Sunteți pe pagina 1din 4

312 ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHENOMENOLOGY

sciences also requires phenomenological clarification. primarily with what Husserl considers the two greatest
The basic question concerns how nature is a necessary threats in his day to the ideal of philosophy as rigor-
and indispensable part of the cultural world and the ous science and its realization. The first is "naturalistic
lifeworld. philosophy," which "falsifies" the ideal, i.e., pursues
the idea of rigor in the wrong way; and the second is
FOR FURTHER STUDY "historicism and Weltanschauungsphilosophie,"which
"weakens" and ultimately calls into question the pur-
Boeckh, August. Enzyklopădie und Methodenlehre der suit ofthe ideal altogether.
philologischen Wissenschaften [1877/86]. Ed. Ernst Bra-
tuschek. Stuttgart: Teubner, 1966 (reprint); abridged trans. In the latter case, some philosophers look at the his-
as On Interpretation and Criticism. Trans. Jean Paul tory of thought and only see a series of failed attempts
Prichard. Norman, Oklahoma: University Press, 1968. to ascertain eterna! truth. With this assessment Husserl
Dithey, Wilhelm. Der Aufhau der geschichtlichen Welt in den
Geisteswissenschafien. Gesammelte Schrijien 1, 1914. wholeheartedly agrees. But then they move from that
Gadamer, Hans-Georg. Wahrheit und Methode. 2nd. ed. to the conclusion that philosophy can never be more
Tiibingen: J. C. B. Mohr, 1965; Truth and Method. Trans. than the expression of the Weltanschauung of its eul-
Garrct Bardcn and John Cumrning. New York: Seabury
Press, 1975. ture and its historical period. (Though he does not say
Husserl, Edmund. Phănomenologische P.1ychologie. Ed. so directly, Husserl implicates WILHELM DILTHEY in this
Walter Bicmel. Husserliana 9. The Hague: Martinus move.) For Husserl this is an invalid inference and an
Nijhoff, 1962; 2nd rev. ed. 1968; Phenomenological Psy-
chology: Lectures, Summer Semeste1; 1925. Trans. John instance ofthe self-refuting relativism he had attacked
Scanlon. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1977. in the Logische Untersuchungen ( 1900-190 1). Philos-
- . Zur Phănomenologie der Jntersuhjektivităt. 3 vo1s. Ed. ophy should stop mulling over its own past and get
Iso Kern. Husserliana 13-15 Dordrecht: K1uwer, 1973.
Mohanty, Jitcndra Nath, ed. Phenomenology and the Human on with its task. The history of philosophy is fine as
Sciences. The Hague: Martnius Nijhoff, 1985. a branch of history, but should not be substituted for
Orth, Ernst Wolfgang, ed. Dilthey und die Philosophie der philosophy itself. This is part of the meaning of the
Gegenwart. Freiburg: Karl Alber, 1985.
Ricceur, Paul. Le conflit des inte1pretations: Essais injunction "to the matters themselves." It is reinforced
d 'hernu!neutique. Paris: Editions du Seu il, 1969; The Con- in the ldeen where Husserl tells us, even before intro-
flict o( lnte1pretations. Trans. Don Ihde. Evanston, IL: ducing phenomenological bracketing, that we should
Northwestern University Press, 1974.
Seebohm, Thomas M. Zur Kritik der hermeneutischen Ver- in effect "bracket" the entire history of philosophy.
nunft. Bonn: Bouvier, 1972. Philosophy may in fact be in history, but its aim is to
transcend history toward the timeless essences that are
THOMAS M. SEEBOHM tobe grasped by phenomenology.
UniversitătMainz Of course, this does not prevent phenomenology
from attempting to grasp the essence of history itself,
and Husserl makes some early efforts in that direction.
"Geschichte" refers, like its English equivalent, both to
HISTORY In order to understand the complex the course ofhuman events, principally in the past, and
relationship between phenomenology and history, the to the discipline whose aim is to know those events.
best place to begin is doubtless EDMUND HUSSERL 's essay In severa! ways Husserl is like Dilthey and the neo-
"Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft" ( 1911 ). Husserl Kantians ofhis time: he abjures Hegelian-style specu-
stands ready to unveil the "phenomenological grasp of lation about the grand sweep ofhistory, aims instead at
essence" (die phanomenologische Wesense1jassung) as the clarification of historical knowledge, and consid-
the culmination ofthe EIDETIC METHOD that will enable ers history a HUMAN SCIENCE that cannot be reduced to
philosophy to be at last what is has always wanted Of integrated with the NATURAL SCIENCES. History is an

but has so far failed to be: strict or rigorous science. empirica! discipline and thus deals with facts. But the
But readers are told very little there about that method; facts it is concerned with are not those of the natural
they will have to wait for the ldeen zu einer reinen world. In ldeen ll [ 1912-15] Husserl works out the no-
Phanomenologie und phanomenologischen Philoso- tion ofthe spiritual or cultural world (geistige Welt) as
phie l ( 1913 ). Instead, the essay is polemic, deal ing a distinct region of reality with its own a priori ontol-

Lester Embree, Elizabeth A. Behnke, David Carr, J. Claude Evans, Jose Huertas-Jourda, Joseph J. Kockelmans, William R. McKenna,
Algis Mickunas, Jitendra Nath Mohanty, Thomas M. Seebohm, Richard M. Zaner (eds.), Encyclopedia of Phenomenology.
© 1997 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
HISTORY 313

ogy and its way ofbeing constituted in consciousness. der geschichtlichen Welt in den Geisteswissenschaften
Husserl 's approach throughout is to trace the basic con- (The make-up ofthe historical world in the human sci-
cepts ofscience back to the prescientific WORLD and the ences, [ 191 0]). Husserl was acquainted with this vol-
attitudes we take toward it. The "natural attitude" of ume at Jeast through the work of his assistant LUDWIG
ldeen 1 is subdivided in ldeen Il into the "naturalistic" LANDGREBE and of GEORG MISCH, who both pubJished

and the "personalistic" attitudes, and it is in the Jatter significant studies of Dilthey in relation to phenomen-
that the human sciences have their source. The basic ology in those years. There is some irony in the fact that
entities here are not things, but persons and communi- Dilthey should have played a positive role here, since
ties of persons, and the basic occurrences are experi- he was the intended target of Husserl's early polemic
ences, thoughts, and actions that stand under relations against historicism.
of motivation rather than causality. In any case, Husserl's concern with history emerges
When these structures of personal and social exis- in his last work out of his reflection on the sta tus and
tence are related to TIME, they reveal features we think significance of science. It is a mistake to think that the
of as historical. Persons are not "in" time in the same scientific consciousness can simply transcend its con-
way that things and natural events are in time. They do crete social situation and go directly to the TRUTH. The
not simply persist through time, and the events of one pursuit oftheoretical truth is itself historical. Even if it
moment in one's life do not simply produce those of is the nature of consciousness to engage in this pursuit,
the next causally. Rather, the past has meaning for the the individual always inherits it as an ongoing activ-
person, and forms an intentiona! background or hori- ity of the society in which he or she takes it up. The
zon for present and future. Persons "survey" time and incipient scientist also builds on the results already ob-
think ofthemselves and the communities to which they tained by others. Thus although a cognitive endeavor
belong in terms of their past and fu ture. such as science - even a "pure" or ideal discipline
By the time of the Cartesianische Meditationen like geometry - is pursued by individuals, it owes
[ 1931] Husserl was sufficiently attentive to both the its undertaking in each case, as well as its capacity to
social and historical aspects of conscious experience advance, to the social context in which it exists. Each
that he attributes them to transcendental and not merely inquirer depends on the sedimented acquisitions ofhis
to empirica! or "personal" consciousness. Constitution or her predecessors.While the cognitive life ofthe indi-
is cumulative and requires GENETIC PHENOMENOLOGY; vidual owes its birth to the social context, and depends
the EGO is not merely an empty subjective pole but is on the same context for its success, there is a negative
the substrate ofhabitualities. The ego constitutes itself side to this dependence. The concepts and methods
for itself, he says, "in the unity of a history." While taken over from the tradition can equally function as
this statement suggests something like a personal or prejudices that skew the individual 's perspective on the
individual history, Husserl goes on in the Fifth Med- subject matter. It can happen in any field that theoret-
itation to a discussion of "personalities of a higher ical progress requires not building on, but criticizing
order," i.e., social groups or communities conceived as and rejecting what is handed down. But even this takes
collective subjects that likewise constitute themselves place against the background ofthe discipline's tacitly
through their history (a theme already touched on in accepted goals, problems, methods, and basic concepts.
the "Gemeingeist" manuscripts of a decade earlier). Thus even conceived as a critica! enterprise opposed
This growing appreciation for the historical char- to accepting anything on authority, science belongs to
acter of even transcendental subjectivity achieves its a historical tradition.
fullest expression in Husserl 's last work, Die Krisis In the Krisis Husserl recognizes that this analysis is
der europaischen Wissenschaften und die transzen- no less true of philosophy itself than it is of the other
dentale Phanomenologie (1936). In part this may re- disciplines. In the modern era philosophy has taken
flect the renewed influence of Dilthey. Though the lat- over from the sciences its mathematical-physical con-
ter had died in 1912, his collected works were being ception ofthe world and then failed to understand sub-
published posthumously. In 1927 volume 7 appeared, jectivity because it has tried to explain it causally as an
containing Dilthey's late manuscript on Der Au/bau element within that world. Even KANT, who recognizes
314 ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHENOMENOLOGY

the constitutive role of subjectivity, sti li conceives of MERLEAU-PONTY especially, as well as PAUL RICCEUR, are
the latter purely in relation to a scientifically construed strongly inftuenced by the Krisis in their approach to
world. Thus there is a need to return to the LIFEWORLD phenomenology. In their work and in that of JEAN-PAUL
in which subjectivity has its home prior to science, SARTRE - especially after L'etre et le neant ( 1943)
and in which the activity of science, and every other - and SIMONE DE BEAUVOIR, the inftuencc of HEGEL
cognitive activity, including philosophy itself, has its and MARX leads to a heavily historicized conception of
point of departure. While the sciences do not need to consciousness and human existence. For these thinkers
understand themselves philosophically in order to suc- the acknowledgment ofhistoricity is not fatal to pheno-
ceed, it is philosophy's task to understand them, and menology, but it does contribuie, together with other
this means tracing them back to their prescientific ori- considerations, to a substantial curtailment of its pre-
gins. But philosophy must likewise understand itself, tensions. The capacity to grasp timeless esscnces, and
and must accordingly circle back on its own origins in thus to attain the status of a rigorous scicnce, is no
the lifeworld. longer touted as phenomenology's chief virtue, as it
lfthe world-as-portrayed-by-science turns out tobe was by the early Husserl, but phenomenology itself.
a historically developed and thus in some sense contin- somewhat more modestly conceived, survives.
gent phenomenon, the prescientific lifeworld, by con- The case is somewhat different for MARTIN IIEI-
trast, seems universal and necessary. Yet Husserl rec- DEGGER, whose ideas on historicity developed con-
ognizes that the lifeworld is itself historical in a less currently with those of Husserl. In a late chapter of
obvious but more important way. Like the common- Sein und Zei! (1927) Heidegger takes up the topic of
sense world evoked by other philosophers with sim- Geschichtlichkeit (historicity) and reveals that he too
ilar concerns, the lifeworld turns out to contain the has been inftuenced by Dilthey. Up to this point his
sediments of past scientific accomplishments. The pre- discussion of authentic human existence has empha-
given, naively intuited world of any individual, inno- sized DASEIN's relation to the future and to the prospect
cent of explicit theoretical interpretation, is therefore of death. Now he turns his attention to birth and ori-
a historically sedimented cultural world that may dif- gins. His previous discussion of social existence or
fer radically from the similarly naive world of another being-with-others as a dimension of Oase in had tied it
culture or historical period. primarily to inauthenticity (das Man ), suggesting that
Thus Husserlmoves from his early, rather hasty dis- authenticity means isolation. Now he suggests that we
missal ofthe importance ofhistory, at least for philos- derive possibilities of authentic existence by choosing
ophy, to an almost obsessive preoccupation with it, to a heros and taking over existing traditions from the past.
conception of consciousness as deeply and pervasively For many readers of Sein und Zeit, especially those
historical at every level - prescientific and scientific, inftuenced by the Sartrean EXISTENTIALISM it helped to
individual and social. And he is led in this direction by inspire, one is struck by a sharp contrast when one
phenomenology itself, in his usual relentless pursuit arrives at this chapter: the authentic self, which had
of die Sachen selbst. Yet this result is bound to raise seemcd a figure oficonoclastic rebellion from the mass,
serious questions about the original idea of phenomen- now emerges as a stern and proud traditionalist paying
ology as rigorous science- that is, as the inquiry that homage by obedience to the authority ofthe past.
rises above historical contingency to attain universal But this conception of the historical character of
eidetic structures. Though Husserl in the Krisis is far Dasein is really only a reflection of a much deeper
from giving up on the ideal - indeed, he presents and more thoroughgoing notion of historicity that en-
phenomenology with even more missionary zeal than compasses the nature of understanding and ultimately
ever before- it is clear that he is struggling mightily that of truth itself. Unlike Husserl, Heidegger is not
with some of the more disturbing implications of his content to raise questions about the historical character
own conception of history. of knowledge, reason, and understanding. He is con-
Most of Husserl 's successors in the phenomenologi- vinced that human existence is radically finite, under-
cal movement take over and develop further the con- standing is a projection of Oase in 's facticity, and truth
ception of historicity found in his late work. MAURICE is something like a historical occurrence ( Geschehen ).
HUMAN SCIENCES 315

Such a conception is bound to conflict with the mani- which they, like ali sciences and also philosophy, origi-
festly "transcendental" project of Sein und Zeit to artic- nale. This genus ofsciences currently includes COMMU-
ulate the general, i.e., the presumably timeless and tran- NICOLOGY, ECONOMICS, ETHNOLOGY, GEOGRAPHY, HISTORY,
shistorical, structures of human existence. This leads POLITIC AL SCIENCE, PSYCHOLOGY, and SOCIOLOGY as sin-
Heidegger, not long after the publication ofthat work, gle disciplines, but human or cultural sciences are also
to what most interpreters see as an abandonment of increasingly included in multidisciplines such as EHI-
phenomenology, at least in any form that could appear NIC STUDIES and those re}ated to ECOLOGY, FEMINISM,
continuous with Husserl or even with the phenomen- RELIGION, and TECHNOLOGY. The rise of sciences of this
ological tradition in FRANCE. And it may be largely the kind, which ha ve their prehistories in the medieval and
influence ofthis !ater Heidegger in France that leads to ancient worlds and were accelerated through the ex-
the decline of phenomenology in that country during panding contact with non-European societies in recent
the POSTMODERN phase. It remains to be seen whether centuries, is as much a distinctive feature ofthe modern
phenomenology will be done in by a conception ofhis- Western wor}d as the rise ofthe NATURAL SCIENCES.
tory that originally arose from phenomenology itself. Beyond such chiefly theoretical disciplines there
are what can be called normative, evaluative, or axi-
FOR FURTHER STUDY
otic disciplines, which are concerned with ARCHITFC-
TURE, DANCE, FILM, LITERATURE, MUSIC, THEATER, etc.,
Carr, David. Phenomenology and the Prohlem of History: A and there are also practica/ disciplines, such as ED-
Studv o{ Husserl:~ Transcendental Philosophy. Evanston,
IL: Northwestern University Press, 1974. UCATION, LAW, MEDICINE, NURSING, PIIYSICAL EDUCATION,
- . Time, Narrative, and Historv. Bloomington, IN: Indiana and PSYCHIATRY. A broader category, CULTURAL DISCI-
University Press, 1986. PLINES, has been called for and theoretical, axiotic,
Dilthey, Wilhelm. Gesammelte Schnjien. 5th ed. Voi. 7. Ed.
Bernard Groethuysen. Stuttgart: Teubncr, 1968. and practica! species might then be recognized within
Gadamcr, Hans-Georg. Wahrheit und Methode. Tiibingen: it, although many cultural "sciences" already include
Mohr, 1962; 7htth and Method. Trans. Garrct Barden and practica! components, e.g., the way psychotherapy is
John Cumming. New York: Seabury Press, 1975.
Hohl, Hubcrt. Lehenswelt und Geschichte. Freiburg: Karl often considered part of psychology. Practica! action
Alber, 1962. always has cognitive foundations within it and when
Janssen, Paul. Geschichte und Lehenswelt. The Hague: Mar- these foundations are scientific, scientific technologies
linus Nijhoff, 1970.
Landgrebe, Ludwig. "Wilhelm Diltheys Theorie der and technigues can be spoken of. There are also eval-
Gcisteswissenschaften." Jahrhuch fiir Philosophie und uational foundations in, e.g., social work, that make
phănomenologische Forschung 9 ( 1928), 237-367. nontheoretical disciplines normative.
Misch, Georg. Lehensphilosophie und Phănomenologie.
Bonn: Cohen, J930; 2nd. ed. Leipzig: Teubner, J93 J The mentioned non-philosophical disciplines have
Olafson, Frederick. The Dialectic o{Action. Chicago: Uni- not only been reflected upon from standpoints in
versity of Chicago Press, J 978. phenomenological philosophy, but also increasingly
Soffer, Gail. Husserl and the Prohlem o{ Relativism. Dor-
drecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1991. have phenomenological tendencies within them. Non-
philosophical contributors to disciplines affected by or
DAVID CARR convergent with philosophical phenomenology include
Emory Universi(v the psychiatrists LUDWIG BINSWANGER and KARL JASPERS
and the SOCioJogists GEORG SIMML'L and MAX WERER. Dis-
tinguishing philosophy as such from human science is
among the problems of the philosophy of the human
HUMAN SCIENCES Also called the "eul- sciences.
tura! sciences," the human sciences (die Geisteswis- A human scientific discipline can be said to be
senschaften, les sciences humaines) are special or pos- phenomenological, first, if it is devoted to basing
itive theoretical sciences that are concerned in various knowledge on the best possible EVIDENCE ofthe matters
ways with aspects of human cultural life and cultural themselves in the relevant region. This evidence can
worlds. These disciplines are related to practica! appli- occur with respect to the ancient Hellenic world, for
cations as well as to the everyday prescientific life from example, not only through the study of texts, but also

Lester Embree, Elizabeth A. Behnke, David Carr, J. Claude Evans, Jose Huertas-Jourda, Joseph J. Kockelmans, William R. McKenna,
Algis Mickunas, Jitendra Nath Mohanty, Thomas M. Seebohm, Richard M. Zaner (eds.), Encyclopedia of Phenomenology.
© 1997 Kluwer Academic Publishers.

S-ar putea să vă placă și