the “norms and worldviews of street-level workers” (p. 199). While
extensive research exists on neoliberalism as it manifests globally, nationally,
locally, institutionally, we know very little about how it functions in front-line
talk with clients, and yet discourse analytic studies have had dramatic impact on
institutional practice (Heritage, Elliott, Beckett, and Wilkes 2007; Waring
2011). This chapter will take a closer look at how neoliberalism and more
specifically New Public Management (NPM) works on a micro level in talk
between social workers and homeless clients at the front line of policy
implementation.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

120 Maureen T. Matarese and Dorte Caswell

Neoliberalism at the Front Lines


Neoliberalism often institutionally manifests itself through New Public Manage-
ment (NPM), which organizes and manages non-businesses according to business
principles (Diefenbach 2009). Soss et al. (2011) suggest “new public management
[has] been deployed as [a] neoliberal response to … challenges of [organizational]
coherence and accountability” (p. 207).
The term “new managerialism” is often used synonymously with NPM, particu-
larly when institutions do not take an expressly NPM approach. According to
Abramovitz and Zelnick (2015) new managerialism is the second of three stages
of privatization, “import[ing] market philosophy and business principles into
non-profit organisations” (Abramovitz and Zelnick 2015, p. 121). These
approaches, while promising transparency, efficiency, and equal treatment, are
critiqued for routinizing practices at the expense of client voice, a loss of prac-
titioner–client relationships, and practitioner stress and burn out (Abramovitz
and Zelnick 2015).
This chapter explores the neoliberal discourses of front-line social workers
and their clients in an urban US homeless shelter. Following Lipsky (2010
[1980]) we argue that these front-line practitioners implement policy in their
everyday work with some discretion, and like Brodkin (2011) we situate street-
level bureaucrats within new managerial institutional space, “highlighting how
new forms of process regulation and managerial structures adjust the behaviour of
the street-level worker through incentive structures, sanctions, and regulations”
(Matarese and Caswell forthcoming, 3). We examine street-level bureaucratic
practice as it exists within an NPM institutional space, acknowledging the influ-
ence of neoliberal principles that dramatically shape talk between caseworkers and
clients.
We focus primarily on routinization specifically through the integration of
documentation and forms into social work interactions. Street-level bureaucrats
“develop routines to deal with the complexity of work tasks” often “because of
the scarcity of resources relative to the demands made upon them” (Lipsky 2010
[1980], p. 83). Routines and particularly documentation within new manage-
rialism not only serve a record-keeping function; they also measure performance
by recording accountable actions and completed goals. The tension between
being responsive to client individual needs and maintaining a common standard
of equal treatment is a central dilemma in social work (Hjörne et al. 2010), and
making required documentation an interactional routine in practitioner–client
meetings serves the interests of time and efficiency.
Discourse analytic approaches to neoliberalism are still scant. Many approaches
focus on the analysis of policy (Fairclough 2000), institutional website and pub-
lications (Urciuoli 2010), textbooks (Gray 2012), and keywords (Holborow
2012). Several scholars examine neoliberalism as it is socially constructed in
moment-to-moment talk. Gray and Block (2012), for example, have begun to
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberal Talk 121

examine neoliberal talk in the classroom. In probably the most dramatic example,
Matarese (2012) describes how caseworkers’ interaction with long-term staying
clients compares to talk with short-term staying clients and undocumented clients,
revealing that undocumented clients are discursively treated like long-term clients,
notwithstanding the length of their shelter stay. Both long-term and undocu-
mented clients endure extensive in situ references to neoliberal ideology, including
invocations of increased individual responsibility, accountability, efficiency, and
speed to goal completion.
However, seemingly few scholars have examined how the very structure of
participant turns at talk can reveal an adherence to neoliberal ideology. Matarese
and Caswell (2014) show how accountability is socially, interactionally constructed
in social work, exposing neoliberal ideologies at work. Matarese (2009) describes
how responsibility and accountability are constructed between caseworkers and
clients, highlighting that responsibility and accountability are not uni-directionally
foisted upon the client but function reciprocally: the responsibility and accountability
of the client generating accountability for the social worker, both of whom are
held accountable by administration.
NPM-initiated standardized formats are not solely a phenomenon of the
United States, but have been analyzed in numerous social work contexts
(Høybye-Mortensen 2015). White et al. (2008) have examined an NPM compu-
terized documentation system using discourse analysis. They argue that although
the form limits the possible narratives, social workers worked around the form’s
narrowness. However they find that the dual use of the form for referral as well as
for assessment purposes was problematic. In a Danish context NPKM standardized
formats have been implemented with unemployed hard-to-place adults, which
has been criticized from a practice perspective as well as in research (Caswell,
Marston, and Larsen 2010). In a worldwide era of NPM and neoliberalism
combined with an increasing reliance on computerized forms of documentation,
this study contributes to a growing literature on documentation paying specific
attention to micro elements of social work practice.
This chapter examines the use of documentation during caseworker–client talk
in an urban American homeless shelter. While we find evidence of managerialism
and ergo neoliberal principles, we identify positive and negative consequences of
the presence of documentation, routines, and standardization. We argue that
form-driven interactions provide limited space for client narrative and extended
participation, but they are transparent to the client. While some interactions do
have space for extended talk, these are characterized by being less transparent for the
client. Our conversation analysis of pauses in particular illustrates the participatory
presence of paperwork in practice. To this end, we pose the following broad
research question: To what extent is documentation present in these interactions,
and to what end? We consider this question in light of how documentation
functions in collaboration with other neoliberal, NPM tenets: efficiency and its
close cousin, speed.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

122 Maureen T. Matarese and Dorte Caswell

Research Context
Responding to record numbers of homeless individuals on the streets and in city
shelters in 2003, a northeast metropolis in the United States created a plan to
drastically reduce those numbers, initiating a plan that included stricter standards
for assessment and accountability and increased responsibility for staff and clients
(DHS 2002, 2004).
Caseworkers facilitated client movement through the system from entry to
departure, coordinating with other city agencies to ensure clients had a stable
legal income prior to housing placement. Three meetings, two toward the
beginning and one toward the end of shelter stay, relied heavily on documents
and forms as a conversational blueprint. Usually the first meeting between a case-
worker and client included an intake assessment, which included basic biographical
information, including the reasons why the client was homeless, relatives with
whom he could live, and so on. Often the second meeting included the psycho-
social assessment, which included the psychological history of the client, as well as
social issues that may be barriers to housing. The housing application was developed
toward the end of a client’s shelter stay and, like those previously described, utilized
the application’s questions as conversational cues.
Check-in meetings did not follow any set series of questions, and while they
often concluded with filling out and signing an Independent Living Plan (ILP),
they allowed, as we will see, conversational flexibility of a sort. The ILP constituted
a contract between the client, the caseworker, and the shelter, providing legal
support for the client responsibility policy in cases in which clients were unable to
complete the minimal actions necessary to move from shelter.

Methodology
This research is part of an IRB-approved, nine-month institutional interactional
ethnography of a city shelter, involving the audio-recording and observation of
eighteen caseworker–client dyads (including six caseworkers and eighteen clients),
totaling fifty-four audio recorded interactions over nine months. The principal
investigator (PI) observed and recorded meetings with clients from shelter entry
until housing placement. She took field notes and conducted interviews with all
clients at the beginning, middle, and end of their shelter stay and with caseworkers
at the beginning, at a mid-point, and at the end of fieldwork. All meetings were
transcribed using Jefferson (1984) conventions, which uses font formatting and
symbols to represent talk how it sounded. All participants gave informed consent
in the language of their choice prior to the first meeting and were able to
withdraw from the study at any time for any reason. All names were given
pseudonyms and other personal data (names of centers, shelters, social security
numbers, etc.) were rendered unrecognizable. The IRB protocol signed by all
participants stipulates that research and analyses have no bearing whatsoever on
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberal Talk 123

the employment, probation, or promotion of case managers or the placement or


sanctioning of clients.
We used discourse analysis (of language in context) and conversation analysis
(of participant turns at talk) to examine the transcribed interactions. These qualitative
approaches stem from social constructionism and ethnomethodology. The former
argues that meaning is socially constructed in situ, and the latter examines the struc-
tures and rules of society, which are observable in the satisfaction of them and in
the breach of those rules (Garfinkel 1967). Together, these provide a window
into the structure of talk, and the circulation of related concepts that collaborate
with and enhance that structure. Brodkin and Marston (2013) suggest that:

a political-organizational view puts [Street-Level Organizations] at the center


of analysis, offering a different perspective on how welfare states work. It
links the micropolitics of SLOs to the macropolitics of the welfare state: it’s a
ways of seeing big by looking small.
(p. 18)

While we do not generalize to anything as broad in scope as “the welfare state”


or even “the shelter system,” we hope by looking very small indeed that we may
provide evidence of the presence of neoliberalism not just in words but in how
those words are organized and presented in talk. If policy is implemented in the
everyday practice of street-level bureaucrats, then the talk of this practice should
tell us how that policy is being implemented, more specifically; thus showing, as
Morpheus so aptly says in The Matrix, “how deep the rabbit hole goes.”
The excerpts provided in this chapter illustrate discourse practices that cut
across the data sample, evolving from iterative analyses of the data rather than a
priori, hypotheses-driven positions. Routinization of social work interaction
through documentation is best revealed through analyses of preference structure,
pauses, and word choice. Preference structure explores turns at talk: turn type
(questions, answers, promises, requests, etc.), normative turns (Sacks 1992). Turns
that violate prior expectation are called “dispreferred” responses; those that satisfy
expected turn structure are “preferred.” Pauses in talk can signal hesitations, sug-
gesting upcoming conversational trouble. Cohesion and coherence analysis allows
us to explore word choice, particularly the clustering, or collocation, of related
words and ideas, as well as how they are carried from one meeting to the next
(Halliday and Hasan 1976).
While the client is a participant in these interactions, the nature of institutional
interaction strengthened by documentation places the role of questioner with the
caseworker, putting her in control of question topics and the routine itself; as
such we place more focus on the caseworker who implements this documentation
in her everyday practice.
We make no generalizations about policy implementation across the country,
state, city, or even within the shelter system as a whole. Rather we wish to
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

124 Maureen T. Matarese and Dorte Caswell

highlight the utility of discourse and conversation analyses as methodologies for


analyzing the production of neoliberal discourses in everyday, seemingly mun-
dane institutional talk.

Document-Focused Routine Talk


The first two excerpts come from talk that uses documents and forms as con-
versational blue prints. The following is taken from an intake assessment interac-
tion and is representative of most intake assessments the PI observed. The
caseworker (CW) meets the client (C) for the first time, explaining the intake
assessment and completing it.

Excerpt 1: Intake Assessment

1. CW: (laughs) Okay, so today I’m meeting with you- close the door for me?
2. C: XXXX
3. today I’m meeting with you to do your long intake basically it’s a set of
questions I’m gonna
4. ask you, about yourself, so I can put it on pa:per, umm, (.) then, (.)
we’ll get into your independent
5. living pla:n which I’ve already constructed so we don’t- I don’t waste
too much of your ti:me I’m
6. already (.) ahead of the game I’m a little prepared for you today, umm so
we’ll go over this, (.) I’ll
7. ask you the questions you answer as honestly as possible I’ll write it
down, (.) as quick as possible
8. and we’ll try to get through this as quick as possible, okay? (.) you have
medicaid?
9. C: °yeah°
10. CW: are you single, divorced, married,
11. C: Single
12. (2.4) ((CW writing))
13. CW: thank you ((to another caseworker))
14. (.9)
15. CW: umm, you’re not a veteran are you? Have you ever been in the army, navy,
16. (.)
17. C: army? no. In my country yes not here.
18. CW: do you have your PA- you don’t know your PA case number, do you?

Two patterns in the data emerge from this excerpt: documentation-centric talk and
the clustering of language around documentation, efficiency, and brevity, illustrating
not only routinization but also the business model and its principles at work.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberal Talk 125

After introducing the procedure for the day, the case worker defines it, making
herself the agent who questions and the client the object of the questioning.
Practitioner-initiated question–answer sequences are common in institutional
interaction. The interactional preferences are clarified in advance here. The
questions begin in line 8 and continue to line 18 and beyond.
The caseworker, in saying “so I can put it on paper” (line 4), signals the result
of this intake question–answer sequence. She brings the bureaucratic necessity of
the paperwork to the foreground, “so” illustrating the result of the talk. Likewise,
in line 7 she articulates the process: she questions, he answers, she writes it down,
integrating the bureaucratic process into the interaction (as illustrated in lines 10–
12 where it follows the aforementioned organization).
New managerialism often emphasizes efficiency and speeding up (Abramovitz
and Zelnick 2015), which here are indicated through “not wasting time” (line 5),
which she pitches as saving the client’s time, and “as quick as possible” (lines 7, 8).
Moreover, the caseworker offers her prior write-up of the client’s service plan
(ILP) as a signal of preparedness and efficiency. The construction of service plans
is meant to be collaborative; however, in the first several meetings some pre-
construction makes sense as all clients take the same early steps toward housing at
the shelter (getting a tuberculosis test, getting a psychiatric evaluation, acquiring
public assistance or other legal means of income). Ritzer (2007) suggests that
speed and efficiency are part of “McDonaldization,” the treatment of non-busi-
nesses (e.g. schools, hospitals) like fast-food businesses. The emphasis on speed
and efficiency here are perhaps, like routines, part of the caseworker’s need to
manage a large caseload. On the other hand, speed and efficiency, like doc-
umentation, have a dual function: to assist the caseworker in maintaining a certain
level of performance, on which she will be assessed.
Finally, the pause in line 12 should not go unaddressed. When a question is asked,
the normative, or preferred, response is to answer, and when a lengthy pause pre-
cedes an answer it is usually a signal of upcoming interactional trouble (Pomerantz
1984; Sacks 1992; Schegloff 2007). In line 12, however, the pause precedes the
caseworker’s next question, indicating instead the participation of the documentation
as a silent actant (Latour 1999) that shapes the interaction by being present.
The second excerpt, from a housing application meeting, includes many of the
same discourse practices. The excerpt begins after general greetings.

Excerpt 2: Housing Application

1. CW: ((to herself)) no medications. ((to client)) okay, what I’m >filling out here<
is your housing application.
2. C: for [°housing alright°]
3. CW: [housing](.) okay? we gonna try to find you somewhere to live. (.) quickly.
4. C: quick (.) rapido
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

126 Maureen T. Matarese and Dorte Caswell

5. CW: rapido.
6. C: hehh
7. (.65) ((caseworker types already known information in his housing
application))
8. CW: You don’t take no medications right?
9. C: °mm°
10. CW: no medications,
11. C: °yeah°
12. (.8) ((typing))
13. CW: (sighs)-kay
14. (.)
15. CW: Do ya ever use drugs?
16. C: No
17. CW: drug?
18. C: drug? No

As in the prior excerpt, this one begins with an introduction to the application
sequence, (lines 1, 3) although it excludes a description of the interactional rules
(question–answer sequences). Notwithstanding an introduction to the rules, the
caseworker leads the client through a series of questions (lines 7, 10, 15, 17)
requiring answers (9, 11, 16, 18). As the client speaks Spanish as his first language,
the caseworker restates some questions (lines 10, 17). Moreover, the extended
pauses (lines 7, 12) and the micropause (line 14) once again signal the presence of
the document as a silent participant, as the caseworker fills out the form. Line 7 is
a particularly long silence left open by paperwork. The complete silence here
highlights once again the participation of the paperwork.
Routinization, a common coping strategy for street-level bureaucrats, is a
double-edged sword, offering benefits and drawbacks. On one hand, both the
intake assessment and housing application meetings show talk that is controlled by
the caseworker’s questions, which almost entirely are derived from required
paperwork. The result is limited possibilities for client participation; short answers
are preferred. Efficiency and brevity are valued, as the caseworker says “quickly,”
“rapido.” One may once again be reminded both of Lipsky’s (2010 [1980]) sug-
gestion of efficiency and routine as a strategy for coping, as well as of the
McDonald’s drive through. Nevertheless, what participation is required is made
transparent from the beginning of the meeting. These routinized meetings are
compared with another meeting that uses a form: the ILP meeting.

More Flexible, Routinized Talk


ILP meetings, in contrast, do not begin with an introduction to the paperwork
and interactional structure. Rather they function like casual check-up meetings,
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberal Talk 127

tailored to the individual concerns of the client and his unique barriers to housing.
As a result, the conversation provides extensive space for client talk, shown here
in italics. This excerpt is taken from the middle of a typical ILP meeting. These
meetings conclude with filling out an ILP form, which will be addressed further
in excerpt 4.

Excerpt 3: ILP Interaction

1. CW: What are you doing to try to get up outta here, Michael?=
2. C: =What am I trying to do right now? (.) I’ve been very, very busy.(.)That’s one.(.)
Two, the guy
3. that I was working with as a driver, you know the driver that was working with me,
(.) he got
4. fired. He got arrested, (.) because he was stealing money. He was doing embezzle-
ment, so
5. I now, ’m doing my truck (.) my route and helping the guy that’s driving also do his
route. So
6. that’s why,=
7. CW: =are you driving now?
8. C: I wish I was. I don’t have my license. (.6)But been trying to, you know, trying to
find
9. another driver, to do my route, that way, I don’t have to be working two, two trucks.
You
10. knowthat way the guy that’s dri- that’s doing my route he could concentrate on his
own route
11. not do my route and his route. That’s the problem there.
12. CW: How much money you making? Are you saving [any money?]
13. C: [Umm]I’m not saving nothing what I’m
14. making is sh- shit ’at’s why I’m pissed off, because I’m doing double work (.) and
they’re not
15. paying me.(.) I even took a whole week off, you know, I even told ’em look, you
know, that’s
16. I how frustrated I was. I was so frustrated that, you know,(.) I’m busting my ass
helping them
17. out, and you know, they don’t treat me like, you know, like shit? No fuck that. But
who
18. come out losing? me.
19. CW: °Alright°. (.) What do you want to do to get outta here? Yeah, what are we
doing=
20. C: What do I want to do to get outta here (.)I’m trying to do anything. (taps
bottle on hands)
21. CW: Anything like what Michael.
22. C: Whatever’ what-
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

128 Maureen T. Matarese and Dorte Caswell

23. CW: Are you on public assistance?


24. C: Well, they’re only giving me food stamps.
25. CW: Why?
26. C: I don’t know.
27. CW: Have you opened a full PA Case?
28. C: I did I I I I’m still- I passed the 45 days. and then (.) they haven’t sent me
no letters or
29. anything.
30. CW: Okay, I’ll check tomorrow and see what’s going on with that status, okay?
=
31. C: =Okay.

As mentioned above, this excerpt includes three lengthy narratives (lines 2–6, 8–11,
and 13–18), allowing the client to relate his experiences working with a delivery
truck. Notably, while client narratives exist, they are initiated by caseworker questions
(lines 1, 7, 12). Her question of saving money (line 12), for example, is a commonly
asked, required question of all clients, necessary for ascertaining a client’s legal income
and preparedness for housing. Thus, even the more casual ILP interactions are still
guided by caseworker questions, maintaining a level of conversational asymmetry.
These extended narratives, during ILP meetings, end with the filling out and
signing of the ILP form. Excerpt 4 is taken from the end of an ILP meeting when
the caseworker introduces the paperwork and fills it out with the client.

Excerpt 4: Conclusion of ILP Meeting

1. CW: I’m gonna do a service plan on you. (.) It’s gonna say reactivate public
assistance, it’s
2. because you need to get your PA back on. because it’s off, (.) follow shelter
rules and
3. regulations, and attend case management meetings with me (.)
4. and I’m gonna be working a lot closer with you now (.) in order to- so
5. we can try to move you outta here, okay?
6. C: (nods)
7. (.34)
8. CW: you need a new psych.
9. C: hmm?
10. CW: you need a new psych. (.) a new psych.
11. (1.70) ((filling out paperwork for psychiatric evaluation))
12. CW: °seven°(mumbles date under breath)
13. (1.50) ((typing))
14. CW: So what do you do during the daytime?
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberal Talk 129

15. C: Hmm?
16. CW: What are you doing in the day now?
17. C: In the day?
18. CW: Yes
19. C: Looking for job. In the city.
20. (3.10) ((typing))
21. CW: So this is your new service plan. For this month, alright? Because you told
me that you
22. don’t have no (.) public assistance I included that in this in this
month you trying to
23. activate your public assistance with them because you need to reopen it in
order for us
24. to find you any type of housing for us to do any type of assistance right
now your
25. public assistance case is closed.
26. C: Right
27. CW: you need a new psych- psychiatric evaluation cause you had one- it’s been-,
you need a
28. new one. okay? so I’m going to schedule you for that.
29. C: a new, right?
30. CW: A new one. I have one but we need another one, cause you’ve been here
three months
31. it’s time.
32. C: three month?
33. CW: yeah every three months you gotta get one of these. Follow shelter rules and
34. regulations, attend case management meetings and reactivate your public
assistance.
35. C: Alright
36. CW: Everything that’s highlighted in the front we’ll discuss here at the back.
Client must
37. Maintain (.) benefits, entitlements, this is basically going to XXX, getting
your PA
38. check turned back on I referred you already I already set up the appointment
that’s how
39. I did all of that. (.) you’ll keep the appointment made for you, You will comply
40. with all the criteria for public assistance in order to get it on, you’ll being all
41. documentation your referral letter, and so forth and so forth, okay?
42. C: Right
43. CW: Follow shelter rules and regulations, (.) basically every month we have to do
a new
44. service plan and once we do in between the month just to make sure it’s
going okay.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

130 Maureen T. Matarese and Dorte Caswell

45. You must sign for your bed every night. If you don’t sign for your bed
every night,
46. You gonna lose it, you know no fighting [no arguing]
47. C: [yeah yeah ye]ah=
48. CW: =no none of that. alright? Meet with me twice a week-, twice a month at
least.
49. If I need to see you more I’ll send you more appointments. Okay?
50. this is the psychiatric evaluation, you need a psych. I’ll refer
51. you to the psych you keep the appointment with the psych be honest with
the psych
52. and that’s basically it. That’s everything I’ve discussed here is highlighted in
the front.
53. If you have any questions you can ask me I need you to sign it here and
date it there.

This excerpt begins with a phrase used with frequency in this shelter: “I’m gonna
do a service plan on you.” The use of “on” here underlines the asymmetrical
relationship between the agent caseworker and the patient client, putting the
client into a position of passive participation in which the preposition “on,” is
loosely synonymous with “about.” This implies that the client is being written
about, not actively involved in the writing and planning himself.
The prior construction of the service plan, which we also noted in excerpt 1 is
alluded to here as well, as the caseworker states “it’s gonna say reactivate public
assistance.” The use of the present participle (“is going”) signals that the decision
regarding what to include in the ILP has already been decided (line 1–2). Like-
wise she says “because you told me that you don’t have no public assistance I
included that in this month” (lines 21–22). The caseworker indicates here that
she included acquiring public assistance on the ILP because he informed her
during the meeting that he did not yet have public assistance. While the intake
and housing meetings had clear introductions, making them transparent, the ILP
meetings have no introductory sequence, thus obscuring the ways in which client
talk is used in the meeting. Is client talk just to inform the caseworker, or do
client admissions during the meeting turn into goals? The pre-construction of the
ILP, as in excerpt 1, highlights the tension between efficiency and participation,
routinization and individualization. Is the client participating in ILP construction
if he is unaware that meeting talk will be translated into goal posts?
This excerpt also invokes policy language, and the caseworker reads require-
ments to the client verbatim. The client is asked to “follow shelter rules and
regulations” (line 33, 43), “attend case management meetings” (line 44), “maintain
benefits” (line 37), and “sign for your bed every night” (line 45). This clear use of
policy language in the meeting inserts policy directly into the front line. This
direct use of policy language brings the voice of the institution to the foreground
of the meeting space.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberal Talk 131

While the intake and housing meetings revealed routines heavily structured
by required shelter documentation, ILP meetings included more flexible rou-
tines. Without an opening sequence introducing the meeting as one guided by
paperwork, the ILP introduced at the end of the meeting sometimes comes as a
surprise to the client (Matarese, fieldnotes, 2006). Drawing on Brodkin (2011)
and Lipsky (2010 [1980]) we suggest that these ILP meetings reveal the ways in
which policy tools with particular goals have unintended outcomes. In this case
we find a lack of transparency regarding the relationship between what is shared
in the meeting and the paperwork introduced at the conclusion of the meeting.
While over time a client’s exposure to this approach may clarify the routine con-
siderably, long-term clients with experience became frustrated and/or surprised
with the relationship between their sharing and the goals set at the terminus of
the meeting.

Flexible, Less Routinized Talk


In this final excerpt, we present an example of an interaction that is in no way
guided by paperwork. While it includes examples of neoliberal discourses, we
focus primarily on the stark shift in the turn type. This meeting begins with the
caseworker asking the client to explain himself after a case conference (group
session to help a client) turned verbally hostile.

Excerpt 5: Flexible Space for Discussion

1. C: All the time I’m going there they say the sa:me thing. blah
2. blahblahblahblah. Oh [Mayor], yeah. It ain’t
3. [Mayor]. (.) Come on. I ain’t jum- you- they got
4. you jumping through hoops, I ain’t jumping through no hoop.
5. CW: Okay, well unfortunately. This is my job, so I have no
6. [choice
7. C: [I’m not talking about you.
8. CW: hhhhhhh ((laughs))
9. C: I’m talking about her,=
10. CW: =right,
11. C: C: Cause the pressure’s on her, right?=
12. CW: =right [the pressure’s on basically all of us.]
39. C: mm-hmm
40. CW: So we have to put the pressure on you guys unfortunately
41. you’ve been here for nine months, so: now the pressure’s on.
42. it’s not like you’ve been here for si:x,=
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

132 Maureen T. Matarese and Dorte Caswell

Notably, there are no question–answer sequences in this excerpt. Rather this


excerpt begins with a client-initiated critique of the city’s mayor (lines 1–4). He
makes a bureaucratic metaphorical reference (line 4), rejecting his engagement in
the bureaucracy of the institution. The client suggests that the shelter adminis-
tration is receiving pressure from the city (line 11), posing the suggestion as a
question, and thereby flipping the normative question–answer script for these
interactions. The caseworker answers (line 12), suggesting that everyone (“us”) is
under pressure from the city. The “pressure” here obliquely refers to performance
measures required of all caseworkers (“us”), the term “the pressure” obscuring
and generalizing the source of the pressure.
This “pressure” links both textually to time-based performance benchmarks
(line 41–42) but also intertextually to references regarding speed and efficiency
across earlier excerpts, confirming that speed and efficiency, while general coping
strategies they may be, are also connected to NPM and neoliberal ways of
thinking. The interaction is a collaborative enterprise, as they together create a
narrative describing pressured conditions at the shelter. Their narrative is closely
linked to time as a measure of performance and thus part of language of new
managerialism focusing on efficiency and speeding up (Abramovitz and Zelnick
2015). Van Berkel (2013) has argued that recent policy developments have not
only made the clients active, but also the professionals at the front line as well as
the organizations implementing the policies. The pressure referred to by the case
worker in the excerpt above is a case of triple activation, making the shelter
organization, the case worker, and the client active in working towards limiting
time spent at the shelter (Van Berkel 2013).

Discussion

Restricted Talk
Documentation created conversational blueprints for verbal interaction between
the caseworkers and clients in intake assessments and housing application meetings,
as well as psychosocial assessments (not shown). Extended client narratives were
rare in the transcripts for these types of meetings, with the one exception “how
did you become homeless,” which could generate a longer answer. Both participants
were constrained by documentation, though the question–answer structure
asymmetrically favored the caseworker. Efficiency through routinization and
brevity was emphasized. Given the emphasis on client-centeredness in social work
(Rogers 1959), conversational asymmetries in these contexts are worth exploring.
There has been some debate about the extent to which social workers can
maintain a “relational and narrative approach” (De Witte, Declercq, and Hermans
2015, 1249) when using computerized systems. DeWitte et al. suggest it is possible.
Our findings do not corroborate DeWitte et al., though there are many other
meetings and moments that are not focused on documentation over the course of
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberal Talk 133

a client’s shelter stay. However, meetings focused around intake, psychosocial,


and housing largely do not contain spaces for narrative and relational work.

Documentation as Participant
Substantial pauses brought attention to documentation as an interactional participant,
albeit an inert one. This finding, in conjunction with question–answer sequences,
highlights the ways in which policy and administration constrain casework practice.
Drew and Heritage (1992) suggest that institutional interaction is marked by an
orientation to “some core goal, task, or identity (or set of them) conventionally
associated with the institution” (p. 22). Participants’ talk is shaped by the orientation
to those institutional norms. The space left in conversation for paperwork reveals
both the caseworkers’ and clients’ orientations to paperwork. The caseworker
refers directly to the paperwork, often quoting it directly, while the client’s
silence while paperwork is filled in is indicative of him waiting for the paperwork
to finish and his next turn at talk.

Flexible Talk and Neoliberalism


Routinization was often collocated with efficiency and speed. The caseworker
used routines to accelerate individual meetings in order to see as many clients as
possible each day. These routinized meetings were transparent, but lacked rich
client participation. In contrast, the ILP interactions were less scripted, including
space for client narratives, but were less transparent. Both appear to have strength
where the other lacks.

Conclusion
Soss et al. (2011), pose the question “does the business model function today as a
dominant ideology, shaping the norms and worldviews of street-level workers?”
(p. 199). Drawing on Goffman (1959), they argue that “if one focuses on the
‘front stage’ of organizational life, where public interactions and self-presentations
play out, the answer would seem to be yes” (p. 199). We, likewise, found that
front-line social worker–client interaction appears to include the ideology at the
turn and word-level. Neoliberal ideology and NPM operate at a structural level
in the meeting talk, by integrating documentation into the structure of interac-
tion amidst a constellation of references to business principles and concepts.
Question–answer sequences in bringing documentation to the foreground reveal
structural routines in those interactions. Words like “as quickly as possible,”
“rapido,” and “I don’t want to waste too much of your time” connect that routine
with efficiency and speed, neoliberal, new managerial tenets (Abramovitz and
Zelnick, 2015). The ILP meetings were likewise constrained by some question–
answer sequences, as compared with the final excerpt, which showed more
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

134 Maureen T. Matarese and Dorte Caswell

client-directed and perhaps insistent talk (Matarese and van Nijnatten 2015). If
policy is indeed put into practice through street-level bureaucrats, then we need
more research detailing the ways in which these neoliberal policies manifest
themselves in front-line service delivery.
Some scholars argue that front-line practitioners who are working in institu-
tions with few resources and “selective” performance benchmarks on which they
are assessed “may go to great lengths to discourage voice, claims making, and the
assertion of rights, avoiding – even suppressing – efforts by individuals to discuss
their needs and life circumstances” (Brodkin and Marston 2013, 29). Evidence
from our study suggests that while we cannot discount the overt and intentional
suppression of client voice by workers (an analysis that would require a focus on
different discourse features), we have shown that the agent of that vocal sup-
pression is, at least in some degree, the required paperwork that together with
performance assessments, benchmarks, and a large caseload makes discursive
deviation from documentation challenging. Future research should consider
exploring more deeply whether and how voice is suppressed in street-level work,
using discourse and conversation analysis as a tool to, for example, look at the type
of interruptions in these meetings, changes of topic, control of topic, and other
language and discourse choices that might convey the suppression of voice.

Appendix: Transcription Conventions (Hutchby and


Wooffitt 2008)
(1.8) Pause. The number represents duration of the pause in seconds, to one
decimal place. A pause of less than 0.2 seconds is marked by (.)
[] Overlap with a portion of another speaker’s utterance.
= Latch: no time lapse between two utterances, used when a second speaker
begins their utterance just at the moment when the first speaker finishes.
: Extended sound.
(hm, hh) Onomatopoetic representations of the audible exhalation of air.
.hh Audible inhalation of air. The more h’s, the longer the in-breath.
? Rising intonation.
. Falling intonation.
, Continuation of tone.
– Abrupt cut off, speaker stops speaking suddenly.
↑↓ Sharply rising or falling intonation. The arrow is placed just before the syllable
in which the change in intonation occurs.
Under Speaker emphasis on the underlined portion of the word.
CAPS Higher volume than the speaker’s normal volume.
° Utterance is much softer than the normal speech of the speaker. This symbol
will appear at the beginning and at the end of the utterance in question.
> <, < > Noticeably faster (>faster talk<), or slower (<slower talk>) than the
surrounding talk.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberal Talk 135

(would) Transcriber has guessed as to what was said, because it was indecipherable
on the tape. If the transcriber was unable to guess what was said, nothing
appears within the parentheses.
(XXXX) Indistinguishable speech.

References
Abramovitz, M., and Zelnick, J. (2015). Privatization in the Human Services: Implications
for Direct Practice. Clinical Social Work Journal, 43(3), 283–293.
Brodkin, E. Z. (2008). Accountability in Street-level Organizations. International Journal of
Public Administration, 31(3), 317–336.
Brodkin, E. Z. (2011). Policy Work: Street-level Organizations under New Manage-
rialism. Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory, 21(suppl 2), i253–i277.
Brodkin, E. and Marston, G. (Eds.) (2013). Work and the Welfare State: Street-level Organi-
zations and Workfare Politics. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.
Buttny, R. (1993) Social Accountability in Communication. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Caswell, D.Marston, G., and Larsen, J. E. (2010). Unemployed Citizen or “at Risk”
Client? Classification Systems and Employment Services in Denmark and Australia.
Critical Social Policy, August 30, 384–404.
De Witte, J., Declercq, A., and Hermans, K. (2015). Street-Level Strategies of Child
Welfare Social Workers in Flanders: The Use of Electronic Client Records in Practice.
British Journal of Social Work. First published online: September 8, 2015. doi:
doi:10.1093/bjsw/bcv076
Department of Homeless Services (DHS) (2002). The Second Decade of Reform: A Strategic
Plan for New York City’s Homeless Services. New York. Retrieved March 2005 from:
www.ci.nyc.ny.us/html/dhs/downloads/pdf/stratplan.pdf
Department of Homeless Services (DHS) (2004). Uniting for Solutions beyond Shelter: The
Action Plan for New York City. New York: New York City Department of Homeless
Services Presses.
Diefenbach, T. (2009). New Public Management in Public Sector Organizations: The
Dark Sides of Managerialistic “Enlightenment.” Public Administration, 87, 892–909.
Drew, P., and Heritage, J. (1992). Talk at Work: Interaction in Institutional Settings (Studies in
Interactional Sociolinguistics 8). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Evans, T. (2011). Professionals, Managers and Discretion: Critiquing Street-level Bureaucracy.
British Journal of Social Work, 41(2), 368–386.
Fairclough, N. (2000). Discourse, Social Theory and Social Research: The Discourse of
Welfare Reform. Journal of Sociolinguistics, 2(4), 163–195.
Garfinkel, H. (1967). Studies in Ethnomethodology. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Goffman, E. (1959) The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life. New York: Anchor Books.
Gray, J. ( 2012). Neoliberalism, Celebrity and Aspirational Content in English Language
Teaching Textbooks for the Global Market. In D. Block, J. Gray, and M. Holborow
(Eds.), Neoliberalism and Applied Linguistics. New York: Routledge.
Gray, J. and Block, D. (2012). The Marketization of Language Teacher Education and
Neoliberalism: Characteristics, Consequences, and Future Prospects. InD.Block, J.Gray,
and M. Holborow (Eds.), Neoliberalism and Applied Linguistics. New York: Routledge.
Halliday, M. A., and Hasan, R. (1976). Cohesion in English. London: Longman.
Harvey, D. (2005). A Brief History of Neoliberalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

136 Maureen T. Matarese and Dorte Caswell

Heritage, J., Elliott, M., Beckett, M., and Wilkes, M. 2007. Reducing Patients’ Unmet
Concerns: The Difference One Word Can Make. Journal of General Internal Medicine, 22,
1429–1433.
Hjörne, E., Juhila, K., and van Nijnatten, C. (2010). Negotiating Dilemmas in the Practices
of Street-level Welfare Work. International Journal of Social Welfare, 19(3), 303–309.
Høybye-Mortensen, M. (2015). Decision-Making Tools and Their Influence on Caseworkers’
Room for Discretion. British Journal of Social Work, 45(2), 600–615.
Holborow, M. (2012). Neoliberal Keywords and the Contradictions of an Ideology. In
D. Block, J. Gray, and M. Holborow (Eds.). Neoliberalism and Applied Linguistics. New
York: Routledge.
Hutchby, I., and Wooffitt, R. (2008). Conversation Analysis. London: Polity.
Jefferson, G. (1984). Notes on Some Orderlinesses of Overlap Onset. Discourse Analysis and
Natural Rhetoric, 500, 11–38.
Latour, B. (1999). On Recalling ANT. The Sociological Review, 47(S1), 15–25.
Lipsky, M. (2010 [1980]). Street-Level Bureaucracy, 30th Ann. Ed.: Dilemmas of the Individual
in Public Service: Dilemmas of the Individual in Public Service. New York: Russell Sage
Foundation.
Matarese, M. (2009). Help Me Help You: Reciprocal Responsibility in Caseworker–
Client Interaction. Paper presented at DANASWAC Conference Gent 20, August
2009.
Matarese, M. (2012). Getting Placed in Time: Responsibility Talk in Caseworker–Client
Interaction. Journal of Applied Linguistics and Professional Practice, 9(3), 319–340.
Matarese, M. and Caswell, D. (2014). Accountability. In C. Hall, K. Juhila, M. Matarese,
and C. van Nijnatten (Eds.), Analysing Social Work Communication: Discourse in Practice.
New York: Routledge.
Matarese, M. and Caswell, D. (forthcoming). “I’m Gonna Ask You about Yourself, So I
Can Put It on Paper”: Analysing Street-Level Bureaucracy through Form-Related Talk
in Social Work. British Journal of Social Work (forthcoming).
Matarese, M. and van Nijnatten, C. (2015). Making a Case for Client Insistence in Social
Work Interaction. Discourse Processes, 52, 670–688.
Maynard-Moody, S. W., and Musheno, M. C. (2003). Cops, Teachers, Counsellors: Stories
from the Front Lines of Public Service. Minnesota: University of Michigan Press.
Peck, J. (2010). Constructions of Neoliberal Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Pomerantz, A. (1984). Agreeing and Disagreeing with Assessments: Some Features of
Preferred/Dispreferred Turn Shaped. In J. Atkinson and J. Heritage (Eds.), Structures of
Social Action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ritzer, G. (2007). The McDonaldization of Society. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications.
Rogers, C. R. (1959). A Theory of Therapy, Personality and Interpersonal Relationships,
as Developed in the Client-Centered Framework. In S. Koch (Ed.), Psychology: A Study
of a Science (Vol. 3). New York: McGraw-Hill.
Sacks, H. (1992). Lectures on Conversation, 2 vols, ed. G. Jefferson. Malden, MA: Blackwell
Publishing.
Schegloff, E. A. (1987). Between Micro and Macro: Contexts and Other Connections. In
J. Alexander (Ed.), The Micro-Macro Link. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Schegloff, E. A. (2007). Sequence Organization in Interaction: Volume 1: A Primer in Conversation
Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Scollon, R., and Scollon, S. W. (2004). Nexus Analysis: Discourse and the Emerging Internet.
New York: Routledge.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberal Talk 137

Scourfield, P. (2007). Social Care and the Modern Citizen: Client, Consumer, Service
User, Manager and Entrepreneur. British Journal of Social Work, 37(1), 107–122.
Scourfield, P. (2015). Even Further beyond Street-Level Bureaucracy: The Dispersal of
Discretion Exercised in Decisions Made in Older People’s Care Home Reviews. British
Journal of Social Work, 45, 914–931.
Soss, J., Fording, R., and Schram, S. F. (2011). The Organization of Discipline: From
Performance Management to Perversity and Punishment . Journal of Public Administration
Research and Theory, 21(suppl 2), i203–i232.
Urciuoli, B. (2010). Neoliberal Education: Preparing the Student for the New Workplace.
In C. J. Greenhouse (Ed.), Ethnographies of Neoliberalism. Philadelphia: University of
Pennsylvania Press.
Van Berkel, R. (2013). Triple Activation: Introducing Welfare-to-Work into Dutch Social
Assistance. In E. Brodkin and G. Marston (Eds.), Work and the Welfare State. Street-level
Organizations and Workfare Politics. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.
Waring, H. Z. (2011). Learner Initiatives and Learning Opportunities. Classroom Discourse,
2(2), 201–218.
White, S., Hall, C. and Peckover, S. (2008). The Descriptive Tyranny of the Common
Assessment Framework: Technologies of Categorization and Professional Practice in
Child Welfare. British Journal of Social Work, 39(7), 1197–1217.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

PART III

The Neoliberal Disciplinary


Regime
Policing Indentured Citizens
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

8
CRIMINAL JUSTICE PREDATION AND
NEOLIBERAL GOVERNANCE

Joshua Page and Joe Soss

In March 2015, the US Department of Justice (DOJ) reported that the city of
Ferguson, Missouri had been operating a “predatory system of government.”
Police were acting as street-level enforcers for a program that used fines and fees
to extract resources from poor communities of color and deliver them to municipal
coffers. Black residents made up 90 percent of those ticketed for public safety
violations and, with the city averaging three warrants per household, fines and
fees became almost-universal experiences for poor, black residents.
Under sharp fiscal pressures, city leaders had chosen to offset revenue losses on
the backs of poor and working-class black residents. The DOJ Report concludes:

Ferguson’s law enforcement practices are shaped by the City’s focus on revenue
rather than by public safety needs. … The City budgets for sizeable increases
in municipal fines and fees each year, exhorts police and court staff to deliver
those revenue increases, and closely monitors whether those increases are
achieved.
(DOJ 2015, p. 2)

Payments were pursued so aggressively that they made up one-fifth of the city’s
entire revenue base in 2013, an 80 percent increase over just two years prior
(DOJ 2015).
To generate sustained revenues, Ferguson officials used criminal justice prac-
tices to construct and exploit long-term financial debts. Even when subjected to
minor fines and fees, Ferguson residents often became ensnared in a perpetual
debt trap that led to new entanglements with the courts, additional fines and fees,
endless payments on interest and, in some cases, debt-based imprisonment – any
or all of which could have ruinous life consequences (DOJ 2015).
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

142 Joshua Page and Joe Soss

“How could this be?” many journalists and public officials asked in shock. The
entire story struck many as deeply un-American, and sharply at odds with how
governance normally works in the United States. Against this view, we argue that
the regime uncovered in Ferguson was no anomaly. Instead, it points us toward
practices that are widespread, longstanding, and worthy of far more critical analysis
than they have received. In this regard, we advance three main arguments.
First, what the DOJ discovered in Ferguson is not exceptional in relation to the
past or present of US governance. Race-, class-, and gender-targeted predation
has been a central and enduring theme in American state and nation building, in the
structure of our political economy, and in the varied forms of social domination that
define American life.
Second, predatory strategies for extracting resources from subjugated communities
shift over time, generally reflecting the broader political rationalities of their era.
Today, they function as an essential but poorly understood element of neoliberal
governance.
Third, predation is more than just a repressive taking of freedoms and resources
from subordinated groups. It is also a productive force that constructs power
relations, subject positions, and terms of civic standing. Among other things, it
produces what we call the “indentured citizen.”
In what follows, we analyze a complex of criminal justice practices that we
conceptualize as predatory, ranging from fine-centered policing to court fees, bail
systems, prison charges, civil asset forfeiture, and beyond. These criminal justice
practices operate today alongside payday loans, subprime auto financing, toxic
credit card deals, for-profit universities, and other efforts to generate revenues by
leveraging the vulnerabilities, needs, and aspirations of subjugated communities
(e.g., Rivlin 2010; Fergus 2017). Indeed, far from being isolated, they reflect
broader shifts in governance that originate and extend beyond the criminal justice
arena itself.
Our aim in this chapter is to clarify the origins, operations, and consequences
of financial predation in the criminal justice field today. The neoliberal era of
governance has been marked by a resurgence and transformation of state predation
on poor communities of color. On one side, we argue that scholars and citizens
will misunderstand state predation in America today if we fail to theorize its
neoliberal character. On the other side, we argue that scholars and citizens will
misunderstand neoliberalism in the USA today if we fail to analyze its distinctive
predatory forms.

Political Economy, Predation, and Contract


To develop these arguments, we begin from a distinction between contract and
predatory conceptions of the state and, more broadly, the political economy. This
contrast is often attributed to Douglass North (1981) and invoked to describe
Charles Tilly’s (1992) “protection racket” model of the resource-extracting state.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Criminal Justice Predation 143

More generally, however, the distinction expresses a contrast between broadly


liberal views of the state and more critical accounts that begin from the state’s role
in structures of domination.
Contract conceptions of the state can be traced back to the European social
contract theorists of the early modern period. They supply the liberal-democratic
image of the state that frames most mainstream studies of US government today.
The contract state is grounded in the consent of the governed. Its officials claim
to be representative of the public, and they are subject to legitimate criticism for
failures in this regard. The contract state fosters economic development in classic
liberal fashion – through establishment of property rights, enforcement of contracts,
investments in collective infrastructure, and so on. It relates to the people in a
manner that is supportive of the liberal equalities of democratic citizenship, on one
side, and the liberal inequalities of market economies, on the other. It funds its own
operations through systems of taxation that are accepted as legitimate preconditions
for these desired arrangements – “the price of civilization” (Sachs 2012).
In contrast, predatory conceptions of the state begin from a conflict perspective.
In this view, resource extraction is a precondition of state making and governance.
First, the need for revenues draws the state directly into expropriative projects and
creates a structural disposition to serve the interests of capital growth and investment
(on which tax revenues depend). Second, although dominant groups may be
subject to effective political opposition, they typically shape state action in ways
that enrich and protect them at the expense of subordinate groups. Third, in the
civic realm, state practices distinguish and empower members of the dominant strata
as the “real citizens,” who are set apart by the civic exclusion and subordination of
other groups.
North’s distinction is helpful for summarizing some very broad contrasts in
theories of the state. But as a framework for understanding concrete relations and
practices, we argue that his account of predation is, in many ways, underdeveloped.
Stronger resources for this task can be found in the writings of scholars who have
been more marginalized in the academy. Beyond the confines of liberal political
economy, particularly helpful historical and theoretical insights can be found in
Black Marxist scholarship interrogating what Cederic Robinson calls the history
of “racial capitalism”; in feminist scholarship on domestic labor expropriation and
social reproduction; and in the burgeoning scholarship on settler colonialism as a
racialized project in liberal societies.
Two points of contrast help clarify the significance of this shift. First, for North
and many other liberal institutionalists, contract and predatory states are opposites.
At a given point in time, a state is, in essence, either one or the other. As a
historical matter, North seeks to explain how institutional changes eventually
banish predation, produce liberal progress, and establish a contract state (see e.g.,
North and Weingast 1989). By contrast, scholars such as W. E. B. Du Bois
(1935) and Manning Marable (1981) shift our attention from the “essential
nature” of the state to a lower level of operations. By focusing on concrete
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

144 Joshua Page and Joe Soss

social relations, they provide guidance for empirical analyses of predatory and
contractual governing practices.
Second, North encourages scholars to ask how contractual institutions work
and, separately, how predatory institutions work. By contrast, scholars such as
Carole Pateman and Charles Mills (2007) advocate investigating their interplay,
asking how the prevailing terms of social contract may presume predation and be
organized around the reproduction and advancement of domination.
Indeed, the entwining of predatory and contractual practices is an abiding
theme in the history of American political and economic development. In the
early Republic, “the growth of a prosperous, liberal democratic society of Anglo-
Americans” was made possible by “a predatory state that financed white liberal
society through its ruthless exploitation of Indian lands and African American
labor” (Young and Meiser 2008, pp. 31–32). Wealth accumulation and national
development advanced through practices of dispossession and work enforcement
targeting Mexicans in the Southwest (Gonzalez 2013; Rana 2010) and through
the extraction of Chinese labor for mining and railroad construction (Takaki
1998; Jacobson 2001). Labor predation operated as well through “bastardy laws,”
which, for most of US history, transformed the children of unmarried parents
(disproportionally poor people of color) into indentured “apprentice laborers” for
white land- and business-owners (Gustafson 2016).
The post-Reconstruction era saw the rise of infamous new predatory practices in
America, from debt peonage and sharecropping to prison industries and convict leas-
ing. Sharecropping practices extracted labor under exploitative market arrangements
secured through inescapable debt. The state held this system in place through laws
forbidding wage competition among landowners, the policing of black “idleness” and
“vagrancy,” brutal violence carried out or permitted by local authorities, and aggres-
sive state enforcement of debtor payments to private creditors (Wright 1997). Like-
wise, in the wake of the 13th and 14th Amendments, crime and punishment became
the basis for a post-slavery system of coercive labor extraction orchestrated by state
authority. In the North, “prison industries” turned carceral facilities into factories, and
inmates into captive labor pools generating private profits. In the South, chain gangs
and convict-leasing contracts were used to reconstruct key elements of the old slavery
and plantation arrangements (McLennan 2008; Oshinsky 1997).
Such practices persisted well into the twentieth century. And by mid-century,
new and varied practices emerged around the construction of hyper-segregated
residential ghettos. Redlining intersected with other state and market practices to
exclude black families from conventional home mortgage markets (Massey and
Denton 1993). As these practices created long-term inequalities of housing and wealth,
they also constructed a powerful opening for predation in the form of contract-
to-deed home purchase markets (Satter 2010). “Urban renewal” initiatives –
decried as “Negro removal” – advanced a new wave of dispossession targeting
black residents of American cities in order to advance state projects and enrich
white investors (Pritchett 2003).
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Criminal Justice Predation 145

The relevant history is too vast to recount here, but this brief discussion suffices
to make our point: Liberal development of civil, political, and social citizenship in
America has been deeply entwined with shifting practices of predation targeted
by race, class, and gender. In many respects, we argue, these practices should be
seen as the pre-history of criminal justice predation today. To say this is to suggest
that scholars misunderstand criminal justice predation today when we view it – as
many do – solely through the narrow lens of crime and punishment. To see the
deeper social and political significance of these criminal justice practices, one must
locate them in relation to broader developments in the American political
economy.

The Neoliberal Character of Criminal Justice Predation Today


The modes of predation carried out through criminal justice practices today share
four key features with earlier regimes of predatory governance in the United
States: First, they are targeted mechanisms of resource extraction, organized by race,
class, and gender, guided by their social and spatial coordinates, and enmeshed in
the reproduction of dominant–subordinate relations. Second, they are pursued by a
mix of state and market actors under enabling conditions defined by government
institutions, laws, and policies. Third, they advance through the construction of
predation opportunity structures – frameworks that convert the needs, vulnerabilities,
and aspirations of subjugated populations into revenue opportunities that can be
leveraged for financial extraction. And fourth, they operate – more successfully in
some cases than others, to be sure – as mechanisms of state building and maintenance
and as bases of accumulation and citizenship for dominant groups.
Now as in the past, however, predation operates as an element of (and thus,
adapts to and reflects) the prevailing political rationality of its era. In the United
States today, we believe this ordering of the political economy is best thought of
as neoliberal in character. Like Wendy Brown (2015) and others, we do not
conceptualize neoliberalism as a break with the past. Neoliberalism is not post-
liberalism. Rather, it is a reweaving of liberalism itself that intensifies some of its
elements at the expense of others. Through the concept of neoliberalism, we aim
to connect the past and present of liberalism – with an eye toward change and
continuity – not to suggest that recent developments are unprecedented.
Broadly speaking, neoliberalism refers to the extension of market rationalities
across an expanding range of social, economic, and political relations. Across fields,
actors are refigured as Homo oeconomicus and positioned in relations of exchange and
competition (Dilts 2011). Today, individuals, governments, nonprofits, and a host
of other actors are all expected to make prudent choices that enhance their own
capacities and lead to a desirable “return on investment” (Schram 2015). Success
and failure, deservingness and moral worth, civic standing and institutional perfor-
mance are all evaluated in ways that turn market criteria into normative ideals or,
conversely, legitimate grounds for condemnation (Brown 2015).
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

146 Joshua Page and Joe Soss

Within the state and across state-led practices, we find that operations in one
arena after another have been redesigned to reflect market principles, service
corporate interests, enforce market participation, and create new arenas for prof-
itable investment (Soss, Fording, and Schram 2011). Thus, reforms since the
1970s have rolled back the market-constraining effects of state regulations and the
welfare state (Harvey 2005; Block and Somers 2014). They have redeployed and
expanded state powers for creating markets, absorbing market costs, marketizing
public endeavors, and pursuing market-supporting disciplinary projects (Wacquant
2010; Peck and Theodore 2012).
At the most basic level, today’s predatory criminal justice practices can be
understood as the convergence of two broader trends in the neoliberalization of
governance. On one side, they have emerged as part of a broader migration of
governmental functions into criminal justice systems. Loïc Wacquant (2010),
Bernard Harcourt (2011), Forrest Stuart (2016), and others have stressed how
police, courts, and prisons have become repositories for diverse social problems
and governmental agendas in recent decades, growing ever more central to govern-
ance in a wide variety of domains. With prisons now the largest public mental
health facilities (Swanson 2015) and police serving as the frontlines for numerous
social interventions (Lyons 2002; Stuart 2016), perhaps the most widely discussed
example concerns the traditional functions of the welfare state. In a similar
manner, the revenue functions of tax systems are now migrating into policing,
judicial, and carceral systems.
On the other side, the turn toward predatory criminal justice practices in local
governance can be seen as part of the broader proliferation of what David Harvey
(2003, 2005) calls “accumulation by dispossession.” Building on traditional
Marxian theories of primitive accumulation (Luxemburg 2003 [1913]; Nichols 2015;
Ince 2016), Harvey’s analysis (2003, 2005) focuses attention on how neoliberalism
rhetorically celebrates free-market exchange but advances through the use of state
and market powers to forcibly expropriate resources from subordinated groups
who are poorly positioned to resist.
At the intersection of these two dynamics, governments and corporations deploy
criminal justice practices today as powerful tools of revenue extraction. Consider the
fines and fees imposed by police, courts, and prisons, which stand at the center of
Alexes Harris’s book, A Pound of Flesh (2016). About 10 million Americans, dis-
proportionately poor people of color, owe about $50 billion in debt due to
criminal justice fines and fees in America today – and make nearly $40 billion in
payments on their legal financial obligations each year (Bach 2015; Lind 2015).
At the courthouse, officials in many states now charge defendants extra fees to
exercise their right to a jury trial, and most states now permit courts to demand
fees from defendants who exercise their right to a public defender. For many of
these defendants, court involvement also results in substantial additional fees
associated with bail. And for those who go to prison, the charges have only just
begun. Today, all fifty states defray prison costs by charging prisoners some form
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Criminal Justice Predation 147

of pay-to-stay fees (Brennan Center 2016). Generally these “user” fees focus on
room and board, but in some states they extend to medical care and clothing
(Shapiro 2016). Beyond the prison walls, probation and parole have also been
restructured to generate revenues for state and local governments. In Massachusetts,
for example, state collections bring in over $20 million per year from monthly
probation fees alone (Massachusetts Trial Court Fines and Fees Working Group
2016).
Nationwide, reports suggest that fines and fees make up as much as 40 percent
of annual revenues in some municipalities. Indeed, in the state of Missouri, Ferguson
is far from the most dependent municipality: Down the road, Pine Lawn brings in
more than 62 percent of its revenue from criminal justice (Better Together 2015).
A lawsuit filed in 2016 by the ArchCity Defenders describes the operation in
nearby Florrisant (Plaintiffs v. The City of Florrisant 2016, pp. 3, 23):

In 2015, the City collected more than $2,300,000 in court fines and fees and
forfeited bond payments, down from [the four preceding years]. The cost to
operate the City’s Municipal Court, by contrast, was budgeted at roughly
$700,000 per year between 2011 and 2015. The City thus netted as much as
$2,200,000 in 2011 and still netted $1,600,000 even in its least profitable
year. The City’s only sources of greater revenue are sales and utility taxes.

Or consider Civil Asset Forfeiture (CAF), a practice that emerged out of the War
on Drugs in the 1980s and expanded in the 1990s. CAF allows authorities to
seize assets they suspect may be connected to a criminal activity. The burden of
proof is then on the owner to show, through a costly court challenge, that the
assets have no criminal history. Between 2001 and 2014, an estimated $2.1 billion
in assets were seized from Americans who were not charged with a crime (Ingraham
2014). In 2013 alone, the police seized assets worth roughly $1.1 billion (Ingraham
2014). An investigative report by The Chicago Reader revealed that from 2009
to 2015 the Chicago Police Department brought in nearly $72 million in cash and
assets through CAF, retaining about $47 million for itself and sharing the rest of the
bounty with the Cook County state’s attorney’s office and the Illinois State Police.
CAF funds were used to finance day-to-day operations and “to secretly purchase
controversial surveillance equipment without public scrutiny or City Council
oversight” (Handley, Helsby, and Martinez 2016).
Surveying this national landscape, Mary Katzenstein and Maureen Waller
(2015, p. 639) conclude that criminal justice institutions today function as a
sprawling system for “taxing the poor” through “government seizure.” Indeed,
Ordower, Sandoval, and Warren (2016, p. 18) argue that in the state of Missouri
revenue functions have become so paramount that many criminal justice practices
now arguably represent the “exercise of the taxing rather than the policing power
of the municipality” and, thus, violate the state’s limits on local adjustments of
taxes. The authors conclude that criminal justice predation has advanced so far
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

148 Joshua Page and Joe Soss

that “the underlying question becomes whether an offender is an offender at all


or merely a target wearing a dollar sign” (Ordower, Sandoval, and Warren 2016,
p. 24). Rewritten as a neoliberal mode of governance, criminal justice operations
today advance “accumulation by dispossession” in a manner that absorbs tax-like
revenue functions – and in the process, reconstructs the criminal justice field itself.
The neoliberal turn may be seen equally in a second set of powerful dynamics:
the predatory uses of criminal justice to create profitable market opportunities and
marketize the state. Policing and punishment have become sites for endless govern-
mental, for-profit, and non-profit efforts to secure moneymaking opportunities.
Indeed, resource extraction from legally entangled groups can fairly be described
today as a site of dynamic innovation, marked by continual efforts to locate or
build new engines of revenue. Through this process, market actors become
lodged in core functions of the state; the state becomes reliant on market actors
whose cooperation must be induced through profits; and market logics and
practices migrate into the everyday operations of public institutions.
Imprisonment in the United States offers a striking example. Today, corporate
prison contracts represent a $5 billion industry in the criminal justice field. The
leading firm Corrections Corporation of America (CCA, recently rebranded
CoreCivic) has been in the prison business since the early 1980s. For three decades,
CCA rode the wave of mass incarceration to remarkable levels of growth and
profit. As continued carceral growth became less certain in recent years, CCA
sought out new opportunities for profit in the area of immigration detention
(Wofford 2014). To extend their market reach, CCA officials then worked to
convert the detention of women and children seeking asylum into a profitable
new market – successfully arguing to the Department of Homeland Security that
detention could function as “an aggressive deterrence strategy” to dissuade future
asylum seekers (Harlan 2016).
Critics often single out “private prisons” run by companies like CCA, decrying
their profit-driven abuses as distinct from practices in “public prisons.” Indeed,
this was precisely the contrast drawn by Obama administration officials in August
2016, when the US Department of Justice announced that it would begin to
“phase out” contracts for the comparatively small number of privately run prisons
at the federal level. Framing the decision as a choice between state and market
institutions – and citing problems related to poor service provision, administrative
costs, and safety and security in the for-profit lock-ups – Deputy Attorney General
Sally Yates explained that “these steps would be neither possible nor desirable
without the Bureau’s superb and consistent work at our own facilities.”
The announcement was a striking piece of political dramaturgy, performing
and shoring up ideological distinctions between state and market. Market profit-
eering is a social problem, it suggested; government prisons offer an alternative we
should embrace as a solution. In reality, however, government prisons today are
shot through with arrangements that generate revenues for a blend of public and
private institutions. Throughout America’s public prisons, for-profit providers
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Criminal Justice Predation 149

prey on captive markets by charging extensive fees to prisoners and their kin for
phone calls, video visitation, care packages, prisoner transportation, banking,
health care, food, commissary, and education. Public facilities routinely contract
out their basic operations in areas such as security, drug treatment, and officer
training. Looking deeper still, one finds that many of the nation’s “public prisons”
are actually designed by private architects, built by private contractors, and
financed with bonds underwritten and purchased by the biggest private banks
(Sorkin 2013). As Christopher Petrella (2016) rightly explained in the Boston
Review: “To believe that Yate’s directive represents a sea change … one would
have to believe in a deep material distinction between ‘public’ and ‘private’ prisons.
In reality, this boundary does not exist.”
Consider, for example, the arrangements that allow prisoners to sustain con-
nections with their families, friends, and broader communities. In most prisons
today, a single telecommunications company is given monopoly control over
phone systems, which they leverage to charge exorbitant per-minute rates for
phone calls to and from inmates (FCC 2015). The annual value of this industry is
estimated at $1.2 billion, generating commissions (or “kickbacks”) of more than
$460 million for public and private carceral institutions per year (Bunn 2015).
Over the past decade, commercial firms have cultivated markets for prison- and
jail-based video interfaces. By arguing that longstanding practices of free, in-
person visitation posed security risks, firms channeled social needs for connection
into more profitable digital formats. Fee-based video visitation is now replacing
free personal visits in many prisons around the country, and JPay Corp has
recently extended the model by introducing the “videogram” – a service that
allows people on the outside to send thirty-second cell phone videos to prisoners
for a fee. JPay maximizes demand for the service by continually sending people
reminders of how much it would mean to their loved one inside to receive a
personalized video. In this manner, gendered ethics of care are leveraged to produce
monetary gains for both JPay and state governments, which receive commissions
from the company.
Such innovations in the criminal justice field frequently mimic the broader
business strategies market firms have developed to pursue what Devin Fergus
(2014, 2017) calls “financial fracking” in poor communities. From payday loans
to furniture rentals, variable-rate credit cards, and subprime mortgages and auto
loans, corporations have devised a remarkable array of predatory techniques that
demonstrate how the limited resources in low-income communities can be
leveraged in profitable ways. In storefronts throughout America’s most dis-
advantaged communities, one finds “service providers” leveraging social vulner-
abilities to move poor people into potentially lucrative contractual arrangements.
Here as in the criminal justice field, companies aggressively charge fees not simply
to cover operating costs but to generate profit streams. These debt-and-interest
schemes are structured so that poor people, without the resources needed to erase
the principal, are compelled to make ongoing payments.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

150 Joshua Page and Joe Soss

In these and other respects, financial predation in the criminal justice arena
mirrors predatory market practices more generally. Working creatively within this
field, a diverse array of public and private actors work creatively to establish new
mechanisms for generating returns on investment. But it is not enough to say that
practical operations in the field today follow a neoliberal logic. It is equally
important to understand how neoliberal political forces and policy agendas
explain, as a historical matter, financialization of the field itself.

A Neoliberal Creation
The financialization of criminal justice practices has grown both wider and deeper
over the past twenty-five years, with a burst of onset in the early-to-mid-1990s
and a period of rapid expansion during the Great Recession that started in 2007.
From 1991 to 2004, prisoners reporting legal financial obligations grew from 25
to 66 percent (CEA 2015). From 1990 to 2014, states charging offenders for
probation and parole supervision rose from twenty-six to forty-four (CEA 2015).
Over this same period, uses of civil asset forfeiture grew dramatically, as did the
rates and levels at which courts imposed monetary bail (CEA 2015).
To explain how these developments emerged, it is helpful to begin with two
insights from scholarship on neoliberalism. First, as Jamie Peck (2010) argues, the
varied forms of neoliberal governance do not emerge from a single master blue-
print but rather through the creative coping strategies of actors on the ground. It
is surely true that some neoliberal reforms began as carefully worked out ideological
agendas. But, as Peck (2010) points out, we have for some time now lived in a
condition of “zombie neoliberalism” in which new developments are driven less
by the dreams of a Friedrich Hayek or Milton Friedman than by the ongoing
need to cope with the disruptions generated by neoliberal policies themselves.
Marketizing reforms repeatedly generate crises, Peck argues, which then create
pressures and opportunities for new rounds of innovation. In this sense, neoliberal
governance advances through efforts to manage what Fred Block and Margaret
Somers (2014, drawing on Karl Polanyi) describe as the instability and unsus-
tainability of utopian, market-fundamentalist schemes. Such coping tactics
reconfigure neoliberal governance, in the criminal justice field as in many others,
but generally in ways that lead to new tensions, problems, and modes of
resistance.
Second, for explanatory purposes, it is important to accurately define a recent
shift in criminal justice predation. As described earlier, it is simply not true that, in
the USA, the 1990s marked the onset of predatory practice in the criminal justice
field. The historical difference is that – from slave patrols to the convict leasing
system and beyond – criminal codes and practices primarily have been used to
facilitate labor extraction. What is more novel in the contemporary scene, and
what must be explained, is the extent to which criminal justice predation has
been financialized.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Criminal Justice Predation 151

Posed in this way, efforts to explain the recent trajectory of the criminal justice
field clearly fit into a broader line of analysis in the study of neoliberalism. Since
the 1970s, a broad array of policy reforms in the United States have financialized
government operations and obligations in piecemeal ways designed to manage
structural contradictions and crises. From this perspective, the financialization of
criminal justice predation appears far less distinctive. Indeed, it reflects what Greta
Krippner (2011) describes as the paradigmatic coping mechanism of neoliberalism:
the dissipation of state crisis through the financialization of state functions and
practices.
To understand the growth of financial predation in America’s criminal justice
systems, one must begin – not inside the criminal justice field itself – but with the
construction of what a 2012 Pew report called “the local squeeze.” In the last
decades of the twentieth century, a number of political and policy developments
combined to produce immense fiscal pressures on local governments. Since the
1970s, neoliberal reforms have devolved a wide range of functions and responsi-
bilities to lower levels of government (Donahue 1999). At the same time, a
number of policy changes combined to deprive local governments of the
resources needed to meet these obligations.
Pro-market reforms concentrated wealth and income at the top of the social
order and shielded corporations and the affluent from taxation (Hacker and
Pierson 2010). After California passed Proposition 13 in 1978, all but four of the
fifty American states imposed restrictions on local governments that further limited
their ability to raise taxes. Local governments borrowed to meet their rising revenue
needs and, through a variety of new bond and credit strategies, took on large
interest-bearing debts that eventually proved tremendously costly in their own
right. And then, when the Great Recession hit, these chronic shortfalls were
transformed into a full-blown fiscal catastrophe. As the housing bubble burst and
the economy went into a tailspin, local governments suffered dramatic declines in
state aid, property taxes, and sales taxes. By 2009, state aid and property taxes
together covered a smaller share of local expenditures than at any time since the
Census began tracking these funds in 1972. Then, in fiscal year 2010, local
governments lost an additional $25 billion in state aid and property tax revenues.
With powerful forces arrayed against raising taxes or federalizing responsi-
bilities, municipalities found themselves in an unsustainable position they had
little ability to change (Ludwig 2015). To understand how they coped, we must
turn to a second leg of our explanation: the racialized politics of criminality and the
pursuit of social order through expanded practices of policing and incarceration that
are signature characteristics of the American neoliberal state (Wacquant 2010).
We need not rehearse here the broad bipartisan political story of the carceral
turn – from the war on crime, through the war on drugs, to broken windows
policing, and the rest. It suffices to note that, by the 1990s, a large and growing
system for policing, adjudication, and incarceration was in place. Moreover, the
1990s was a particularly intense decade of moral panic over “underclass
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

152 Joshua Page and Joe Soss

pathologies,” driven by powerful discourses of social disorder and calls to get


tough on crime and other “bad behaviors.”
Political pressures to crack down on the “undeserving” combined with limited
local control over sentencing, probation, and parole to make it exceedingly difficult
for municipal officials to cope with their fiscal crisis by cutting investments in public
safety and crime management (an austerity-politics response more common for
social services). But the same political pressures that blocked criminal justice cutbacks
offered a uniquely hospitable environment for a different response to fiscal pres-
sures: converting criminal justice systems into revenue streams. In the name of “law
and order,” cities and counties created new violations, added on supplemental
fines, and raised fine levels. In the name of protecting taxpayers from a further
fleecing at the hands of criminals, they piled up fees of all sorts – from pre-trial,
through court appearances, and on to probation and parole. And in the name of
an aggressive war on drugs, they developed and expanded Civil Asset Forfeiture
procedures to seize cash and goods suspected to have illicit origins.
These actions appeared to many as a win-win, a meeting of virtue and necessity.
Local officials were getting tougher on criminals, pursuing public safety more
vigorously, and meeting the community’s significant fiscal needs all in one swoop.
And not surprisingly, financialization of the criminal justice field was an exceedingly
popular idea among the powerful commercial firms who were flocking to govern-
ment in the 1990s as new outsourcing initiatives opened up markets for lucrative
public-private contracts. Indeed, to explain the financial turn in criminal justice,
one must incorporate a third and final element of neoliberal reform: the political
campaign to “reinvent government” by privatizing and marketizing policy practice
more generally.
Because growing fiscal pressures at the local level and the rise of the carceral
state coincided with widespread privatization in American governance, corporations
were presented with attractive new opportunities for profitable investment. The
entry of these firms into the field should be seen – not as a first-order cause in this
context – but as a byproduct of changes in criminal justice that accelerated predation
and shaped its trajectory.
If only fiscal pressures and “tough on crime” agendas had been at work, we
would expect local governments to have pursued only changes that enriched
government and advanced social control – and to have jealously guarded revenues
against market competitors. That, of course, is not what happened. The broader
push to privatize state functions and apply market models to governance directly
financialized the criminal justice field in a number of new ways. Here as elsewhere
in governance, for-profit actors flooded the field, bringing along the conventional
revenue-maximizing focus of market firms and shareholders. Contract-for-payment
and pay-for-performance now became organizing principles of administration.
This development, in turn, changed the contours and culture of the field, filling
criminal justice policy networks with organized actors who pushed payment-
centered innovations. And frequently, these innovations were brokered to ensure
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Criminal Justice Predation 153

that governments would receive a set percentage of revenues generated by market


firms’ new practices – and thus, would support their expansion.

Neoliberal Modes of Legitimation


Critical historical scholarship has interrogated the ongoing challenge, visible from the
outset, of how dominant groups could justify predatory takings while maintaining an
ideological self-image of the USA as a thoroughly liberal contract state. Solutions
came in many forms. White elites deployed the doctrine of Terra nullius, for
example, to deem Native lands “uninhabited and ungoverned” and, thus, existing
in a quasi-state of nature legitimately available for the taking (Pateman 2007;
Bruyneel 2007). During and after slavery, constructions of racial and gender dif-
ference were fashioned and deployed to justify the violent expropriation of labor
and land, and to construct a delimited white-male herrenvolk democracy (Du Bois
1935; Wolfe 2001). Public officials used state laws, policies, and delineations of
citizenship to underwrite and legitimate predation – in ways that made their
violent takings appear (to themselves and other elites) both legal and morally
defensible (Rana 2010; Smith 1997).
Now, as in the past, legitimating discourses of predation reflect and reinforce
dominant governing rationalities. The strength and scope of market fundamentalism
helps us understand why state and market actors operate from a perspective that
makes ongoing criminal justice predation appear permissible, reasonable, and right.
In her powerful analysis of neoliberalism as a de-democratizing force, Wendy
Brown (2015) highlights how this rationality erodes the public nature of state
institutions and any ethos in which public things are seen as held in common and
valued for their commonality. Neoliberalism, she argues, substitutes market
transactions – purchasing, consuming, exchanging, competing – for shared parti-
cipation in common institutions and shared valuation of collective public goods.
Return on investment becomes a critical benchmark for success in all endeavors.
Public institutions strive to cover their own costs in a “self-sufficient” manner and
orient themselves toward publics, increasingly, as producers exchanging goods
with consumers.
Living under this logic, Americans have learned to expect the “user fee” as a
basis for funding public institutions, and to take a skeptical view of arrangements
that enlist us all – even non-users – in underwriting shared institutions through
taxes. The shift toward this consumer-purchasing logic has transformed our public
parks, public health programs, and public universities, reaching deep into the
corners of almost all our public institutions.
State predation in the legal arena is often legitimated on precisely these grounds.
The targets of predation, in this frame, are just the paying consumers of govern-
ment services (Eisen 2015). As a legitimating device, the discourse of “user fees”
works by assimilating predatory practices into normal state operations and equating
predatory targets with the citizen-consumer role normalized by neoliberalism.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

154 Joshua Page and Joe Soss

By contrast, a second legitimating discourse operates by constructing a symbolic


contrast between citizens in full standing and the suitable targets of predation.
The real citizens in this rendering are “taxpayers” who lead “self-sufficient”
lives – those who have earned and deserve a legitimate place as recipients of the
benefits and services associated with the contract state. They are the makers who
have been repeatedly victimized by the takers (the street criminals, the welfare
queens, the undocumented immigrants, and all the rest).
The people paying fines and fees, in this framing, are the civic failures of
neoliberalism who have mismanaged their own lives and refused to take personal
responsibility. These are the latest of liberalism’s others, the underclass “free-
loaders” who disrespect authority and prey on those who “play by the rules.”
When authorities force them to pay up at the courthouse, such people are only
getting what is coming to them. They are paying back the civic debt they owe.
They are finally being forced to pitch in their fair share.
But of course, such figures are more than just the latest of liberalism’s others.
Their specific cultural resonance is rooted in old discourses of race and criminality
that scholars such as Khalil Gibran Muhammad (2010) remind us have been
deeply and distinctively lodged in state institutions and practices throughout
American history. Against this backdrop, lower-class black Americans today are,
in a sense, always-already positioned as suspect figures – likely criminals, or
“takers” in some way, who owe a civic debt that justifies making them pay up.

Indentured Citizenship
As it rewrites the relation of state and market, neoliberalism reconstructs the
political citizen as a marketized subject (Brown 2015; Crenson and Ginsberg
2002). Indeed, many critical studies of neoliberalism interrogate shifts in citizenship
ideals, emphasizing the rise of the dutiful worker-citizen, the consumer citizen,
the managed citizen, the custodial citizen, and more (Wolin 2008; Soss, Fording,
and Schram 2011; Lerman and Weaver 2014). Alongside these forms, criminal
justice predation produces the indentured citizen as a key political figure of the
neoliberal era. The civic position of the indentured citizen is structured by terms
of debt and discourses of indebtedness. Through predation, the indentured citizen
is brought into being as a different kind of governable subject; the state–citizen
relation is rewritten around a market model of creditor–debtor relations.
Financialized criminal justice practices do not simply take through force or
make coercive use of involuntary labor: They generate legal and civic violations
that they then leverage to move individuals into positions of financial obligation.
Through this process, debt itself becomes the marker of a distinctive civic status
rooted in violation of the social contract.
Thus, unlike some earlier targets of state predation, indentured citizens are not
privately owned as chattels and may not experience unremunerated labor. They
retain a variety of formal legal rights, even when a subset of these rights is stripped
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Criminal Justice Predation 155

away through legal entanglement. The terms of their citizenship are refracted
through the lens of debt, rendering their citizenship morally suspect and materially
reconstructed.
Through predatory practices, alleged civic debts are made politically legible and
governable through their conversion into quantified financial debts – which then
become the basis for attenuating various rights of citizenship and making them
conditional on the civic obligation to pay. Once debt is established, new fees and
expenses often mount quickly. From this point onward, the foremost civic obliga-
tion becomes the act of making reliable payments to public and private creditors.
When indentured citizens fail to meet this “civic minimum” (White 2003), they
risk incarceration or other state actions that further erode their rights and standing.
Critically, the indentured citizenry in America today is far larger than the
incarcerated or even convicted population. First, even among those who are arrested
or charged with crimes, many are never convicted of anything. Second, beyond the
people who are directly assessed fines, fees, and so on, one must include a far
larger group of secondary targets – that is, the people who come to bear the
financial burdens of predation and find themselves drawn into relations of ongoing
debt and payment.
Here as in the past, gender is critical for understanding the organization of state
predation. Women are, of course, direct targets of state predation alongside men.
But it is important to recognize both the greater prevalence of men among direct
targets of policing and incarceration and the fact that it is women who shoulder
the primary burdens of financial extraction through the criminal justice system.
Roughly one in four women in the USA have a family member in prison – a
number that rises to 44 percent among black women – and women make up an
estimated 83 percent of family members covering costs for incarcerated populations
(Ella Baker Center 2015). It is typically women who co-sign the bail contracts,
who cover the fines and fees and prison charges while men are imprisoned, and
who take on additional debts when the men return to the community branded an
“ex-felon” and find they are unable to secure work (Katzenstein and Waller
2015).
Among families trying to maintain contact with a prison inmate, an estimated
one in three goes into debt (Ella Baker Center 2015). And in states such as
Florida and Wisconsin, unpaid criminal justice debts transfer to the family estate
after an ex-prisoner dies (Lind 2015). Payments on such debts leave many women
unable to keep up with living expenses, including food, utilities, and rent. Such
dynamics combine with others to push a significant number of women into the
kinds of eviction processes analyzed in Matt Desmond’s widely discussed book
Evicted (2016).
Through this process of secondary stigmatization and extraction, women who
have not themselves been charged with criminal violations become indentured
citizens in their own right. As predatory state practices expand, they reconstruct
both sides of the state–citizen relationship. Thus, in the city of Ferguson, the
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

156 Joshua Page and Joe Soss

municipal court ceased to “act as a neutral arbiter of the law or a check on


unlawful police conduct. [It began to use] its judicial authority as the means to
compel the payment of fines and fees that advance the City’s financial interests”
(DOJ 2015). At the same time, criminal justice predation also transformed
Ferguson citizens by further “undermin[ing] community trust,” cultivating fear
and avoidance of public authorities, and breeding a combustible mix of frustration,
anger, and expectations of injustice.

Predation and Resistance


Though it remains legal and widespread, criminal justice predation has become the
target of growing political resistance. The contours of critique are, in some cases,
politically telling. On the left, progressive liberals such as Senator Bernie Sanders
(2015) and scholar James Galbraith (2009) equate predation with profiteering by
market firms, faulting government only for failing its obligation to protect the
citizenry. On the right, libertarian conservatives such as Rand Paul (2015),
George Will (2012), and the Cato Institute (2010) decry predation by state
authorities as a classic example of “big government” run amok. Each side applies
its own forms of erasure to obscure politically inconvenient storylines and single
out its perennial bête noir.
Alternative grounds for critique and resistance can be found in scholarly
and activist discourses addressing neoliberalism. Here, the tidy opposition of state
and market gives way to a critical analysis of how states have been marketized and
how markets have become state projects. In America today, criminal justice preda-
tion operates through hybrid governing practices. It blurs state–market boundaries as
it draw diverse actors together in projects of dispossession targeting marginalized
populations.
While political partisans may not highlight these interplays, they are resonant
features of life in targeted communities. It is little surprise that insurgent movements
like #blacklivesmatter call to end “money bail, mandatory fines, fees, court sur-
charges and ‘defendant funded’ court proceedings” and equally insist on stopping
“the privatization of prisons, jails, probation, parole, food, phone and all other
criminal justice related services” (MBL 2016). Like the recent and widespread
protests inside US prisons (Woolf 2016), the movement for black lives is partly a
struggle against predation itself – and against the significant role predation plays in
making the celebrated “liberal-contractual” relations of more advantaged Americans
possible. In this sense, they should be recognized as counter-movements to
neoliberalism – the driving force of predation within and beyond the criminal
justice field.
Such disruptive resistance should not surprise anyone. As Onur Ulas Ince
(2016) rightly stresses, the history of expropriation and dispossession has always
also been a history of political resistance, from the anti-enclosure riots, Diggers,
and Levellers of sixteenth and seventeenth century England to slave revolts,
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Criminal Justice Predation 157

mutinies on the sea, and colonial rebellions of various sorts up to the present day.
It is through such acts of mass resistance that political communities from time to
time are able to undermine prevailing regimes of predation, reorganize the
capitalist state, and create, at least for a while, a more just and democratic system
of societal institutions.

References
Bach, D. (2015). UW Project Focuses on Fines and Fees that Create “Prisoners of Debt”.
UW Today, December 4. Retrieved from: www.washington.edu/news/2015/12/04/
uw-project-focuses-on-fines-and-fees-that-create-prisoners-of-debt/
Better Together (2015). General Administration Study #2: Municipal Structure, Powers, Funding,
and Operations. Retrieved from: www.bettertogetherstl.com/wp-content/uploads/2015/
12/Better-Together-General-Administration-Report-2-FINAL-.pdf
Block, F., and Somers, M. R. (2014). The Power of Market Fundamentalism: Karl Polanyi’s
Critique. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Brennan Center for Justice (2016). Is Charging Inmates to Stay in Prison Smart Policy?
Retrieved from: www.brennancenter.org/states-pay-stay-charges
Brown, W. (2015). Undoing the Demos: Neoliberalism’s Stealth Revolution. New York: Zone
Books/Near Futures.
Bruyneel, K. (2007). The Third Space of Sovereignty: The Postcolonial Politics of U.S.–Indigenous
Relations. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Bunn, C. (2015). Prison Phone Rates Generate Billions for Companies. The Chicago
Defender, October 21. Retrieved from: http://chicagodefender.com/2015/10/21/
prison-phone-rates-generate-billions-for-companies-cause-stress-for-black-families/
Cato Institute (2010). Policing for Profit: The Abuse of Civil Asset Forfeiture. Retrieved from:
www.cato.org/events/policing-profit-abuse-civil-asset-forfeiture
Council of Economic Advisors (CEA) (2015). Fines, Fees, and Bail. Issue Brief, December.
Retrieved from: https://obamawhitehouse.archives.gov/sites/default/files/page/files/
1215_cea_fine_fee_bail_issue_brief.pdf
Crenson, M. A. and Ginsberg, B. (2002). Downsizing Democracy: How America Sidelined
Its Citizens and Privatized Its Public. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University
Press.
Desmond, M. (2016). Evicted: Poverty and Profit in the Modern City. New York: Penguin
Random House.
Dilts, A. (2011). From “Entrepreneur of the Self” to “Care of the Self”: Neoliberal
Governmentality and Foucault’s Ethics. Foucault Studies, 12, 130–146.
Donahue, J. (1999). Hazardous Crosscurrents: Confronting Inequality in an Era of Devolution.
Century Foundation Report.
Du Bois, W. E. B. (1935). Black Reconstruction in America: An Essay Toward a History of the
Part Which Black Folk Played in the Attempt to Reconstruct Democracy in America,
1860–1880, Vol. 6. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Eisen, L-B. (2015). Charging Inmates Perpetuates Mass Incarceration. Brennan Center for Jus-
tice. New York: NYU School of Law. Retrieved from: www.brennancenter.org/sites/
default/files/publications/Charging_Inmates_Mass_Incarceration.pdf
Ella Baker Center (2015). Who Pays? The True Cost of Incarceration on Families, September.
Retrieved from: http://whopaysreport.org/who-pays-full-report/
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

158 Joshua Page and Joe Soss

Federal Communications Commission (FCC) (2015). FCC Takes Next Big Steps in Reducing
Inmate Calling Rates, Also Seeks Comment on Reforms for Video Visitation and Additional Reforms
for International Rates and Ancillary Charges, October 22. Retrieved from: https://apps.fcc.
gov/edocs_public/attachmatch/DOC-335984A1.pdf
Fergus, D. (2014). Financial Fracking in the Land of the Fee, 1980–2008. In R. Cramer
and T. Shanks (Eds.), The Assets Perspective (pp. 67–97). New York: Palgrave MacMillan.
Fergus, D. (2017). Land of the Fee: Hidden Costs and the Decline of the American Middle Class.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Galbraith, J. (2009). The Predator State: How Conservatives Abandoned the Free Market and
Why Liberals Should Too. New York: Free Press.
Gonzalez, G. (2013). Guest Workers or Colonized Labor?: Mexican Labor Migration to the
United States. London: Routledge.
Gustafson, K. (2016). The Legal Manufacture of Hardworking Bastards: Marriage, Bastardy, and
Apprenticeship Laws and the Policing of Race and Labor in North Carolina, 1741–1870.
Unpublished Manuscript.
Hacker, J. S., and Pierson, P. (2010). Winner Take All Politics. New York: Simon and Schuster.
Handley, J., Helsby, J., and Martinez, F. (2016). Inside the Chicago Police Department’s
Secret Budget. The Chicago Reader, September 29. Retrieved from: www.chicagoreader.
com/chicago/police-department-civil-forfeiture-investigation/Content?oid=23728922
Harcourt, B. (2011). The Illusion of Free Markets. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Harlan, C. (2016). Inside the Administration’s $1 billion Deal to Detain Central American
Asylum Seekers. The Washington Post, August 14. Retrieved from: www.washingtonpost.
com/business/economy/inside-the-administrations-1-billion-deal-to-detain-central-
american-asylum-seekers/2016/08/14/e47f1960-5819-11e6-9aee-8075993d73a2_story.
html?utm_term=.d8c38824c285
Harris, A. (2016). A Pound of Flesh: Monetary Sanctions as Punishment for the Poor. New
York: Russell Sage Foundation.
Harvey, D. (2003). The New Imperialism. New York: Oxford University Press.
Harvey, D. (2005). A Brief History of Neoliberalism. New York: Oxford University Press.
Ince, O. U. (2016). Bringing the Economy Back In: Hannah Arendt, Karl Marx, and the
Politics of Capitalism. Journal of Politics, 78(2), 411–426.
Ingraham, C. (2014). Civil Asset Forfeitures More than Double under Obama. The
Washington Post, September 8. Retrieved from: www.washingtonpost.com/news/
wonk/wp/2014/09/08/civil-asset-forfeitures-more-than-double-under-obama/
Jacobson, M. F. (2001). Barbarian Virtues: The United States Encounters Foreign Peoples at
Home And Abroad, 1876–1917. London: Macmillan.
Katzenstein, M. F., and Waller, M. R. (2015). Taxing the Poor: Incarceration, Poverty
Governance, and the Seizure of Family Resources. Perspectives on Politics, 13(3), 638–656.
Krippner, G. R. (2011). Capitalizing on Crisis: The Political Origins of the Rise of Finance.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Lerman, A., and Weaver, V. (2014). Arresting Citizenship: The Democratic Consequences of
American Crime Control. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Lind, D. (2015). At Least 2 States Let Prisons Charge the Families of Dead Ex-Prisoners for
Their Food and Health Care. Vox, October 16. Retrieved from: www.vox.com/2015/
5/26/8660001/prison-jail-cost
Ludwig, M. (2015). Across the South, Many Jails are Illegal Debtors’ Prisons. Truthout,
September 17. Retrieved from: www.truth-out.org/news/item/32832-many-jails-are-
illegal-debtors-prisons
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Criminal Justice Predation 159

Luxemburg, R. (2003). The Accumulation of Capital. New York: Routledge.


Lyons, W. (2002). The Politics of Community Policing: Rearranging the Power to Punish. Ann
Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
Marable, M. (1981). Blackwater: Historical Studies in Race. Dayton, OH: Black Praxis
Press.
Massachusetts Trial Court Fines and Fees Working Group (2016). Report to Trial Court
Chief Justice Paula M. Carey. November 17. Retrieved from: www.mass.gov/courts/
docs/trial-court/report-of-the-fines-and-fees-working-group.pdf
Massey, D. S. and Denton, N. A. (1993). American Apartheid: Segregation and the Making of
the Underclass. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
McLennan, R. M. (2008). The Crisis of Imprisonment: Protest, Politics, and the Making of the
American Penal State, 1776–1941. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Movement for Black Lives (MBL) (2016). End the War on Black People. Retrieved from:
https://policy.m4bl.org/end-war-on-black-people/
Muhammad, K. G. (2010). The Condemnation of Blackness: Race, Crime, and the Making of
Modern Urban America. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Nichols, R. (2015). Disaggregating Primitive Accumulation. Radical Philosophy, 194,
18–28.
North, D. (1981). Structure and Change in Economic History. New York: W.W. Norton.
North, D., and Weingast, B. (1989). Constitutions and Commitment: The Evolution of
Institutions Governing Public Choice in Seventeenth-Century England. The Journal of
Economic History, 49, 803–832.
Ordower, H., Sandoval, J. S. O., and Warren, K. (2016). Out of Ferguson: Misdemeanors,
Municipal Courts, Tax Distribution and Constitutional Limitations. Saint Louis University
Legal Studies Research Paper No. 2016–2014.
Oshinsky, D. (1997). Worse Than Slavery: Parchman Farm and the Ordeal of Jim Crow Justice.
New York: Free Press.
Pateman, C. (2007). The Settler Contract. In C. Pateman and C.W. Mills (Eds.), Contract
and Domination (pp. 35–78). Malden, MA: Polity.
Pateman, C. and Mills, C.W. (2007). Contract and Domination. Malden, MA: Polity.
Paul, R. (2015). Statement posted to Twitter. Retrieved from: https://twitter.com/randpaul/
status/631608896826777600
Peck, J. (2010). Zombie Neoliberalism and the Ambidextrous State. Theoretical Criminology,
14(1), 104–110.
Peck, J., and Theodore, N. (2012). Reanimating Neoliberalism: Process Geographies of
Neoliberalisation. Social Anthropology, 20(2), 177–185.
Petrella, C. (2016). No Easy End to Prison Profiteering. Boston Review, August 25.
Retrieved from: http://bostonreview.net/us/christopher-petrella-doj-private-public-
prisons
Pew Charitable Trusts (2012). The Local Squeeze: Falling Revenues and Growing Demand for
Services Challenge Cities, Counties, and School Districts. Retrieved from: www.pewtrusts.
org/en/research-and-analysis/reports/0001/01/01/the-local-squeeze
Plaintiffs v. The City of Florissant (2016). No. 4:16-cv-1693. United States District Court for
the Eastern District of Missouri Eastern Division.
Pritchett, W. (2003). The “Public Menace” of Blight: Urban Renewal and the Private
Uses of Eminent Domain. Yale Law and Policy Review, 21(1), 1–52.
Rana, A. (2010). The Two Faces of American Freedom. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

160 Joshua Page and Joe Soss

Rivlin, G. (2010). Broke, USA: From Pawnshops to Poverty, Inc. – How the Working Poor
Became Big Business. New York: Harper Collins.
Sachs, J. D. (2012). The Price of Civilization: Reawakening American Virtue and Prosperity.
New York: Random House.
Sanders, B. (2015). Sanders, House Leaders Introduce Bill to Ban Private Prisons.
Retrieved from: www.sanders.senate.gov/newsroom/press-releases/sanders-house-leaders-
introduce-bill-to-ban-private-prisons
Satter, B. (2010). Family Properties: How the Struggle Over Race and Real Estate Transformed
Chicago and Urban America. New York: Metropolitan Books.
Schram, S. F. (2015). The Return of Ordinary Capitalism: Neoliberalism, Precarity, Occupy.
New York: Oxford University Press.
Shapiro, J. (2016). State-By-State Court Fees. National Public Radio, May 19. Retrieved
from: www.npr.org/2014/05/19/312455680/state-by-state-court-fees
Smith, R. M. (1997). Civic Ideals: Conflicting Visions of Citizenship in U.S. History. New
Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Sorkin, M. (2013). Drawing the Line: Architects and Prisons. The Nation, August 27.
Retrieved from: www.thenation.com/article/drawing-line-architects-and-prisons/
Soss, J., Fording, R. C., and Schram, S. F. (2011). Disciplining the Poor: Neoliberal Paternalism
and the Persistent Power of Race. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Stuart, F. (2016). Down, Out, and Under Arrest: Policing and Everyday Life in Skid Row.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Swanson, A. (2015). A Shocking Number of Mentally Ill Americans End Up in
Prison Instead of Treatment. The Washington Post, April 30. Retrieved from: www.
washingtonpost.com/news/wonk/wp/2015/04/30/a-shocking-number-of-mentally-
ill-americans-end-up-in-prisons-instead-of-psychiatric-hospitals/?utm_term=.5d786e
2a2d44
Takaki, R. (1998). A Different Mirror for Young People: A History of Multicultural America.
New York: Seven Stories Press.
Tilly, C. (1992). Coercion, Capital and European States, A.D. 990–1992. New York: Wiley
Blackwell.
United States Department of Justice Civil Rights Division (DOJ) (2015). Investigation
of the Ferguson Police Department, March 4. Retrieved from: www.justice.gov/
sites/default/files/opa/press-releases/attachments/2015/03/04/ferguson_police_depa
rtment_report.pdf
Wacquant, L. (2010). Crafting the Neoliberal State: Workfare, Prisonfare, and Social
Insecurity. Sociological Forum, 25(2), 197–220.
White, S. (2003). The Civic Minimum. New York: Oxford University Press.
Will, G. (2012). When Government is the Looter. The Washington Post, May 18.
Retrieved from: www.washingtonpost.com/opinions/when-government-is-the-looter/
2012/05/18/gIQAUIKVZU_story.html?utm_term=.39ee5e4589d5
Wofford, T. (2014). The Operators of America’s Largest Immigration Detention Center
Have a History of Inmate Abuse. Newsweek, December 20. Retrieved from: www.
newsweek.com/operators-americas-largest-immigrant-detention-center-have-history-
inmate-293632
Wolfe, P. (2001). Land, Labor, and Difference: Elementary Structures of Race. The
American Historical Review, 106(3), 866–905.
Wolin, S. (2008). Democracy, Incorporated: Managed Democracy and the Specter of Inverted
Totalitarianism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Criminal Justice Predation 161

Woolf, N. (2016). Inside America’s Biggest Prison Strike: “The 13th Amendment Didn’t
End Slavery”. The Guardian, October 22. Retrieved from: www.theguardian.com/
us-news/2016/oct/22/inside-us-prison-strike-labor-protest
Wright, G. (1997). Old South, New South: Revolutions in the Southern Economy Since the Civil
War. Baton Rouge: LSU Press.
Young, R., and Meiser, J. (2008). Race and the Dual State in the Early American
Republic. In J. Lowndes, J. Novkov, and D. T. Warren (Eds.), Race and American Political
Development (pp. 31–58). New York: Routledge.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

9
NEOLIBERALISM AND POLICE
REFORM

Leonard Feldman

Scholars of police reform, noting some of the difficulties involved in relying on


the US courts and Constitutional jurisprudence to limit police violence and
reform police practices, argue that the more systemic efforts of the Department of
Justice in transforming whole departments constitute a more promising avenue of
change. Indeed, they argue, the attempt to rein in police violence and halt
racially discriminatory police practices may be more fruitfully pursued at the policy
level, in the shadow of the courts, than directly in the courts themselves. The
tendency in the literature is to make a contrast between the more individualized
remedies of criminal prosecutions and civil litigation, on the one hand, and the
more structural reforms of DOJ interventions. For instance, Chase Madar (2014)
writes, “far more useful are the DOJ Civil Rights Division’s root-and-branch
interventions into violently dysfunctional police forces, triggered by ‘patterns and
practices’ of systematic rights violations rather than any one particular incident.”
There is a good deal to recommend this position, but two additional points
should be made about the DOJ investigations: First is the frequent and central
role of political protest in triggering the investigations. Second is the prominent
role of neoliberal techniques and approaches within both the investigative reports
and the memoranda of understanding or consent decrees that usually result from
DOJ investigations. Highlighting them can help make clear what is distinctive in
this reform effort, in contrast to the turn to the courts. Ultimately, I suggest that
we might characterize these reform efforts as a redeployment of neoliberal techniques
for more democratic ends.
In this chapter I examine how governance technologies closely linked to neo-
liberalism such as quantitative performance measurement, managerial audits best
practices, and benchmarking, are being redeployed in the service of police
reform. I first describe how neoliberalism as a political form involves the
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberalism and Police Reform 163

development of particular technologies of measurement, observation, and coor-


dination. Then I consider how these play out in the governance of policing, in
the implementation of CompStat in the 1990s, and in recent efforts by the
Obama Administration to reform municipal police departments, including the
Department of Justice “pattern or practice” investigations into excessive force and
systemic racism in local departments. I argue that Department of Justice findings
reports combine legal-juridical, muckraking, and managerial frames, and that the
implicit alliance between protest movements such as Black Lives Matter and the
Civil Rights Division shows the way in which, in very particular contexts, a social
logic of surveillance can redirect the neoliberal audit in the direction of democratic
oversight.
My argument proceeds in the following steps: First, drawing on the work of
Wendy Brown, I examine the role of specific governance techniques such as
benchmarking, best practices, and quantitative performance measurement as they
are described in the literature on neoliberalism and as implemented, specifically,
in the administration of police in (a) the rise of CompStat and (b) the use of “best
practices” in the President’s Task Force on Twenty-first Century Policing. Then
I turn to the specific efforts of the Department of Justice to reform local police
departments, briefly looking at how agonistic political action has played a central
role in triggering Department of Justice investigations and showing how neoliberal
governance techniques and rationalities such as experimentalism, benchmarking,
and best practices get incorporated into what are essentially legal reports concerning
systemic police law-breaking. In particular I show how the use of quantitative
benchmarking for judging incidences of police violence involves the creative
redeployment of CompStat techniques from their traditional analysis of criminal
violence to the analysis of police violence. In arguing that neoliberal governance
rationalities play a role in police reform efforts, I do not mean to deny the well-
documented role of neoliberal policies in facilitating or producing the intensified
policing of urban space and the refocusing of punitive and carceral mechanisms
on subjects who fail to self-regulate according to market norms (Rose 1999;
Wacquant 2009; Harcourt 2011; Soss et al. 2011). I rather wish to supplement
that picture with an account of how neoliberal governance logics can become
attached to different political projects. The Department of Justice reports involve
such a redirection, as they bring together features of a traditional legal brief, a
journalistic exposé, and a neoliberal audit.

Benchmarking and Quantitative Performance Measurement


Recent work in political theory suggests that the importation of market logics
into the state constitutes one of the paradigmatic features of neoliberalism.
According to Wendy Brown (2015, p. 34), this “economization of law” includes the
application of market rationalities to state institutions: “Centralized authority, law,
policing, rules, and quotas are replaced by networked, team-based, practice-oriented
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

164 Leonard Feldman

techniques emphasizing incentivization, guidelines, and benchmarks.” Brown


(2015, p. 122), extending Foucault’s insights into neoliberalism as a governing
rationality, sees contemporary neoliberalism as producing its own distinctive
“administrative form” – governance, as opposed to government. Governance,
Brown argues (2015, p. 123), “signifies a transformation from governing through
hierarchically organized command and control – in corporations, states, and non-
profit agencies alike – to governing that is networked, integrated, cooperative,
partnered, disseminated, and at least partly self-organized.” Brown argues that
neoliberal governance is not agent-centered, as compared to older models of
authorities and subordinates. Rather, governance is “institutionalized in processes,
norms and practices” (Brown 2015, p. 124). This means a transformation from hier-
archical commands and straightforwardly punitive techniques to more supposedly
collaborative forms whereby workers in an organization are made increasingly
responsible, while their entrepreneurial activity is guided by “benchmarks and
inspection” (Brown 2015, p. 127). Best practices and benchmarking are promi-
nent techniques of contemporary neoliberal governance, whereby organizations
emulate their more successful competitors. As Brown writes (2015, p. 136):

“[B]enchmarking” may sound like a fancy word for goal-setting, but its
meaning is rather different. Benchmarking refers to the practice of a firm or
agency undertaking internal reforms on the basis of studying and then
importing the practices of other, more successful firms or agencies.

“Best practices,” according to Brown (2015, p. 135), marketize institutions and


domains that were at least partially insulated from economic rationality. Best
practices and benchmarking thus position organizations in competition with each
other even as they seek to emulate each other through relentless comparison via a
standardized metric. Furthermore, the basis of comparison is usually some quantita-
tive measurement of performance. As Bruno (2009, p. 278) argues, “benchmarking
helps decision-makers to reach consensus by translating political problems of
collective action into statistical issues of quantification.”
Brown shows how these neoliberal governance rationalities have insinuated
themselves into the management of academia. For faculty, the norms of profes-
sional success have been transformed, from teaching and research that serves the
public good to individualized and entrepreneurial standards achievement, measured
through market-friendly indicators such as grant funding and citation counts:

This professionalization aims at making young scholars not into teachers and
thinkers, but into human capitals who learn to attract investors by networking
long before they “go on the market,” who “workshop” their papers, “shop”
their book manuscripts, game their Google Scholar counts and “impact factors,”
and, above all, follow the money and the rankings.
(Brown 2015, p. 195)
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberalism and Police Reform 165

There is, indeed, a broad range of literature that (a) examines the use of quantitative
performance measurement in evaluating academic professors and (b) links this trend
to the neoliberalization of academia. But Brown may be said to too quickly
connect practices of governance and techniques of measurement and ranking as
integral and necessary parts of the same political project – neoliberalism. As Feller
(2009, p. 328) writes, “The analytical issue that emerges from this discussion is
how most properly to couple propositions relating to international trends towards
neoliberal modes of governance … with those that describe and account for
similar trends towards program management and performance measurement.”
The use of numbers to assess performance long predates neoliberalism and the
new public management. As Le Galès (2016, pp. 15–16) cautions, “a large part of
the quantification or the strengthening of the spirit of managerialism does not fall
under neoliberal dynamics. The logic of the rationalisation of activities, including
through measurement and quantification, has a long history.” This does not mean
that one should not theorize the way technologies, practices, and concepts connect
in ways that render them part of a distinct ideological and political project. But
it does mean that one should assume that those connections are contingent
articulations.
Scholars have tended to be critical of the application of best practices, bench-
marking, and quantitative performance measurement metrics to their own practice
as academics, as well as to the institutions and practices of the welfare state. I
argue that much of this critical literature applies well to data-driven trends in
policing as well, such as the CompStat system discussed in the next section.
Nevertheless, I also argue that these techniques associated with neoliberalism can
be (and have been) redirected, and form a significant element in recent efforts to
combat police violence. My point is neither to besmirch critics of the neoliber-
alization of higher education, nor is it to foster a dismissive attitude towards the
efforts of the Department of Justice to achieve structural reforms of American police
departments. Rather, my point is that the political effects of the incorporation of
governance techniques and rationalities that go by the name of neoliberalism are
highly contingent, context dependent, and not always de-democratizing.

Data-Driven Policing and Its Limits


Neoliberal political rationality can be understood as one that subjects state actors,
decisions, and processes to norms of market efficiency and quantitative performance
measurements. As William Davies (2014, p. 28) puts it, “The neoliberal state is an
aggressively utilitarian state, in the sense that it seeks to make all political, legal
and public action subject to quantitative empirical evaluation.” The paradigmatic
case of neoliberal rationality in policing is surely the CompStat system, developed
by the NYPD in the 1990s and quickly adopted by other large police departments,
which inaugurated an era of quantitative performance measurement. There are at
least three respects in which CompStat represents a neoliberal governing
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

166 Leonard Feldman

rationality: First, it is promoted as the importation of accountability systems from


the corporate sector into the administrative state. William Bratton (New York
Police Department Commissioner from 1994 to 1996) and his co-author William
Andrews are quite explicit about this:

Like the corporate CEOs of that era, we began with a large, unfocused,
inward-looking, bureaucratic organization, poor at internal communication
or cooperation and chronically unresponsive to intelligence from the outer
world. We reduced layers of management, drove responsibility down to the
operating units, improved communication and data processing, tightened
accountability, and rewarded results. In short order, we had the NYPD’s
bureaus and divisions competing with criminals, not with one another.
(Bratton and Andrews 1999)

The NYPD was to “compet[e] with criminals” largely through better data. But
more fundamentally, the turn to CompStat as a management philosophy repre-
sents the hallmarks of neoliberal political rationality as Brown (2015, p. 132)
identifies them: devolution and responsibilization – pushing decision-making
down to lower levels of the organization while “moral[ly] burdening … the
entity at the end of the pipeline.”
Second, CompStat, while promoted as introducing accountability into poli-
cing, actually transforms accountability, as police become less accountable to the
communities in which they serve and more accountable to their leaders (Potter
2015), an aspect of what Brown describes as neoliberal de-democratization.
Finally, whether understood as leading inexorably to actual quotas for arrests and
summonses or, as instituting “performance goals” to “maximize employee per-
formance” (Bronstein 2015, p. 583, citing Operations Order No. 52 from Police
Commissioner, NYC Police Department), CompStat ended up generating a
fixation on quantitative measures of performance (Potter 2015).
CompStat’s purpose was to generate comprehensive statistics on crimes – with
data and mapping of crime that would enable police commanders to hold sub-
ordinates responsible for crime levels, and develop specific strategies for response
(Eterno and Silverman 2010). Two perverse outcomes have been noted in the
literature: First, police departments respond to the imperative to improve their
numbers (i.e. reduce crime) by reclassifying certain reported events as not-crime,
or as misdemeanors as opposed to felonies. Second, the focus on quantitative
performance measurement leads to pressure on police officers to meet informal
(and officially denied) quotas of arrests and summons. As Bronstein (2015, p. 565)
notes, “While CompStat was revolutionary for the NYPD, its unintended con-
sequence appears to be a department-wide fixation on quantifying enforcement
activity.” There is no necessary link between a focus on quantified measures of
criminal activity and quantified measures of enforcement activity. After all, police
departments could emphasize a qualitative shift in policing (e.g. from one driven
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberalism and Police Reform 167

by arrests and summonses for quality of life offenses to one focused on colla-
borative problem solving and increased visibility) and then attempt to identify a
causal relationship between that shift in policing and a reduction in criminal
activity. Instead, it appears that the data-driven quantifying approach simply
migrated from the crime side to the enforcement side. This turn to numbers did
not require any link between increasing arrests and summonses and decreasing the
crime rate. Rather, it appears as though CompStat ushered in a new police
rationality (numbers-driven, where “hard” quantitative measures of both crime and
police performance are prioritized over qualitative assessments) that made statis-
tical performance measures dominant. The “numbers game” thus designated
strategies to lower crime statistics through underreporting and strategies to keep
numbers of arrests and summonses high. Bronstein (2015, p. 564) cites an inter-
view with a retired NYPD detective who articulates the shift to a quantitative
rationality: “It used to be, ‘what’s his story?’ Now it’s, ‘what are his numbers?’
That’s all they care about. CompStat was great, but now they [have] started
putting numbers on everything.” In combination with Broken Windows policing,
the “results” for low-income communities of color were ever-increasing contacts
with police and the criminal justice system more generally, intrusive police surveil-
lance, criminal records for misdemeanor offenses, and the associated social costs of
what Lerman and Weaver (2014) call “custodial citizenship.”
The quantification of policing has followed a market logic, where the broader
social goal (reducing crime) has been transformed into a productivity metric
(measuring number of arrests and summonses). Police officers are subjected to a
regime of responsibilization, urged to be more entrepreneurial and “proactive” in
producing more arrests. However, focus on quantitative performance measure-
ments comes to an abrupt halt when it comes down to documentation of the use
of force. Indeed, the sustained public attention to racialized police violence in the
aftermath of Ferguson has revealed that a key impediment to police reform is
the absence, not the presence of practices of governmentality such as the collection
of good quantitative data: The US government simply did not track the number
of police killings nationally, much less other data concerning the circumstances of
the violence such as the racial identity of the victim and perpetrator or whether
the victim of the homicide was armed or unarmed (Lowery 2014). It took projects
such as The Guardian’s “The Counted,” again, inspired by popular political protest,
to remedy that. James Scott (1998) examines the relationship between the rise of
statistics and the expansion of state power. Measuring, quantifying, calculating,
render a society legible to the state. By contrast, “an illegible society … is a hindrance
to any effective intervention by the state, whether the purpose of that intervention
is plunder or public welfare” (Scott 1998, p.78). While US society has been
rendered legible by the precise mapping of crime data, it is local police departments
who have, up until very recently, remained illegible to the federal apparatus: The
absence of state-collected data on police killings by the United States federal
government marks a peculiar lacuna: How is it that the state cannot employ its
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

168 Leonard Feldman

paradigmatic mode of visioning when it turns its lens away from the population and
resources it manages and towards the organization of coercive power that assists in
that managing? It was only as a result of the efforts of journalists and activists to
create a comprehensive accounting of police killings since 2013 that the DOJ’s
Bureau of Justice Statistics changed its own practice of data collection – from
requests for voluntary reporting by local departments to an approach that searched
media and utilized information from medical examiners and coroners to supplement
that reporting (Banks et al., 2016; see also Bialik 2016). Not surprisingly, the
state’s effort to offer an accounting of its own violence lagged behind the efforts
of non-state social movement and journalistic actors.

Benchmarking and Best Practices in Police Reform


A task force, established by Presidential executive order in 2014, with a staff
provided by the Department of Justice’s community policing division, published
its recommendations after conducting a series of “listening sessions” with police,
civilians, academics, and politicians. The final report of the President’s Task Force
on 21st Century Policing is largely framed by the goals of “building trust”
between police and community and promoting “procedural justice” whereby
improved perceptions of the fairness, professionalism, and impartiality of the
police lead to increased public compliance.
While those are the goals, the main mechanism for achieving them is the
articulation and promotion of best practices, a term which is repeated twenty-eight
times in the report. Indeed, the central mission of the Task Force is the formulation
of best practices, as articulated in the 2014 Executive Order establishing it, and
included in the report’s appendix:

Sec. 3. Mission. (a) The Task Force shall, consistent with applicable law,
identify best practices and otherwise make recommendations to the President
on how policing practices can promote effective crime reduction while
building public trust.
(President’s Task Force on 21st Century Policing 2015, p. 79)

The report situates the Department of Justice as a kind of partner and coordinator
in the consensual goal of promoting best practices, not an overseeing political
authority with the capacity to compel change. For instance, when discussing the
need to develop stronger forms of civilian oversight, the report justifies the
necessity of doing so not in order to combat police abuse, but rather “to strengthen
trust with the community” (Task Force 2015, p. 26). And the role of the
Department of Justice is not to compel such reforms. Rather:

the U.S. Department of Justice’s Office of Community Oriented Policing


Services (COPS Office) should provide technical assistance and collect best
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberalism and Police Reform 169

practices from existing civilian oversight efforts and be prepared to help cities
create this structure, potentially with some matching grants and funding.
(Task Force 2015, p. 26)

While the task force report situates the Department of Justice in a collaborative
relationship with local police departments, once the DOJ opens an investigation
into a police department for systemic violations, its relationship to the offending
department shifts to a mixture of collaboration and coercion. In Cincinnati,
Schatmeier (2013) argues that the success of the DOJ monitoring process hinged
on its incorporation of “soft law” techniques to supplement and modify the tradi-
tional “command and control” approach. Schatmeier (2013, p. 573) describes this
as a process in which “the parties set benchmarks and develop plans for achieving
them in lieu of the regulator deciding which approach the regulated agency must
follow.” In a Collaborative Agreement that amended its more traditional Memor-
andum of Understanding, benchmarks were established, and the traditional court
supervision of the agreement between the department of justice and the city’s
police department was supplemented by Rand Benchmark auditing (Schatmeier
2013, pp. 573, 570). Nevertheless, DOJ pattern or practice investigations often
result in a consent decree that is enforced by the courts, or in a settlement
agreement operating under the threat of litigation, meaning that soft law and hard
law are combined.
But there is another dimension of “soft law” worth noting. More broadly,
Department of Justice resources are finite; thus, they select only a small number
of police departments where police violence has become already politicized
(either by protest movements or by political leaders) for investigation and eventual
transformation. One study documented thirty-eight police departments subject to
formal investigation by the Justice Department and nineteen of those cases
resulting in a Consent Decree between 2000 and 2013 (Rushin 2014). Nevertheless,
the goal is to shape police department policies more broadly: In addition to using
benchmarking and best practices within their agreements, the DOJ hopes to
establish benchmark policies to be emulated by non-investigated departments.
Indeed, as Chanin (2011; see also US DOJ 2001) notes, the settlements established
with police departments through the “pattern or practice” investigations tend to
follow a “best practices” template established by the Department of Justice, with
model use of force policies, accountability structures, and data collection proce-
dures. By spreading best practices policy through the threat of investigation and
litigation, the DOJ is creating a hybrid of “command and control” and more
lateral norm diffusion.

Department of Justice Policy Reform’s Roots in Democratic Protest


There appears to be no systematic process governing the Department of Justice’s
opening of an investigation into a municipality’s police department. Rushin
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

170 Leonard Feldman

(2014) describes various ways the DOJ identifies targets of investigation: the role
of academic studies into particular departments, existing civil litigation against
police, department whistle-blowers, and media reports of both systemic police
misconduct and particularly shocking individual cases. What needs to be
acknowledged is the way the latter – media coverage of cases – is itself frequently
triggered by popular political protest against racialized police violence. For
instance, in Cincinnati, riots protesting the killing of an unarmed African-American
teenager, Timothy Thomas, led the Cincinnati mayor to request DOJ intervention
(Schatmeier 2013, p. 557). Similarly, in Baltimore, the mayor requested a full-
scale civil rights investigation by the DOJ in the wake of protests over the death
of Freddie Gray in police custody (Broadwater 2015). And the DOJ’s investiga-
tion of the Ferguson Missouri police department was initiated in the immediate
wake of the Black Lives Matter protests in that city following the killing of
Michael Brown by Officer Darren Wilson (Apuzzo and Fernandez 2014). Whether
the protests’ effects are mediated through the actions of local officials such as
mayors, or without such mediation, they are clearly playing a significant role in
setting the Department of Justice’s agenda in terms of which police departments it
chooses to investigate. Any attempt to evaluate the institutional effect of popular
protests, such as those of the Black Lives Matter movement, should recognize
their role in prompting official action. (At the time of my writing this, the
nominee to be the next Attorney General, Jeff Sessions, if confirmed, appears
likely to end the investigations entirely, or drastically curtail them, as a result of
his view, expressed during his Senate confirmation hearing, that they unfairly
stigmatize the police [Fritze 2017].)
Agonistic democratic action is not only an instigator for DOJ intervention: In
addition, citizen “sousveillance” (Mann and Ferenbok 2013) of police encounters
with civilians gets incorporated into the official findings section of their reports.
For instance, the report on the Chicago Police Department frequently cites cell-
phone videos of police violence to contradict police officers’ accounts. The report
notes that the videos’ relationship to officer testimony suggested a much deeper
and extensive problem of excessive force since “the inaccurate descriptions of
events that were undercut by video we reviewed bore striking similarities to
descriptions provided by officers in numerous cases with no video” (US DOJ
2017, p. 36).
The report stops short of urging more, and more organized, citizen surveillance
of police activity, as is promoted by groups such as Cop Watch. Indeed, the Chicago
report marginalizes the agency of the observer taking the video, describing the video
as an object without an author that “surfaced”:

In one incident captured on cell-phone video, an officer breaking up a party


approached a man, grabbed him by the shirt, and hit him in the head with a
baton. In his reports, the officer, using language very similar to that used in
many other reports we reviewed, falsely claimed that the victim had tried to
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberalism and Police Reform 171

punch him. Before the video surfaced, the officer’s supervisor had approved
the use of force and the victim had pled guilty to resisting arrest. The officer
has since been relieved of his police powers and is facing criminal charges for
his conduct.
(US DOJ 2017, p. 39)

The report does not take this as an opportunity to articulate and defend the
principle, currently contested, of a Constitutional right of individuals to film the
police. Rather, the report uses this as an opportunity to promote a policy of police
body cameras. Thus, as in the case of the democratic protests that sometimes
prompt DOJ investigations, the cell-phone video evidence within the report sig-
nifies the underacknowledged dependence of the official investigations upon
non-institutional, agonistic democratic action.

Policing the Police through Quantitative Performance


Measurement
If agonistic democratic action is at the origin of Department of Justice investigations,
and if policy reform is the goal via the court-monitored consent decrees that are its
conclusion, in between lie various neoliberal practices of governance and measure-
ment. The Department of Justice reports combine multiple frames of analysis. I
argue that the reports combine the frames of the journalistic exposé, the legal
brief, and the performance audit. The exposé side of the reports is the one that,
not surprisingly, receives the most attention from coverage of the reports by
journalists themselves. For instance, newspaper articles of the DOJ report on
Ferguson emphasized the evidence of systemic corruption (the explicit reliance of
the city on police and court-administered fines) and overt racism of city employees.
Here the basic idea is the exposure of malfeasance, especially through vivid
anecdotal evidence or accounts of systemic practices and policies.
The legal brief side of these reports can be found in the way that the DOJ
frames its evidence: It articulates the Constitutional standard for distinguishing
excessive from reasonable force, and then asserts that it will demonstrate, with the
evidence provided, as it says in its report on the Chicago Police Department, that
it has “reasonable cause to believe that the unreasonable force we identified
amounts to a pattern or practice of unlawful conduct” (2017, p. 25).
Department of Justice reports combine these two frames when they document
shocking evidence of excessive force, link that force to a systemic issue such as a
problematic department policy, and compare both the policy and the incident to an
established legal standard. For instance, in their report on Chicago, the DOJ finds:

The use of unreasonable force to quickly resolve non-violent encounters is a


recurrent issue at CPD. This is at least in part because CPR’s policy permits
the use of Tasers in situations where it is unreasonable … Some CPD officers
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

172 Leonard Feldman

resort to Tasers as a tool of convenience, with insufficient concern or cogni-


zance that it is a weapon with inherent risks that inflicts significant pain. Use
of a Taser “is more than a de minimis application of force” and is a “very
significant intrusion on [a person’s] Fourth Amendment interests.” Abbott v.
Sangamon County, Ill., 705 F.3d 706, 726, 730 (7th Cir. 2013). In an incident
we reviewed, a man died after hitting his head when he fell while fleeing
because a CPD officer shot him with a Taser. The man had been suspected
only of petty theft from a retail store. IPRA deemed this use of a Taser
justified.
(2017, p. 33)

The report establishes that such police killings are not shocking aberrations but
systemic patterns by bringing forth evidence of many such incidents and by
connecting those individual incidents to bad policies.
But it turns out that DOJ investigators also put numbers on everything,
including police killings and other use of force incidents. DOJ investigations
establish evidence of unconstitutional, illegal, and policy-violating uses of force
through a CompStat-like approach to quantitative performance measurement.
However, instead of measuring police productivity against a norm or quota, they
establish excess violence against quantitative benchmarks of “normal” force rates.
For instance, in their investigation of the East Haven Connecticut Police
Department for racially profiling Latino drivers for traffic stops, the DOJ uses
benchmarking across squads within the department, and benchmarking in comparison
of individual officers:

We similarly found some EHPD officers with massive disparities in their


stops of Latinos as compared to other officers in EHPD. Indeed, one officer
had a stop rate of Latinos of 40.5%, an extraordinary deviation from the
baseline of other EHPD officer activity. EHPD accordingly permitted officers
with stops rates of Latinos that approached one in two or one in three to
operate without oversight or discipline, strong evidence that EHPD at the
very least enabled their discriminatory conduct.
(US DOJ 2011b, p. 7)

In their investigation of the New Orleans police department, the DOJ establishes
a benchmark “use of force” rate per arrest nationally, not to establish the exces-
sive force of the NOPD but to infer that the police department has a culture and
practice of underreporting use of force:

We reviewed all uses of force reported by NOPD officers for the month of
June 2010, 34 reports in all. During this same month, NOPD effectuated
6,787 arrests. Nationwide, estimates of force rates vary, but generally range
from approximately 2–5% (i.e. for every 100 arrests, officers use reportable
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberalism and Police Reform 173

force in approximately 2–5 arrests). Thus, in the month of June 2010, if


NOPD officers were using force at the national average rate, one would
expect to have seen between approximately 135 and 340 uses of force, rather
than the 34 NOPD reported.
(US DOJ 2011a, p. 14)

In this way, the report normalizes a certain level of police violence – “using force
at the average national rate” – in order to diagnose the deeper problems related to
excessive force in this case, concerning the systemic lack of accountability and
review of all incidents of police use of force.
In addition to establishing numerical benchmarks of “normal” police use of
force, a frequent technique employed in DOJ is a random sample audit. For
instance, in their review of the Newark Police Department, the DOJ randomly
selected 100 use of force incident reports from a nine month period and deter-
mined that one-third of them were excessive, based on the testimony of the
officer alone (US DOJ 2014). Similarly, in their report on the Baltimore police
department (US DOJ 2016), the DOJ investigators used random sampling to
audit arrest reports, stop-and-frisk stops of pedestrians, and instances of non-
deadly force in order to demonstrate pervasive and consistent racial disparities
across the range of coercive police actions.
Finally, in the DOJ investigation of the Washington DC police department
(Yeomans 2006), the investigation even benchmarked a “normal” rate of excessive
force. They consulted experts to identify what would constitute a “normal” rate
of excessive force in a “well-managed and supervised” department (1–2 percent
of all uses of force) and then identified, through random sampling, that in the DC
case 15% of uses of force were excessive. Similarly, the DOJ even benchmarked
the violence of police dogs, establishing that “in tightly run canine programs,
bites occur in only about 10 percent of deployments” whereas in the period
under review, the Washington canine unit saw “bites nearly 70 percent of the
time the canines were deployed” (Yeomans 2006).
In the DOJ investigations, CompStat’s quantification of policing is redirected
from an emphasis on “performance” measurements along the lines of productivity
and efficiency towards an analysis of discriminatory enforcement, underreporting
of force, and excess violence. The DOJ investigations and reports, I argue, are a
hybrid technology: Institutionally, they are prompted in part by bottom-up agonistic
democratic protest, but are conducted as top-down assertions of centralized federal
authority. Substantively, they combine the form of the journalistic exposé with
the neoliberal audit. I would like to cautiously suggest that the DOJ approach in
these cases offers evidence for the political value of what Sanford Schram (2015,
p. 174) calls “work[ing] through rather than around neoliberal policies to address
the inequities they create” and what James Ferguson (2009, p. 173) describes as “the
possibility of a truly progressive politics that would also draw on governmental
mechanisms that we have become used to terming ‘neoliberal’.”
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

174 Leonard Feldman

Ferguson’s examples of such a possibility are instructive. In discussing cash


grants for the poor in lieu of traditional welfare state programs as neoliberal,
Ferguson claims (2009, p. 174) that, despite the redistributive ambitions, such
proposals also involve “recognizably neoliberal elements, including the valorization
of market efficiency, individual choice, and autonomy; themes of entrepreneurship;
and skepticism about the state as a service provider.” More broadly, Ferguson asks
us to think about “techniques” as migratory, but in a different way than Brown’s
account of the “promiscuity” of neoliberal frames and technologies, in which, for
instance, the best practices approach transforms different domains in a way that
renders them all fundamentally alike. Ferguson emphasizes the way in which the
process of diffusion, migration, and uptake can transform their political effects:
“Techniques, that is to say, can ‘migrate’ across strategic camps, and devices of
government that were invented to serve one purpose have often enough ended
up, though history’s irony, being harnessed to another” (2009, p. 174).
Thinking about the Department of Justice investigations into local police
departments as a hybrid technology has broader implications for how we think
about the relationship between neoliberal governance methods and democratic
practice. While Brown is surely right to emphasize the profoundly depoliticizing
and dedemocratizing effects of the proliferation of market logics and market
metrics to an ever wider range of institutions and spaces, it is important not to
overdetermine the conclusion theoretically in advance of an investigation into the
specific ways benchmarks, best practices, and performance metrics are utilized.
Another technology central to policing – surveillance – might serve as a useful
case in point. Police surveillance powers are expanding dramatically, through
everything from social media and high altitude aerial surveillance to sophisticated
data-mining and the Department of Homeland Security “fusion centers.” But
surveillance technologies in the form of police-worn body cameras are already
being promoted as a panacea for police violence, promising to offer hard evidence
of excessive force and a deterrent to brutality in the first place. Skeptics rightly
worry that such cameras will be one more tool of civilian surveillance by the
police, that the audio-visual data’s being administered by police departments will
lead to its concealment, and that, far from being an objective record of events,
the framing effect of the camera will encourage the public’s identification with
the police. These concerns should not, however, lead to the conclusion that video
surveillance is essentially a tool of domination. Public surveillance (or better,
sousveillance) of the police, in the form of cell-phone videos, streamed online
and eventually taken up by the news media, are an important democratic iteration
of the technology (Squillacote and Feldman n.d.).
Indeed, one way of understanding the core meaning of democracy in the
context of a complex state apparatus is in terms of social surveillance. For
instance, Rosanvallon (2008) sees a compatibility across and between surveillance
of parts of the state administrative apparatus by independent commissions, internal
organizational audits along the lines of the New Public Management, and the
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberalism and Police Reform 175

surveillance of social movement organizations, media, and at the broadest level,


the internet. (“The internet,” he writes, “is … creating an open space for oversight
and evaluation. The Internet is not merely an ‘instrument’: it is the surveillance
function” [2008, p. 70].) Thought of this way, the linkages I articulate between
the Department of Justice investigations, the form of the neoliberal (or New
Public Management) audit, and social movement activities of surveillance and
denunciation are less surprising than one might suppose given the left critique of
neoliberalism. Those linkages might even be said to indicate the health and
vitality of institutional and extra-institutional democratic practice.

References
Apuzzo, M. and Fernandez, M. (2014). Justice Dept. Inquiry to Focus on Practices of
Police in Ferguson. New York Times. Retrieved from: www.nytimes.com/2014/09/04/
us/politics/justice-dept-to-investigate-ferguson-police-practices.html
Banks, D., Ruddle, P., Kennedy, E., and Planty, M. (2016). Arrest-Related Deaths Program
Redesign Study, 2015–2016: Preliminary Findings. Bureau of Justice Statistics. Retrieved
from: www.bjs.gov/content/pub/pdf/ardprs1516pf.pdf
Bialik, C. (2016). The Government Finally has a Realistic Estimate of Killings by Police.
Retrieved from: https://fivethirtyeight.com/features/the-government-finally-has-a-rea
listic-estimate-of-killings-by-police/
Bratton, W. and Andrews, W. (1999). What We’ve Learned about Policing. City Journal.
Retrieved from: www.city-journal.org/html/what-we’ve-learned-about-policing-
11790.html
Broadwater, L. (2015). Baltimore Mayor Seeks Federal Investigation of Police Department.
Baltimore Sun. Retrieved from: www.baltimoresun.com/news/maryland/politics/bs-m
d-ci-doj-partnership-20150506-story.html
Bronstein, N. (2015). Police Management and Quotas: Governance in the CompStat Era.
Columbia Journal of Law and Social Problems, 48(4), 543–581.
Brown, W. (2015). Undoing the Demos: Neoliberalism’s Stealth Revolution. New York: Zone
Books.
Bruno, I. (2009). The “Indefinite Discipline” of Competitiveness Benchmarking as a
Neoliberal Technology of Government. Minerva, 47(3), 261–280.
Chanin, J. (2011). Negotiated Justice? The Legal, Administrative, and Policy Implications of
“Pattern or Practice” Police Misconduct Reform. PhD Dissertation, American University
School of Public Affairs. Retrieved from: www.ncjrs.gov/pdffiles1/nij/grants/237957.pdf
Davies, W. (2014). The Limits of Neoliberalism: Authority, Sovereignty, and the Logic of Competition.
London: Sage.
Eterno, J. and Silverman, E. (2010). The NYPD’s CompStat: Compare Statistics or
Compose Statistics? International Journal of Police Science and Management, 12(3), 426–449.
Feller, I. (2009). Performance Measurement and the Governance of American Academic
Science. Minerva, 47, 323–344.
Ferguson, J. (2009). The Uses of Neoliberalism. Antipode, 41(s1), 166–184.
Fritze, J. (2017). Jeff Sessions Voices Concern about Use of Consent Decrees for Police.
Baltimore Sun. Retrieved from: www.baltimoresun.com/news/maryland/politics/blog/
bal-jeff-sessions-voices-concern-about-use-of-consent-decrees-for-police-20170110-
story.html
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

176 Leonard Feldman

Harcourt, B. (2011). The Illusion of Free Markets. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Harmon, R. (2012). The Problem of Policing. Michigan Law Review, 110, 761–817.
Le Galès, P. (2016). Performance Measurement as a Policy Instrument. E-Prints – Centre
D’Etudes Europeennes. Retrieved from: www.sciencespo.fr/centre-etudes-europeennes/
sites/sciencespo.fr.centre-etudes-europeennes/files/1606%20Le%20Gales%20Performance
%20Measurement.pdf
Lerman, Amy E. and Weaver, Vesla M. (2014). Arresting Citizenship. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
Lorenz, Chris (2012). If You’re So Smart, Why Are You Under Surveillance? Universities,
Neoliberalism, and New Public Management. Critical Inquiry, 38(3), 599–629.
Lowery, Wesley (2014). How Many Police Shootings a Year? No One Knows. Washington
Post, September 8.
Madar, Chase (2014). Why It’s Impossible to Indict a Cop. The Nation. Retrieved from:
www.thenation.com/article/why-its-impossible-indict-cop/
Mann, S. and Ferenbok, J. (2013). New Media and the Power Politics of Sousveillance in
a Surveillance-Dominated World. Surveillance & Society, 11(1/2), 18–34.
Potter, G. (2015). Police Violence, Capital and Neoliberalism. Imagining Justice. Retrieved
from: http://uprootingcriminology.org/essays/police-violence-capital-neoliberalism/
President’s Task Force on 21st Century Policing (2015). Final Report of the President’s Task
Force on 21st Century Policing. Washington, DC: Office of Community Oriented Policing
Services.
Rosanvallon, P. (2008). Counter-Democracy: Politics in an Age of Distrust. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Rose, N. (1999). Powers of Freedom: Reframing Political Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Rushin, S. (2014). Federal Enforcement of Police Reform. Fordham Law Review, 82, 3189–3247.
Schatmeier, E. (2013). Reforming Police Use-of-Force Practices: A Case Study of the
Cincinnati Police Department. Columbia Journal of Law and Social Problems, 46, 539–585.
Schram, S. (2015). The Return of Ordinary Capitalism: Neoliberalism, Precarity, Occupy. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Scott, J. (1998). Seeing Like a State. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Soss, J., Fording, R., and Schram, S. (2011). Disciplining the Poor: Neoliberal Paternalism and
the Persistent Power of Race. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Squillacote, R. and Feldman, L. (n.d.). Police Abuse and Democratic Accountability: Agonistic
Surveillance of the Administrative State. Manuscript submitted for publication.
United States Department of Justice (US DOJ) (2001). Principles for Promoting Police Integ-
rity: Examples of Promoting Police Practices and Policies. Retrieved from: www.ncjrs.gov/p
dffiles1/ojp/186189.pdf
United States Department of Justice (US DOJ) (2011a). Investigation of the New Orleans
Police Department. Retrieved from: www.justice.gov/sites/default/files/crt/legacy/2011/
03/17/nopd_report.pdf
United States Department of Justice (US DOJ) (2011b). Findings Letter RE: Investigation of
the East Haven Police Department. Retrieved from: www.justice.gov/sites/default/files/
crt/legacy/2011/12/19/easthaven_findletter_12-19-11.pdf
United States Department of Justice (US DOJ) (2014). Investigation of the Newark Police
Department. Retrieved from: www.justice.gov/crt/about/spl/documents/newark_find
ings_7-22-14.pdf
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberalism and Police Reform 177

United States Department of Justice (US DOJ) (2016). Investigation of the Baltimore Police
Department. Retrieved from: www.justice.gov/crt/case-document/baltimore-police-
department-findings-report
United States Department of Justice (US DOJ) (2017). Investigation of the Chicago Police
Department. Retrieved from: www.justice.gov/crt/case-document/file/925771/download
Wacquant, L. (2009). Punishing the Poor: The Neoliberal Government of Social Insecurity.
Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Yeomans, W. (2006). Findings Letter re Use of Force by the Washington Metropolitan Police
Department. Retrieved from: www.clearinghouse.net/chDocs/public/PN-DC-0001-
0002.pdf
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

PART IV

Urban Governance
At Home and Abroad
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

10
NEOLIBERALIZING DETROIT

Jamie Peck and Heather Whiteside

Introduction: Detroit as Target


“It’s there for the taking.” That is how Fred Siegel of the Manhattan Institute
described Detroit in the summer of 2013, as the city tumbled inexorably towards
what would be the largest municipal bankruptcy in US history. It was a flippant
remark that spoke volumes about the conservative movement’s strategic line on
the still-unfolding financial crisis that had been enveloping cities across the
country in the years since the Wall Street crash of 2008. And it also represented a
blunt summary of the ideologically consistent but in practice continuously evolving
position of the Manhattan Institute, a New York based think tank that since the
late 1970s has been at the forefront of the development of a distinctively neo-
liberal approach to urban policy, including workfare, zero-tolerance policing, and
a pro-corporate development ethos. “The depth of corruption and dysfunction
[in Detroit] is so fantastic,” Siegel continued, “it’s so far that you might describe it
as Third World dysfunction. There is no need [for conservatives] to gin it up. It’s
just right there” (quoted in Gold 2013, p. 2). The financial travails of Detroit
would be an opportunity for conservative intellectuals and opinion shapers to rail,
once again, against the poisonous legacy of New Deal urbanism, and to repurpose
their parables of welfare dependency and governmental failure, this time to frame
and facilitate a first-world model for financially mandated structural adjustment at
the urban scale. Detroit was going to have to pay the price for what Siegel’s
Manhattan Institute colleague, Steven Malanga (2013a, p. A13), pointedly
described on the Wall Street Journal’s op-ed page as “tin-cup urbanism.”
The political rationalities and policy technologies of neoliberalism are well
suited to these moments (and sites) of crisis. In fact, it could be argued that they
have been made, and repeatedly remade, for these very circumstances. There is
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

182 Jamie Peck and Heather Whiteside

blame shifting happening here, but also quite purposeful forms of social, institu-
tional, and spatial targeting – all sutured to a favored package of policy “solutions.”
And while there are plenty of repeating refrains and routines, the fact that the
terrain and the targets are always moving means that what is better understood as
a contradictory process of neoliberalization can in fact only operate as an adaptive
mode of governance, a “flexible credo” (see Peck 2010). In the context of the
extended fallout of the Wall Street crash of 2008 and the Great Recession, what
began as a banking (and financial) crisis was duly rescripted, in a now-familiar
fashion, as a crisis of and for the social state, not least at the urban scale. This, in
turn, has been associated with new rounds of improvised crisis management,
creative institutional destruction, and experimental reregulation. Prior to the
bankruptcy declaration of 2013, Detroit had already been placed under the control
of an emergency manager – corporate restructuring specialist, Kevyn Orr – whose
appointment over the heads of elected local officials and the mayor was an
initiative of Republican Governor Rick Snyder, courtesy of brazenly anti-
democratic state law PA 436–2012. Subject to what Orr liked to call “the rule of
reason,” the city’s accelerated restructuring was being guided by the principles of
technocratic financial management, in effect a normalized mode of neoliberal
governance based on the principles of privatization, outsourcing, governmental
purging, and lean administration. Reflecting a political culture in which most
forms of public-sector investment and sociospatial redistribution are liable to be
reflexively tagged in the pejorative language of “bailouts,” local-government
profligacy and “deadbeat cities” are frequently indicted:

[T]he hard truth is that Motown is a victim of its own political vices and a
bailout would merely forestall the necessary rehab … Misrule has resulted in
the nation’s highest violent crime rate, worst schools, blight and corruption …
As history shows, sending more cash to Detroit won’t fix its breakdown in
self-government. Another bailout would merely support its toxic political
culture of neglect and corruption.
(Wall Street Journal 2013, p. A14)

The roots of this toxic culture are often laid at the door of “the man who killed
Detroit” (Malanga 2013b), Mayor Coleman Young, whose two decades in office
(1974–1993) began with the oil crisis and a worldwide recession, spanning the
extended restructuring of the auto industry and the progressive detachment of the US
federal government from urban financing and urban policy. For conservative
critics, his was the unapologetic face of New Deal urbanism, the personification
of Big Municipal Government, a tax-and-spend Democrat ruling almost uncon-
tested over a city scarred by too much bureaucracy, too much welfare, too much
union power, too much regulation, and too much federal largesse, and not nearly
enough free-enterprise spirit, individual responsibility, and fiscal control. To a
considerable degree, these fed into normalized understandings: “To suburban
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberalizing Detroit 183

whites … the disintegration of cities like Detroit [was] irrefutable evidence that
the politics of liberalism, and the programs of the Great Society in particular, had
been a terrible social and economic mistake” (Thompson 2001, p. 242).
Rationales of this sort effectively established the pretext for an unprecedented
assault on public-sector programs, public-sector employees, public-sector unions,
and public-sector pensions, not only in Detroit but in cities across the country
(see Tabb 2014; Davidson and Ward 2017). In this context, a neoliberal version
of what “history shows” would be pre-emptively stitched together with a new
generation of technocratic, autocratic, and postdemocratic interventions, variously
justified in terms of an austere policymaking commonsense, the rule of financial
reason, and (even) a twenty-first century reboot of “Caesarism” (see Gillette
2014; Eide 2016; cf. Peck 2017).
The critical analysis of neoliberalism, it follows, must involve acts of decon-
struction as well as reconstruction. With this as its goal, the chapter develops a
reading of neoliberal urbanism through the prism of Detroit, exploring the
extended prehistory of the city’s bankruptcy filing and fiscally cleansed present.
Like the character in Hemingway’s The Sun Also Rises who, when asked how he
ended up bankrupt replied both ways, “gradually and then suddenly,” financial
default was for Detroit above all an historical process more than it could ever be
reduced to some legally bracketed event. It was an historical process, furthermore,
that brings vividly to light the social, spatial, and scalar dynamics of neoliber-
alization, across the long arc from defensive entrepreneurialism to disciplinary
financialization.
In a somewhat more abstract register, this extended case also speaks to the
character of “neoliberal urbanism” as an analytical frame, midlevel concept, and
conjunctural formation (see Theodore et al. 2011; Peck et al. 2013; Hackworth
2017; Peck 2017), and as a signifier for a rolling and roiling process of restructuring,
enacted in the name of free markets and smaller states, that in its contradictory
practice is neither static nor singular. It is never static in the sense that neoliber-
alization denotes a direction rather than a destination: rather than proceeding in a
linear fashion towards some more market/less state equilibrium, neoliberalization
follows a zigzagging path of creative destruction grounded in the dialectical
interplay of deregulatory rollbacks and the variously crisis-assisted, experimental,
and strategic rollout of corporate-centric and market-friendly modes of governance.
It is not singular in the dual sense of the absence of a paradigmatic “master transition”
or definitive case, coupled with conditions of contradictory coexistence, in which
actually existing neoliberalism is unable to stand on its own (or monopolize the
social field), but can only be found in context-specific conjunctures, recombinant
forms, and volatile hybrids. Together, these conditions of existence mean that
neoliberalism is not just contingently but necessarily variegated, mutating,
unevenly developed, shape-shifting, and site-shifting; that it is marked by family
resemblances, recurring tropes, and patterned routines but at the same time
exhibits the characteristics of a non-repeating and open-ended historical process;
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

184 Jamie Peck and Heather Whiteside

and that its contradictory historical geographies are therefore always in the
making, flanked as they are by ongoing dynamics of contestation, crisis, and
consolidation.
Reading the Detroit case in these terms means taking account of what has been
an extended and especially checkered history of neoliberal restructuring, refracted
through a constitutive politics of race, in which the intersecting dynamics of dein-
dustrialization, suburbanization, segregation, and municipal-state incapacitation
have combined to produce an overdetermined and by any measure structural
crisis, to which an accumulating series of reactions and responses have amounted
to radically less than a resolution. When it comes to the question, then, of why it
was that Detroit went broke, and why its metastasizing state of bankruptcy far
exceeds the legal or technical definitions of the term, there is no shortage of cir-
cumstantial causes – or for that matter culprits. Local journalist Nathan Bomey’s
pithy checklist is arguably as good as any:

The contraction of the U.S. auto industry. White flight and the exodus of
wealth that began in the 1950s. Discriminatory real estate practices. The
1967 riots. Regional political discord. Pervasive government corruption. A
lack of corporate social responsibility. The destruction of black neighborhoods
to make room for highways.
Former mayor Coleman Young. Former mayor Kwame Kilpatrick.
Former president George W. Bush. Wall Street bankers. A dysfunctional
mass transportation system. Shattered public schools. The disintegration of
the job market.
Predatory lenders. The Great Recession. A collapse in home prices.
Greedy unions. Democrats who were in bed with unions. Republicans who tried
to kill unions. Republicans who were in bed with big business. Skyrocketing
taxes. A failure to collect those taxes. Crime-ridden neighborhoods. Police
brutality. Police lethargy. Drugs. Blight.
Neglectful City Council members. Hapless bureaucrats. Generous pen-
sions. Gold-plated health care benefits. Overspending. An explosion of debt.
A culture of denial.
(in Bomey and Gallagher 2016, p. 1)

By way of a prequel of sorts to the recent round of critical analyses that have
problematized the neoliberalization of Detroit in the restructuring present (see
Akers 2015; Peck 2015; Peck and Whiteside 2016; Hackworth 2017), the chapter
returns to the final decades of the twentieth century, in particular to the mayoral
administration of Coleman Young (1974–1993), in order to reassess what Hack-
worth has called conservative “parables” of the Motor City, which have been
purposefully mobilized for their negative demonstration effects, ostensibly as proof
of the “failures of Black militancy and Keynesianism” (2017, p. 10). Counter to
these revisionist conservative histories of Detroit, we will develop the argument
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberalizing Detroit 185

that Coleman Young’s Detroit was, at the same time, a protean site for the production
of emergent forms of neoliberal urbanism, just as its constrained circumstances
illustrated many of the practical and political limits of progressive governance in
the context of devolved financial discipline. The chapter’s conclusion returns to
post-bankruptcy Detroit, where “Made in Detroit” can be read as more than a
hipster marketing slogan and more as a question concerning the source, character,
impact, and provenance of this stressed and incomplete process of neoliberal
transformation, a question of the ongoing remaking of Detroit.

Between Entrepreneurialism and Empowerment


No figure looms larger in revisionist conservative historiographies of Detroit than
Coleman Young. It was Young, the one-time labor organizer and socialist firebrand
who as mayor, in the words of James Q. Wilson (1998, p. 3), had rejected racial
integration and balanced economic development “in favor of a flamboyant black-
power style that won him loyal followers, but he left the city a fiscal and social
wreck.” It was Young the “closet Marxist” (Mitsotakis 2013, p. 2) who in the
course of “his 20-year reign [had] ignored crime, inflamed racial tensions and
built a patronage machine” (Wall Street Journal 2013, p. A14). And it was Young
who for the right would symbolize for the realm of urban governance a variant of
the pathologizing trope of “welfare dependency,” with all of the same racial sig-
nifiers, a “tin-cup” entitlement culture based on the cultural suppression of
entrepreneurialism and self-reliance under which “the increasingly distressed
city became a fiscal ward of the state and federal governments” (Malanga 2013a,
p. A13).
These arguments have been afforded a degree of academic credibility – and
indeed a broad measure of mainstream policymaking acceptance – in the shape of
Edward Glaeser’s influential version of neoclassical urban economics. The book that
secured the Harvard economist’s reputation as a globally renowned urban guru,
Triumph of the City, is a freewheeling celebration of the benefits, not to say glories,
of a pre- and post-New Deal amalgam of deregulated urban development, freed
from governmental interference and powered by a combination of human capital
and competitive spirits. Written, marketed, and promoted with the assistance of the
Manhattan Institute (where Glaeser is a long-established senior fellow), Triumph
borrows liberally from the narrative conceits of Freakonomics-style popular eco-
nomics and the new genre of feel-good urbanology to construct a bracingly
affirmative account of the power and potential of cities, with but one notable
exception – Detroit. Motown duly serves as the anti-competitive counterpoint
and “the book’s prime example of decline” (Economist 2011, p. 92), an industrial-era
anachronism and a “toxic” expression of municipal welfarism (Glaeser 2011,
p. 57). Young is taken to personify what Glaeser calls the “edifice complex,” an
excessive reliance on grandiose infrastructure projects; he is accused of playing
Robin Hood by not only raising the taxes but then by redistributing, therefore
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

186 Jamie Peck and Heather Whiteside

practically inviting businesses and the aspirant middle-classes to escape to the


suburbs. More perniciously, however, Detroit under Coleman Young is pre-
sented as a textbook illustration of the so-called “Curley effect,” a model of
“racial favouritism” in which local political leaders harvest electoral rewards by
catering to the dominant ethnic group in the city, while actively marginalizing
others. Despite the fact that the Curley hypothesis was dressed up with algebraic
“proofs,” and named as if by misdirection after an Irish-American mayor of
Boston, it is the failed development strategies, affirmative-action policies, and
“righteous anger” of Coleman Young that is afforded critical-case status, since it
was in Detroit that the “effect” could be connected to a pattern of predicted
outcomes in which not only jobs, white residents, middle-class families, and
enterprising individuals but “civilization [itself] had fled the city” (Glaeser 2011,
p. 55).
In the wake of Detroit’s accelerating financial crisis, post-2008, this (per)version
of historical causality has been deployed – to considerable effect, it must be said –
to rationalize, to justify, and to legitimate new rounds of social-state purging,
privatization, public-service triage, and neoliberal policy experimentation. As
Jason Hackworth has argued, conservative parables of governmental profligacy,
racialized dependency, cultural dysfunction, unchecked union power, and entre-
preneurial deficit have been (re)mobilized in order to paint Detroit as a bastion of
municipal socialism and welfare-state bloat, as a Great Society dystopia, when in
fact the city has been subject to decades of classically neoliberal restructuring:

Far from being a profligate quasi-socialistic local state, [Detroit’s] governance


has been characterised by brutal budget cuts to virtually every one of its
departments and intense collaboration with the private sector for 60 years.
Though Coleman Young … is often framed as a misguided socialist by
neoliberals … he is arguably more remembered by Detroiters as being a
handmaiden for the automakers … [In accordance with neoliberal principles,
public] spending has been cut, unions decimated, taxes slashed, services
streamlined, and yet neither meaningful investment nor social stability has
returned. It is difficult to frame Detroit as an over-interventionist collectivist
government, if one is interested in historical fact.
(2017, pp. 4–5)

Analysts of the actually existing history of the Coleman Young regime disagree
about some things, it is true, but there is near consensus around the fact that the
mayor, from the outset, was both a fiscal realist and an economic-development
pragmatist. His public-service reforms, just as they were motivated by the pressing
need to tackle institutionalized racism (especially in the police service) and
advancing affirmative action, were also governed by principles of conservative
fiscal management. Shrewd observers rated it as a “notable achievement” that the
city had remained “intact” after Young’s first year in the “God-awful job of
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberalizing Detroit 187

Mayor of Detroit,” given the scale of the challenges that had been inherited:
“The city payroll was met each week, with the help of a few hundred layoffs.
The garbage got picked up. The teachers didn’t strike. The police didn’t revolt”
(Tyson 1975, pp. 237–238). With little or no alternative but to govern as a fiscal
conservative, Young proved to be a skillful interlocutor between the city’s frag-
mented constituencies, fashioning a “financial leadership strategy [and] governing
style” around an often volatile mixture of interests that included “interest group
politics in the New Deal tradition; a tough bargaining position with the unions;
active confrontation with opponents and critics; and maintaining the independence
of city management structures, that is, protecting them from what have been
called fiscal managers” (Rich 1989, p. 234). Few others could have straddled
(indeed for the most part managed) these often-conflicting interests the way that
Young did, a man whose own biography expressed “the contradictory relationship
between big business, big labor, and the black community” (Hill 1983, p. 106).
The trials and tradeoffs associated with navigating conflicts and contradictions
of this magnitude have led some to characterize city management as exhibiting an
effectively decades-long “regimeless” mode of governance (Reese and Sands
2013), but in many respects Detroit was one of the pioneers of the pro-corporate,
real-estate based model of downtown development (see Orr and Stoker 1994;
Eisinger 2003). Young put his political machine, not to say his own energy and
charisma, at the service of a business-friendly revitalization effort, cultivating elite
partnerships with prominent figures from the business community like Henry
Ford II (whom he liked to call Hank the Deuce), General Motors’ president
Elliot Estes, oil baron and developer Max Fisher, and property magnate and
investor Al Taubman. Dedicating both public dollars and political capital to major
redevelopment projects may have resembled a classic case of growth-machine
politics, at least on the surface, but Detroit was a site for the production of frustrated
prototypes, at best. When Young was first elected to office, the city was already
on a steep path of economic decline, an existential (pre)condition that in a
material sense preempted much of the realistic scope for rational economic planning
or strategic prioritization (Hill 1983; Rich 1989; Boyle 2001). With development
strategies pursued in the face of persistent negative economic growth, as a creative
and proactive player on the metropolitan political scene, the mayor evidently felt
that there were few, if any, alternatives to working tirelessly on cementing the
alliances with those corporate, financial, and development interests with residual
commitments to downtown.
Young’s early 1970s election may indeed have been “a black political victory,
pure and simple,” and his administration would move with urgent purpose to
combat “blackjack rule by police,” while opening up African-American
employment opportunities across the public service, but economic development
and job creation were overriding priorities for this self-proclaimed “pragmatic
radical” from the beginning too (Darden et al. 1987, p. 216; Hill 1983; Young
with Wheeler 1994, p. 212). At first, the model of governance was effectively
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

188 Jamie Peck and Heather Whiteside

corporatist, the mayor working with local business and labor leaders to broker
major development projects with the assistance of significant federal funding.
Having secured more than $2 billion in federal support for his public-private
partnership program under the Ford administration, Young would later capitalize
upon much closer ties to President Carter, of whom the mayor had been an early
supporter. Carter’s urban-policy program was all but made in Detroit, with key
political operatives relocating to Washington, DC, as federal funds were soon
flowing back to the Motor City. What Edward Glaeser would subsequent diagnose
as the mayor’s “edifice complex” can be seen in less pejorative terms as “a suc-
cessful partnership [forged] with a select group of private-sector interests to pursue
a classic downtown-renewal strategy based on bringing upscale commercial
establishments, hotels, apartments, and convention facilities to Detroit to offset
the decline in manufacturing industry” (Orr and Stoker 1994, p. 51). The Young
administration’s strategy was to parlay those powers that remained at the city’s
disposal into a network of economic-development agencies within which the
capacities of the public and private sectors could be combined – organizationally,
financially, and through interlocking directorships – in pursuit of what Richard
Child Hill called a “corporate center strategy.” In its most fulsome expression this
envisaged:

[A] riverfront teeming with the tourist and convention crowds, a strong “first
downtown” serving as the financial pillar to the region’s economy, a “second
downtown” thriving on “culture and silicon,” a surrounding expanse of
neighborhoods whose population stability and economic well-being [would
be] assured by the retention and attraction of modern industries to renovated
industrial corridors and port facilities. This is the best of all possible worlds:
the full flowering of the Detroit Renaissance.
(Hill 1983, p. 105)

In this context, the appeal – both material and symbolic – of large-scale, “visible,”
and landscape-altering development projects is not difficult to understand (see
Thomas 2013). As historian Kevin Boyle (2001, p. 122) assessed the situation,
“Young needed help – any help – and it is easy to see how he could have been
seduced by the promise of a new factory, sports arena, or high-rise.”
That this “conserving strategy” effectively failed, concerned as it was to restore
Detroit’s economic fortunes, says at least as much about the scale of private-sector
disinvestment from the city during the 1970s and 1980s, coupled with unprece-
dented rates of white flight and inner-city deprivation, as it does about some
endogenous form of governance failure (see Thompson 2001; Shaw 2009). Spe-
cialists in the comparative analysis of urban-political regimes, in fact, score Detroit
according to its structural location in the “least advantaged bargaining context”
available to Western cities, one of private-sector dependency in which those
nominally in charge possess “few choices” since the initiative is with business,
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberalizing Detroit 189

subject to the vagaries of market conditions (Kantor et al. 1997, pp. 352–353).
Coleman Young may have enjoyed a substantial level of political autonomy,
courtesy of his practically unassailable electoral position, but his policymaking capacity
and room for political-economic maneuver were both profoundly constrained,
in turn, by the city’s fiscally hobbled state and by the centrifugal forces of
deindustrialization and suburbanization.
During the time that Detroit enjoyed (preferential) access to federal funds, the
preconditions for what has been labeled a “vendor regime” strategy were in
place, albeit one in which the mayor’s office could be said to have been reduced
(though never naively) to “facilitat[ing] business privilege” (Kantor et al. 1997, p. 360).
Once Reagan was in the White House, the foundations of Detroit’s fragile
public-private partnership quickly began to unravel. The president whom Young
had famously called “Old Pruneface” abruptly installed an effectively anti-urban
program, slashing federal transfers to the cities, and to Detroit in particular (see
Figure 10.1). Now that what Young liked to refer to as his city’s “Jimmy Carter
dollars” had stopped flowing, his capacity to deliver public-sector funding for
development projects was sharply attenuated. Worse still, federal finances had
been used to underwrite general revenue spending for several years, as the tax base
continued to shrink (Anton 1983; Young with Wheeler 1994). At the beginning
of the Reagan years, Young vividly portrayed the city’s vulnerable state this way:
“This is not a TV Western and there is no cavalry out there galloping to our
rescue. All we can do is circle the wagons – and live or die based on our own
strength” (quoted in Fireman 1981b, p. 11A).

FIGURE 10.1 Federal funding for cities … and for Detroit


Source: Authors’ calculations based on the Fiscally Standardized Cities database, Lincoln
Institute of Land: http://datatoolkits.lincolninst.edu/subcenters/fiscally-standardized-
cities/
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

190 Jamie Peck and Heather Whiteside

In fact, Detroit was already teetering on the brink of bankruptcy. Following a


close call with insolvency in the mid-1970s, paralleling the New York City crisis,
an initial round of structural changes had been pushed through, but by the end of
the decade it was clear that “the glue … was coming apart,” and that the city was
on a path to become a “fiscal leper,” having lost access to the open bond market,
in the absence of “fundamental, not makeshift, changes in [its] revenue structure”
(Rich 1989, pp. 246, 258, 237). In 1981, Young launched what amounted to a
“save-the-city plan,” described as an “all-or-nothing strategy” for averting financial
default (Fireman 1981c, p. 1A). The city’s financial situation was undeniably dire,
but there was little or no evidence that this could be accounted for by budgetary
profligacy or municipal mismanagement. A blue-chip commission empanelled to
investigate the rapidly advancing budget crisis (chaired by a retired senior executive
from Ford, Fred Secrest) had concluded that “the city’s budget crisis was not
attributable to poor fiscal management but to a variety of factors beyond the city’s
control, including a declining tax base, rising unemployment, shrinking population
and rapid inflation” (Fireman 1981a, p. 3A), going as far as to praise the munici-
pality’s “excellent financial management” (Secrest Task Force, quoted in Detroit
Free Press 1981a, p. 8A). Speaking at the Detroit Economic Club, prominent
financier Felix Rohatyn, arguably the most important figure in the management of
New York City’s fiscal crisis, concurred while adding:

Detroit’s problem is not a gigantic accumulation of short-term debt as a result


of a decade of hidden deficits; it is not a result of poor fiscal management,
weak mayoral leadership, failure to face problems and lack of co-operation
among business, labor and government.
(quoted in Detroit Free Press 1981a, p. 8A, emphasis added)

Rohatyn’s credibility had been important to the balancing act that the mayor had
to strike (“The iceman cometh. Maybe now the people will believeth,” he had
told the press), given the need to secure “trust, participation, and sacrifice” across
all of the city’s constituencies and interested parties (Young with Wheeler 1994,
p. 260).
Some of the most difficult negotiations were with the city’s unions, where
Young (a former union activist himself) engaged in hardball negotiations that he
described as “rough [but] the alternatives are much rougher … That’s not a
threat, it’s a fact” (quoted in Fireman 1981a, p. 3A). Confronted with the stark
alternatives of “brinksmanship or statesmanship,” the unions opted for the latter,
accepting a package of wage and benefit concessions in exchange for job security
(Rich 1989, p. 257). Young’s strategy, which he described as a “three-legged
stool,” the loss of any one of which would leave the city and his administration
“on our ass,” eventually worked, an experience that had been for the mayor “the
ultimate exercise in politics” (Young with Wheeler 1994, p. 261). A municipal
default was averted, at the eleventh hour, by the imposition of an austerity
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberalizing Detroit 191

budget, a state-approved increase in the income-tax rate for commuters and


residents, and an emergency bond issue of $125 million, which was rated as an
“extraordinary” accomplishment in the local press (Kushma 1984, p. 10A).
Young secured waged concessions from the public-sector unions, including a
two-year wage freeze in the early 1980s, and reduced the size of the municipal
workforce to levels not seen since the 1930s (Kushma 1984). Six thousand city
workers were fired by 1984 and most community recreation facilities (skating
rinks, pools) were shuttered, initiatives that the mayor’s former press secretary
describes as being in an effort to “[keep] a pretty tight rein … in some very difficult
economic times” (quoted in Bomey and Gallagher 2016).
Detroit was actively exploring how it might learn to live in the context of
diminished means, to cope with a downsizing economy and a depopulating city,
while also authorizing (under profoundly constrained circumstances) strategies of
revitalization. Resonances with today’s Detroit, in this context, are difficult to
miss. It was Coleman Young, for example, who floated the idea – in the context
of the financial crisis of the early 1980s – of a “self-service city,” in which
voluntary contributions and community labor would selectively replace a range of
municipal functions, including the adoption of parks and park maintenance, the
clearing of vacant lots, the reflation and animation of gift economies, and (even)
the recruitment of residents to positions in the police reserves and as fire-department
auxiliaries (see Cheyfitz 1980; cf. Boyle 2001; Kinder 2016). While acknowl-
edging the laudability of these and other voluntary efforts, these prototypical
experiments in DIY urbanism were criticized at the time for their distributional
consequences, since local residents were effectively “compensating for public
resources flowing to private corporations” (Hill 1983, p. 112).
Subsequent analyses of the deteriorating fiscal health of US cities would con-
firm Detroit’s uniquely challenging situation: for Coleman Young to restore the
levels of public-service provision to something resembling those prevailing when
he was about to enter office, in 1972, the revenue-raising capacity of the city
would have to be boosted by 92 percent by 1982, a deterioration that was
attributed to “social and economic trends outside the control of city officials”
(Ladd 1994, pp. 241, 255). It is notable, in this context, that Detroit was experi-
encing an especially aggravated form of fiscal stress, but it was one that was
nevertheless systematically felt across many of the big-city economies in the United
States, where a structural gap had opened up between (constrained) revenue-
raising capacities and (often unmet) service needs and budgetary demands. While
the fiscal health of the typical big city improved marginally during the 1980s,
following the return of geographically uneven economic growth, Detroit was one
of a handful of cities in which structural budget problems continued to deepen,
presenting an unpalatable choice between severe reductions in public services or
large, and potentially damaging, tax increases (Ladd 1994).
In retrospect, the close call with municipal bankruptcy in 1981 bifurcated the
Coleman Young years in a more than temporal sense. The vendor regime of the
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

192 Jamie Peck and Heather Whiteside

1970s had been aspirational, purposeful, and in some respects visionary; it had
been a time of building, albeit in the face of macroeconomic uncertainty and
unrelenting tides of disinvestment, decentralization, and deindustrialization. After
the early 1980s, in the final decade of Young’s time in office, the vendor regime
would visibly fracture as the administration became increasingly embattled, while
an inexorably deteriorating set of political and economic fundamentals continued
to erode what realistic prospects the city might have had.
At the symbolic heart of Detroit’s rebuilding efforts during the 1970s was the
aptly named Renaissance Center, the downtown office and hotel complex
developed by Henry Ford II, Al Taubman, and financier Max Fisher with a
funding package exceeding $500 million, where the City of Detroit’s role had
been mostly facilitative – land clearance, technical support, and cheerleading. In
1982, Ford pulled his investment out of the loss-making venture that itself was
soon in mortgage default. Downtown Detroit has been blighted by an oversupply
of office space ever since, every subsequent development project involving public
subsidies of some kind to this day (Galster 2012; Reese and Sands 2013). At
Young’s inauguration in 1974, Ford had spoken expansively of a “new coalition”
between business, labor, and government in Detroit (quoted in Darden et al.
1987, p. 216); a decade later it was clear that Detroit needed the auto companies
much more than they needed the city, their subsequent involvement in develop-
ment projects being reduced to matters of “public relations or corporate charity,”
while the attitude of the remaining business community towards the Young
administration veered between appeasement, indifference, and active hostility
(Orr and Stoker 1994, p. 58). All along, it had been clear that the political fortunes
of the Young administration, and the viability of the city’s economic-development
strategy, were “inextricably tied to [an] investment agenda set by the corporate
business community” (Hill 1983, p. 108).
If Coleman Young had initially ridden into office on a wave of community
support, the institutionalization of which squeezed out more autonomous neigh-
borhood organizing initiatives for a while, by the late 1980s his administration
was struggling to manage, if not contain, a much more restive array of social
movements (see Shaw 2009). For many, the now-notorious case of GM’s new
plant in Poletown was the tipping point. In 1980, the company had issued a
challenge to the City of Detroit to deliver a development site appropriate for the
construction of a large-scale plant, larded with all of the usual subsidies. In what
immediately became a priority for the administration, an almost 500-acre site was
identified in Poletown, the seizure and clearance of which entailed $200 million
in direct costs to the City but also the obliteration of a vibrant neighborhood
(including two schools, sixteen churches, a hospital, and more than 3,000 resi-
dents), overriding what had been a concerted campaign of community opposition
(Fasenfest 1986; Darden et al. 1987; Wylie 1989). The company was practically
gifted the site, for $8 million, complete with a twelve-year tax abatement, after
which it would eventually deliver barely half of the promised 6,000 jobs. The
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberalizing Detroit 193

sense of betrayal generated by the Poletown controversy would prove to be a


long-lasting one, even if Young claimed (erroneously) that “that one plant makes
up for every g–damn thing that went into the suburbs [over] the past 20 years”
(quoted in Kushma 1984, p. 10A).
It is no coincidence that Young’s successor, Dennis Archer, came to power
with the backing of community activists, in addition to pragmatic sections of the
business community. Young had notably declined to attend the inauguration of
President Bill Clinton, but Archer would be quick to capture what benefits there
were from the third-way urban policy that followed. Detroit’s (competitively
tendered) bid for one of the newly designated Empowerment Zones was con-
sidered one of the best prepared, securing the city a $100 million grant and some
symbolic visibility, setting the stage for several years of incremental improvements
under the new mayor, albeit drawing upon an entirely conventional package of
development initiatives, projects, and tropes (Eisinger 2003). Detroit went on to
turn every page in the increasingly dog-eared playbook of orthodox economic-
development initiatives. There would be new sports stadiums, General Motors
would purchase and come to use the Renaissance Center as its world head-
quarters, legalized casino gambling was introduced (one of Coleman Young’s
long-frustrated projects), and public-private partnerships like the Riverwalk and
Campus Mauritius projects were launched, aimed at downtown restoration
and beautification. Ultimately, sustained economic growth would prove elusive
and debt-reliant governance would intensify, financialization eventually pulling
the city’s finances apart by 2013.

Conclusion: Default Explanations


Across the field of critical urban studies, explanatory invocations of “neoliberalism”
have acquired something akin to a default position in recent years. Much of this
work, understandably, has been concerned with the real-time analysis of the
various breaking edges of transformation, often tagged to processual under-
standings of neoliberalization as an adaptive technology of governance repeatedly
reanimated by crisis conditions as well as strategic considerations (see Theodore
et al. 2011; Peck et al. 2013). It is not uncommon, however, for work in this
vein to rely upon stylized sketches of the past and historically foreshortened forms
of analysis, which in some cases may ignore conservative reform narratives in the
service of critical genealogies, chronologies, and periodizations (see Jessop 2012).
Complementing earlier explorations of the dynamics of municipal bankruptcy
and financialized urban governance in the Motor City (see Peck 2015; Peck and
Whiteside 2016), the purpose of this chapter has been to revisit and reevaluate the
storied time of Coleman Young’s Detroit. Young’s time in office coincided not
only with a dramatic acceleration in the rate of deindustrialization (nationally and
locally), remembered by the mayor as “a bleak period of neglect and retrogression
[across] the urban scene” (Young with Wheeler 1994, p. 256), but also with the
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

194 Jamie Peck and Heather Whiteside

rise of a “new class” of managers and financial technocrats in fiscally distressed


cities (Rich 1989, p. 233); all of which would combine in Detroit to manifest as a
painful, protracted experience of financialized intermediation, institutionalization,
and intensification (Peck and Whiteside 2016).
If bankruptcy is a condition that strikes in two ways, slowly, and then suddenly,
Detroit’s 2013 default can be seen as a precipitative event many decades in the
making. The conservative narrative suggests that by triggering the suburbanization
of jobs and middle-class whites, the 1967 riots were Detroit’s pivotal moment,
even though historical processes of deindustrialization and racial exclusion had
been metabolizing for most of the postwar period, the late 1960s rebellion being
just one of their overdetermined effects (Sugrue 2005; Fine 2007). Similarly,
Detroit’s bankruptcy merely punctuated what has been a long-run process of
neoliberalization together with all the attendant constraints imposed by trenchant
economic stagnation, decades-long credit rating downgrades, and marked revenue
loss, leading ultimately to intense debt reliance. Having declared the largest
municipal bankruptcy in US history, the city has since been subjected to a poli-
tically steered and racially targeted process of “financialized” restructuring, based
on a neoliberal model of technocratic governance, and involving court-administered
“adjustment,” municipal downsizing, and public asset stripping.
In the world of Realpolitik, Detroit’s bankruptcy seems destined to remain
an indelible point of reference, moving forward, a moment that will be taken to
signify a kind of “reset” in ideological and institutional terms. Detroit is now
being repurposed, in leaner form, for new markets and for emergent modalities
of market rule. A privatized city has sprouted in the midst of municipal
insolvency – Quicken billionaire Dan Gilbert, alone, now owns sixty buildings,
or 9 million square feet of downtown real estate (Austen 2014). What was once
partnering with (or pandering to) big business under Coleman Young has
become outright fire sale under emergency management. As compensation for
their bankruptcy-induced paper losses, bond insurers Syncora and FGIC now
own significant portions of city property, including choice parcels of land,
buildings, and parking lots. An important pillar of economic revitalization and
fiscal recovery now rests with financialized-corporate partnerships of various
sorts, from the Red Wings arena (or Little Caesars Arena, renamed in honor of
its benefactor Mike Illitch, owner of Little Caesars Pizza, the Detroit Red
Wings, along with much Detroit real estate) to soccer stadiums and other
investor-led plans for Detroit’s urban housing, retail, and entertainment infra-
structure. Real estate brokers and P3 investors are having a field day with the
redevelopment of bankrupt Detroit, making good on earlier dreams of a fiscally
cleansed, investment-opportunity-rich landscape. As the CEO of Detroit’s
Regional Chamber of Commerce puts it: “The bankruptcy has only made
Detroit a more attractive investment … Bankruptcy isn’t a dirty word in business
any longer. It often means good investments at a great price” (Sandy Baruah,
quoted in Aguilar 2014, p. 1).
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberalizing Detroit 195

Accompanying the new commanding heights (and depths) of urban financial-


corporate ownership is the increasingly ubiquitous narrative that Detroit will be
saved by the peripatetic class of “creatives,” hipster entrepreneurs bringing their
ideas, technology, and energy to Detroit, usually from one of the coasts but
nearly always from outside. The subjects of this celebrated startup culture, nor-
matively young, degree-bearing, and white as they invariably are, tend to live in
entirely different worlds to their (hardly close) working-class, African-American
neighbors, the latter being mostly excluded from this development script.

Nowadays, tales of the city’s slow recovery tend to focus on plucky hipsters
from Los Angeles or Brooklyn colonizing abandoned spaces, opening pickle
companies or tilling little urban agriculture plots. Glossy magazines acclaim
Detroit as the next Berlin; never mind that Germany’s reunified capital has
always floated on a bed of cushy federal subsidies.
(Kimmelman 2017, p. C1)

This can be read as another chapter in Detroit’s extended and tortuous history of
racialized development, the apparent need to “import” entrepreneurship repre-
senting another marker of localized cultural deficits, the pernicious imagery of
intrepid pioneers populating the new “frontiers” – for the most part a culturally
demarcated archipelago of downtown enclosures – evoking a familiar array of racial,
class, and indeed colonial signifiers (see Binelli 2013; Eisinger 2015; Moskowitz
2015; Kinney 2016). As this new population trickles into Detroit, it is worth recalling
one of Coleman Young’s memorable observations about the city’s long-run battle
against depopulation: “what’s at the root of that loss? Economics and race. Or
should I say, race and economics” (quoted in McGraw 2005, p. 28).

References
Aguilar, L. (2014). Detroit’s Challenge: To Spread the Wealth. Detroit News, November
17. Retrieved from: www.detroitnews.com/story/business/real-estate/2014/11/17/
detroit-bankruptcy-investment/19153475/
Akers, J. (2015). Emerging Market City. Environment and Planning A, 47, 1–17.
Anton, T. (1983). Federal Aid to Detroit. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution.
Austen, B. (2014). The Post-Post-Apocalyptic Detroit. New York Times, July 11.
Retrieved from: www.nytimes.com/2014/07/13/magazine/the-post-post-apocalyptic-
detroit.html?_r=0
Binelli, M. (2013). Detroit City is the Place to Be. New York: Metropolitan Books.
Bomey, N. and Gallagher, J. (2016). How Detroit Went Broke: The Answers May
Surprise You – and Don’t Blame Coleman Young. Detroit Free Press, December 19.
Retrieved from: www.freep.com/story/news/local/michigan/detroit/2013/09/15/
how-detroit-went-broke-the-answers-may-surprise-you-and/77152028/
Boyle, K. (2001). The Ruins of Detroit: Exploring the Urban Crisis in the Motor City.
Michigan Historical Review, 27(1), 109–127.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

196 Jamie Peck and Heather Whiteside

Cheyfitz, K. (1980). The Self-Serve City. Monthly Detroit, November, 79–82.


Darden, J. T., Hill, R., Thomas, J., and Thomas, R. (1987). Detroit: Race and Uneven
Development. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press.
Davidson, M., and Ward, K. (Eds.) (2017). Cities under Austerity: Restructuring the U.S.
Metropolis. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
Detroit Free Press (1981a). The City. Detroit Free Press, June 12, 8A.
Detroit Free Press (1981b). Mayor Young. Detroit Free Press, September 13, 36A.
Economist (2011, February 12). A Tale of Many Cities. Economist, 91–92.
Eide, S. (2016). Caesarism for Cities. City Journal, 26(1), 70–75.
Eisinger, P. (2003). Reimagining Detroit. City and Community, 2(2), 85–99.
Eisinger, P. (2015). Detroit Futures: Can the City Be Reimagined? City & Community, 14,
106–117.
Fasenfest, D. (1986). Community Politics and Urban Redevelopment: Poletown, Detroit
and General Motors. Urban Affairs Quarterly, 22(1), 101–123.
Fine, S. (2007). Violence in the Model City. East Lansing: Michigan State University Press.
Fireman, K. (1981a). Layoffs Loom if Rescue Plan Vetoed. Detroit Free Press, April 2, 3A, 13A.
Fireman, K. (1981b). Trials of Coleman Young: Joy – and Fury. Detroit Free Press, January
6, 1A, 11A.
Fireman, K. (1981c). Young Goes for Broke with Save-the-City Plan. Detroit Free Press,
March 23, 31A, 5A.
Galster, G. (2012). Driving Detroit. Philadelphia: Pennsylvania University Press.
Gillette, C. P. (2014). Dictatorships for Democracy: Takeovers of Financially Failed Cities.
Columbia Law Review, 114(6), 1373–1462.
Glaeser, E. (2011). Triumph of the City. New York: Penguin.
Gold, H. (2013). Detroit, The Right’s Perfect Pinata. Politico, August 18. Retrieved from:
www.politico.com/story/2013/08/detroit-michigan-conservatives-095630?o=0
Hackworth, J. (2007). The Neoliberal City: Governance, Ideology, and Development in American
Urbanism. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Hackworth, J. (2017). Defiant Neoliberalism and the Danger of Detroit. Tijdschrift voor
Economische en Sociale Geografie, forthcoming.
Hill, R. C. (1983). Crisis in the Motor City: The Politics of Economic Development in
Detroit. In S. S. Fainstein, N. I. Fainstein, R. C. Hill, D. Judd, and M. P. Smith (Eds.),
Restructuring the City: The Political Economy of Urban Redevelopment (pp. 80–125). New
York: Longman.
Hodge, T. R., Skidmore, M., Sands, G., and McMillen, D. (2015). Tax Base Erosion and
Inequity from Michigan’s Assessment Growth Limit: The Case of Detroit. Public Finance
Review, 43(5), 636–660.
Jessop, B. (2012). Left Strategy. Transform!, 10, 9–17.
Kantor, P., Savitch, H. V., and Haddock, S. V. (1997). The Political Economy of Urban
Regimes: A Comparative Perspective. Urban Affairs Review, 32(3), 348–377.
Kimmelman, M. (2017). The Lights Are On in Detroit. New York Times, January 11, C1.
Kinder, K. (2016). DIY Detroit. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Kinney, R. J. (2016). Beautiful Wasteland. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Kushma, D. (1984, January 1). Detroit Mayor Endures. Detroit Free Press, 1A, 10A.
Ladd, H. F. (1994). Big-City Finances. In G. F. Peterson (Ed.), Big-City Politics, Governance,
and Fiscal Constraints (pp. 201–269). Washington, DC: Urban Institute Press.
Malanga, S. (2013a). The Real Reason the Once Great City of Detroit Came to Ruin.
Wall Street Journal, July 27, A13.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Neoliberalizing Detroit 197

Malanga, S. (2013b). The Man Who Killed Detroit. Wall Street Journal, August 2.
Retrieved from: www.wsj.com/video/opinion-the-man-who-killed-detroit/86E6D085-
86E5-47B2-9DA1-DCD4776674F9.html
Marback, R. (1998). Detroit and the Closed Fist: Toward a Theory of Material Rhetoric.
Rhetoric Review, 17(1), 74–92.
McGraw, B. (2005). The Quotations of Mayor Coleman A. Young. Detroit, MI: Wayne State
University Press.
Mitsotakis, S. (2013). Detroit Betrayed: The Radical Wrecking of an Iconic City. Forbes,
January 13. Retrieved from: www.forbes.com/sites/realspin/2013/01/13/detroit-betra
yed-the-radical-wrecking-of-an-iconic-city/#2ac0f8f64476
Moskowitz, P. (2015). The Two Detroits: A City Both Collapsing and Gentrifying at the
Same Time. Guardian, February 5. Retrieved from: www.theguardian.com/cities/2015/
feb/05/detroit-city-collapsing-gentrifying
Orr, M. E., and Stoker, G. (1994). Urban Regimes and Leadership in Detroit. Urban
Affairs Review, 30(1), 48–73.
Peck, J. (2010). Constructions of Neoliberal Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Peck, J. (2014). Pushing Austerity: State Failure, Municipal Bankruptcy and the Crises of
Fiscal Federalism in the USA. Cambridge Journal of Regions, Economy and Society, 7(1), 17–44.
Peck, J. (2015). Framing Detroit. In M. P. Smith and L. O. Kirkpatrick (Eds.), Reinventing
Detroit (pp. 145–166). Piscataway, NJ: Transaction.
Peck, J. (2017). Transatlantic City, Part 1: Conjunctural Urbanism. Urban Studies, 54(1),
4–30.
Peck, J., Theodore, N., and Brenner, N. (2013). Neoliberal Urbanism Redux? International
Journal of Urban and Regional Research, 37(3), 1091–1099.
Peck, J., and Whiteside, H. (2016). Financializing Detroit. Economic Geography, 92(3),
235–268.
Ravitch, R. (2014). So Much to Do. New York: Public Affairs.
Reese, L. A., and Sands, G. (2013). No Easy Way Out: Detroit’s Financial and Govern-
ance Crises. Retrieved from: www.dmu.ac.uk/documents/business-and-law-documents/
research/lgru/laurareeseandgarysands.pdf
Rich, W. C. (1989). Coleman Young and Detroit Politics: From Social Activist to Power Broker.
Detroit: Wayne State University Press.
Segal, D. (2013). Motor City Missionary. New York Times, April 14, BU1.
Shaw, T. C. (2009). Now is the Time!Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Sugrue, T. J. (2005). The Origins of the Urban Crisis. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Tabb, W. (2014) The Wider Context of Austerity Urbanism. City, 18, 87–100.
Theodore, N., and Peck, J. (2012). Framing Neoliberal Urbanism: Translating “Common
Sense” Urban Policy Across the OECD Zone. European Urban and Regional Studies,
19(1), 20–41.
Theodore, N., Peck, J., and Brenner, N. (2011). Neoliberal Urbanism: Cities and the Rule
of Markets. In G. Bridge and S. Watson (Eds.), The New Blackwell Companion to the City
(pp. 15–25). Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
Thomas, J. M. (2013). Redevelopment and Race. Detroit: Wayne State University Press.
Thompson, H. A. (2001). Rethinking the Collapse of Postwar Liberalism: The Rise of
Mayor Coleman Young and the Politics of Race in Detroit. In D. R. Colburn and J. S.
Adler (Eds.), African-American Mayors: Race, Politics, and the American City (pp. 57–79).
Urbana: University of Illinois Press.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

198 Jamie Peck and Heather Whiteside

Tyson, R. (1975). Mayor Young a Year Later. The Nation, March 1, 237–240.
Wall Street Journal (2013). Saving Detroit from Itself. Wall Street Journal, July 27, A14.
Wilson, J. Q. (1998). The Closing of the American City. New Republic, May 11, 30–38.
Wylie, J. (1989). Poletown. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.
YoungC. with Wheeler, L. (1994). Hard Stuff. New York: Viking.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

11
POLITICAL DISSENT IN AMMAN,
JORDAN
Neoliberal Geographies of Protest and Policing

Jillian Schwedler

Jordan is a non-democratic country that has a long but uneven history of vibrant
political protest. It is a country of some 7 million people, with a monarchy that
hails from the Arabian peninsula and more than half the population as refugees.
The capital city of Amman is a sprawling metropolis that just a century ago was a
dusty outpost. While the dramatic expansion of the city over the past century
created new spaces available for protests – such as locations adjacent to Parliament,
the Office of the Prime Ministry, the Professional Associations Complex, and
Gamal Abdul Nasser traffic circle (known locally as the Interior Ministry Circle,
Dakhaliya) – other prominent sites of protest – like the city center – have become
significantly less visibile and less disruptive. Some of these changes came by
design, as discussed below, but many did not.
Alterations to the city’s geography emerged through the creation of entirely
new neighborhoods and commercial spaces, and the repurposing of others. The
meanings attached to specific places also evolved, resulting as much from
the new built environment as from the ways in which people came to use those
spaces. Protesters adapted to the changes, adopting new locations and abandoning
others.
This chapter explores a geography of dissent in Amman. First, I examine
militarization and the increased securitization that emerged first under neoliber-
alism and now during the crisis temporality of the ISIS threat. Efforts to create or
maintain order are not imposed on the spaces of the city, but rather they are
directly built into it.
Second, I examine the spatial dynamics of protest and policing, examining how
policing practices vary across the city’s geography, affected in large part by ques-
tions related to class, visibility, and the tribal or ethnic associations of individual
neighborhoods. I then examine two protests in particular: the spring 2002 protests
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

200 Jillian Schwedler

against the Israeli invasion of several Palestinian towns, and the March 24 Youth
Movement that emerged in 2011.
Third, I examine regime efforts to control spaces of protest in the aftermath of
protests, including attempts to strip them of their meaning. I examine erasures,
enclosures, and exposures as three techniques for inscribing new meaning on
places that came to be associated with political dissent.

State Attempts at Controlling Public Space


As James C. Scott illustrates, all cities are conceived with questions of order and
control in mind (1999). The many urban planning documents for Amman imagined
new neighborhoods, public spaces, modes of transport, and patterns of leisure
activities, all of which required efforts to alter existing spaces or create new ones.
The effects of some of those projects, along with the dramatic expansion of the
city, had profound impacts on the political work of protests.
It is not that urban planners are directly implicated in the militarization of
cities, however. Rather, it is the very act of designing (whether an object, a
building, or a city) that resembles the function of the army in the way that both
fundamentally anticipate, and encourage specific behaviors. Regardless of inten-
tion, the creation of a new city supervised by a limited number of actors, and its
control by military elements, insures for designers that their anticipation proves
true (Lambert 2015, p. 4).
Thus it is not necessary that urban development projects explicitly embody
regime efforts to control or prevent the expression of political dissent, because
they already seek to direct and ecourage certain behaviors while discouraging
others. They may have aimed to create a sense of national memory, evidenced in
the 1955 urban plan and in the King Hussein Gardens project that houses the
Royal Automobile Museum. But the greatest constraint on protest and other
public expressions of political dissent came through such conventional repressive
measures as the imposition of martial law in 1957, the dissolution of parliament
and dismissal of the cabinet that year, and the defeat of the Palestinian militias
during the Black September civil war of 1970–1971.
Yet some urban development plans – like gated communities, the Abdali
project, and high-end commercial districts and tourist resorts – require that
explicit techniques of policing and surveillance be built into the plans. Other
urban developments and public infrastructure have the capacities for militarized
use during periods of crisis times built into them. The first such large-scale urban
development project was that of Paris in the late nineteenth century.

Militarization of Public Space


As scholars have long documented, Haussmann’s Paris was fashioned in part to
adjust the spatiality of the streets to accommodate the needs and hardware of
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Political Dissent in Amman, Jordan 201

modernizing armies, as well as to inhibit the mobilization and ability of revolu-


tionaries to control certain neighborhoods. Militarizing public space was also a
core technique of colonial administration. Lambert notes that, “One of the first
decisions of the French colonial administration in Algeria in 1830 consisted in
naming the streets of Algiers’s Casbah as well as in assigning a number to each
home” (2015, p. 5). Surveillance and policing is facilitated through legibility, as
discussed in more detail below. The objective of militarization is to create spaces
that are controllable through surveillance and policing during periods of normal
politics, but immediately accessible to militarized control during periods of crisis.
In Jordan, the militarization of the city is not always visible in the built envir-
onment. The city has no central square, and its maze of streets and steep roads are not
conducive to the movement of troops or heavy weaponry. But the more recent
improvements to the city’s infrastructure have militarized capacities. The road
past the King Hussein Medical Center was widened and repaved in 2006, almost
immediately following the December 2005 hotel bombings. In June 2006, it
carried a large contingent of troops and armored vehicles past spectator stands
from which King Abdullah and other government officials observed the forces in
commemoration of Army Day. The timing of the celebration was saturated with
meaning: although Army Day is celebrated annually on June 10, the regime had
not mounted large parades for at least a decade (Schwedler 2012). I mentioned to
a high-level army officer (not at the event) that I noticed that the medians on the
road had been removed so that the troops could march there. He said that the
road was also built to be an airstrip if needed.
New overpasses and underpasses are also built to accommodate the weight and
width of armored vehicles, as is the Abdoun bridge. The latter extends to a wide
road that descends gradually, with branches that curve west toward the airport
road and east toward the eastern neighborhoods of Amman. Underneath the
Abdoun bridge, a widened road is being constructed to facilitate movement into
and out of the city center from the south.
Cities are also militarized in less permanent infrastructure. In normal as well as crisis
times, numerous government agencies and security forces engage in the quotidian
militarization of public spaces. These include blocked roads, deviated passages, speed
bumps, no photography zones, tanks and sandbags, temporary and permanent no
parking zones, concrete barriers around buildings, the parking of government vehicles
to create blockages or bottlenecks, security points on roads and at hotels, malls, and
government buildings. These measures are not merely necessary inconveniences in
crisis times of heightened securitization. They are also practices whose irregularity dis-
rupts the routine movement of people as they seek to move within and across the city.

Securitization
Militarization is an aspect of securitization, but the latter extends to an almost
permanent and routine surveillance of daily life. Securitization also entails
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

202 Jillian Schwedler

increased mediation by nonhuman actors. Security camera networks and their


transactions multiply without human intervention. These also entail a speeding up
of transactions. In this way, networks of information – like Internet traffic – is
always both human and nonhuman (Grusin 2015, p. xiv). There is an accelerated
nonhuman rhythm (phrase borrowed from Grusin 2015, p. xiv).
As is the case with many neoliberal cities, Amman has become increasingly
securitized over the past decade. Consumer spaces and financial districts are in
need of constant surveillance, to protect foreign investment and agents, whom
the government has struggled to attract. The regime has adopted use of cameras
and facial recognition software, but not in all parts of the city. Securitization is
least visible in west Amman, where it is also most present.
As Fawaz et al. note of Beirut:

The various security mechanisms of Beirut ultimately consolidate in the


formation of an anxious cityscape with varying levels of intensity: “hot”
spots – the symbolic centers of political control – where the map reflects an
intense concentration of security elements, and “diffuse” areas where the
presence of the security apparel becomes comparatively diluted – nonetheless
almost always present. Security is furthermore a dynamic and continuously
changing concept. It operates within temporal regimes of “crisis time” and
“normal time” as well as night/day, weekday/weekend, etc. curing which
the cordoned-off areas spill over to their surroundings, including in their
bunkers additional streets and blocks, while additional “hot spots” are created
and neighborhood-level organization of security patrols and surveillance are
deployed.
(Fawaz et al. 2015, p. 10)

Attempts to map or identify such blockages will necessarily be valid and accurate
for only a moment; the boundaries and intensities of securitization are always in
flux. Indeed their unpredictability is a central factor in the functioning of their
power. Securitization is therefore not a set of techniques as much as a range of
practices that are always changing or potentially in flux. These insights bring the
differential geography of securitization into view. They help us to extend our
understanding of the control of public space and thus the policing of protest to
times and spaces beyond the actual protests themselves.

Crisis Temporalities
Periods of crisis always bring new and deepened practices of securitization and
militarization. Following the hotel bombings in December 2005 the city of
Amman saw a dramatic increase in concrete roadblocks that prevent vehicles from
approaching government buildings and hotels. Security checkpoints upon entering
the building became permanent. Shopping malls which already had security at the
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Political Dissent in Amman, Jordan 203

entrance increased surveillance and also established concrete barriers near major
entrances. The crisis temporality of the hotel bombings became semipermanent, a
new kind of normal for the capital city.
Curfews are another practice common to crisis temporalities. They illustrate
the ways in which controlling bodies by preventing them from exiting their
homes or moving in public keeps “unauthorized” bodies both out of our homes
and from escaping their own homes (Lambert 2015, p. 5).1
With the outbreak of the uprising in 2011 in new crisis temporality emerged in
Jordan. Even as the protests died down and the king claimed that politics had
returned to a new normal, the outcome was that the escalated securitization never
ended. And now with the threat of ISIS and its attempts to launch a major attack
inside of the kingdom, the crisis temporality is again the new normal. It
authorizes a permanent state of threatened securitization, much like the September
11 attacks in the United States created a permanent state of crisis.
At the same time, the Hashemite regime has aggressively marketed Jordan’s
“climate of stability” and its status as the moderate and friendly state in the
Middle East that the United States and much of the world so desperately wants.

Normal Temporalities
As noted, the militarization and securitization of public space is no less ongoing in
normal temporalities than it is at times of crisis. The surveillance and security
practices around spaces such as malls and commercial centers, for example, have
created an environment in which ostenibly public spaces are really private spaces,
unequally accessible and thus subject to all manner of private securitization. The
presence and unpredictability as to the location of no parking signs, security
cameras, speed bumps, and other blockages of public roads and spaces create
obstacles that people need to navigate on a daily basis (Fawaz et al. 2015, p. 9).
During a trip to Amman in 2016, numerous interviewees expressed frustration
at the extent to which it has become difficult to park and to navigate traffic in
the city. Two people separately told me that they felt that people had become
more rude, perhaps frustrated because of the periodic blockage of streets by police
vehicles. Drivers are increasingly thoughtless, they told me, stopping their own
cars where ever they choose, even in the middle of a traffic circle. While it is
unclear if the practice of police blocking road traffic has actually increased, the
effect is one of a strong police presence and the randomness of harassment as
people try to move about their daily lives.
Securitization has thus become a routine part of life in Amman, its practices
reproduced by a range of actors other than the regime.
As Sewell notes:

It is not only states that engage in the policing of spaces – that is, in activities
of surveillance and coercion. Both private firms and labor unions police the
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

204 Jillian Schwedler

factory floor, youth gangs cruise their neighborhoods protecting their


boundaries against incursions by gang members from other neighborhoods,
and eighteenth century neighbors were kept under informal surveillance
by gossiping shopkeepers and market women. This private policing ranges
from highly formal to extremely informal in both its procedures and its
punishments.
(2001, p. 69)

Spatial Dimensions of Protest Policing


Understanding these ongoing and permanent, if changing, forms of securitization
facilitates our understanding of how the policing of protest either deviates from or
reproduces quotidian forms of policing and surveillance. This section examines
some spatial dimensions of protest policing, with particular attention to variations
across neighborhoods based on economic status, tribal affiliation, or ethnicity.
How do policing practices vary? As one interviewee put it to me, what matters
most is not what you say, but who is saying it and where they are saying it.

Neighborhood
In theory, and in police academies, the policing of protest is based primarily on
the behavior of the protesters. The police are there to make sure that protesters
have the ability to express their freedom of speech but that they do so in a
manner that does not neglect the rights and property of others. In practice, the
policing of poor neighborhoods and people of color in the United States for
example, has always varied dramatically from quotidian policing practices in
wealthier neighborhoods. Similarly during protests, patterns of police repression
can be contingent on precisely who is doing the protesting, and where. Speaking
about the United States, Lambert observes:

Although the principle of citizenship is based on equality, in reality, we can


only observe how, in many of our cities, there are territories of sub-citizenry
where the police significantly increases violence, rather than diminishes it.
(2015, p. 5)

As we will see below, those policing practices extend well beyond the temporality
of the protest event itself.
In Jordan, policing of different neighborhoods varies considerably, in part based
on the real and perceived association of certain neighborhoods with different
communities of people. Some neighborhoods are associated with certain tribes or
other loyalist groups, although those loyalties are often exaggerated. But it is
nonetheless true that some communities are more assertive in expressing direct
critique of the regime, or even the king, than are other communities. The
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Political Dissent in Amman, Jordan 205

participation of Palestinians in the protest associated with Jordan’s uprising was


disproportionately low. As one longtime Jordanian activist told me, “You can yell
‘Yoskut Abdullah’ in places like Hay Tufayleh” – a neighborhood in southern
Amman that is settled largely by members and relatives from the East Bank town
of Tufayleh – “but do it in [Palestinian] Jebal Hussein and you will get tear-
gassed.” As discussed below, the police may react strongly to a smaller protest but
stand by while larger groups say identical things. Most likely, there are strong
identity-based reasons why Hay Tufayleh is allowed to say things that the
predominately Palestinian area of Jebal Hussein is not.
In many ways, these increased security mechanisms affect a reversal in

the private/public divide, allowing private control over the use of public
spaces. They also establish new social hierarchies defined according to users’
competence and the various forms of capital they can activate in this new
order. Hence, the implications of security deployment vary considerably
across users, depending on one’s position in the social, gender, moral,
national, and class hierarchies.
(Fawaz et al. 2015, pp. 10–11)

Class
Class has always been an important component affecting practices of policing
across the geography of a city. Policing is both more present and less visible in
many wealthier neighborhoods, where a wide range of surveillance techniques
and technologies are built into the architecture of commercial establishments and
private residences. Recall that a key dimension of the reconstruction of Paris
entailed the movement of working-class people out of affluent areas. Haussmann’s
reconstruction of Paris explicitly sought to make it harder for insurgents to avoid
the artillery and cavalry that could quell their uprising (Jordan 1996, p. 188–192).
As Sewell notes with reference to the insurrections in European capital cities
such as Paris, Berlin, Vienna, and Rome:

Not only did they have densely built poor neighborhoods whose labyr-
inthine streets were susceptible to barricades, but these working-class quarters
were within easy striking distance of the neighborhoods of the rich and of
the grand public squares of the ceremonial city.
(2001, p. 62)

In Amman, the policing practices between wealthier and poor neighborhoods are
significant. In places like the Wahdat refugee camp, the general police routinely
patrol the streets, as though they are neighborhood cops. When protests do
emerge, security forces make little attempt to stop the protest or clear the streets,
monitoring primarily to make sure the crowd does not turn violent. In wealthier
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

206 Jillian Schwedler

neighborhoods, the quotidian policing is less visible, except for traffic officers at
intersections and the board guards who stand in the booths in front of embassies,
staring down at their mobile phones and likely texting their friends. But it is also
more present, in the surveillance technologies. During protests in wealthier
neighborhoods, furthermore, security forces are typically out in force, even if
they are not necessarily aggressive in engaging the protesters. But the visibility of
the police is exponentially higher, sending a strong signal to protesters. On some
occastions, police attempt to prevent protesters from reaching the planned site.
This is particularly the case when numbers of people are expected to arrive from
other parts of the city or country.
Thus the tactics for policing and repressing protests are in part a function of the
space, visibility, and potential for disruption, but they are more significantly a
function of class and proximity to high-valued neighborhoods or commercial
districts. On campuses and in refugee camps – which are located in all parts of
Amman – the typical strategy for policing protests is containment, so that people
even just outside the area would probably be unaware of the demonstrations
nearby. As a student activist at the University of Jordan told me in 2006, “We can
do anything we want, as long as we don’t try to leave campus and march [down
University Road] toward downtown.” In proximity to neoliberal spaces, far less
protest activity is tolerated.

Contentious Spaces
Not all spaces are equally contentious. Many sites of protest are chosen for
symbolic reasons, such as the Occupy Wall Street movement, or because they are
the actual sites of the administrative offices embodying the power against which
the protesters aim to make claims. The symbolic meaning(s) of a place also can
have profound effects on the impact of a protest, and the political work that it
does, as well as the response of the security forces. Protest can entail engaging in
an activity that is viewed by some segment of the population or government as
unacceptable for that location: sit-ins by blacks in “white only” establishments;
“kiss-ins” by queer couples in redneck bars; stamping “keep money out of politics”
on US paper currency, and so on.2 These protests are contentious because they
transgress accepted understandings about the appropriate use of that particular
place, and by whom.
In the next sections, I explore two sets of protests, bringing to light questions
of political geography, visibility, and the meaning of particular public places. The
first are the massive protests that took place in Amman (and, indeed, across
Jordan) in 2002, in which the regime attempted to use symbolic space to deflate
anger expressed by protesters toward Israel and the Jordanian regime (for maintaining
the peace treaty), and transform it into support for humanitarian intervention for
Palestinians. The second are the March 24 Youth protests that took place as part
of Jordan’s 2011 uprising, in which a few hundred protesters aimed to set up a
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Political Dissent in Amman, Jordan 207

permanent “camp” near the Ministry of the Interior until demands for reforms
were met.

The Queen’s March3


In the spring of 2002, Israel invaded several towns under Palestinian control, and
Jordanians took to the streets across the country in the tens of thousands, to
protest. This included Jordanians in predominately Palestinian areas such as the
refugee camps, as well as in the supposedly loyalist and tribal areas. In Amman,
the protest continued for seven weeks, with the largest protests spreading over
each Friday–Saturday weekend. Some were so large that all of the major inter-
sections of the city came to a standstill. The army came in with tanks to monitor
many of the intersections, and to contain the protesters, but it made few efforts to
actually end the protest. To do so would have taken extreme repression of the
sort the regime has been reluctant to adopt.
A few weeks into the protests, the regime launched a campaign aimed at
redirecting the anger of the protest away from demands to abrogate Jordan’s
peace treaty with Israel, and toward the needs of the Palestinian people as a result
of the crisis. That is, it aimed to direct outrage away from critique and instead
toward humanitarian assistance. The king announced a fund raising initiative,
accompanied by a telethon with many local celebrities and politicians appearing.
Jordanians were encouraged to send a text to a specific number from their mobile
phones, which would enable them to donate 10 Jordanian dinars, approximately
$14, to the humanitarian relief effort.
A second initiative was launched by the Jordan River Foundation, a royally
affiliated organization. The event was to be a large march in support of the need
for Palestinian humanitarian relief, organized to commence at the Fifth Circle (a
traffic circle along Zahran road, leading into downtown Amman). That site held
no special or relevant symbolism connected to Palestinians or the particular con-
flict, and many activists mocked the choice of location, with its five-star hotels
including the Ritz Carlton. Queen Rania let the march, accompanied by pro-
minent businessmen, parliamentarians, and other powerful individuals including
from many of the prominent tribal families.
While Jordanians were protesting in spaces that signified, either directly or
indirectly, the authorities they felt were responsible for enabling Israel’s actions,
the Queen’s March took its assembly of elites and notables just one kilometer
away to a UN office of humanitarian affairs. The office was also closed when they
arrived.
The importance of the march is that it illustrated the regime’s recognition of
the national outrage against the United States and Israel, at a time when the
regime was deeply committed to maintaining good relations with both states.
The alternative march, although it was not joined by average or working-class
Jordanians, sought to align the regime with sympathy and caring for the
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

208 Jillian Schwedler

Palestinians without taking in expressions of outrage at Israel or the United States.


The Queen’s March conveyed its own meanings, by the symbolism of the desti-
nation, but without trying to reinscribe new meaning or its alternative humani-
tarian message onto the spaces at which tens of thousands of Jordanians were
assembling.

March 24 Youth Movement4


Jordan’s uprising during 2011 received far less attention than did those in Egypt,
Syria, Yemen, Libya, and Tunisia, but it was not less significant even if it did not
escalate sufficiently to topple the regime. Tens of thousands of Jordanians pro-
tested weekly through much of that year, but most of the protests adhered to
familiar patterns and took place in the usual symbolic locations. On March 24,
2011, hundreds of Jordanians calling themselves the March 24 Youth began an
indefinite sit-in at the Dakhaliya traffic circle, not far from an office of the Ministry
of the Interior. As one participant stated prior to the event:

We are a mixture of free Jordanian young men and women, who are tired of
delays and the promise of reform, who see the spread of corruption, the
deterioration of the economic situation, the regression of political life, the
erasure of freedoms, and the dissolution of the social fabric.
(Jadaliyya Reports 2011)

The riot police showed up in force but with few signs of intervening on the first
day. It merely blocked off the traffic circle while some officers spoke to some of
the protesters. As had become common at many protests in Jordan, the protesters
decided to position themselves as a pro nationalist group. They did not call for
the downfall of the regime, and they even brought Jordanian flags and photos of
the king to assuage concerns that their protest was going to call for his downfall.
A few hours into their protest, a second group that described itself as a Loyalty
March, positioned themselves facing the March 24 Youth. This group chanted in
praise of King Abdullah and launched insults at the March 24 Youth, but the first
day of the sit-in was mostly calm, and the evening passed with little incident
(Jadaliyya Reports 2011). As one eyewitness described the scene:

Underneath the bridge was a fairly well-organized group of young 20-


something year olds. They had their posters in Arabic and English. They had
a truck with a sound system. They had low-level organizers with bullhorns
who would walk around making sure their group kept to the sidewalk. They
had brooms and garbage bags, and people designated the task of keeping the
area clean. They had tents, food, laptops, Internet connections, digital cameras,
camcorders, a live feed going, as well as a fire roaring in near-freezing
weather. At the tip of the sidewalk, their members were lined up facing the
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Political Dissent in Amman, Jordan 209

circle, where across from them was another group, and in between them
both were about two dozen policemen.
(Tarawnah 2011)

In the morning, as the Youth began their morning prayers, the Loyalty March
began blaring patriotic music over the prayers. One protester told me that the
security forces and the loyalists were under the belief, erroneously, that the pro-
testers were made up primarily of Islamists who wanted to call for the downfall of
the regime. He said that numerous protesters told them otherwise, but they were
convinced that it was an Islamist event.
As the day progressed, busloads of baltajiya – pro-regime “thugs” who are not
formally employed by the regime but who often arrive to do the dirty work the
regime wants done – arrived and took up positions surrounding the peaceful
protesters. They began to throw stones and beat on the protesters with their
clubs, all the while the Darak forces stood by and did nothing. Many protesters
struggled to escape around barricades and over fences that had been rapidly
assembled to contain them. In the melee, one Jordanian was killed (Bouziane and
Lenner 2011; Tobin 2012). The incident was captured on video and posted to
YouTube.
The protest, and its repression, was notable because it took place in the climate
of widespread protest across the Kingdom. It was also during a period of crisis
temporality, with uprisings across the region challenging various regimes. But
only this protest was severely repressed in Jordan, although without question the
security forces worked hard to contain protest across the country. In that context
however, the question arises as to why this severe response to a relatively small
protest.
The protest was certainly contentious because it was intended as an indefinite
sit-in, much like the one in Cairo’s Tahrir Square. From the regime’s perspective,
preventing the establishment of an ongoing sit-in was probably of the utmost
importance. The location of the protest at the Dakhaliya traffic circle was even
more contentious. Although the site was not a well-known or possibly ever used
site for protest, its location near the Ministry of the Interior suggested that the
protesters were attempting to inscribe new meaning on the location. In fact, as
we shall see below, they were somewhat successful in that endeavor, even though
the protest was crushed on only the second day.
These two examples illustrate the extent to which the meaning and practices of
a particular location – that is, its cultural understanding as a place – can produce
observable effects in terms of regime response. In the Queen’s March, the regime
sought to appropriate the pro-Palestinian narrative of the widespread protest, and
turn it into a pro-Palestinian humanitarian relief narrative. It did so through the
symbolic meaning of the location of the path of the March, ending at a United
Nations humanitarian relief agency. In the March 24 Youth protest, by comparison,
the choice of a location near the Ministry of the Interior let the regime repress
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

210 Jillian Schwedler

the protesters in a manner they had not done with any of the other protests, the
thousands of protests, that had taken place even in the crisis temporality of the
Arab uprisings.

After Protests
The policing of protest does not end when protests do. By adopting an analytic
framework that examines securitization through the lens of political geography,
or place in space, we begin to see broader patterns of control, repression, and the
mechanisms that work to silence or obscure a range of practices of political dissent
that play out across the spaces of the city.
The March 24 Youth movement attempted to inscribe new meaning onto the
Dakhaliya traffic circle, and in many ways it succeeded. The resources of security
forces are always significantly greater than those of protesters, which is why the
latter need to exploit every sliver of power they can leverage, including the
mobilization of meaning. As Sewell puts it:

Insurgents are normally resource-poor – at least by comparison with the


states, established churches, local oligarchies, corporate capitalists, and other
entrenched interests against whom they are contending. This limits the forms
of spatial agency that are available to them. Whereas business corporations or
states can engineer massive changes in the physical environment – by building
factories, roads, canals, ports, new urban neighborhoods, and the like – insurgents
in contentious politics must generally accept the physical environment as given.
Insurgents produce space above all by changing the meanings and strategic
uses of their environments.
(2001, p. 55–56)

After protests, therefore, regimes engage in practices that work to remove the
remnants of any narrative of insurgency and any challenges to their claims to
legitimate authority. They do this through a variety of means, some of which are
aimed at ostensibly reconstructing areas damaged by the protest, and others of
which serve as warnings and reminders to people to consider the consequences
before engaging in such protests ever again.
In post-civil war Beirut, the reconstruction of the city functioned not just to
repair neighborhoods, but to entirely refashion large districts into elite enclaves. As
Mona Fawaz argues, security concerns were primary considerations during recon-
struction, manifest explicity in the “privatization of security and its deployment to
protect the rich” (Fawaz et al. 2015, p. 9). Post-protest security practices are aimed
more at preventing future challenges to elite interests then they are at redressing the
grievances, injustices, and inequalities that led people to protest in the first place.
There are three additional techniques that aim to control pubic space con-
nected to protests (and possibilities of expressing political dissent), all of which
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Political Dissent in Amman, Jordan 211

betray insecurities about losing control of the narratives and symbolism of spaces.
Some of these efforts are connected with repurposing spaces, the effects of which
are an apparent erasure of revolutionary temporalities, or at least attempts at such
erasures.

Exposures
One set of practices or techniques after protests end is to create exposures.
Following Michael Brown’s death and the large protest in Ferguson, Missouri,
the city cut down dozens if not hundreds of hardwood trees that surrounded park
where Brown was killed and that stood in front of many private homes and
apartment complexes. Such a move is unquestionably an act of violence on a
poor community – brake trees and green spaces are often a luxury. In Cairo,
numerous trees were also cut down after the uprising, exposing the neighborhood –
as it had exposed the neighborhood in Ferguson – to not only a punishment, but
also to an increased sense of surveillance and exposure.
As Parker argues, similar techniques have been used in poorer neighborhoods
in Amman. He notes that, “wider boulevards were cut through the refugee
camps and popular quarters of East Amman, opening them to surveillance and
military intervention” (Parker 2009, p. 112).

Erasures
Another set of practices that follow protests entail erasures: efforts to scrub out a
particular place, along with the meaning that was inscribed into it as a result of
the protest. For example, in Bahrain the regime entirely disassembled the sculpture
at the Pearl Roundabout where protesters had assembled in massive numbers. It
removed the symbol of the protest in an attempt to erase the temporality that
imagined a new future, and to reinscribe the space with the memory of both a
failed protest and the regime’s willingness to go to great lengths to crush it.
But those efforts have not been successful. Even with the Pearl Roundabout
sculpture removed, Bahrainis have continued to stencil images of the sculpture all
over Bahrain. The regime whitewashes over the images quite quickly, but those
who stencil them take photographs and post them on the Internet, on sites such
as www.rebeliouswalls.com. Some have even gotten tattoos of the roundabout
sculpture. The regime has tried to erase the symbolic image, even removing from
circulation a coin depicting it. Their efforts suggest a desire to eliminate from
memory the possibilities that were introduced with the uprising, and the new
temporality that came with it.
In Cairo, too, paintings and posters signifying the revolution have since been
removed. But people do not stop trying to maintain the revolutionary meaning
of the space, even if through small steps such as walking across the square wearing
a T-shirt with a provocative, revolutionary message. There, the regime has also
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

212 Jillian Schwedler

tried to introduce new signification in those spaces. For example, in Tahrir, the
regime has erected a statue that commemorates and celebrates the contribution of
the police to the nation. While in Rabaa, another statue has been erected, this
one commemorating the military. These symbols remind Egyptians who came
out of the revolution on top.
Both the moves of the activists and protesters, and the efforts of the regime,
point to the importance of such public spaces and the meanings attached to them.
No one in Egypt mistakes the fact that the current regime means to crush any
revolutionary activity. Protest continues, however, although very rarely in Tahrir.
It is a mistake to think that the struggle has stopped in such spaces. Using a lens of
geography and place, we see that protest extends well beyond conventional spatial
and temporal boundaries, to include an ongoing struggle over the use and
meaning of public places.

Closures and Enclosures: The Landscapes of Policing


Finally, a third technique has been to try to and close public spaces, particularly
those that have been used for protest, in order to both reduce accessibility as well
as to inscribe new meaning upon them. As with the earlier examples, efforts to
change the meaning can, at least for a time, serve to also remind the population
of the lengths to which the regime is willing to go in order to limit or silence
voices of dissent. In Cairo, the Gamal Abdul Nasser subway station underneath
Tahrir has been closed indefinitely, but the symbolism of the square is now so
powerful that it is unlikely that what happened there will be forgotten. For the
regime, it is at best a bracketing of that new meaning, rather than a full erasure.
A variation on this technique is to reconstruct or repurpose the spaces of protest
in ways that aim to create new meanings. In Jordan, one of the most significant
developments since 2014 has been the efforts, so far successful, to enclose former
sites of protest with fences. This has taken place in at least three locations: at the
Fourth Circle, at Dakhaliya circle, and at the field adjacent to the Kaluti mosque.
The Fourth Circle is located at the main office of Prime Ministry. In the 1990s,
it was a common location for protest. At that time, there were no underpasses and
overpasses so that protests at this circle could effectively shut down all traffic at the
major intersection and create considerable congestion in the city. With the 2000s,
however, the high-speed underpasses made it extremely difficult for protesters to
stop traffic. Even more, a protest that clustered around the pedestrian area of the
square might not even be visible to passersby in cars traversing the underpasses. This
is a case of urban development rendering protest less visible, and thus making
protesters do lesser or at least different kinds of political work.
With the outbreak of the uprisings in 2011, however, the Circle came into
increased use once again. Many different protests were held there, including by
the Islamist Salafi protesting to have some of their number released from prison.
Tribal groups also protested there to prevent the construction of nuclear energy
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Political Dissent in Amman, Jordan 213

facilities on their land. Teachers, who had been struggling to develop a union for
years, also protested there. And the list goes on. In 2015, however, the traffic
circle was fenced off, and the spaces that were previously open to pedestrians
were landscaped with trees and flowers.
The pedestrian area around the Dakhaliya traffic circle suffered a similar fate. It,
too, has since 2015 being fenced off and landscaped. The large field adjacent to
the Kaluti mosque has also been fenced off, although to date it is still a dusty
field, perhaps too large for the regime to pay for landscaping. In these and other
ways, protest and the policing of protest might better be understood as ongoing
processes and practices, not simply undertakings of limited spatial and temporal
duration. They entail struggles over space and place, struggles that reveal that the
work of protests is not merely about making claims, but also about making
meaning in the context of an expanding neoliberal city.

Struggles of Public Spaces


Struggles over public spaces are not limited to interactions between protesters or
activists and security forces. They are a routine part of daily life for many who
live in Amman, or indeed in any urban or other setting. Regimes draw up plans
about how to use and develop public space; people always engage with and traverse
spaces in their own ways.
As Parker notes, when the municipal government closed the Abdali transit
terminal and moved it farther out of the city, the result was not merely an incon-
venienced population. Rather, people created entirely new “informal hubs” for
transportation in “defiance of urban planning” (Parker 2009, p. 113). Such efforts
and practices are not rare. They are, rather, a routine part of the practices of the
population. That is, on a routine basis urban residents in Amman interact with, and
resist, the materiality of the built environment. It seems almost sport the extent to
which residents rip up and cut out speed bumps intended to slow traffic, removing
them in a matter of hours or perhaps days. They also tear down parking signs that
are not to their liking and use public spaces in their preferred manner.
It is a losing battle for the regime, in some ways, in that they cannot control all
public spaces. Despite the construction of the elaborate and beautiful parks, in the
west part of the city, people continue to picnic along the highways, and on public and
private land overlooking the Jordan River Valley. They bring chairs, water pipes,
barbecue equipment, blankets, and everything to spend the day on the road side.
Protests are not separate from, but rather they are an integral part of, the ways
in which people utilize the spaces and places of the city and inscribe them with
meanings through their practices. The changing levels of securitization and
militarization that characterize the neoliberalization of this and other major urban
centers, particularly those that strive to elevate themselves in the global economy
and cosmopolitan culture that goes along with it, create new practices as people
stubbornly refuse to fall in line.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

214 Jillian Schwedler

Notes
1 The violence of the physical structures is made explicit in such moments, but is not
absent during “normal” times.
2 Jasper gives numerous examples (1997, p. 6).
3 This section builds on the analysis presented in Schwedler and Fayyaz (2010).
4 This section builds on the analysis presented in Schwedler (2013).

References
Bouziane, Malika, and Lenner, Katharina (2011). Protests in Jordan: Rumblings in the
Kingdom of Dialogue. In Center for Middle Eastern and North African Politics (Ed.),
Protests, Revolutions, and Transformations: The Arab World in a Period of Upheaval. Working
Paper No. 1, July, 148–165.
Fawaz, Mona, Harb, Mona, and Gharbieh, Ahmad (2015). Beirut: Mapping Security. The
Funambulist: Politics of Space and Bodies, 1(September), 8–13.
Grusin, Richard (2015). Introduction. In Richard Gruisin (Ed.), The Nonhuman Turn
(pp. vii–xxix). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Jadaliyya Reports (2011). Jordan’s March 24 Youth Sit-in Violently Dispersed. March 26.
Retrieved from: www.jadaliyya.com/pages/index/1012/jordans-march-24-youth-sit-
in-violently-dispersed-
Jasper, James M. (1997). The Art of Moral Protest: Culture, Biography, and Creativity in Social
Movements. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Jordan, David P. (1996). Transforming Paris: The Life and Labors of Baron Haussmann. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Lambert, Léopold (2015). Introduction: Militarized Cities, The Funambulist: Politics of Space
and Bodies, 1(September), 2–7.
Parker, Christopher (2009). Tunnel-Bypasss and Minarets of Capitalism: Amman as Neoliberal
Assemblage. Political Geography, 28, 110–120.
Schwedler, Jillian (2012). The Political Geography of Protest in Neoliberal Jordan. Middle
East Critique, 21(3) (December), 259–270.
Schwedler, Jillian (2013). Jordan. In Paul Amar and Vijay Prashad (Eds.), Dispatches from the
Arab Spring (pp. 243–265). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Schwedler, Jillian, and Fayyaz, Sam (2010). Permitting Protest. In Laleh Khalili and Jillian
Schwedler (Eds.), Policing and Prisons in the Middle East: Ambiguities of Coercion (pp. 279–294).
New York: Columbia University Press and Hurst Publishers.
Scott, James C. (1999). Seeing Like a State: How Certain Schemes to Improve the Human
Condition Have Failed. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Sewell, William H., Jr. (2001). Space in Contentious Politics. In Ronald R. Aminzade
et al., (Eds.), Silence and Voice in the Study of Contentious Politics (pp. 51–88). New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Tarawnah, Naseem (2011). The Quick Death of Shabab March 24 and What It Means for
Jordan. Black Iris blog, March 26. Retrieved from: http://black-iris.com/2011/03/26/
the-quick-death-of-shabab-march-24-and-what-it-means-for-jordan/ (accessed January
30, 2016).
Tobin, Sarah A. (2012). Jordan’s Arab Spring: The Middle Class and the Anti-Revolution.
Middle East Policy, 19(1) (Spring), 96–109.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

PART V

Forward
Working Through Neoliberalism
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

12
THE KNIGHT’S MOVE
Social Policy Change in an Age of
Consolidated Power

Sanford Schram

With the election of Donald J. Trump as President, we confront the possibilities


for fundamental transformation for the welfare state along neoliberal lines. While
most people may have not voted for neoliberalism, it is distinctly possible that
that is what they will get with a Trump administration working in tandem with
Republican majorities in the House and Senate. Neoliberalism in fact is today
increasingly best characterized as the public philosophy that orients decision-
making at the individual and collective level, across all spheres of social life, not
just the market but also civil society and the state as well. Across the developed
world but elsewhere too, changes in social welfare policies in particular but public
policy more generally reflect the growing influence of the market-centered
philosophy of neoliberalism (Schram 2015). It has become the default logic for
public policymaking today. A long time in coming to ascendancy, neoliberalism
arose in response as the welfare state gained traction during and after the Great
Depression of the 1930s (Peck 2011). Neoliberalism’s basic tenets were promulgated
by Ludwig von Mises, Friedrich Hayek, and Gary Becker. It came to be asso-
ciated with the “Chicago School” of Economics. Especially as articulated by
Becker and Chicago School fellow travelers, neoliberalism is centrally about the
superiority of economic logic as the basis for all decision-making, public as well as
private, collective and individual. A critical feature of neoliberalism is that it blurs
the boundary between the market, civil society, and the state. Neoliberalism dis-
seminates economic rationality to be the touchstone not just for the market but
for civil society and the state as well. Its emphasis on economic rationality as
standing in for what is rational per se promotes marketization of an increasing
number of practices throughout society. Most dramatically, it has led to wholesale
revision in public policy in a number of domains to be more consistent with
market logic in the name of better promoting market-compliant behavior by as
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

218 Sanford Schram

much of the citizenry as possible. It places increased emphasis on people practicing


personal responsibility by applying economic logic to all forms of decision-
making across a variety of spheres of life. People are expected to practice personal
responsibility by investing in their own human capital to make themselves less of
a burden on society as a whole or face the consequences of a heightened disciplinary
regime. It is this last part that is often neglected (Harcourt 2010). Neoliberalism’s
emphasis on personal responsibility for the choices people make has led to a more
get-tough approach to social welfare policy.
The ongoing neoliberalization of social welfare policy itself is now taking place
during a time of transformation that is fraught with risks for individuals, families,
and societies as a whole, indeed for the global economy overall. The ascendency
of neoliberalism as the prevailing rationality of our time is unfolding during what
policy analysts call a “critical juncture,” where a well-ingrained “path dependency”
in social welfare policies has come under increased pressure to change (Pierson
2000). This critical juncture is associated with a cyclical swing back from policy
commitments that have dominated the social welfare state in the Post-World War
II era (Stiglitz 2012). The waning of support for the welfare state is however
complicated by changes in the economy in recent years. In today’s world, post
the Great Recession, when the economy seems to be recovering but in an
increasingly unequal way, there is return of what we can call “ordinary capitalism”
that has provided a new neoliberal normal of growing inequality and dwindling
economic opportunities for people on the bottom of the socio-economic order
(Schram 2015, chapter 1). Under neoliberalism’s insistence on the pervasive reliance
on economic logic as the basis for all decision-making, public as well as private,
collective as well as individual, the state buttresses markets rather than counters
them and inequality grows virtually unabated, as not a bug but rather as feature of
this latest (neoliberal) iteration of the return to ordinary capitalism (Sassen 2006).
In this context, the neoliberalization of social welfare policy indicates a stark
shift in orientation. While the state’s social welfare policy in capitalist societies has
always been attuned to market forces, neoliberal welfare policy represents a sig-
nificant shift away from a state that sought to buffer the effects of the market for
those who were least able to participate in it effectively to now re-purposing the
welfare state to be one that explicitly is committed to buttress the market rather
than to counteract its most deleterious effects (Schram 2015, chapter 1). Examining
changes in major social welfare policy primarily in the USA but also in other
countries provides evidence of how the neoliberalization of social welfare policy
today includes putting in place a heightened disciplinary regime for managing
subordinate populations who are deemed to be deficient in complying with the
dictates of an increasingly marketized society where people are expected to
leverage their human capital in order to provide for themselves and their families.
In what follows, I trace the rise of neoliberalism as the default logic of today’s
political economy throughout the world. I examine in detail its animating sources
and its underlying philosophical roots. I review how it has come to be the
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

The Knight’s Move 219

common sense of capitalist political economies across the globe, and how it
operates to structure public policymaking and policy design in those societies. I
specify as an example the way neoliberalism has influenced welfare policy
implementation in the United States. I conclude with considerations on how to
get beyond neoliberalism in social welfare policy via what I call a “radical incre-
mentalism” that makes small changes within the existing social welfare policies
that lay the groundwork for more progressive changes down the road. The
example provided is the current controversy over repealing Obamacare. If public
policymaking were chess, social justice advocates must consider making the
“knight’s move” to work around the prevailing political limits to progressive
change.

The Rise of Neoliberalism: From Explicit Theory to Default Practice


Neoliberalism evolved in the twentieth century from being the preoccupation of
economic theorists to becoming the default logic for public policymaking across
the globe. At first, it was sustained largely in the writings of Ludwig von Mises
and Friedrich Hayek and their followers in the Mt. Pelerin Society (Stedman
Jones 2014). It most centrally is reflected in their critiques of the welfare state but
especially the thinking of John Maynard Keynes and the idea that the state should
be a bulwark to counter the market. For Keynes, only the state was large and
powerful enough to counter the excesses that come with swings in the market.
The rise of Keynesianism and its emphasis on countercyclical policy provoked a
strong reaction from theorists like Hayek in particular.
Hayek believed that the state could not be omniscient and that the decen-
tralized market produced more points of information and was therefore a more
intelligent system of decision-making. Hayek’s Road to Serfdom critiqued the idea
of welfare state that would undermine the autonomy of markets. He did concede
the need for the state to provide for those who could not participate in the
market enough to sustain themselves and their families. Hayek’s work went on to
prove to be catalytic in rolling back welfare state policies, not just in capitalist
societies but eventually also in communist countries after the fall of the Soviet
Union.
Hayek, however, was no simple conservative or classic economic liberal who
prized individual freedom in some unreflective way. His neoliberalism was well
captured when he said:

We assign responsibility to a man, not in order to say that as he might have


acted differently, but in order to make him different. … It is doubtless
because the opportunity to build one’s own life also means an unceasing task,
a discipline that man must impose upon himself if he is to achieve his aims,
that many people are afraid of liberty.
(Hayek 1960, pp. 70–75)
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

220 Sanford Schram

While vigilant in highlighting unwarranted forms of coercion, Hayek was in


many ways the father of what would come to be called “responsibilization” and
the idea that society needed to be structured to discipline subordinate populations
to be economically compliant. Hayek saw neoliberalism in the practices that
worked to produce a certain type of citizen/subject who was market savvy and
compliant in all their choice making activities.
Milton Friedman was distinctively influential in developing the Chicago
School of economic theorizing. His biggest contribution to the rise of neoliberalism
was to oppose his ideas of monetarism to that of Keynesianism (Stedman Jones
2014). Rather than an active state counteracting the swings of the market, the
state should back away from such fiscal policies that raised or lowered taxes and
spending and instead impose a stable monetary system of moderate predictable
growth. The goal of the state should not be to aggressively respond to market
swings but instead should tamp things down by putting in place a stable flow of
money. By the late 1970s, in the USA in particular, the problems of simultaneous
high inflation and low economic growth – that is, stagflation – produced growing
frustration with Keynesian policies, the election of Ronald Reagan as president,
and the institution of Friedman’s monetarism as official policy by the US govern-
ment’s Federal Reserve Board which was charged with primary responsibility for
managing the monetary system. Friedman’s ideas had gone from the classroom
and his textbooks to the halls of government. Now the state’s job was not to
counter the market but to support it.
The “Reagan Revolution” as it was called produced reductions in social welfare
spending, deregulation of the economy, and tax cuts for the wealthy (Moynihan
1988). It was mirrored in the policies of Margaret Thatcher in her long run as
Prime Minister of England (Krieger 1986). It was Thatcher who gave us TINA
(there is no alternative) as the most thoughtless version of the need to back away
from Keynesianism (Hay and Payne 2015). As this would become a common-
place slogan, the era of big government was over. While poverty rose and
inequality accelerated, the momentum had swung away from the Keynesian
welfare state toward a neoliberalized political economy where the state facilitated
rather than counteracted an economy that had these inequitable outcomes. Growing
poverty and inequality were not unintended as much as they were defining features
of a system where the state facilitated economic growth that produced winners
and losers.
By then neoliberalism was more a “thought collective” than an explicit ideological
program (Mirowski 2014). Its tacit nature is represented in how it came to be
implicitly associated with what was called the “Washington Consensus” (Williamson
2004). The Washington Consensus involved committing international lending
practices to promoting economic liberalization in the debtor countries. Most
famously, donors such as the World Bank and the International Monetary Fund
came to impose “structural adjustment” policies on the borrowing countries in
exchange for the loans received. Latin American, African, and Asian countries in
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

The Knight’s Move 221

particular commonly found the new terms of loans to involve conditions that led
to deregulation of the economy, reductions in taxes, cuts in social welfare
spending, and privatization of state operations as well as the imposition of mon-
etarist policies. Problems of growing poverty and accelerating inequality again
were immediately noticeable but did not deter the growing insistence for
“structural adjustment.” The Washington Consensus extended beyond the state
to include the non-governmental organizations and others involved in promoting
development to economically disadvantaged parts of the world.
Neoliberalism is not anti-liberalism, instead it is a new form of liberalism. It is
about both economic and political liberalism (Brown 2015). It is very much an
attempt at a return to the classic laissez-faire, free market economic liberalism of
Adam Smith. But it is also based in an appreciation that with the New Deal in
the USA and social democracies in Europe there was the rise of a welfare state
that was justified by a pro-government interventionist form of political liberalism
which unavoidably remade the relationship of the state to the market. Neoliber-
alism might have at its core a wish or desire to roll back the state to return to
laissez-faire economic policies and put in place a market fundamentalism. In this
sense neoliberalism is a form of conservatism that seeks to undo the welfare state
as a counter to the market. Yet, as much as conservatives might have wished that
that would happen, they quickly saw that history was not something that could
be simply undone.
Instead, neoliberals were with time to appreciate the implications of Karl
Marx’s understanding of history as an undeniable force in shaping people’s ability
to act. In 1848, Marx wrote in The Eighteenth Brumaire Louis Napoleon:

Men make their own history, but they do not make it as they please; they do
not make it under self-selected circumstances, but under circumstances existing
already, given and transmitted from the past. The tradition of all dead
generations weighs like a nightmare on the brains of the living. And just as they
seem to be occupied with revolutionizing themselves and things, creating
something that did not exist before, precisely in such epochs of revolutionary
crisis they anxiously conjure up the spirits of the past to their service, borrowing
from them names, battle slogans, and costumes in order to present this new
scene in world history in time-honored disguise and borrowed language.
(Marx 1937, p. 5)

For Marx, people are not completely free to act, individually or collectively, but
they are free to act in response to structured conditions in any one place and
time. In other words, they have to account for what came before and not simply
wish it away. This was very true for neoliberals who wished to roll back the
welfare state and enact a return to some type of market fundamentalism.
This points toward what has become a critical feature of neoliberalism, especially
in its relationship to the welfare state. While neoliberalism might have wanted to
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

222 Sanford Schram

repeal welfare policies, as attempted under Reagan and Thatcher, more often
than not, something else happened. Repeal was perhaps Plan A, but given that
the welfare state had come to be entrenched, they could not simply undo it. The
welfare state had become institutionalized. Its policies had acquired their own
path dependency that generated a positive “policy feedback” (as policy analysts call
it) (Mettler and Soss 2004). As people came to be accustomed to the benefits they
gained from relying on the welfare state, they became more politically supportive
of maintaining these policies. So in that sense, there was no real chance of totally
going back to a set of policies like those that pre-dated the welfare state. That
would be Plan A. And if Plan A was not possible then a Plan B was needed. If
the welfare state could not be repealed so as to reinstate market fundamentalism,
then the next best thing would be to marketize the state. Over time, this has
come to be a hallmark characteristic of neoliberalism, perhaps more than monetarism,
deregulation, and tax cuts. Instead of repealing the welfare state, neoliberalism
involves marketizing welfare state operations so they run more like a business
in the name of getting everyone involved in them, policymakers, program
administrators, and clients, to act in market compliant ways.
In this sense, given the deep path dependencies of the welfare state, neoliberalism
is really Plan B for market fundamentalists (Schram 2015, pp. 28–31). It is what
they had to do given the historical significance of the welfare state, the path
dependency of its policies, the positive policy feedback that they generated and
the unavoidable reality that history is a real force that cannot simply be dismissed
or wished away. Further, in an age of prolonged partisan polarization and resulting
policy gridlock, it is not surprising that the deadlock produces what Jacob Hacker
(2004) has called “policy drift,” where unchanged public policies drift away from
addressing the social and economic challenges people confront in a changing
society. Therefore, it is not surprising that neoliberalism is most often confronted
with confusion when it is introduced as a topic of analysis. It is less a full-blown
ideology than a hybrid practice that has evolved out of historical circumstances.
In practice, neoliberalism is not about market fundamentalism as much as it is
about marketizing the state. It is less about doing away with the state than getting
it to operate in market compliant ways. In fact, it might be best to refer to neo-
liberalism not as an ideology at all but instead as a more subordinate meaning
system, a “practical rationality,” that is., the common sense for making public
policy today in a post-Keynesian era (March and Olsen 2010).
Jamie Peck (2010) aptly speaks of “zombie neoliberalism,” where neoliberal
policy changes get enacted simply because they go unchallenged as the default
logic for making public policy in the current era. While neoliberalism might have
been an explicit theoretical orientation at one point, today it is more an implied
understanding of what is to be done. Today, almost no one admits to being a
neoliberal even if they pursue neoliberal marketizing strategies for changing the
relationship of the state to the market. It is generally understood as the common
sense of public policymaking in the USA most especially but increasingly
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

The Knight’s Move 223

elsewhere as well that when the welfare state cannot be rolled back, we search for
ways to marketize it so that it becomes less of a counter to the market and
something that runs along market lines so as to better promote markets.
Wendy Brown (2015) has insightfully noted that neoliberalism is more about
the state than the market. She notes it is most centrally about changing politics so
that it too operates in market compliant ways, as in allowing wealth to dominate
the electoral process and monied lobbyists to draft the laws that get enacted as
well as rewriting public policies to be more supportive of markets and those who
dominate them. Neoliberalism’s greatest effects are perhaps seen in its being the
default logic for the politics of remaking the state, more so than in how it works
to reshape markets.
The zombie-like quality of neoliberal thought today is perhaps no accident, as
Henry Giroux (2015) notes:

Neoliberalism is not merely an economic system, but also a cultural apparatus


and pedagogy that are instrumental in forming a new mass sensibility, a new
condition for the widespread acceptance of the capitalist system, even the
general belief in its eternity. Seeking to hide its ideological and constructed
nature, neoliberal ideology attempts through its massive cultural apparatuses
to produce an unquestioned common sense that hides its basic assumptions
so as to prevent them from being questioned.

Therefore, a good case can be made that neoliberalism has gone from being an
explicit economic philosophy to an implicit understanding about the politics
associated with remaking the state. It is the common sense of the politics of
public policymaking. It reflects history as a real force to be contended with. It
raises the issue of what Hegel called the “cunning of reason,” where actors
unknowingly enact what history has led them to do in spite of their own best
intentions (Fraser 2009). The thoughtlessness of neoliberalism today may only
make it that much harder to counteract. It is something that people do simply
because that is the way things get done at this point in time. As a result, neoliberal
failures often lead to a doubling-down where they are replaced or modified with
other even more intensified forms of neoliberalism. Nowhere is this tragedy more
noticeable it seems than when we look at the neoliberal marketization of US
welfare policy for the poor.

Marketizing the Welfare State: Neoliberal Social Welfare Policy


Neoliberalism as enacted today is producing nothing less than a regime-wide
transformation of the welfare state. We can see this transformation as traversing
the continuum of domestic policy across the welfare state. The idea of state policy
existing on a continuum is put to good use by Pierre Bourdieu. Bourdieu (1994)
has noted that the state is riven with conflict and that it is better to characterize it
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

224 Sanford Schram

as a “bureaucratic field.” Bourdieu suggests that within this bureaucratic field there
is a continuum of domestic policy, with the left hand of the state providing aid and
the right hand of the state imposing discipline. Yet for Loïc Wacquant (2009),
there has been a joining of the left and right hands of the state in recent years as
policies have become more punitive, emphasizing punishing the poor for their
failure to conform to social and legal norms, especially regarding work and family.
Social welfare and criminal justice policies, for instance, have become more alike,
aiding and disciplining the poor simultaneously so that they will be less likely to
engage in deviant social practices. Neoliberalism is spreading punishment across
domestic policies in the name of disciplining the poor to become personally
responsible, market-compliant actors (Soss, Fording, and Schram 2011a).
Yet neoliberalization involves more than punishment in the name of dis-
ciplining the poor. The marketization of social welfare policies actually has been
the most noteworthy development under neoliberalism. In policy after policy,
there has been a dramatic shift to relying on private providers, where clients
are turned into consumers who get to make choices, and both are held accoun-
table via performance measurement systems that indicate whether market-based
objectives have been met. Examples in the USA include: welfare reform where
private providers now dominate in placing clients in jobs, managed-care systems
for regulating the private provision of publicly funded health care, Section 8
vouchers for subsidizing low-income families’ participation in private housing
markets, and education vouchers that subsidize parents’ placing their children in
private charter schools (where students must score sufficiently high on standardized
tests for the schools to continue to participate in the privatized public education
system in that locality).
Neoliberalism involves both carrots and sticks; it is about discipline more than
just punishment (Soss, Fording, and Schram 2011a, pp. 6–9). Discipline is not just
negative in limiting people’s behavior; it is also productive in seeking to bring
into being a new type of responsibilized citizen/subject who applies economic
rationality to all their choice making practices. To help usher in this new citizen/
subject, service providers across the social welfare state are also being disciplined
in ways that make for profound transformations in the delivery of all kinds of
public services. As part of the effort, public policies across the social welfare
continuum are themselves undergoing a fundamental transformation as they
are being neoliberalized to shift to imposing discipline to achieve market com-
pliance by all actors in the system, service providers as well as clients. From
income redistribution programs such as public assistance for the poor to criminal
justice policies such as the system of mass incarceration that has arisen in the era
of the war on drugs, social welfare policies are becoming more alike as they feature
a strong disciplinary approach grounded in marketized operations. Increasingly,
for-profit providers are required to demonstrate they can meet performance
standards. Clients must manage to make do with whatever limited opportunities
the economy provides.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

The Knight’s Move 225

Getting people to be self-reliant in an economy that offers them dwindling


opportunities inevitably intensifies the disciplinary core of social welfare’s neoli-
beralization. Today, many people are still struggling with the effects of the Great
Recession and the growing inequality and economic hardship it has produced.
It has proven to be a pivotal moment not just economically but also politically.
Just as the roots of the economic transformation stretch back before the Great
Recession, the influence of wealth to forestall state action to address issues of
social welfare has been growing for just as long (Bonica et al. 2013). The growing
inequality in income and wealth has led to massive expenditures in lobbying by
the wealthy to lower taxes, reduce regulation of business, and limit social welfare
legislation. As a result, there is now the distinct possibility of the United States
moving to a tiered society. At the top, there is a limited stratum of upper-class
and upper-middle-class people, ensconced in positions of corporate oversight and
needed professional occupations. At the bottom is everyone who is increasingly
deemed as not deserving of the state’s attention, in part because they failed to
position themselves as successful participants for the globalizing economy and are
therefore seen as a burden that a globally competitive corporate sector cannot and
will not carry. At the extreme, those in poverty are cast aside as disposable
populations who are to be monitored, surveilled, disciplined, and punished more
than they are to be helped.
The hollowed-out welfare state has less to offer those disadvantaged by eco-
nomic transformation. Increasingly what it does have to offer is not so much
assistance as discipline, discipline focused on getting people to internalize market
logic and accept personal responsibility for the need to find whatever means,
however limited, to get by in the changing economy (Soss, Fording, and Schram
2011a, chapter 2). This is the core of what is being called neoliberalism, a new
liberalism that restructures the state to operate consistently with market logic in
order to better promote market-compliant behavior by as many people as possible
(Brown 2003, 2006).
Neoliberalizing social welfare programs prioritizes people learning to be eco-
nomically minded about everything they do so they can more profitably develop
their human capital and become less in need of relying on the government for
assistance. Everyone must learn to think about all aspects of their lives in terms of
return on investment (what is commonly now called ROI) (Heady 2010). Even
government programs for the poor come to be centered on inculcating this
neoliberal ethos (Schram 2006, chapter 5). The result is that self-governance
replaces the government. It is the ultimate form of privatization. Neoliberalism is
heavily invested in getting ordinary people to be not just factors in production
but sources of capital themselves. Activating those on the bottom of the socio-
economic ladder to participate more extensively in investing in their own futures
through acquiring debt, whether for schooling, buying a home, or other
purposes, becomes an important source of economic growth in an economy led
by the financial industry (Coole 2012).
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

226 Sanford Schram

Yet, for those who fail at becoming on their own financially savvy neoliberal
citizen-subjects who can develop and leverage their own human capital, the state
works to inculcate market-compliant behavior via a panoply of incentives and
penalties. And when that does not work, especially as the inequitable economy
grows in ways that do not create economic opportunities for them, then coercive
controls are imposed. The goal is to control and contain those left behind so as a
disposable population they are less of a burden on the rest of society. Social
welfare institutions must of necessity be adjusted accordingly. In the transformed
context, we see a shift from redistributing resources to the economically dis-
advantaged to an emphasis on enforcing compliance to behavioral standards so
that subordinate populations become less of a burden on society.
Given its disciplinary focus, neoliberal social welfare unavoidably has moralistic
and tutorial dimensions, focused on telling the poor how to behave, more so than
providing them with needed assistance. The inculcation of personal responsibility
becomes central to the welfare state. In this highly neoliberalized paternalistic
context, the helping professions that provide the critical social services are inevitably
transformed. It is here at this neoliberal terminus that we find a transformed social
work, depoliticized and refocused on managing disposable populations. Social
work no longer stands outside power but now is more than ever thoroughly
assimilated to it. Across a wide variety of populations in need of various forms of
assistance and treatment, social work shifts to technologies of the state, forms of
governmentality, practices associated with getting served populations to inter-
nalize an ethic of self-discipline and personal responsibility. The goal of this
responsibilization is for subordinate populations to handle their own problems as
best they can on their own, with the aim that they become less of a burden for
the constrained state. As a result, they should become more willing to take up
whatever limited positions in the globalizing economy that they are afforded.
Social work increasingly comprises forms of psychological services focused on
helping realize the disciplinary demands of the neoliberalizing state, which is now
ever more dedicated to managing rather than serving disposable populations.
When examining changes across a number of different areas of human service
provision today, most striking are the parallel shifts in treatment toward a more
disciplinary approach to managing service populations (Schram and Silverman
2012). It is the end of social work as we knew it and the ascendancy of a neo-
liberal regime that disciplines subordinate populations to be market compliant
regardless of the consequences.

Neoliberal Governance: Organizational Reforms and New


Policy Tools
The marketization of the welfare state involves both neoliberal organization
reforms and policy tools to enact its market-centered focus to combating welfare
dependency. Neoliberal organizational reforms, such as devolution, privatization,
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

The Knight’s Move 227

and performance management accountability schemes, have been joined with


paternalist policy tools, including sanctions – that is, financial penalties – for
noncompliant clients, to create a flexible but disciplinary approach to managing
the populations being served (Soss, Fording, and Schram 2011b). What we can
call “neoliberal paternalism” represents a significant movement to marketize the
operations of social service organizations more generally so that they inculcate in
clients rationally responsible behavior that leads them to be market compliant,
and thus less dependent on the shrinking human services and more willing to
accept the positions slotted for them on the bottom of the socioeconomic order
(Brown 2006). Organizations are being disciplined so that they can be held
accountable for in turn disciplining their clients in this more market-focused
environment. Neoliberal paternalism is transforming the human services into a
disciplinary regime for managing poverty populations in the face of state austerity
and market dysfunction.
This transformed environment involves: (1) deskilling in staffing patterns asso-
ciated with relying on former clients as caseworkers, (2) marketizing of adminis-
trative operations stemming from the reliance on for-profit providers who are
held accountable via performance management schemes, and (3) disciplining of
clients via paternalist policy tools. These changes in organization and policy were
a long time in coming. From the penultimate moment of the welfare rights
movement in the early 1970s until the passage of welfare reform legislation in the
mid-1990s, the number of welfare recipients stabilized at relatively high levels (even
as benefits declined), and recipient families came to have essentially entitlement
rights to assistance, albeit modest, and often welfare policies have long been
entwined with multiple purposes, among the most important of which have been
to return to the roots of social service work and instill or restore morality in the
poor so as to assimilate marginal groups into mainstream behaviors and institutions
(Katz 1997). Further, as Richard Cloward and Frances Fox Piven (1975) contend,
welfare policy has historically served to “regulate the poor,” effectively under-
mining their potential as a political or economic threat. Others have noted that
welfare served to regulate gender relations by stigmatizing single mothers receiving
aid (Gordon 1994). The stigmatization of welfare recipients as undeserving people
who need to be treated suspiciously has not only deterred many welfare recipients
from applying for public assistance but also communicated to the “working poor”
more generally that they should do whatever they can to avoid falling into the
censorious category of the “welfare poor.” Welfare reform in the 1990s, however,
accentuated the disciplinary dimensions of welfare policy in dramatic ways.
The shift to a more disciplinary approach to managing the welfare poor was
facilitated by a concerted campaign by conservative political leaders to replace
poverty with welfare dependency as the primary problem to be attacked (Schram
and Soss 2001). With this heightened rhetoric about welfare dependency, the
importation of behavioral-health models of treatment and associated organiza-
tional and staffing patterns came to be seen as not only plausible but desirable. As
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

228 Sanford Schram

a result, welfare reform has remade the delivery of welfare-to-work services along
lines that parallel addiction recovery programs (see drug treatment example
below). Welfare agencies have instituted services that are the social welfare policy
equivalent of a twelve-step program: individuals learn in the new “work-first”
regime to be “active” participants in the labor force rather than “passive” reci-
pients of welfare (Schram 2006, chapter 7). Such a view of welfare dependency
has led to the importation of a “recovery model” into welfare reform, one aspect
of which is the staffing of welfare-to-work contract agencies with “recovered”
former welfare recipients. While former recipients have been relied on in the
past, several studies of welfare reform have in recent years noted that the agencies
studied had undergone change such that now about one-third of the case
managers are former recipients (Watkins-Hayes 2009; Ridzi 2009). This propor-
tion indicates numbers that go beyond mere tokenism (Turco 2010). One of the
virtues of the recovery model is that it is consistent with long-standing calls for a
representative bureaucracy (RB) that can practice cultural competence (CC)
concerning the unique needs of its clients: a culturally competent bureaucracy is
one “having the knowledge, skills, and values to work effectively with diverse
populations and to adapt institutional policies and professional practices to meet
the unique needs of client populations” (Satterwhite and Teng 2007). A repre-
sentative bureaucracy that draws from the community it is serving is seen as
furthering the ability of an agency to practice cultural competency in ways that
are sensitive to community members’ distinctive concerns and problems (Carrizales
2010). In other words, RB = CC. The recovery model holds out hope that a
more representative bureaucracy will be more sensitive to the ways in which its
welfare clients are approaching the unique challenges that have brought them to
the agency’s doorstep.
Yet there are ironies in this way of moving toward realizing the RB = CC
formula. Former recipients, as indigenous workers from the community, under
the medicalized version of welfare are seen as former addicts in recovery. If welfare
is seen as a dangerously addictive substance, then the implementation of a dis-
ciplinary treatment regime is a logical next step. The medicalization of welfare
in fact should be seen primarily in metaphorical terms as just described and the
main way of providing this medicalized treatment has been to increasingly rely on
former clients who have gotten off welfare and can serve as “success story” role
models in ways that are consistent with the “recovery model” in addictions
treatment (Watkins-Hayes 2009; Ridzi 2009). The decentralized service delivery
systems and private providers that so characterize welfare reform are fertile ground
for the importation of medical models of dependency treatment. The use of
performance management systems is also entirely consistent with the need to track
measureable outcomes resulting from the provision of services or the application
of treatment to clients.
Under this scheme, case management is a routinized and deskilled position
focused largely on monitoring client adherence to program rules and disciplining
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

The Knight’s Move 229

them when they are out of compliance. There is, in fact, evidence that with the
shift to a more decentralized, privatized system of provision, local contract agencies
have gone ahead and moved to a more deskilled welfare-to-work case manage-
ment by replacing civil servants, social workers, and other professionals with
former welfare recipients (Watkins-Hayes 2009; Ridzi 2009). In the process, a
form of community self-surveillance is put in place that Cathy Cohen calls
“advanced marginalization,” where some members of a subordinate group get to
achieve a modicum of upward social-economic mobility by taking on responsi-
bilities for monitoring and disciplining other members of that subordinate
community (Cohen 1999).
While this staffing pattern may at times be relied on for less controversial reasons
as a simple cost-saving measure consonant with the business model, it is also
entirely consistent with a recovery model philosophy that puts forth former reci-
pients as behavioral role models. These former recipients are frequently referred
to in the literature as “success stories” (Schram and Soss 2001). Yet the recovery
model suggests they are hired for another reason. The recovery model is grounded
in the philosophy that underpins the twelve-step program of Alcoholics Anonymous
and its predecessors, which over time has spread to other areas of drug treatment
and mental health services, along with the core conviction that clients must be
willing to support one another in overcoming their addictions (AA 1953).
Government programs now run more like businesses, and the application of
the business model to welfare involves getting case managers and their clients to
internalize the business ethic as well. Policy changes emphasize case managers
using disciplinary cost-saving techniques to get clients to move from welfare to
paid employment as quickly as possible regardless of whether they and their
children improve their well-being.
In the new neoliberalized welfare system, local devolution and privatization have
been joined by performance management. Performance management accountability
schemes measure the performance of private contract agencies to hold them
accountable for meeting performance outcome goals. Performance management
more than anything else has led many working in the system to suggest that “social
work” has been replaced by a much more preferred “business model” (Soss,
Fording, and Schram 2011a). Agencies inevitably feel the pressure to outperform
the other agencies being evaluated in these performance schemes. Proponents of
neoliberal organizational reform predict that local organizations will respond to the
competition among provider agencies by innovating in ways that advance statewide
goals and improve client services. Devolution will provide the freedoms they need to
experiment with promising new approaches. Performance feedback will provide
the evidence they need to learn from their own experiments and the best practices of
others. Performance-based competition will create incentives for local organizations
to make use of this information and adopt program improvements that work.
Studies have suggested several reasons why organizations may deviate from this
script in “rationally perverse” ways. Performance indicators provide ambiguous
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

230 Sanford Schram

cues that, in practice, get “selected, interpreted, and used by actors in different
ways consistent with their institutional interests” (Moynihan 2008). Positive
innovations may fail to emerge because managers do not have the authority to
make changes, access learning forums, or devise effective strategies for reforming
the organizational status quo. Performance “tunnel vision” can divert attention
from important-but-unmeasured operations and lead managers to innovate in
ways that subvert program goals (Radin 2006). To boost their numbers, providers
may engage in “creaming” practices, focusing their services on less-disadvantaged
clients who can be moved above performance thresholds with less investment
(Bell and Orr 2002).
In this environment, case managers are under constant pressure to get their
clients to stay in compliance with welfare-to-work rules and if the clients fail to
do so they are penalized with sanctions that reduce their benefits. This pre-
occupation with monitoring clients for compliance represents a change in the role
of the case manager as part of the administrative transformation of welfare policy
implementation. The rise of neoliberal paternalism in fact is associated with a shift
in the nature of casework, marked by the passage of federal welfare reform in
1996 (Lurie 2006). The prime directives for TANF (Temporary Assistance for
Needy Families) case managers today are to convey and enforce work expecta-
tions and to advance and enable transitions to employment. Efforts to promote
family and child well-being are downplayed in this frame, but they are not
entirely abandoned. Under neoliberal paternalism, they are assimilated into efforts
to promote work based on the idea that “work first” will put clients on the most
reliable path toward achieving a self-sufficient, stable, and healthy family.
Thus, case managers today initiate their relationships with new clients by
screening them for work readiness and delivering an “orientation” to describe
work expectations and penalties for noncompliance. In parallel with individualized
drug treatment plans, welfare-to-work case managers then develop “individual
responsibility plans” – or “contracts of mutual responsibility” – to specify the
steps that each client will take in order to move from welfare to work. These rites
of passage establish a relationship in which the case manager’s primary tasks are to
facilitate, monitor, and enforce the completion of required work activities. In
celebratory portrayals of the new system, case managers are described as being
deeply involved in their clients’ development, as “authority figures as well as
helpmates” (Mead 2004).
In some states, this ethos is expressed by the neoliberal relabeling of
caseworkers as “career counselors.” The label evokes images of a well-trained
professional who draws on diverse resources to advise and assist entrepreneurial
job seekers. In practice, however, few aspects of welfare case management today
fit this template. It is rare today that welfare-to-work caseworkers have a social
work degree of any kind. Many, however, have management degrees from
Strayer, DeVry, Capella, or other vocationally oriented schools that line the strip
malls across the country. It is common in many states that a sizeable number of
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

The Knight’s Move 231

case managers are former recipients who qualified for their jobs by virtue of their
experience with the system. Under the business model of service provision, the
relationship between client and case manager is rooted in an employment metaphor:
the client has signed a “contract” to do a job and should approach the program as
if it were a job.
The case manager’s job is now to enforce that contract, often using the threat
of sanctions to gain compliance. As one major study reported, case managers
spend most of their time enforcing compliance to individual responsibility plans and
very little time counseling clients (Soss, Fording, and Schram 2011a, pp. 223–226).
The change is palpable. One former recipient case manager as reported in this
study stressed in a most poignantly metaphorical way that welfare is no longer a
social service. She suggested it was now herding cattle instead of tending sheep;
while a shepherd takes care of the sheep, a cattle herder just runs the herd
through a pen in an insensitive fashion.
The shift from tending sheep to herding cattle at one level is not necessarily
that significant since both can be interpreted as dehumanizing. Yet the desensitiza-
tion implied by this way of characterizing the shift is noteworthy in itself. It also
points to another problem with performance measurement. The preoccupation
with numbers emphasizes meeting benchmarks as the primary goal irrespective of
whether the client is actually helped. In the public management literature, this is
the problem of suboptimization. Simon Guilfoyle (2012) refers to suboptimization as
analogous to synecdoche, in which a part stands in for the whole. Suboptimization
occurs when a measure of one particular outcome of service provision implies
that other dimensions, usually less measureable, if no less important, have also been
met. Suboptimization is rife in human services where the intended outcomes
almost always include difficult-to-measure subjective states of being, including
improvements in overall well-being. Suboptimization results when outcome goals
are achieved in name only and the full spirit of the goal is lost or forgotten in the
process. Meeting performance benchmark targets can misleadingly imply that the
overall goal has been met when in fact only an indirect indicator implies that is
the case. Welfare-to-work targets might be met but all that has really happened is
that we have moved clients from the “welfare poor” to the “working poor” with
no real improvements in their overall well-being.
Yet suboptimization’s deleterious effects go further. They can produce an
instrumentalization, a veritable means–ends inversion, where the performance
measurement benchmark or target becomes the end in itself. Under these conditions,
human service professionals are encouraged to forget about the overall goals of
their program and focus exclusively on meeting the designated benchmarks.
Once this happens, it is likely that all work with clients is converted into activities
associated with meeting the target irrespective of whether the broader goal
is achieved. Once an agency puts in place a performance measurement system it
risks creating an instrumentalization that changes the very work that human ser-
vice workers do. With all the debate about “high-stakes testing” under neoliberal
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

232 Sanford Schram

education reform, the threat of performance measurement to change how work is


done is most popularly discussed in the mainstream media as the “teach to the
test” effect, where school teachers teach students only what they need to know to
improve their test scores even if this means their overall learning is not really
enhanced (because critical thinking skills and other important forms of learning
are neglected).
The “business model” may be replacing “social work” as the way to deliver
neoliberal, marketized welfare-to-work programming but the results are proving
to be devastating for the poor who are increasingly blamed for their welfare
dependency as a treatable condition. The result is that more of the “welfare
poor” are being made into the “working poor,” while their poverty persists but
employers increasingly profit (Edin and Shaefer 2016, pp. 157–158).

Getting Beyond Neoliberal Welfare Policy: The Road to


Radical Incrementalism
The disciplinary approach to the poor is spreading beyond welfare to other policies
and from the USA to other countries (Brodkin and Marston 2013). The results
elsewhere are proving no better than in the USA. As more and more evidence
mounts about the horrors of neoliberal welfare policies, interest grows in moving
beyond neoliberal insistence that the welfare state buttresses markets rather than
counters them. Yet, just as neoliberals could not simply wish away the welfare
state the same is true for the opponents of neoliberalism. The road beyond neo-
liberalism is most likely one that goes through it, not around it. That means
engaging it, not ignoring it, and in the process trying to bend it to better purposes
and more humane ends. I call this sort of realistic approach “radical incrementalism,”
where small incremental steps within the existing regime are strategically taken to
lay down a path for eventually getting beyond it (Schram 2015).
The key to practicing radical incrementalism successfully is to avoid replicating
the limitations of status quo-reinforcing incrementalism that does little more than
put a band aid on a bullet wound to cover over the problems the existing political
economy perpetuates, especially for those on the bottom of the socio-economic
order. One critical way to do this is to push for small, feasible changes that are
directed at revising the embedded power relations that limit addressing a socio-
economic problem. For instance, even though they are less redistributive than
proponents of a social wage or advocates of social democracy may wish, revised
welfare policies that enhance people’s ability to participate in markets effectively
so as to live decently still today need to be supported, even as we insist that
existing social protections be maintained and even improved so that no one has to
endure poverty whether they are participating in labor markets or not. Like the
paradox of radical incrementalism itself, we need to consider the value in working
through neoliberalism in order to get beyond this. Historically, some of the most
important political insights come from considering the analytical power of
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

The Knight’s Move 233

paradox, whether it is Rousseau’s musing about forcing people to be free or other


paradoxes. In fact, in recent years, there has been a revival of interest in considering
paradoxes when examining the strategies of a “new realism” for promoting social
change (Coles 2016; Phulwani 2016). The same is true for social policy change
today under neoliberalism, with its increasing economic inequality, concentration
of political power, and policy gridlock born of partisan polarization. Yet, we can
do this; we can do two things at once. We can walk and chew gum at the same
time. We can work both sides of the street. We can work through neoliberalism
so as to get past it. Rather than bemoaning its hegemonic status, we should begin
the process of working through it in radically incremental ways. Right now
before neoliberalism imposes any more hardship than it already has done.
In other words, in today’s policy climate, we may need to accept that progressive
policy change is not a linear matter of building on what came before to make
the next steps to better realizing an inclusive social democracy for US citizens.
We might need to consider taking to heart literary theorist and father of formalism
Viktor Shklovsky’s (2005) recommendation that we make the “knight’s move.”
In 1923, Shklovsky was writing as someone concerned about the future of artistic
freedom under Soviet communism. He suggested that the knight was a chess
metaphor that allowed us to think about how to move forward but under con-
strained circumstances. The knight could move sideways, jumping over other
pieces on the board, it could work around obstacles to get to where it needed to
go. Yet, Shklovsky also appreciated that the knight’s options for movement were
prescribed, its freedom to act differently was constrained by the rules of the game
and the terrain of the board at any one point in time. Power, as Michel Foucault
recognized, creates its own resistance, both by inciting opposition to its con-
straints but also then pre-scripting the types of responses that are feasible given
that structure of power. Foucault came to be accused of being a neoliberal for
suggesting how working through it rather than ignoring it might be the imperative
for getting change. Foucault appreciated such an “inside-out” strategy might
reduce power’s oppressiveness even if only incrementally but significantly, espe-
cially for those who suffered most from neoliberalism’s disciplinary insistences
(Golder 2015). In order to counter the inequities of the market today, we may
need to consider how to work through neoliberalism in order to get beyond it.
A controversial example is Obamacare (the Patient Protection and Affordable
Care Act of 2010). Obamacare radically revises the health care system in the USA
to extend access to care, control pricing, and improve quality by not doing away
with the existing mixed system of public and private insurance, but rather by
building on that deeply path dependent system. It holds out the potential to
revise the power relationships between the state, insurance markets, and providers.
It relies on market exchanges to extend private insurance to the uninsured (publicly
subsidized for low-income participants). While polling indicates it is not over-
whelmingly popular, costs for co-pays and premiums can be high for the non-
poor, and Republicans have moved now to repeal it, it already seems to have
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

234 Sanford Schram

come to be embedded in the welfare state, proving difficult to eliminate, thanks


in no small part to the benefits it affords people, especially those with pre-existing
conditions, families with uncovered young adult children, and women in need of
access to preventive services such as birth control. It may have already become
path dependent without overwhelming positive policy feedback (Schram 2015).
Obamacare is deeply entwined in the existing public and private system of
delivering health care, relying on Medicare, Medicaid, employer-provided insur-
ance, and market exchanges for personal insurance. As a result, Obamacare remains
opaque for much of the public and makes it part of what Suzanne Mettler (2011)
calls the “submerged state.” This situation has perhaps limited its popularity and
led to people voting for candidates like Trump without knowing that they would
be authorizing repeal of the health insurance they seek to keep (Krugman 2017).
It also possibly deceives its opponents that they could repeal it without facing
public backlash. It might lead policymakers to be forced to contrive votes for repeal
by denying possibilities for incremental reform, hoping that “repeal and replace”
will not turn out to be “repeal and repent” (Farrell 2017). With 20 million newly
insured at risk of being without the ability to access affordable insurance (with or
without subsidies from Obamacare), the political backlash against those who vote
for repeal could be significant. But most importantly, the embeddedness of
Obamacare makes it difficult to dislodge irrespective of whether it has produced
positive policy feedback in the form of increased public commitment to the
policy itself. It may have made itself irreplaceable without public support.
Universal coverage, improved cost controls, and a more equitable health policy
might be better realized through more dramatic reform such as the institution of a
single-payer system. Yet, the politics of today under neoliberalism simply do not
allow that. In the meantime, while we are waiting for a more progressive political
climate to possibly never come, we might be better spending our time trying to
figure out how to work through neoliberalism in spite of constraining insistence
on the hegemony of market logic. The case of Obamacare highlights how
working through neoliberalism may be the radically incremental thing we need
to be doing in order to improve health care for millions of Americans. It may
even lay the basis for eventually getting beyond the limitations of neoliberal
health policy. Such is how the knight’s move may prove effective in an age of
neoliberalism. Working through market hegemony may be the best option today
and it may lead to a more inclusive social democracy down the road. The paradoxes
of politics in an age of neoliberalism need to be given consideration.

Acknowledgements
Thanks are extended to Adam Dahl, Rom Coles, Mitchell Dean, Tom Grimwood,
Patricia Jefferson, John Maher, Melania Papa-Mabe, Marianna Pavlovskaya,
Matt Sparke, Amanda Tillotson, and Vanessa Wells for helpful comments on an
earlier draft.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

The Knight’s Move 235

References
Alcoholics Anonymous (AA) (1953). Twelve Steps and Twelve Traditions. New York: Alcoholics
Anonymous.
Bell, Stephanie and Orr, Larry (2002). Screening (and Creaming?) Applicants to Job
Training Programs: The AFDC Homemaker–Home Health Aide Demonstrations.
Labour Economics, 9(2), 279–301.
Bonica, Adam, McCarty, Nolan, Poole, Keith T., and Rosenthal, Howard (2013).
Why Hasn’t Democracy Slowed Rising Inequality? Journal of Economic Perspectives, 27(3),
103–124.
Bourdieu, Pierre (1994). Rethinking the State: On the Genesis and Structure of the
Bureaucratic Field. Sociological Theory, 12(1), 1–19.
Brodkin, Evelyn Z. and Marston, Gregory (Eds.) (2013). Work and the Welfare State: Street-
Level Organization and Workfare Politics. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.
Brown, Wendy (2003). Neo-Liberalism and the End of Liberal Democracy. Theory &
Event, 7. Retrieved from: http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/theory_and_event/
Brown, Wendy (2006). American Nightmare: Neoliberalism, Neoconservatism, and
De-Democratization. Political Theory, 34(6), 690–714.
Brown, Wendy (2015). Undoing the Demos: Neoliberalism’s Stealth Revolution. Cambridge:
Zone Books.
Carrizales, Tony (2010). Exploring Cultural Competency within the Public Affairs Curriculum.
Journal of Public Affairs Education, 16(4), 593–606.
Cloward, Richard A. and Piven, Frances Fox (1975). Notes toward a Radical Social Work.
In Roy Bailey and Mike Brake (Eds), Radical Social Work. New York: Pantheon.
Cohen, Cathy (1999). The Boundaries of Blackness: AIDS and the Breakdown of Black Politics.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Coles, Romand (2016). Visionary Pragmatism: Radical and Ecological Democracy in Neoliberal
Times. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Coole, Diana (2012). Reconstructing the Elderly: A Critical Analysis of Pensions and
Population Policies in an Era of Demographic Aging. Contemporary Political Theory, 11,
41–67.
Edin, Kathryn and Shaefer, H. Luke (2016). $2.00 a Day: Living on Almost Nothing in
America. New York: Mariner Books.
Farrell, Henry (2017). Republicans Midnight Vote Was about Bridge Building: Actually It
Was Bridge Burning. The Washington Post, January 12.
Fraser, Nancy (2009). Feminism, Capitalism and the Cunning of History. New Left Review,
56 (March–April), 97–117.
Giroux, Henry A. (2015). Neoliberalism, Violence and Resistance: A Discussion on
Forthright Radio. Truthout, August 24. Retrieved from: www.truth-out.org/opinion/
item/32464-neoliberalism-violence-and-resistance-a-discussion-on-forthright-radio
Golder, Ben (2015). Foucault and the Politics of Rights. Palo Alto: Stanford University
Press.
Gordon, Linda (1994). Pitied but Not Entitled: Single Mothers and the History of Welfare,
1890–1935. New York: Free Press.
Guilfoyle, Simon (2012). On Target? Public Sector Performance Management: Recurrent
Themes, Consequences and Questions. Policing, 6(3), 250–260.
Hacker, Jacob (2004). Privatizing Risk without Privatizing the Welfare State: The Hidden
Politics of Social Policy Retrenchment in the United States. American Political Science
Review, 98(2), 243–260.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

236 Sanford Schram

Harcourt, Bernard (2010). Illusions of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Hay, Colin and Payne, Anthony (2015). Civic Capitalism. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Hayek, F. A. (1960). The Constitution of Liberty. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Heady, Lucy (2010). Social Return on Investment Position Paper. New Philanthropy
Capital, April. Retrieved from: www.thinknpc.org/publications/social-return-on-
investment-position-paper/
Katz, Michael (1997). Improving Poor People: The Welfare State, the “Underclass,” and Urban
Schools as History. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Krieger, Joel (1986). Reagan, Thatcher and the Politics of Decline. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Krugman, Paul (2017). Donald Trump’s Medical Delusions. New York Times, January 13.
Lurie, Irene (2006). At the Frontlines of the Welfare System: A Perspective on the Decline in
Welfare Caseloads. Albany: State University of New York Press.
March, James G. and Olsen, Johan P. (2010). Rediscovering Institutions: The Organizational
Basis of Politics. New York: Simon and Shuster.
Marx, Karl (1937). The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Napoleon, trans. Saul K. Padover.
Moscow: Progress.
Mead, Lawrence (2004). Government Matters: Welfare Reform in Wisconsin. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Mettler, Suzanne (2011). The Submerged State: How Invisible Government Policies Undermine
American Democracy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Mettler, Suzanne and Soss, Joe (2004). The Consequences of Public Policy for Democratic
Citizenship: Bridging Policy Studies and Mass Politics. Perspectives on Politics, 2(1), 55–73.
Mirowski, Philip (2014). Never Let a Serious Crisis Go to Waste: How Neoliberalism Survived
the Financial Meltdown. London: Verso.
Moynihan, Daniel P. (1988). Came the Revolution: Argument in the Reagan Era. New York:
Harcourt.
Moynihan, Donald P. (2008). The Dynamics of Performance Management: Constructing Information
and Reform. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.
Peck, Jamie (2010). Zombie Neoliberalism and the Ambidexterous State. Theoretical Criminology,
14(1), 104–110.
Peck, Jamie (2011). Constructions of Neoliberal Reason. London: Oxford University Press.
Phulwani, Vijay (2016). The Poor Man’s Machiavelli: Saul Alinsky and the Morality of
Power. American Political Science Review, 110(4), 863–875.
Pierson, Paul (2000). Increasing Returns, Path Dependence and the Study of Politics.
American Political Science Review, 94(2), 251–267.
Radin, Beryl (2006). Challenging the Performance Movement: Accountability, Complexity, and
Democratic Values. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.
Ridzi, Frank (2009). Selling Welfare Reform: Work-first and the New Common Sense of
Employment. New York: New York University Press.
Sassen, Saskia (2006). Territory, Authority, Rights: From Medieval to Global Assemblages.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Satterwhite, Frank J. Omowale, and Teng, Shiree (2007). Culturally Based Capacity Build-
ing: An Approach to Working in Communities of Color for Social Change. Los Angeles:
California Endowment and Compass Point Nonprofit Services.
Schram, Sanford F. (2006). Welfare Discipline: Discourse, Governance and Globalization.
Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

The Knight’s Move 237

Schram, Sanford F. (2015). The Return of Ordinary Capitalism: Neoliberalism, Precarity,


Occupy. New York: Oxford University Press.
Schram, Sanford F. and Soss, Joe (2001). Success Stories: Welfare Reform, Policy Dis-
course, and the Politics of Research. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and
Social Science, 577, 49–65.
Schram, Sanford F. and Silverman, Basha (2012). The End of Social Work: Neoliberalizing
Social Policy Implementation. Critical Policy Studies, 6(2), 128–145.
Shklovsky, Viktor (2005). The Knight’s Move, trans. Richard Sheldon. Champaign, IL:
Dalkey Archive Press.
Soss, Joe, Fording, Richard C., and Schram, Sanford F. (2011a). Disciplining the Poor:
Neoliberal Paternalism and the Persistent Power of Race. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Soss, Joe, Fording, Richard C., and Schram, Sanford F. (2011b). The Organization of
Discipline: From Performance Management to Perversity and Punishment. Journal of
Public Administration Research, 21, i202–i232.
Stedman Jones, Daniel (2014). Masters of the Universe: Hayek, Friedman, and the Birth of
Neoliberal Politics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Stiglitz, Joseph (2012). The Price of Inequality: How Today’s Divided Society Endangers Our
Future. New York: W. W. Norton.
Turco, Catherine J. (2010). Cultural Foundations of Tokenism: Evidence from the
Leveraged Buyout Industry. American Sociological Review, 75(6), 894–913.
Wacquant, Loïc (2009). Punishing the Poor: The Neoliberal Government of Social Insecurity.
Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Watkins-Hayes, Celeste (2009). The New Welfare Bureaucrats: Entanglements of Race, Class,
and Policy Reform. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Williamson, John (2004). The Washington Consensus as Policy Prescription for Develop-
ment, A Lecture in the Series “Practitioners of Development” Delivered at the World
Bank on January 13. Retrieved from: www.iie.com/publications/papers/william
son0204.pdf
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

13
NEOLIBERALISM
Towards A Critical Counter-Conduct1

Barbara Cruikshank

In the style of Michel Foucault (2008, pp. 8–9), this chapter asks, Why do so
many write “with so much passion and so much resentment against our most
recent past, against our present, and against ourselves,” that politics, democracy,
freedom, and equality are threatened, destroyed, or negated by neoliberalism; that
the exercise of power is “depoliticized” by neoliberalism to displace or suppress
politics; that individual liberty is no more than an instrument of neoliberal sub-
jection; that our present is dominated by neoliberalism; that we are not free?
Why seek the pathway to freedom in critical analysis that exposes and defines
neoliberalism or sets political resistance against neoliberalism? I argue that critical
conducts – activist and academic alike – too often remain under the spell of the
repressive hypothesis and its presumption that freedom and knowledge are
external to and under the thumb of power, in this case, neoliberalism. It is as if to
resist, we must dare to speak the dirty and frightful word, “neoliberalism,” as if to
knowingly defy the silence imposed upon the truth by power is to call out the
name of that truth.
If neoliberal hegemony determines the reality of the present, however, then
from what vantage point is anyone capable of seeing clearly through the fog that
engulfs the present? There is widespread disagreement about what neoliberalism
is, as we shall see, in part because there is disagreement over which vantage point
it is necessary to take: a vision of the past that is lost, of the future to come, or the
possession of a critical perspective on the present. Nevertheless, there is broad
agreement among its critics of what the proper perspective must achieve; it is
necessary to turn neoliberalism into a target of resistance, that is, to essentialize
neoliberalism as self-evidently real, if hidden, stable, the name of a grave and
unified threat. There is also widespread agreement among neoliberalism’s critics
that change is necessary to overcome the hegemony of neoliberalism, which
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Towards a Critical Counter-Conduct 239

defines, determines, and stabilizes the present. Change, then, is understood as the
temporal limit of the present. The agent of change, however, does not live in the
present, and must be fashioned and brought into being as a collective, a movement,
or a revolutionary army by critical conduct, that is, by critical thought, political
organizing on the left, solidarity, and unified resistance to neoliberalism.
I am adapting the concepts of conduct and counter-conduct for my own purpose
that were introduced by Michel Foucault in lectures given in 1977–78 and now
published in translation (Foucault 2008). Those concepts and Foucault’s manner
of critique are given clarity and breadth by Davidson (2011) and Butler (2004). As
Foucault expressed them, between the two, conduct and counter-conduct, there
is “an immediate and founding correlation” (p. 196). They are alike in that their
coherence comes from practicing certain rules, norms, and strategies for con-
ducting oneself and for conducting others, for exercising power and freedom.
The difference between them is that counter-conducts are:

movements whose objective is a different form of conduct, that is to say:


wanting to be conducted differently, by other leaders (conducteurs) and other
shepherds, towards other objectives and forms of salvation, and through
other procedures and methods. They are movements that also seek, possibly
at any rate, to escape direction by others and to define the way for each to
conduct himself.
(pp. 194–195)

I am adapting and extending these concepts to practices of conducting and


counter-conducting critical analyses and writing critical theories, to conducting
and counter-conducting readers persuaded by critical theory, and to conducts and
counter-conducts of exercising power and freedom in resistance.
There is certainly sense in pursuing the “immediate and founding correlation”
between neoliberalism as a conduct and critics of neoliberalism as a counter-
conduct. It is by giving the status of conduct to the critics, however, that I am
able to fashion a critical counter-conduct. And it is for that purpose that I am also
adopting Foucault’s widely known critical attitude toward the repressive
hypothesis, which, in a nutshell, is the seemingly incorrigible presumption that
power represses freedom, action, truth, and speech in a zero sum balance. Readers
are likely to be familiar with Foucault’s critical attitude towards the repressive
hypothesis: power does not only repress, but also produces freedom, action, truth,
and speech. His reconceptualization of power undercuts claims that revealing the
truth hidden behind the mask of power is a pathway to liberation. To name and
unmask neoliberalism, then, is not going to overcome the power of neoliberalism,
nor will it set repressed resistance free from under the heel of neoliberal hegemony.
Neoliberalism, like power, is not a singular or unified agency of repression; it does
not have a face. I adopt his critical attitude towards the repressive hypothesis
found discernable here in the strategies, norms, and expectations that govern and
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

240 Barbara Cruikshank

which set the limits of critical conduct. Those limits, I argue, not only mislead
resistance against neoliberalism; those limits have become obstacles to critical
thought and action in the present. This is why, as will be explained throughout
this chapter, it is necessary to fashion a different form of critical conduct, a critical
counter-conduct.
Adamantly, by “critical conduct” I do not mean to evoke what is called “critical
theory” in academic circles. Critical theory may be implicated here by the use
of that phrase by some practitioners cited here as examples of what I call critical
conduct, to be sure. But in no way is this chapter a blanket statement that all
or even most critical conduct succumbs to the repressive hypothesis, only critical
conduct that proceeds to name, define, critically analyze, and target neolibera-
lism as the proper target of political resistance. Wherever the phrase “critical
conduct” appears in this chapter, it is an abbreviation of “the critical conduct of
those who write and speak with passion, resentment, and conviction, to expose
the truth of neoliberalism and do so in resistance to a reality determined by
neoliberalism.”
What I am calling critical conduct repeatedly insists that neoliberalism is the
defining reality of the present and the obstacle to true freedom, democracy, and
all hope for a better day. As a consequence, critical conduct closes the door to
contingent forces of change in the present and rudely slams it in the face of those
who are presently engaged in resistance that is not conducted according to the
limits set by critical conduct. Two additional consequences follow from critical
conduct setting change at the limit of the present. That temporal limit aligns
easily with the repressive hypothesis, which in this instance situates change at
the threshold between neoliberal hegemony (repression) in the present and the
moment of overcoming the present (liberation). Both the necessary critical vantage
point to see neoliberalism for what it is and the very possibility for freedom to act
upon that vision are only to be found on the outside or on the other side of the
present. Setting change at the temporal limit of the present pitches us into
the lurch on the promise of pulling us out. The limits of critical conduct have
consequences that impose obstacles to critical thought and action.
The most troubling consequence is the disparagement, devaluation, and displace-
ment of struggles underway in the present that are deemed to be insufficiently
unified against neoliberalism, insufficiently radical in their revolt or in their
analysis of the present, or so hoodwinked by neoliberalism that they are unable to
see what should or must be done. Often enough, however, this chapter suggests a
different vantage point to see that struggles underway in the present are organized
and conducted explicitly against the repressive hypothesis, against the idea that
power is unified and singularly repressive. Those in struggle may refuse, rather
than merely fail, to fashion themselves into the collective agent of change that
critical conducts aim to bring into being. Instead, they organize and resist power
that is understood to be polymorphous, unevenly and unstably distributed in all
kinds of relations, places, among human and non-human forces.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Towards a Critical Counter-Conduct 241

Understanding power as uneven and unstable, rather than repressive, opens the
door to contingency. There is no assurance that power can be overcome once and
for all, but there is assurance that no singular power, with the possible exception
of forcible violence, can remain unified and stable. The same understanding, I
will argue later on, should be applied to resistance and to the left. Many in
struggles underway refuse to conduct themselves in unified resistance against
neoliberalism not only because they do not agree that power is singular and
repressive, but more precisely because the uneven, unstable, and contingent
distribution of power is painfully evident in the history of struggle. Moreover, in
the contingency of struggle undertaken amidst uneven and unstable powers, one
should expect surprises; new and unforeseen powers may emerge, there will be
unintended consequences of struggle that may redistribute power or give new
scope to power for better, for worse, or a mixture of both. Even though resistance
may be repressed or met with violence, there is no certainty of the result. It may
serve the intention to bring resistance to an end, or unintentionally enliven
resistance, draw in new recruits and pull the uncommitted to the side of resis-
tance. So the organization and expression of resistance in ways that defy the
repressive hypothesis are made in order to grapple within the uneven, unstable,
and contingent distribution of power, rather than to overcome the singular power
of repression once and for all. That objective sets a new limit for a critical
counter-conduct.
Resistance conducted in ways that run counter to the repressive hypothesis will
disappoint the expectations set by critical conduct. Moreover, as is explained
below, the expectation of finding and sharing a critical vantage point on the
present is another limit of critical conduct that is countered by the expectation of
finding a critical vantage point only within the present. These new limits placed
upon critical counter-conducts are evident in new vocabularies, new forms of
association, new modes of organizing, in the temporality and scales of struggle
underway. For example, affinity, coalition, and intersectionality run counter to
solidarity and unity; pre-figurative, alternative, and direct-action in the present
counter visions for overcoming the present; horizontal rather than from above or
below; leaderless rather than grassroots; post-politics rather than consensus politics.
And running counter to setting the scale of struggle on the state, nation, institu-
tions, law, or ideology, recent struggles set the scale of their conduct at the level
of micro-power: community, the street, local, associations of many kinds, the
personal, identity, lifestyle, and practice.
I suggest these movements as the proper object of critical diagnosis and as
models for critical counter-conduct, one that analyses practices of freedom and
resistance already underway as “the diagnostic of power,” a phrase and direction
for critical counter-conduct signaled by Lila Abu-Lughod (1990). Critical counter-
conduct takes the vantage point of what is said and done in the present and
expects that change is continuous, contingent, erupting in places and from forces
that are unexpected.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

242 Barbara Cruikshank

Although I originally embarked on this chapter in the winter of 2016, already


in this winter of 2017, I feel somewhat vindicated in the argument made then to
expect surprises. Over the last few months, the most potent and unexpected
resistance to neoliberalism erupted in the electoral arena rather than in the
numerous trenches set up and massive protests by the left around the world since
the global financial crisis in 2008. Amidst that crisis, hand-wringing on the part of
neoliberal capitalism, discussed briefly below, especially finance capital, was
matched momentarily by jubilant declarations from the left that the Washington
Consensus – neoliberalism – was finally dead. Jubilance was squashed, in part, by
bailouts of big banks and industries, refusal by the European Union to bail out
member countries, policing and violent repression of protest. And it was squashed
also in part by the critical conduct of Naomi Klein, who published an international
best-seller, The Shock Doctrine: The Rise of Disaster Capitalism, in the summer of
2008, at the height of the crisis. Klein pointed to the history of natural disasters
and crises to argue that rather than roiling or ending neoliberal capitalism, they
actually smoothed the way for the ascent of neoliberal hegemony. The 2008
financial crisis would be no exception, a conclusion confirmed by Mirowski
(2013). Indeed, despite the astonishing number, size, and scale of sustained resis-
tance from the left sparked by the crisis – starting with Iceland’s Pots and Pans
Movement, M-15 in Spain, Occupy Wall Street, Hong Kong, Greece, those
lumped together as the Arab Spring, extending to the Gezi Park protests in
Turkey in 2013 – the diagnoses of neoliberalism as hegemonic under examination
in this chapter went largely unchanged. Of course, there are important exceptions
to what I am calling critical conduct to be found in Amar (2013) and in Soss,
Fording, and Schram (2011).
The big surprise finally came in the latter part of 2016 and has culminated, so
far, in the election of Donald Trump to the presidency of the United States on a
platform of white nationalism, anti-establishment, pro-jobs, anti-global trade, and
free spending; the relative success of the Bernie Sanders’ campaign for president
in the name of political revolution and socialism; the Brexit vote in the United
Kingdom; the escalating support for nationalist parties of the far right in Europe.
All of which, in the words of Nancy Fraser (2017), “signal a collapse of neoliberal
hegemony.” Time will tell, of course. These ascendant forces may face the same
fate as Syriza in Greece, for example. But to my knowledge, nobody saw any of
this coming before the summer of 2016 and few, including the winners, could
credibly claim no surprise in the fall of 2016. While it is now shockingly evident
that the most potent resistance to neoliberalism is, to date, electoral and largely
from right-wing forces, the left-wing models of resistance I use here to model a
critical counter-conduct are, I hope, still persuasive. The newly ascendant right-
wing forces are no more or less unified, coherent, or expected than the left-wing
forces that surged in the recent past. It is troubling that the certainty in which
critical conduct held neoliberal hegemony was not shaken despite all the evidence
of vitality and open resistance by the left over many years. Just a moment later,
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Towards a Critical Counter-Conduct 243

signs of vitality on the right appear to have shaken the certainty of neoliberalism to
the point of breaking. Still, as I see it, the lesson to expect surprises is vindicated.
In what follows, this chapter asks, What is neoliberalism? After a quick survey
of the answers given to that question by practitioners of critical conduct and the
usage of the concept in political life, the chapter proceeds to point out the
agreements and disagreements over neoliberalism to articulate the limits set upon
critical conduct. The chapter next proceeds toward and finally arrives upon a
critical counter-conduct.

What Is Neoliberalism?
Is neoliberalism an ideology? An economic or political doctrine, or a theory of
political economy (Harvey 2005)? A counter-revolution against Keynesianism or
a rebellion against the state (Duménil and Lévy 2004)? A state formation, a state
of exception, or a global assemblage (Wacquant 2009; Ong 2006, 2007)? An
imperial order (Petras 2011)? A revolution in the rationality or purpose of govern-
ment or of liberalism (Brown 2015; Feher 2009)? A market rationality applied to
everything and everywhere or applied in enclaves, certain spheres, regions, or
sectors (Ferguson 2006)? A practice of privatization, deregulation, or devolution?
A political culture or a cultural politics (Duggan 2003)? The only alternative,
either because the left lacks an alternative vision, ideology, or the “decline of
socialism” (Brown 2003; Fukuyama 2012)? The only alternative because the left
was caught in the grip of neoliberalism, side-tracked by anti-racist and identity
politics from advancing a unifying vision of equality and solidarity to overcome
neoliberal capitalism (Brown 2003; Dean 2009; Duggan 2003)? The only alternative
because the left, caught in the grip of resistance to capitalism, failed to invent its
own art of government (Foucault 2008, pp. 93–94)? Or is it the only alternative
even in the face of its own failure because neoliberalism’s success is due to its
ability to pass for “common sense” despite all evidence to the contrary (Mirowski
2013)? Is it hegemonic, under strain, or already surpassed by a new era dubbed
“post-neoliberal” inaugurated by the pink tide in Latin America? (Brenner, Peck,
and Theodore 2010; Petras and Veltmeyer 2014)?
Recently published left-leaning studies define and dispute neoliberalism in all
these terms. Without any intended glibness, one could say that neoliberalism is a
conceptual contest or conceptual dispute on the left. As is often noted, and in the
words of Wendy Larner (2006, pp. 449–451), “the concept of neoliberalism is
overwhelmingly mobilized and deployed by left-wing academics and political
activists.” Others have taken notice of the remarkable profusion of studies taking
neoliberalism as the proper object of analysis and resistance, and the no less
remarkable repetition that neoliberalism is hegemonic in our time. Some have
ably defended doing so (Mirowski 2014). Neoliberalism, despite voluble dis-
agreement over what it is and how to define it, is a term of negative judgment
that is difficult to find in use by anyone other than its critics.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

244 Barbara Cruikshank

To my knowledge, no one advocated for or in the name of “neoliberalism”


per se, with the possible exception of the highly secretive Mont Pélerin Society
which originated in 1947, whose members founded and headed institutions to
spread neoliberalism – unnamed as such and under the cover of calling for market
freedom and limited state power – such as the Federalist Society, the American
Heritage Foundation, and the Institute for Economic Affairs, among hundreds of
others spread around the world. That history is documented by Philip Mirowski
(2014). Mirowski suggests that evidence of a neoliberal political movement existed
in Latin America and Francophone countries in the 1980s, so that neoliberalism
emerged as a critical category earlier there than in the United States, for example,
but he does not suggest that movement was conducted openly under the banner
of neoliberalism. (p. 18). Nevertheless, since June of 2016, in the moment Brexit
shocked the world by voting to leave the European Union, itself an institution
for protecting finance capital from democracy, there is more evidence of neoli-
beralism as the name used by its practitioners for scrutiny under pressure of what
was previously called “market competition,” “capital account liberalization,”
“free trade,” “globalization,” “privatization,” “foreign direct investment,” and so
on (Ostry, Loungani, and Furceri 2016).
What I am calling “critical conduct” is the conduct of scholars and activists
who take neoliberalism to be a proper object of critical analysis and resistance.
(Emphatically, again, I do not mean to implicate critical theory writ large or the
Frankfurt School in particular in the category of critical conduct.) Despite wide-
spread disagreement over what it is said to name, amidst a profusion of critical
studies, theories, analyses, and protests over nearly two decades, “neoliberalism” is
uttered in critical conduct as the defining word of our times. It has taken on a
multifaceted character that is singularly and self-evidently bad and only gets
worse. “Neoliberalism” names a unity, often with force and agency of its own,
that wages successful assaults upon equality, democracy, liberal democracy,
democratic citizenship, the environment, the poor, the middle-class, public things,
and public life. Neoliberalism is presented as wily and capable of undercutting all
efforts to resist its hold on individuals, common sense, government, institutions,
and political culture. What hope these studies supply for emancipation or escape
from neoliberalism is dependent on the whole-scale rejection of the present. The
means and purpose of overcoming the present are also disputed. They range from
calls to envision the coming revolution to reviving Enlightenment principles, to
take a blind leap of faith that another world is possible or to establish forms of
government, old and new, from liberal democracy, radical democracy, communism,
and republicanism, to anarchy.
So there is disagreement about what neoliberalism is and how to overcome it,
yet agreement that it encompasses and defines the present. A norm of critical
conduct is discernable: to diagnose the present. There is disagreement also about
how to overcome the present, but no disagreement that it is the purpose of critical
conduct to get us there. Another discernible norm, then, is for critical conduct to
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Towards a Critical Counter-Conduct 245

overcome the present. Implicitly there is agreement that critical conduct must
define, expose, and target power or, in a word, to essentialize, neoliberalism as
the real, determining condition of the present. There is certainly also explicit
agreement that the neoliberal condition of the present will overcome only by
resistance. While it is often only implicit that the strategy of critical conduct is to
conduct that resistance by dint of its diagnosis, we turn now to one of the more
explicit expressions of that strategy.
Bernard Harcourt asserts that for the task of resistance, “properly defining
neoliberalism becomes of vital importance” (2010, p. 23). Calling neoliberalism
out into the open, naming and defining it, is an urgent matter of critique. The
“central task of critique is to lift the veil from the purported orderliness or market
efficiency; to unmask the ostensible neutrality of the economic analysis; to expose
the distributions that are at the heart of all political interventions” (p. 27). Critical
conduct guided by the norms of conceptual definition, exposure, and resistance
to power, however, will inevitably generate a tautology: power is hidden because
power can mask itself. The singular face of neoliberalism is masked by its own
indefinite presence, hidden in the barely perceptible and gentle force of a nudge
to do or to choose this over that, narrowing down democratic freedom to consumer
choice, reducing citizens to human capital, driving the rampant privatization of
public goods and services, and pulling the strings of protest against “too much
government.” It is the face of a singular power and the essential reality of
the present.
While aiming to expose power as the target of resistance, the tautology of
power draws instead to conclusions that defeat resistance. For example, Sandy
Schram (2015, p. 192) asserts that:

neoliberalism is the pervasive reality of the state today. It is the common


sense of how to get things done. Whenever it fails for whatever reason, it is a
good bet that the chosen responses will be to double down on neoliberalism
and take it to another level.

Neoliberal hegemony makes itself inevitable by making anything else unthink-


able. “The polity/citizenry cannot imagine capitalism’s demise because neoliberal
forms of discourse have rendered unthinkable more socially just alternatives …
To use a common philosophical term, neoliberalism is hegemonic” (Bialostok,
Whitman, and Bradley 2012, p. 79). Neoliberal ideology functions in such a way
that it distracts resistance away from itself and away from critical conduct, simul-
taneously, according to Jodi Dean (2009) and Lisa Duggan (2003). The strategy of
critical conduct is to unify resistance into a force that is powerful enough to
topple the unity of power. Any resistance that is not conducted by the norms and
strategies of critical conduct, then, only serves to secure the veil covering the face
of power. The strings pulling unwitting and distracted resistance to the wrong
targets (e.g., racism, sexism, environmental degradation, neo-colonialism), into
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

246 Barbara Cruikshank

disunity and disconcerted resistance, are held by the invisible hand of power. In
short, critical conduct renders resistance underway into an obstacle and into
further evidence that power is hidden. The strategy of critical conduct results,
then, in taking up a quarrel on the side of the true left against the false left, which
dismisses, displaces, and denigrates any resistance underway in the present reality
as defined by critical conduct.
Even when the veil of power is lifted, however, the face of neoliberalism
remains in dispute, as noted above in the disparate answers given to the question,
What is neoliberalism? First, disagreement over the definition of neoliberalism
indicates that “lifting the veil” does not expose the real truth to one and all or
unify the target of resistance even amongst the practitioners of critical conduct.
Rather, it plants the stakes of truth and reality in a conceptual dispute. The many
different faces exposed and the proliferation of definitions leaves critical conduct
in confrontation with a many-headed beast. Which head must be cut off to bring
the beast down? The project of defining and exposing the real truth does not
compel any agreement on the definition of neoliberalism, but it does compel
critical conduct to repeat the repressive hypothesis as a necessary condition of any
definition. Second, added upon conceptual dispute are the difficulties of exposing
(epistemology), disagreement over the definition or the face of neoliberalism
(power), critical conduct is also engaged in fierce disagreement over the nature of
the veil that masks neoliberalism (method), over the proper weapon to slay the
beast (mode of resistance), and who is poised to wield that weapon (political
subject). These disagreements increase the stakes of critical conduct, planting
them deeper into political dispute.
Harcourt also warns that “useful categories – categories that serve to reveal
illusions and targets of resistance at one point in time – get in the way of
addressing new problems that emerge in later times” (p. 28). That time has
come not only with the category of neoliberalism, and not because times
change and new problems arise, which of course they do. Rather, the time
has come because critical conduct, exposing the truth hidden by power,
revealing the true and proper target of resistance, is a conceptual contest that
turns its own categories into self-evident realities. To be rendered into “useful
categories,” not only neoliberalism, but also “resistance,” must be accepted as
stable, fixed, and self-evident, the site of a singular truth and reality. Any
resistance that does not measure up to that category is not real or true resis-
tance. It is the first rule of critical conduct that the self-evidence of categories
be accepted as the essential sites of critical thought and action where reality,
truth, and power are at stake. Acceptance of the self-evidence is the first rule
of critical conduct. It is critical conduct itself that renders neoliberalism an
arresting site of contest. I am not saying that conceptual dispute stops critical
thought and action or turns it into idle speculation. Rather, I am saying that the
norms, practices, and strategies of critical conduct are obstacles to critical thought
and action.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Towards a Critical Counter-Conduct 247

Towards a Critical Counter-Conduct


Even when neoliberalism is treated as paradoxical it retains the qualities of
singularity, “ubiquitous and omnipresent, yet disunified and nonidentical with
itself,” as Wendy Brown describes it, it is also “the face of an order replete with
contradiction and disavowal” (2015, pp. 48–49). Nevertheless, Brown warns
against and provides the perspective for avoiding one of the obstacles to critical
thought and action produced by critical conduct, essentialism and the self-evidence
of neoliberalism as an all-encompassing reality. “Alertness to neoliberalism’s
inconstancy and plasticity cautions against identifying its current iteration as its
essential and global truth and against making the story I am telling a teleological
one, a steady march toward end times” (p. 21). That is made possible by taking
her perspective from the vantage point of what is said and done in the articulation
and utilization of neoliberal rationality. This perspective affords tremendous
insight into neoliberalism while avoiding essentialism.
Yet the paradox at the core of her book is not perceived from the vantage
point of what is said and done. It appears, instead, at the intersection of two
vantage points. The second vantage point is taken from the position of what it is
that neoliberalism “undoes”; homo politicus is undone by homo economicus: “the
vanquishing of homo politicus by contemporary neoliberal rationality, the insistence
that there are only rational market actors in every sphere of human existence, is
novel, indeed revolutionary, in the history of the West” (p. 99). Brown does not
take the vantage point of what is said and done when she addresses what is
undone, but the vantage point of “the West,” the conceit of which is a “public
life,” at its best educated and democratic, represented by “informed political passion,
respectful deliberation, aspirational sovereignty, sharp containment of powers that
would overrule or undermine it” (p. 39). Homo politicus lived in the West, in a
sovereign public sphere peopled by sovereign citizens. “In the beginning, there
was homo politicus …” (p. 87). So begins Brown’s compact origin myth of homo
politicus, whose story begins with Aristotle and who “remains alive and important”
through to modernity (p. 98). The implementation of neoliberal rationality
through the privatization and marketization of everything, including the public
sphere, staged a revolution that stripped sovereignty from homo politicus, reducing
him to homo economicus. Homo economicus may be free, but not sovereign. Therein
lies the paradox: “the neoliberal revolution takes place in the name of freedom – free
markets, free countries, free men – but tears up freedom’s grounding in sovereignty
for states and subjects alike” (p. 108). By “undoing the demos,” neoliberal rationality
destroyed the only political subject capable of staging a counter-revolution to
restore the West.
The vantage point provided by the mythical existence of homo politicus, then,
provides the wedge for critical conduct in Brown’s argument. This raises the
obstacle to critical thought and action, whereas the other vantage point, of what
is said and done vis-à-vis neoliberal rationality, offers no strategy, subject, or
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

248 Barbara Cruikshank

target of resistance. With homo politicus vanquished, who is left living in the present
capable or willing to wage a counter-revolution against neoliberalism? Assuming
we believe in him and desire to resurrect him to re-take his place in the history of
the West, how might that be accomplished? Absent homo politicus, there appear to
be no other resources in Brown’s critique of neoliberalism. Perhaps there are such
resources, but they are buried deep under homo politicus. With no other recourse,
neoliberal rationality bears down upon Brown’s book and the very possibility of
critical conduct.

Neoliberalism is the rationality through which capitalism finally swallows


humanity – not only with its machinery of compulsory commodification and
profit-driven expansion, but by its form of valuation. As the spread of this
form evacuates the content from liberal democracy and transforms the
meaning of democracy tout court, it subdues democratic desires and imperils
democratic dreams.
(p. 44)

Like the other diagnostics of the present noted above, Brown’s too draws the
conclusion that neoliberalism is totalizing and hegemonic. Neoliberalism has,
effectively, thoroughly, and completely overtaken the state, common sense,
extinguished democratic freedom, the sovereignty of citizens, and successfully
thwarted anti-capitalist and democratic forces and smothered aspirations that run
counter to neoliberalism. Neoliberalism is presented as pervasive and spread so
deep that there is, in reality, no alternative.
Put another way, accepting the self-evidence of neoliberalism as your starting
point, and taking the rejection of neoliberalism as your end point, are the limits
set for critical conduct. Brown overcomes the first limit, but not the second. If
you do not accept the limits for critical conduct, you are a neoliberal apologist, at
worst, or at best insufficiently critical in your analysis or revolutionary in your
aspirations. Within these limits, neoliberalism is the only possible target of resistance
and “neoliberalism” is the only weapon to slay it in the arsenal of critical conduct.
With no toehold for unified resistance “in reality,” and with faint hope for
mounting such resistance in the present, critical conduct is reduced to Manicheanism:
neoliberalism is an unmitigated evil, a target of rejection and refusal, rather than
of resistance. Rejecting neoliberalism is good, and to fail to do so is evidence of
blindness, acquiescence, cowardice, or the awesome power and total success of
neoliberalism. Since there are no cracks in neoliberalism’s grip upon the present
to exploit from the perspective of critical conduct, and apparently no one but the
practicioners of critical conduct have the vantage necessary to diagnose the pre-
sent for what it is, the question of resistance against neoliberalism is to slay the
many-headed monster on the pretense of defining it.
I certainly hear an echo of the repressive hypothesis at work in the oppositional
logic – repressed or emancipated – of critical diagnostics. Somehow, it is
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Towards a Critical Counter-Conduct 249

neoliberalism that stands between us and true freedom. Why is neoliberalism so


pervasive and powerful, an insurmountable barrier to freedom? Some critics reply,
with the classic tautology upholding the repressive theory of power: resistance to
neoliberalism is repressed by neoliberalism (in this usage neoliberalism is clearly
both a weapon and the target for neoliberals, as well as for emancipatory pro-
jects). Brown succeeds in avoiding that tautology by illuminating the positive
power of neoliberal rationality to shape the present. Nevertheless, she is drawn to
the conclusion that the neoliberal revolution cannot be turned back. Either
way, then, as a repressive force or as a productive force, the power of neoliber-
alism is tautological and total. As such, resistance must come from somewhere
outside neoliberalism.
Others have noted limitations imposed upon critical thought and action by
taking up the position of anti-neoliberalism. This is where critical conduct comes
in from nowhere to provide the vantage point of normative theory as a toehold
for resistance. For example, Clive Barnett (2010, p. 26) writes:

Neoliberalism as an object of analysis is certainly a critics’ term. The explicit


formulation of neoliberalism into an object of theoretical analysis … [indicates]
the turning-in of intellectual curiosity around a very narrow space … As long
as this remains the horizon of normative reflection, critical human geo-
graphers will continue to always know in advance what they are expected to
be critical of but will remain unable to articulate convincingly what they are
being critical for.

Anti-neoliberalism, in other words, is a position that limits critical thought to


resistance against neoliberalism at the expense of envisioning a normative alter-
native to neoliberalism. After introducing another important resource for a critical
counter-conduct, I return to Barnett’s call for normative commitment.
James Ferguson (2009) wrote an inspired response to the reduction of critical
conduct to a great refusal and narrowing the scope of resistance to anti-neoliberalism.
Ferguson’s patience is tested by groups he calls “the antis.” “Anti-globalization,
anti-neoliberalism, anti-privatization, anti-imperialism, anti-Bush, perhaps even
anti-capitalism – but always ‘anti’, not ‘pro’” (p. 166). He is also impatient with
critical conduct that merely casts judgment and he heeds the call made upon the
left to invent or to re-invent the arts of government by Michel Foucault. To do
so, Ferguson suggests, progressives and leftists need to think in terms of appro-
priating neoliberal policies and programs. The cases in point are redistribution
schemes and governing techniques of direct cash transfer policies and programs
implemented in Brazil, Venezuela, Bangladesh, and Mexico. His focus is con-
centrated on the ANC’s proposal for South Africa’s basic income grant (BIG).
Conditional (e.g., on kids attending school to qualify for Bolsa Família in Brazil)
or unconditional, direct payments provide income without stipulating how
income is spent. (Notably, experiments with basic income are currently underway
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

250 Barbara Cruikshank

or planned today for locales in several countries, including Canada, Finland, India,
Kenya, and the United States.) In South Africa, Ferguson saw basic income as a
recognizably neoliberal policy of redistribution: reliance on or bolstering markets;
individual entrepreneurship and autonomy; cutting the state out as a service
provider; and privatizing social provisions. Advocates for BIG appropriate both
“pro-poor” arguments from the left and “anti-poor” arguments from the right:
for example, the charge that the nanny state is racist, moralizes over the “deserving”
and the “underserving” poor, buys off the legitimate dissent of the poor, and will
replace social welfare techniques like the means-test with a universal cash payment.
Advocates also swing accusations against big government, corruption, and the
dependency produced by the over-weaning nanny state which coddles the poor
and their bad behavior, so BIG replaces welfare with individual responsibility,
“investing in human capital,” and entrepreneurship. There is not one governing
rationality, but many, appropriated and re-appropriated by the advocates of BIG,
willy-nilly. In Ferguson’s view, such policies are never simply either neoliberal or
resistant to neoliberalism, a perspective that undermines the antis’ critical position
from somewhere outside neoliberalism and their stance of resistance to neoliberalism.
If, as “antis,” critics of neoliberalism treat programs like BIG as an unmitigated
evil to be completely rejected and shunned, the left will never take advantage of
the opportunity there is to re-appropriate neoliberalism’s policies and programs to
fight poverty. His essay comes with warnings neither to embrace nor reject neo-
liberal policies and techniques, but to ask, are they appropriable? Ferguson gives
several other historical examples to show that antis need to reconsider the
historical record of how unpredictable policies and programs are, in fact. Once
enacted even the purely progressive or conservative policy may be appropriated
by the other side.
Ferguson’s examples of appropriation are readily generalizable, I believe, even
to antis. For example, neoliberal policies and techniques are undergoing appro-
priation by those struggling against police violence and student debt in the USA.
A signature technique of neoliberal policing, CompStat, originally designed to
hold police responsible, became a big data technique for tracking and mapping
crime. These data techniques are currently being appropriated by those combatting
police violence and racial profiling to expose and resist the fully neoliberalized,
professionalized, racialized and militarized policing we have come to know under
the mantra of Broken Windows.2 Another example is Strike Debt, a campaign to
oppose the predatory debt practices of finance capitalism and the neoliberal logic
for policies to “liberalize” or “privatize” higher education. It is a coherent neo-
liberal argument to say that a degree paid for with publicly funded students loans
to a for-profit institution is fraud because graduates cannot realize their “human
capital” with a “bad” degree. Nevertheless, that argument is being appropriated as
an argument that for-profit institutions cannot be “incentivized” to be capable
and trustworthy educators because their motive is profit rather than education.
That is a neoliberal argument turned against the privatization of education. We
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Towards a Critical Counter-Conduct 251

do not have to resuscitate homo politicus or aristocratic visions of liberal arts education
and Enlightenment principles, nor to embrace communitarian visions of liberal
arts education to make “good citizens,” to defend public provision for higher
education. It may even be possible to further appropriate neoliberal techniques
and policies ascendant in public schools, public universities, and adapt them for
transportation, police and prisons, health care, finance, among other sectors
under pressures of withdrawing state funding and encroaching state regulation,
marketization, and privatization. Appropriation may fail or succeed (or both) to
secure the future of education, and the question now is if appropriation and
re-apporopriation will proceed apace. The strategy of appropriation will be
sorely tested if it is true that the recent ascendance of nationalism spells the end
of neoliberal hegemony.
Ferguson’s suggestion that it is possible to resist neoliberalism by appropriating
it for the left provides inspiration for critical counter-conduct. I agree with him
that by treating neoliberalism as a great and unified evil to draw a line in the sand,
critics are telling their audiences that there is no adequate resistance underway. I
also agree with the implication of his argument, that any resistance taking the
form of rejection, anti-neoliberalism, will find no traction for resistance in the
present. However, Ferguson also suggests that the left is exhausted:

neither the governmental mechanisms, nor the strategies of mobilization, that


the left came to rely on in the twentieth century (and which characterized,
in different ways, both socialist and social democratic or “welfare state”
regimes) are capable of getting the sort of traction they once did.
(p. 167)

He cites two reasons why “progressive thought and politics” (p. 168) are incapable
of mounting an adequate response to neoliberalism. First, transnational forms of
government, finance, philanthropy, and second, the dramatically shrinking formal
wage labor sector have rendered leftist strategies and their dreams of social
democratic government anachronistic. Yet in his impatience with the “antis,”
their judgment that neoliberalism is a bad thing and an appropriate target of
refusal, Ferguson neglects to see that the antis are not only anti-neoliberal, and
left strategy is not limited to “anti” neoliberalism.
Many on the left are actively fashioning strategic and governmental counter-
conducts within a present they may even believe is irredeemably neoliberal. They
can be found doing so both guided by and standing aside from repressive hypotheses.
While Ferguson’s patience is tested by the antis’ overly quick and facile rejection of
neoliberalism, mine is tested by the ways that critical conduct, and in this way like
Ferguson, discount, disparage, and disavow the variety and scale of resistance on
the left. The antis, so to speak, are in fact contributing to the reinvention of neoli-
beralism by resisting, forcing neoliberalism to respond, and maybe also appropriating
the neoliberal arts of government in practicing critical counter-conducts, but not in
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

252 Barbara Cruikshank

ways that are recognizable, apparently, to Ferguson. And the antis certainly do not
satisfy Barnett’s call for normative theory to set out a normative vision of what we are
for, anarchism and participatory democracy notwithstanding.
Like both Barnett and Ferguson, I suspect that little good can come from
endlessly repeating that neoliberalism is bad. However, I do not have faith in
Barnett’s vantage point that abandons critical conduct and the present to assert
normative commitments and build a movement on visions of what “we” are for.
To make good on the promise of normative visions and commitments entails
either consensus or coercion to unify others to resist in the name of, and then to
live according to, shared and settled commitments. That is no better and no more
achievable than the unity called forth by critics in the name of resistance to
neoliberalism. What I am aiming at here is the reinvention of critical conduct to
avoid its bad consequences, not to abandon the present or the search for critical
vantage (be it political, theoretical, or conceptual perspective) on neoliberalism.
Ferguson offers the vantage point of the present to locate resources and strategies
for resistance to neoliberalism. Whether neoliberalism is conceived as a repressive
form of government, an ideology, or as rationality of power that is capable of
producing reality and shaping subjectivity, there is a strong tendency in critical
conduct to essentialize neoliberalism as hegemonic and insurmountable, barring
the possibility that any critical vantage point is possible within the present. And the
call to normative commitment takes its critical vantage from outside the present.
Ferguson demonstrates that the present does afford a vantage point that offers a
non-essentialist perspective on neoliberalism. This overcomes the temporal limit
imposed on change by the repressive hypothesis that is set between repression/
present and liberation/future. However, why is there not enough vantage from the
present for him to see the innumerable signs of vitality on the left in the present?
Despite his valuable contribution, in addition to Brown’s, toward de-essentializing
neoliberalism, Ferguson essentializes the left as a unified body of shared aspiration
that is no longer stabilized and supported by its necessary conditions. In effect, he
displaces the left from the present. He can see that power is unevenly and
unstably distributed so that neoliberalism is in a continuous state of transformation
amidst the appropriation and re-appropriation of techniques and policies of
government. However, he does not see resistance and the left in similar terms, as
in a continuous state of change and contestation. This is why it is not enough for a
critical counter-conduct to avoid the essentialism of the repressive hypothesis and
adopt the vantage point of the present. It is also necessary to treat resistance as a
diagnostic of power, even if it does not meet your expectations or satisfy your
understanding of the proper role, conduct, and purpose of the left.

Critical Counter-Conduct
Rather than banish the concept of neoliberalism from critical conduct and get
back to the purportedly real world of politics, my aim so far has been to
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Towards a Critical Counter-Conduct 253

investigate and counter what is done with the word, how it is used to fight
conceptual and political battles, how it came to be an arresting site not of
definition, but of conceptual contest, and to treat its usage in critical conduct
more as a speech act with real consequences and not as barking in the wind.
This is to practice what I now propose as the rules, norms, and strategies for a
critical counter-conduct and its “immediate and founding correlation” with
critical conduct will be obvious. First, to breach the self-evidence of neoliber-
alism in the world and in critical conduct, do not argue over what neoliberalism
(or power) is, in reality, or call out its name as an act of resistance. Rather,
analyze what is said and done in the world and within critical conduct; analyze
the effects of putting neoliberalism into conceptual and political dispute. That
rule guided my analysis of critical conduct and helped to explain how critical
conduct poses obstacles to thought and action that is critically necessary to resist
neoliberalism.
The effects of critical conduct do not repress a more true or politically useful
critique. Rather, they displace and disparage resistance underway in the present,
including resistance to neoliberalism. The second rule is: do not attempt to
expose what (e.g., power) is hidden. Look instead at what is said and done to see
how power works (rule #1), and above all, look to resistance underway and
practices of freedom as the diagnostics of power in the present. “Protests against
neoliberalism” is a misnomer to frame protest from the left if we listen to what is
actually said in protests, although neoliberalism is certainly a focal point of resistance
in many cases as well, particularly in Latin America and ever more so in the
European Union. (It is possible to interpret protest from the right as anti-neoliberal,
such as the Tea Party’s protest against corporate bailouts and the rising tide of
nationalism in the European Union and elsewhere.) For example, anti-austerity
was the focal point of Spanish Indignados and Greece; anti-redevelopment and
anti-gentrification of Gezi Park Protests; global inequality of Occupy Wall Street;
prison abolition in the USA, extractivism in Latin America, and there are far too
many more focal points of recent and ongoing protest to list, including corruption,
environmental degradation, state and police violence, government secrecy and
cyber- security, prison abolition, and electoral reform.
Recent protests have been transformative. Strike Debt, as already mentioned,
and anti-austerity in Greece transform national and personal debt from something
that by right must be paid, into a target of resistance. Critical counter-conducts
may resist neoliberalism, not in name, but in its immediate encounter. For
example, protests in Ferguson, Missouri targeted the tyrannical system of fines
and court fees that locked people into the judicial system and subjected them to
police violence and entrenched injustice. That system was built upon rollbacks of
public financing for public goods including public safety and justice. Resonating
across the country, many new organizations and movements appeared which ran
counter to the conduct of the civil rights movement. As a result, rather than
appearing as good governance, the withdrawal of public financing came to appear
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

254 Barbara Cruikshank

as fostering tyranny and pushed police into acting in patterns deemed by the
Department of justice to be unconstitutional.
Resistances from publicizing state secrets to protest against racial profiling have
made security and police over into the forces of imperial and racial tyranny.
These and other transformations (distinct from but in kind with what Ferguson
terms “re-appropriation”) are the effects of resistance underway. It is true that
many of these protests are committed to aspirational norms, but more importantly,
they are conducted by those norms, such as direct action, horizontalism, non-
violence, transparency, real or direct democracy. By refusing to take the form of a
party, vanguard, or a revolutionary army, or in some cases refusing to adopt a
reformist platform and make demands of any kind, they are conducted and even
self-proclaimed as “anti-politics,” a refusal to act politically that way. They are
political counter-conducts.
Political and critical counter-conducts will never match expectations set by the
oppositional and Manichean logic of repression–liberation. Critics from the left
are quick to point out that recent protest movements failed to become fully
revolutionary, failed to slay the many-headed beast or chop off even one of its
heads. Protests, it is said, were insufficiently unified, organized, militant, led, too
local, and focused on the wrong target. Alain Badiou (2010, p. 5) writes that
recent uprisings and protests are “[a]s yet blind, naïve, scattered, and lacking a
powerful concept or durable organization.” As Badiou casts them, the liberating
force of uprisings remains in its infancy, the infancy of the coming revolution. To
become mature and capable of liberation, riots and uprisings must harness them-
selves to the discipline of a “powerful concept or durable organization.” Yet,
from my perspective, political counter-conducts generate intense instability in all
forms of organized and disciplined politics, from the state to social movements.
That instability resonates beyond the event of protest, riot, or occupation. I am
attempting here to extend that resonance to critical conduct. The strategy I propose
for critical counter-conduct is to expect surprises.
There is a purpose as well as strategy in refusing to conduct political action in
the terms of organized, disciplined, and unified politics. Rather than pursuing
liberation out from under repressive power, and rather than foregrounding the
coming revolution, recent protests and uprisings implicitly, and at times explicitly,
reject the repressive hypothesis. They do not aim to overtake the powers of the
neoliberal state and overthrow the system of global capitalism by waging revolution,
be it violent or non-violent, and instead they practice counter-conducts,
horizontalism, and direct action, and aim to transform political action in resistance
to the limits of action imposed upon politics itself. They reject political vanguards
and opt for leaderless movements. They reject preceding resistance on a settled
focus of resistance such as neoliberalism or a normative vision and opt for building
egalitarian consensus from the ground up amongst anyone who shows up. The
profusion of critical counter-conducts, activist practices, “alternative” lifestyles,
economies, and so forth, evince the vitality of resistance under neoliberalism. As
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Towards a Critical Counter-Conduct 255

practices of freedom, counter-conducts run directly counter to the idea that


neoliberalism has completely overtaken the freedoms of citizens or destroyed the
public sphere.
Democratic counter-conducts (“This is what democracy looks like!”) do not
proclaim the sovereignty of the people or attempt to take over the state; they do
not see democracy as a kind of government or a way of establishing relations of
ruling others or being ruled by others; they practice democracy as a counter-
conduct to organized democratic politics. Among other things, antis debate the
Western and imperial bias of “democracy”; whether democracy is, can, or should
ever be the form of the state; the forms, inclusiveness, and effectiveness of
democratic practices within movements; and what it means to practice democracy
in the conditions of the present.
Yet Wendy Brown suggests in the strongest possible terms that neoliberalism
effectively banishes homo politicus from the stage of history and “undoes” the
demos. Neoliberal “reorientations also entail an existential disappearance of freedom
from the world, precisely the kind of individual and collaborative freedom asso-
ciated with homo politicus for self-rule and rule with others” (p. 110). But what are
these new counter-conducts of protest and resistance if not powerful evidence
that in the present and under neoliberalism the freedom of self-rule and rule with
others are alive and well? Brown mentions recent protests and movements in
positive terms, but she disavows the evidence I see by taking her vantage point
from the past, from what is lost to the present. By following a third rule of critical
counter-conduct, it is possible to see what is new and different without melancholy:
take one’s vantage point in and from the present. Homo politicus may well be
dead, and quite sincerely, I hope that is true. I prefer to join in with those making
a concerted effort to reinvent politics in and on their own terms. Rather than
seeking to revive homo politicus, we are trying transform “the West,” an ideal built
upon slave labor, imperialism, and settler colonialism, to be and to conduct ourselves
politically in a different way or by coming to politics just as we are. We even
sometimes acknowledge the part of and welcome non-human actors in political life.
Counter-conducts can only appear in critical conduct as more evidence of
neoliberalism’s hegemony. By countering the idea that the truth will set us free
from power, the fundamental pillar of the repressive hypothesis, critical counter-
conduct establishes a norm for counter-conduct: Do not wage resistance by
speaking the truth to power and do not resist in the hope of freedom to come.
Practice freedom and exercise power, not in the name of truth, principles, or
aspirations, but as much as possible in full awareness that the conduct you are
undertaking is both in your hands and undertaken amidst an uneven and unstable
distribution of freedom and power, making it fraught with risks and dangers. Be alert
and vigilant at all times and never trust that principles, knowledge, or power will
place or keep your political conduct on the right path. I am proposing critical
counter-conduct not to more fully realize freedom in the future, but to realize
here and now that we are freer than we feel.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

256 Barbara Cruikshank

Notes
1 It is a pleasure to acknowledge those who read or commented on earlier drafts and
presentations of this chapter. Despite their criticism, insight, and aid, all the faults of the
essay remain mine to bear. Many thanks to Ivan Ascher, Leonard Feldman, Farah
Godrej, Fred Schaffer, Sandy Schram, Jillian Schwedler, and John Seery. I am grateful
to acknowledge the inspiration I took while writing this chapter from the members of a
graduate seminar, particularly from Siddhant Issar and Candice Travis.
2 See, for example, Mapping Police Violence at mappingpoliceviolence.org; Fatal Encounters
at fatalencounters.org; Killed by Police at killedbypolice.net; The Guardian project, “The
Counted: People Killed by Police in the U.S.,” at theguardian.com.

References
Abu-Lughod, L. (1990). The Romance of Resistance: Tracing Transformations Through
Bedouin Women. American Ethnologist, 17, 41–55.
Amar, P. (2013). The Security Archipelago: Human Security States, Sexuality Politics, and the
End of Neoliberalism. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Badiou, A. (2010). The Rebirth of History: Times of Riots and Uprisings. London: Verso.
Barnett, C. (2010). Publics and Markets: What Is Wrong with Neoliberalism? In Susan Smith,
R. Pain, Sallie A. Marston, and J. P. Jones (Eds.), The Handbook of Social Geographies.
Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications.
Bialostok, S., Whitman, R. L., Bradley, W. S. (Eds.) (2012). Education and the Risk Society:
Theories, Discourse and Risk Identities in Educational Contexts. Rotterdam: Sense Publishers.
Brenner, N., Peck, J., and Theodore, N. (2010). After Neoliberalism? Globalizations, 7,
327–345.
Brown, W. (2003). Neoliberalism and the End of Liberal Democracy. Theory & Event, 7, 1.
Retrieved from: https://muse.jhu.edu/ (accessed November 10, 2003).
Brown, W. (2013). Neoliberalism and the End of Liberal Democracy. Theory & Event, 7.
doi: doi:10.1353/tae.2003.0020.
Brown, W. (2015). Undoing the Demos: Neoliberalism’s Stealth Revolution. New York: Zone
Books.
Butler, Judith (2004). What Is Critique? An Essay on Foucault’s Virtue. In Sara Salih (Ed.),
The Judith Butler Reader. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.
Davidson, A. (2011). In Praise of Counter-Conduct. History of the Human Sciences, 24,
25–41.
Dean, J. (2009). Democracy and Other Neoliberal Fantasies: Communicative Capitalism and Left
Politics. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Duggan, L. (2003). The Twilight of Equality: Neoliberalism, Cultural Politics, and the Attack on
Democracy. Boston, MA: Beacon Press.
Duménil, G. and Lévy, D. (2004). Capital Resurgent: Roots of the Neoliberal Revolution.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Feher, M. (2009). Self-Appreciation: or, the Aspirations of Human Capital. Public Culture,
21, 21–41.
Ferguson, J. (2006). Global Shadows: Africa in the Neoliberal World Order. Durham, NC:
Duke University Press.
Ferguson, J. (2009). The Uses of Neoliberalism. Antipode, 41(S1), 166–184.
Foucault, M. (2008). The Birth of Biopolitics: Lectures at the College de France, 1978–79.
Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave MacMillan.
Rethinking Neoliberalism; edited by Sanford F. Schram and
Marianna Pavlovskaya
Format: US_6x9 (152.4 × 228.6 mm); Style: Supp; Font: Bembo;
Dir: //integrafs5/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/RNM_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/
9781138735958_text.3d;

Towards a Critical Counter-Conduct 257

Fraser, N. (2017). The End of Progressive Neoliberalism. Dissent. Retrieved January 12, 2017
from: www.dissentmagazine.org/online_articles/progressive-neoliberalism-reactionary-
populism-nancy-fraser
Fukuyama, F. (2012). The Future of History: Can Liberal Democracy Survive the Decline
of the Middle Class? Foreign Affairs, January/February. Retrieved March 29, 2017 from:
www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/2012-01-01/future-history
Harcourt, B. (2010). Dismantling/Neoliberalism. Carceral Notebooks, 6, 21–32.
Harvey, D. (2005). A Brief History of Neoliberalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Larner, W. (2006). Review of A Brief History of Neoliberalism. Economic Geography, 82,
49–51.
Mirowski, P. (2013). Never Let a Serious Crisis Go to Waste: How Neoliberalism Survived the
Financial Meltdown. London: Verso.
Mirowski, P. (2014). The Political Movement that Dared Not Speak its own Name: The
Neoliberal Thought Collective Under Erasure. Institute for New Economic Thinking,
Working paper No. 23. Retrieved November 15, 2016 from: www.thing.net/~rdom/
ucsd/Borders/The_Political_Movement_that_Dared_not_Speak_its_own_Name.pdf
Ong, A. (2006). Neoliberalism As Exception: Mutations in Citizenship and Sovereignty.
Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Ong, A. (2007). Neoliberalism as a Mobile Technology. Transactions of the Institute of British
Geographers, 32, 3–8.
Ostry, J., Loungani, P., and Furceri, D. (2016). Neoliberalism Oversold? Finance and
Development, 53, 38–41.
Petras, J. (2011). Social Movements in Latin America: Neoliberalism and Popular Resistance.
London: Palgrave.
Petras, J. and Veltmeyer, H. (Eds.) (2014). The New Extractivism: A Post-Neoliberal Development
Model or Imperialism of the Twenty-first Century?Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Schram, S. (2015). The Return of Ordinary Capitalism: Neoliberalism, Precarity, Occupy. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Soss, J., Fording, R. C., Schram, S. F. (2011). Disciplining the Poor: Neoliberal Paternalism and
the Persistent Power of Race. Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Wacquant, L. (2009) Punishing the Poor: The Neoliberal Government of Social Insecurity.
Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

S-ar putea să vă placă și