Sunteți pe pagina 1din 13

Journal of Biomedical Informatics 37 (2004) 86–98

www.elsevier.com/locate/yjbin

Cognitive schema and naturalistic decision making in


evidence-based practices
Paul R. Falzer*
Department of Psychiatry, Yale School of Medicine, CMHC, 34 Park Street, Room 144, New Haven, CT 06508, USA
Received 11 November 2003

Abstract

A recent article in this journal proposed a naturalistic approach to decision making that overcomes problems intrinsic to classical
decision theory. The approach emphasizes cognitive and multi-level processes, the development of expert reasoning, and the role of
decision support in individual and organizational decision making. The current paper builds on this effort by suggesting a natu-
ralistic, multi-level, theory that can facilitate the dissemination of evidence-based practices (EBPs). The paper presents ‘‘Image
Theory,’’ a theory that has been extensively investigated in other disciplines, but has yet to be utilized in medical decision research. It
is suggested that its rich, empirically tested, distinctions among kinds of cognitive and organizational processes and types of de-
cisions and tasks make Image Theory especially valuable in describing impediments to implementing EBPs. The paper discusses how
naturalistic theory can assist clinicians, administrators, researchers, and policy makers in achieving a balance between evidence-
based medicine and patient-centered practice.
Ó 2004 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.

Keywords: Medical decision making; Naturalistic decision making; Classical decision theory; Image Theory; Cognition; Dissemination; Heuristics;
Sub-optimality; Diagnostic reasoning; Psychiatry; Mental health; Schizophrenia

1. Introduction value’’ and using information in an ‘‘optimal’’ fashion.


Rationality and optimality are normative concepts: They
The decision making practices of healthcare practi- presume an inclination to aggregate information accu-
tioners have long been of interest to administrators, rately and consistently, and an ability to make judg-
researchers, and educators. Recent attention that has ments that are at least logically sound, if not empirically
focused on the subject is owing in part to the growing correct [3].
popularity of evidence-based practice (EBP) initiatives. Though most medical practitioners are eager to base
According to Sackett and associates, ‘‘Evidence-based clinical decisions on the best available evidence [4], there
medicine (EBM) is the conscientious, explicit, and ju- has been noticeable reluctance to implement EBP ini-
dicious use of current best evidence in making decisions tiatives [5–7]. The resistance is owing in part to the
about the care of individual patients’’ ([1], p. 72). As the normative thrust of CDT. Some critics have argued that
definition indicates, there is an intimate relationship the deliberate and judicious application of evidence that
between EBM and clinical decision making. is requisite to sound clinical practice is inconsistent with
According to Elstein [2], this relationship has been the normative standards and algorithmic applications
predicated on the conceptual framework and terminol- that characterize EBPs [8].
ogy of Classical Decision Theory, or ‘‘CDT.’’ In its There have been exemplary adaptations of the origi-
original form, CDT focuses on strategies of rational nal expected value model in psychology [9] and eco-
decision making, particularly on ‘‘maximizing expected nomics [10]. In addition, theoretical variations such as
behavioral decision theory [11] and multi-attribute util-
ity theory [12], and new applications in risk management
*
Fax: 1-203-974-7719. and communication [13,14] have demonstrated CDTÕs
E-mail address: paul.falzer@yale.edu. resilience. Nonetheless, discontinuity is evident when

1532-0464/$ - see front matter Ó 2004 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
doi:10.1016/j.jbi.2004.02.002
P.R. Falzer / Journal of Biomedical Informatics 37 (2004) 86–98 87

principles of CDT are applied to practical situations. conventional treatment of choice and a newer alterna-
Thoughtful observers who are committed to CDT-based tive. A matrix that represents this decision appears in
approaches find this discontinuity troubling [15], while Table 1, where an expected value is calculated for each
less sanguine critics suggest that even the most malleable therapy by multiplying the positive and negative utilities
forms of CDT are inadequate to the tasks of describing, by their respective probabilities, then subtracting the
evaluating, and aiding human decisions [16]. Alternative negative result from the positive. This calculation shows
approaches to classical theory, inspired principally by that conventional treatment has a higher expected value,
Simon [17,18], began appearing in economics, sociology, even though the alternative has a better positive out-
and communication over half a century ago. Within the come (+8 versus +5). The reasons for this apparent
past 15 years, these approaches began to coalesce under anomaly are that the alternative also has a worse neg-
the rubric of Naturalistic Decision Making, or ‘‘NDM’’ ative outcome ()4 versus )2) and a lower probability of
[19]. success (.6 versus .9). Given the data in Table 1, a cli-
This paper discusses why NDM theories are better nician who chooses to prescribe conventional treatment
able than CDT-based theories to assist clinicians, edu- is making a rational decision. However, the rationality
cators, and administrators in understanding the appar- standard requires more than reaching the correct con-
ent resistance to EBM, and in developing strategies to clusion: The choice between conventional and alterna-
overcome the disparity between principle and practice. tive therapies must be made by discerning the relevant
The discussion begins by indicating why optimality utilities and probabilities, then aggregating them cor-
presents an intractable problem for medical decision rectly [27].
making, then introduces an NDM-inspired approach Grounding EBPs on CDT requires that there is sub-
that was developed specifically for medical decision stantial data from randomized clinical trials to conclude
making. This discussion leads to presenting another that a given treatment has a sufficiently high probability
NDM theory that has yet to be applied to medicine, but of a good outcome. In Table 1, the probability of .6
has distinctive features that make it especially attractive suggests that while the alternative treatment has prom-
for medical decision making. The paper concludes by ise, the evidence is insufficient to warrant its recom-
indicating how this theory may be helpful in addressing mendation as an EBP, even if results to date (as
the disparity between principle and practice, and in represented by the utilities) are highly favorable. To say
promoting the adoption of EBPs. that a treatment is ‘‘evidence-based’’ is to assert that
both determinants of expected value are sufficiently
high. EBPs are practices that follow normative stan-
2. Optimality in classical decision theory dards. Evidence-based treatment guidelines function as
decision aids that identify evidence-based treatments,
According to Hammond ([20], p. 53), two metatheo- summarize supporting evidence, and compare preferred
ries have been persistent rivals in the history of science treatments to alternatives.
and particularly in research on judgment and decision
making. There is ‘‘correspondence’’ metatheory, that 2.1. The problems of optimality
strives for empirical accuracy, and ‘‘coherence’’ me-
tatheory, that focuses on achieving logical or statistical Three points should be emphasized about the concept
rationality. In the decision theory literature, correspon- of optimality: First, optimal standards are embedded in
dence is exemplified in BrunswikÕs probabilistic func- the logic of a normative model. In models such as ex-
tionalism [21,22] and by the cognitive heuristics theory pected value or BayesÕ Theorem, procedures that pro-
of Tversky and Kahneman [23], which will be discussed duce an optimal decision are properties of the norm.
momentarily. Prime applications of coherence in the Conditions of optimality cannot be arbitrary, subjective,
decision theory literature include Peterson and BeachÕs
Bayesian-inspired claim that persons function as intui-
tive statisticians [24], and studies by Hoffman and as- Table 1
sociates on regression models as representations of An expected value decision matrix
clinical judgment [25,26]. A brief account of the coher- Therapy Variable Outcome EV
ence-inspired concept of expected value illustrates the
normative aspect of both correspondence and coher- Positive Negative
ence, and the importance they afford the concept of Conventional Probability .9 .1
optimality. Utility 5 )2
P U 4.5 ).2 4.3
In rudimentary form, expected value is a linear model
that expresses a multiplicative relationship between two Alternative Probability .6 .4
variables: probability and utility. To illustrate, suppose Utility 8 )4
P U 4.8 )1.6 3.2
that a clinician must choose between two therapies, a
88 P.R. Falzer / Journal of Biomedical Informatics 37 (2004) 86–98

or externally imposed. Second, optimality is a single effect of positive and negative phrasing on perceptions
universal standard that applies to all of the phenomena of risk.
that fall within a normative or procedural domain. All Owing to compelling explanations, clever procedures,
EBPs are evaluated by the same procedures; applying and recent adaptations, work on cognitive heuristics has
these procedures in every instance is a sine qua non of won a prominent place in the medical decision making
optimal decision making. Third, optimality is an ab- literature [39]. Together, these studies offer considerable
stract standard that is two steps removed from concrete support for the claim that decision making is so rife with
information and actual clinical situations. The first re- sub-optimal tendencies that optimality is nothing more
move refers to the aggregation of individual phenomena than a will-o-the-wisp: Optimality is an unfeasible ob-
into a domain (for instance, all cases of acute schizo- jective because the standards of an optimal decision are
phrenia). The second remove extracts normative prin- embedded in the logic of normative models, and medical
ciples from this domain, and these principles become the practitioners do not follow normative models when they
standards of optimality ([28], p. 253). make decisions.
The argument advanced here is that the quest for The universal and abstract qualities of CDT limit its
optimality is daunted by two intractable problems: First, value even as a descriptive tool or benchmark. In ev-
optimality is not feasible in the domains that comprise eryday medical practice, decision making is affected by a
decision making; second, optimality has marginal rele- variety of contingencies and constraints. But at two
vance to medical practice. The three characteristics levels of abstraction, these variegations fade into a single
identified above will guide a discussion of these prob- procedure and a universal set of norms. For CDT, there
lems. is significant transfer of decision skills across contexts.
Since CDT-based approaches depict optimality as a In principle, all decisions are essentially identical, whe-
predicate of sound decision making, the results of hun- ther they pertain to taking an umbrella to work, be-
dreds of studies conducted over the past 50 years should ginning a relationship, engaging in arbitrage, or
give us pause. Beginning with MeehlÕs [29] research that recommending surgery. In practice, however, medical
compared clinical with actuarial predictions, and pro- decision making requires specialized training, skill, and
ceeding through the work of Goldberg [30], Dawes [26], expertise. Applying a model to medical decision making
and others, studies have found almost universally that that is equally appropriate to buying a set of tires raises
medical practitioners lack the perceptive and integrative the specter of EBM as a degenerate form of medical
power that are requisite to optimal decision making. practice. The discontinuity between universality in
(Kleinmuntz [31] gives a comprehensive review of these principle and variety in practice is responsible in part for
studies.) According to Fischhoff [15], the inclination to what has been depicted as a stalemate between EBP
make sub-optimal decisions is owing to inherent limi- initiatives and the aims of patient-centered medicine
tations of cognitive capacity, compounded by a lack of [40].
proper training and reluctance to employ counter-intu- Optimality is a universal standard with abstract
itive processes. The work of Peterson, Beach, and as- conditions that operate simultaneously in two domains:
sociates [32] supports this observation. They conducted Along with two removes of data, there is an abstraction
studies that compared subject responses to normative from individual decision maker to an idealized entity. As
predictions of BayesÕ Theorem and found consistent described by Beach and Lipshitz, what results ‘‘is an
patterns of sub-optimal decision making. However, abstract system of propositions that is designed to de-
other lines of research found that clinicians utilize in- scribe the choices of an ideal hypothetical decision ma-
formation so poorly and inconsistently that they are ker—omniscient and computationally omnipotent
outperformed even by a simplified model of their own Economic Man’’ ([16], p. 21). The idealization exacts a
judgments [33]. price, because Economic Man exists in a world of om-
Tversky, Kahneman, and associates suggest that de- niscience and omnipotence. Medicine is not practiced in
cision making is sub-optimal because people simply do that world, but in situations that require decisions to be
not follow normative strategies [34]. Instead, we employ made urgently, oftentimes with scarce and unreliable
a variety of cognitive short-cuts known as heuristics. The information, using quality and effectiveness criteria that
first heuristic they identified is a tendency to treat dis- are evolving to meet the demands of a dynamic health-
tributional characteristics of a sample as representing a care system. Standards of optimality can assist decision
parent population [35]. A profusion of studies has makers in identifying errors and isolating problems.
shown that employing this ‘‘representativeness’’ heuris- However, in developing solutions, whether they take
tic, or others such as ‘‘availability’’ and ‘‘anchoring,’’ form of decision support, educational programming, or
leads to incorrect decisions [23,36]; moreover, experts organizational initiatives, optimality yields to standards
are as inclined to use heuristics as laypersons [35]. Per- that emerge from a variety of fallible sources, including
haps the most intriguing studies of all concern the expert opinion, consensus, objective assessment, and
heuristic known as ‘‘framing’’ [37,38], which refers to the administrative procedure.
P.R. Falzer / Journal of Biomedical Informatics 37 (2004) 86–98 89

3. A naturalistic alternative to classical decision theory thought. In SvensonÕs schema, there is even a level 4, in
which unfamiliarity is palpable and novel alternatives
Of the naturalistic alternatives to CDT that have been must be elicited or created (p. 22). For Patel and asso-
advanced over the past 15 years, one stands out as par- ciates, these cognitively demanding situations are the
ticularly relevant for medical researchers, clinicians, and grist of medical decision making. They are the reason
educators. This is the cognitive naturalistic approach of why medicine is practiced with expertise, but never
Patel and associates. Their earliest work was inspired by mastered.
SimonÕs research on cognitive patterns in expert decision
making [41]. A series of studies [42,43] contributed to the 3.1. Requisite Variety in naturalistic theory
medical education literature by describing the develop-
ment of medical knowledge and expert use of clinical It was Ashby [53] who posited as a fundamental thesis
information. With the publication of several landmark that only variety can destroy variety (p. 207). There is an
papers [44–46], the original thrust has expanded to in- analogous principle in NDM, that only a theory that
clude extensive work on cognition, on the relationship allows a broad range of description can encompass the
between individual and organizational decisions [47], variegations of human activity. The inclination of CDT
and the affect of technology on decision processes [48]. to treat all decisions as the same inherently limits its
A recent paper by Patel et al. [49] drew the concepts descriptive power. Patel et al. [49] illustrate this limita-
and findings of previous work together. It offered a co- tion by noting that CDT-based research treats proba-
gent critique of CDT, made a case for expanding the bility principally as a strength-of-belief indicator. But
scope of decision research beyond the confines of nor- the concept of probability does not translate so readily
mative modeling, and proposed rudiments of a cogni- from the self-contained world of logic to the mediated
tively-rich NDM theory. It is also suggested that this world of experience.
approach can facilitate the dissemination of EBPs: Suppose that the probability of recovery from a
chronic disease is estimated at about 60%. But when a
The principal thrust of evidence-based medicine is on the dis- physician tells a patient, ‘‘based on what we know, there
semination of cutting-edge clinical evidence in order to improve are about 6 chances in 10 that you will recover from this
decision-making practices. . . However, the availability of evi- condition,’’ it is not likely that she is saying: ‘‘The strength
dence does not guarantee that it will be applied in a given deci-
sion-making context. Evidence is invariably perceived evidence
of my belief about your recovering is 6 on a scale of 10.’’
in the physicianÕs mind ([50], p. 162). We know it is inaccurate to gauge individual performance
from a population percentage, but this grammatical
One might argue that adaptations of classical theory, mistake is so common that we simply assume the physi-
exemplified by the studies of heuristics, give the cogni- cian to be saying: ‘‘Given that you are a typical member of
tive aspects of decision making their due. However, even the population of persons with this condition. . .’’ How-
the most cognitively oriented CDT approaches give an ever, she might mean something entirely different, such as:
inadequate account, owing to their consuming interest ‘‘You have the disease now, but based on what we know
in optimality ([49], pp. 58–59). Under optimal condi- about it, we should assume that you will recover.’’ Saying
tions, decision makers become transducers, with a cog- ‘‘6 out of 10’’ can mean a number of things, but the sheer
nitive apparatus that works like a choice-selecting variety of possibilities can only be grasped by a model that
mechanism. But cognition has a more significant role is able to account for empirically diverse meanings. Ra-
when decisions are made with limited information, un- ther than performing expected value calculations or
der the pressure of time, when uncertainties are incal- comparing actual behavior with optimal performance,
culable, and there is no universally correct answer. In Patel and co-workers [54] utilize empirical methods such
such cases, medical decision making is more about as think-aloud protocols and semantic network analysis
problem-solving than deliberation and choice. Expert [44] to examine cognitive and organizational processes,
decision makers frequently are called upon to engage in and patient–physician interaction [55].
original thinking; at these times, they are generating NDM approaches offer greater variety of explanation
options as well as selecting from them. than their CDT counterparts, while retaining one of the
PatelÕs naturalistic theory is cast in the tradition of features that has made CDT attractive to medical deci-
cognitive psychology [51], which expanded the study of sion makers. Purely descriptive approaches tend over-
behavior to include situations that are novel and lacking look the intrinsically prescriptive nature of certain
sufficient recognition. To be sure, there are events in decision making situations [56]. For instance, replacing
which people know their way about and can respond normative principles with descriptive models would
routinely. These are what Svenson [52] refers to as lead to an unsatisfactory result in medical practice,
‘‘Level 1’’ decisions. But, higher up the ladder of cog- which is driven by standards such as ‘‘health,’’ ‘‘quality
nitive complexity are decisions at level 3, where situa- of care,’’ and ‘‘expertise.’’ When norms are instilled with
tions are novel and coping with them requires original the imprint of optimality they become abstract and
90 P.R. Falzer / Journal of Biomedical Informatics 37 (2004) 86–98

unapproachable. By contrast, a naturalistic theory al- dynamics affect the implementation of EBPs in organi-
lows norms to be averred—not as unrealistic ideals, but zational arenas [60,61].
as desirable regularities. In sum, Patel and associates have developed a cog-
For instance, one recommendation for the treatment nitive naturalistic approach that regards medical deci-
of acute episodes of schizophrenia is that the dosage of sion making as a complex process of problem-solving. It
anti-psychotic medication should fall in the range of depicts cognitive activity as a generative capacity whose
300–1000 mg. chlorpromazine equivalent units per day study requires a variety of descriptive means and
[57]. Lehman et al. [58] found a conformance rate to this methods. Unlike CDT-based approaches, decision
standard of 62.4%. Attending physicians, administra- making is conceived as a multi-level process, with norms
tors, and members of quality improvement committees that are established and implemented by organizational
would not read these findings as illustrating sub-stan- initiatives. The following section examines a different
dard practice and them dismiss them. Instead, they will NDM-inspired theory, developed by experimental and
acknowledge that a 100% conformance rate is neither organizational psychologists, that has made a sub-
possible nor desirable because there are instances in stantial contribution to the literature on management
which a dosage outside the standard range is clinically and decision making. Its similarities to the approach of
indicated. Then, a quality improvement goal might be Patel and associates are remarkable, considering that the
established at 70% conformance this year and 75% in the two were developed independently. It is suggested
following year. Some administrators would expect to see nonetheless that ‘‘Image Theory,’’ whose principal fea-
bottom-line results only, but others will want to know tures are discussed below, has distinctive characteristics
whether (or which) physicians are practicing polyphar- that make it attractive to medical decision making, es-
macy, or whether a combination of medications is tar- pecially in assisting the efforts of administrators, prac-
geting a specific sub-set of cases, and whether these titioners, educators, and researchers to address the
deviations are producing a good clinical outcome. disparity between principle and practice that has daun-
As optimality has no organizational analog, the only ted EBM.
way for a CDT-based approach to study organizational
decision making is to treat organizational units as if they
were individual entities. However, Patel and associates 4. Image Theory
note that practices occurring at the individual level are
not fully accounted for by organizational processes, and Image Theory, or ‘‘IT’’, [62,63] is one of the most
vice-versa. In their words: ‘‘Team decision-making is fully developed and extensively researched applications
characterized by emergent properties that cannot be of NDM. Like the approach of Patel and associates, IT
captured by merely studying individual decision-mak- emphasizes descriptive modeling; it is cognitively rich
ers’’ ([49], p. 66). At least two (and usually more) or- and is designed to work with multi-level data. IT rep-
ganizational levels are at work in any medical decision, resents an intersection of three traditions: empirical
and these respective decisions have a complex relation- theories of decision making, cognitive psychology, and
ship. Organizational initiatives reciprocally effect the organizational behavior. The term ‘‘image’’ hearkens to
ways that cognitive data are conceptualized and insti- Miller, Galanter, and PibramÕs classic work on cognitive
tutionalized [59], while interpersonal and organizational theory [51], where images are portrayed as complex

Table 2
The principal concepts of IT
Concept Explanation
Schemata The cognitive apparatus that organizes plans for action
Trajectory image Goal agenda and vision of the future
Strategic image Means of achieving the goal agenda
Value image Imperatives for behavior
Decisions Processes for implementing a plan
Progress Assessment of the current plan
Adoption Consideration of candidate goals or plans
Strategies Tasks involved in developing a plan
Screening Non-compensatory elimination of unacceptable candidates
Choice Compensatory selection of the best candidate

Assessments Procedures for evaluating a plan


Image compatibility Relationship between a goal and a forecast of progress
Violations Interferences with accomplishing a plan (sources of image incompatibility)
P.R. Falzer / Journal of Biomedical Informatics 37 (2004) 86–98 91

cognitive schema with pictorial, semantic, and emo- be one of the five salads on the menu or one of the eight
tional constituents. The principal function of cognitive pastas?) In other instances, decisions are made from a
schemata is to formulate, test, and execute behavioral limited set of options that remain after others are
plans. screened out. (If the choice is a salad, then will the
IT exists into two forms: The form that focuses on dressing be Italian or oil and vinegar?) In a few cases,
processes of individual decision making has been re- decisions begin de novo and lead to adopting a new
searched more extensively than the other, which de- goal. But typically, decisions involve an assessment of
scribes organizational processes. The multi-level aspect progress to date, and this assessment affects subsequent
of IT will be illustrated in a subsequent section. In the determinations.
meantime, this presentation will concentrate on the Most clinical decisions are what IT calls progress
individual form, whose principal concepts appear in decisions. Yet, IT is perhaps unique in the way it dis-
Table 2. The concepts that are delineated in Table 2 are tinguishes progress from adoption. Investigations of IT
best introduced informally. A discussion of the three have devoted considerable attention to the progressive
images of IT leads to a more detailed consideration of aspect of decision making [28,64]. For instance, Dune-
decisions, strategies, and assessments. gan [65] investigated progress decision phenomena by
giving subjects the following scenario:
4.1. The three images of IT
Six months ago, you succeeded in obtaining money for a special
advertising campaign. Now, you are deciding whether to con-
When people make decisions, they are making plans tinue this campaign, using the remaining 20% of the budget that
to do something. For instance, we decide to move, was allocated.
marry, or take a new job. These are big decisions with
major consequences. Plans are operative in smaller Half of the subjects received a positive message about
decisions as well, such as ordering from a menu at a progress. The other half received a negative message that
restaurant or buying a bottle of water at a local stand. had essentially the same information, but framed nega-
In all cases, we are formulating a goal (or set of goals) tively. Results showed that the progress accounted for
and projecting this goal into the future. For example, over half of the variance in the decision of whether to
we move to a new town for a better quality of life or continue the project. When the framing condition and
closer proximity to work. We buy water to quench an overall satisfaction with the project were entered first in
immediate thirst or quell the urge to stop for a meal. In a hierarchical regression equation, progress was still
IT, a decision includes all the aspects of a cognitive statistically significant.
plan. This study shows that image compatibility—in this
As noted in Table 2, IT consists of three images: instance, compatibility between a goal and progress to
There is a ‘‘trajectory’’ image, which comprises the goal date—gives a reasonable explanation of the ‘‘framing’’
agenda and future vision, a ‘‘strategic’’ image, which phenomenon that was identified by studies of cognitive
comprises the means of achieving this agenda and ful- heuristics. Indeed, the way information is framed exerts
filling the vision, and a ‘‘value’’ image, which consists of an influence on subsequent decisions. However, cog-
principles and imperatives. For instance, we marry in nitive heuristics theory depicts framing as an enigmatic
order to solidify our lives and raise children. Of course, source of sub-optimality, but IT studies have found
marriage is no guarantee, nor is it requisite for living a that positive and negative messages evoke different
full life or having children. The decision to pursue these cognitive strategies: A positive frame promotes pro-
goals in this way involves a principle, and value-driven cesses that are performed quickly, whereas a negative
principles are routinely invoked when people make de- frame leads to greater deliberation. IT and heuristics
cisions. For instance, we decide to do what is right by studies obtain the same results, but IT sheds additional
ordering food that is inexpensive and low in cholesterol. light on why positive and negative messages evoke
This decision may follow imperatives, such as ‘‘eat different responses.
healthy!’’ or ‘‘save for a vacation!’’. The importance of
the value image is discussed in the final section of this 4.3. Screening and choice strategies
paper.
Along with studies of image compatibility in progress
4.2. Adoption and progress decisions decisions, IT research has also examined compatibility
assessments in adopting a course of action. Adoption
Like the cognitive naturalistic approach of Patel and decisions involve a comparison between attributes of a
associates, IT models a multiplicity of decision strate- decision option and a set of criteria [66]. There is a
gies. However, IT invokes a different set of concepts in compatibility test for adoption decisions, in which each
describing these strategies. There are instances in which instance of a disjunction between attribute and criterion
a choice is made from several good candidates. (Will it counts as a ‘‘violation.’’ An option is discarded when the
92 P.R. Falzer / Journal of Biomedical Informatics 37 (2004) 86–98

violation count exceeds an arbitrary critical number that 1. Image compatibility may be a crucial factor in clinical
is known as the ‘‘rejection threshold’’ [67]. The mecha- decisions. Studies have demonstrated that image com-
nism of counting and discarding is a simple, conserva- patibility is more important than overall satisfaction and
tive, and non-compensatory strategy called screening. exhibits a more powerful effect than message framing [73].
Patel and associates have investigated a screening These findings also suggest ways that image incompati-
mechanism in the filtering of non-salient cues [68]. IT bility may be inhibiting the implementation of EBPs: New
builds on this work by having developed a compatibility guidelines are expected to be adopted wholesale, with
test, as expressed by formula (1): minimal deliberation. However, if new EBPs imply sig-
Xn X m nificant changes in clinical practice, they are likely to
I¼ Wc Vtc ; ð1Þ promote greater deliberation and incline practitioners to
t¼1 c¼1 minimize risk [74]. A conservative tendency implies re-
where I ¼ incompatibility score; V ¼ incompatibility sistance to new ideas. But the principal impediment may
value (1 or 0); and W ¼ value weight.The incompatibility be owing to the way that clinicians are processing the call
score is obtained by multiplying each value by its re- to alter their decision making practices, especially in light
spective weight, then summing the products. In a of how the new guidelines are presented to them.
screening decision, this total is compared against an The extent of image compatibility may further com-
arbitrary but consistent standard. IT studies have found pound a conservative tendency. New EBPs are likely to
that unit weighting (W ¼ 1 in formula (1)) is appropriate be rejected when a patientÕs progress comes close to
for some decisions and differential weighting (W > 0 and matching a treatment goal or when progress falls far
6¼ 1) is more appropriate for others [69]. In either case, a short. In the former case, clinicians are inclined to stay
stable application of this standard produces a consistent the course instead of opting for an alternative. In the
rejection pattern [70]. latter case, they may be inclined to adjust the trajec-
The companion to screening is choice, which involves tory—the goal of treatment—rather than adopting a new
the selection of one option from among others by a means of achieving the current goal [75].
compensatory process of weighing and valuing. In the 2. Progress decisions may be foremost in clinical de-
practice of choice, attributes of various candidates are cision making. While some clinical decisions are pri-
compared with one another and the candidate is selected marily concerned with adopting treatment goals and
that has the highest value [71]. IT proposes that choice prescribing therapies, adoption yields to progress as-
decisions typically occur after screening is concluded. For sessments as clinicians begin to gauge a patientÕs current
instance, in evaluating candidates for a job, a list is win- condition against expected results. Progress decisions
nowed first, then a selection is made by choosing among are occurring concomitantly on organizational levels, as
the survivors. Findings from IT research indicate that administrators compare current data with previous
identical criteria may be utilized in screening and choice, quarters and use these comparisons to make projections.
but they are utilized differently because decision makers If clinical decisions eventually become progress deci-
make multi-stage decisions by partitioning screening sions, it is mistaken to treat the implementation of an
tasks from choice [72]. Screening, choice, and multi-stage EBP solely as the adoption of a new strategy. If EBPs
decision making are discussed further in the following are to have staying power, they must be adopted in the
section, which highlights the value of IT for clinical de- first place and then survive a series of progress assess-
cision making. ments. As the implementation of EBPs involves both
adoption and progress decisions, factors affecting im-
4.4. Image Theory and clinical decision making plementation will not be fully comprehended by models
that neglect or deemphasize the aspect of progress.
Image Theory is a naturalistic theory that resembles 3. Screening is a powerful and conservative mechanism
the cognitive naturalistic approach of Patel and associ- of clinical decision making. IT research suggests that
ates. IT posits that decision processes involve three alternatives are routinely discarded once they reach a
cognitive schemata: A trajectory image represents the rejection threshold, and candidates that fail to survive
formulation of goals; a strategic image represents the screening are not considered further. Note how the
means of achieving the goal agenda, and a value image screening mechanism may have a determinative effect on
represents the behavioral imperatives that affect both a decision to implement an EBP. The Schizophrenia
goals and strategies. IT offers a rich account of medical PORT treatment recommendations [57] recommend
decision making as consisting of adoption and progress conventional neuroleptic medications such as haloperi-
decisions, screening and choice strategies, and compat- dol rather than atypical medications such as olanzapine,
ibility assessments. This section identifies four ways that except for treatment-refractory patients. This is a con-
IT can make a distinctive contribution to the literature troversial claim, given that that there is limited evidence
on clinical decision making, particularly on investigating suggesting that atypicals may be associated with better
factors that influence the adoption of EBPs: symptomatic relief than conventional neuroleptics
P.R. Falzer / Journal of Biomedical Informatics 37 (2004) 86–98 93

[76,77], especially for cases that present both positive have different trajectories and may invoke different
and negative symptoms [78]. Moreover, these guidelines strategies.
do not take into account the considerable evidence that However, there is one activity in medicine that dis-
some atypicals are more easily tolerated than conven- plays most directly the complex relationships among
tional neuroleptics and lead to fewer side effects [79]. individual and organizational decision making. This is
For patients and physicians, tolerability, and comfort the activity known as treatment planning. Even given
may be at least as important as symptomatic relief [80]. ITÕs limited study of organizations, its amenability to
In the language of IT, the presence of side effects, neg- describing treatment planning is an outstanding feature.
ative symptoms, and a patientÕs reluctance to take a This section indicates how IT can assist clinicians, ad-
medication totals three violations, and this number may ministrators, and decision support staff in assessing a
exceed the rejection threshold. Consequently, a medi- range of phenomena that affect treatment decisions, in-
cation choice may be made among the atypicals and not cluding resource allocation, clinical outcomes, quality
the neuroleptics, as required by the PORT guidelines. improvement initiatives, and organizational policies.
4. IT examines decision making practices by using Treatment planning practices vary widely across or-
simple empirical measures. Considering the richness of ganizations and across programs or units within an or-
findings from IT studies, it is surprising how easily the ganization. However, planning is directly or indirectly
concept of image compatibility is assessed. For instance, influenced by almost every aspect of the healthcare
DuneganÕs research [65] utilizes single Likert-type scales system: There are factors unique to individual patients,
with questions such as, ‘‘How close is the current image such as their distinctive problems and goals. The way
to the target image?’’ and, ‘‘In terms of the ultimate that these issues are addressed depends on the patientÕs
objective, how well is the project doing?’’ The advantage diagnosis and specific symptoms, their resources, atti-
of simple measures with high face validity is evident, tudes toward treatment, and their support systems.
particularly in applied research, where complex psy- Treatment goals and strategies also are affected by the
chometric instruments may be resisted and results ig- abilities and interests of clinicians and clinical staff, by
nored. the availability of programs, and by unit- and organi-
zational-level culture, habit, camaraderie, and morale.
Programmatic factors are influenced by caseloads and
5. An application of Image Theory: treatment planning as level of care assignments, which are affected in turn by
a multi-level and longitudinal process funding levels, administrative directives and initiatives,
accreditation standards, and ultimately, agency and in-
As noted previously, IT exists both as an organiza- stitutional policies. Some programs and agencies regard
tional theory and a theory of individual decision treatment planning as a deliberative process that is tai-
making. The organizational and corresponding cogni- lored to the needs of individual patients. The burden of
tive images appear in Table 3. The two sets of images decision making may be carried instead by algorithms
are isomorphic, which enables an exploration of multi- and critical pathways, making treatment planning rou-
level relationships and cross-level interactions. How- tine and almost superfluous. Nonetheless, the interplay
ever, the organizational form of IT has yet to be tested of clinical, social support, organizational, fiscal, ad-
extensively, but studies to date [81] suggest that IT has ministrative, and regulatory forces is evident even when
potential as a multi-level theory. The value of a multi- discretion is highly circumscribed.
level naturalistic theory is apparent when clinical and Despite wide ranging differences in organizational
administrative practices are joined or juxtaposed. For vision and culture, the basic structure of a treatment
instance, the adoption of an EBP requires organiza- plan is remarkably similar across agencies and
tional initiative along with individual implementation. programs. Generally, there is a problem list and perhaps
Even when they work in harmony, these two levels a companion list of goals. Specific interventions or

Table 3
The organizational images of IT
Organizational Description Related Cognitive Guiding Question
Image Image
Vision Goal agenda and timelines Trajectory Where are we going and what are we trying
to become?
Strategy Blueprint for accomplishing the goals that Strategic How are we striving to achieve the goals
comprise the vision that constitute our vision?
Culture Collective beliefs and values shared by members Value Who are we and what do we stand for?
of an organization
94 P.R. Falzer / Journal of Biomedical Informatics 37 (2004) 86–98

treatments are invoked to address the problems and ticular treatments. Compliance with standards, regula-
achieve the goals over a specified period. A plan also tions, and initiatives can be assessed, and the role of
may include elements of a diagnostic assessment, such as various organizational factors on treatment and effec-
a formulation and clinical summary, and contingencies tiveness can be gauged as well. These capabilities dem-
in the event of emergency or non-responsiveness. To onstrate that IT can work with a combination of
utilize the language of IT: Treatment plans specify the decision making processes, including decisions made by
trajectory and strategic images. They may also include a single clinician, micro-organizational decisions of a
criteria for assessing progress and contingencies in the treatment team, and macro-organizational decisions of
anticipation of image incompatibility. an administrative or oversight body.
Consider the following extract from a plan that may This treatment planning example also illustrates the
have been formulated in a public mental health setting potential of IT in longitudinal tracking, which is partic-
for treating a person with schizophrenia: This patient is ularly important for work with chronic conditions such
experiencing auditory hallucinations, and the treatment as schizophrenia. If treatment plans are created carefully
goal is to reduce their intensity and frequency. The and updated regularly, they will comprise a record of
planÕs problem and goal comprise the trajectory image. progress in alleviating problems and achieving goals.
The intervention is medication therapy with haloperidol This record can form a narrative that sheds light on the
PO 10 mg bid, daily medication delivery and monitoring long-term effects of treatment. The task of creating such
by the treatment team, and a follow-up appointment in a record is facilitated by decision-support tools. In par-
30 days. This intervention, which comprises the strategic ticular, logical data modeling techniques describe the
image, was chosen from a list of alternatives, which in- treatment planning process in a manner that reflects the
clude other traditional neuroleptics and atypicals, and ways that decision-makers are using information [82].
other supportive and psychosocial interventions. Some Data modeling and IT are natural companions.
candidates on this list were screened out immediately—
for instance, treatment with chlorpromazine or thiorid-
azine—and the psychiatrist made a choice from the items 6. Discussion: narrowing the gap between principle and
that remained. practice
The plan is scheduled for a progress assessment after
30 days. At that time, the psychiatrist evaluates the This paper began by suggesting that EBP initiatives
patientÕs condition and decides whether to continue or have been daunted by a disparity between principle and
modify the current therapy. This evaluation compares practice. It has been contended that a reliance on CDT
the patientÕs current condition to the goal of treatment. and the pursuit of optimality have upset the balance
Incompatibilities may be found in the course of assess- between the application of best evidence and the pro-
ing progress. For instance, the patient may be showing vision of patient-centered care. Though some critics may
extra-pyramidal side effects or lethargy, or report that insist that these are polarities of medical practice and
hallucinations have not diminished. These incompati- inherently at odds, others are searching for a synthesis,
bilities may lead to the consideration of alternatives—for of medical practice informed by a combination of clin-
instance, a different medication, a modification of the ical expertise and empirical data. Even the staunchest
current regimen, or the addition of another treatment advocates of EBM acknowledge that the vicissitudes of
such as an anticholinergic agent. medical practice require normative standards to be re-
At the individual patient level, treatment planning is laxed. CDT has demonstrated the ability to be flexible
a straightforward application of IT, with trajectories, [83]; along with the momentum that results from a
strategies, and progress assessments. The IT conception myriad of studies and a wealth of accumulated knowl-
applies, no matter how individualized and complex is edge, this flexibility has allowed CDT-based approaches
the plan, or how standardized and routine. While to thrive, despite their limitations.
treatment planning decisions may be scrutinized against Yet another reason for the continued popularity of
a variety of normative standards, IT does not prescribe CDT is the presumption that medicine and CDT share
an optimal resolution. In one given instance, a pattern common values. The final section of this paper discusses
of violations might lead to a change in strategy; the same how NDM, and IT specifically, can enable researchers,
incompatibilities in another situation might precipitate a practitioners, educators, and others to address the role
change in the treatment goal. that values play in medicine and medical decision
As IT describes individual progress, it also enables making. It is suggested that in the realm of values, or
the effects of fiscal, programmatic, administrative, and what IT refers to as the value image, EBM meets patient-
policy decisions to be evaluated by combining progress centered practice.
assessments across units, programs, and service lines. It The claim still resonates that science should be ‘‘value
is through these assessments that determinations are free.’’ Without delving into the intent of this statement
made about the clinical- and cost-effectiveness of par- when it was first uttered by Max Weber, there is a
P.R. Falzer / Journal of Biomedical Informatics 37 (2004) 86–98 95

distinction to be drawn between basic science and the There is another value-based initiative whose promi-
applied science of medicine. Patel and associates [49] nence has coincided with the rising interest in EBM.
express concern that equating the two has carried for- Over the past decade, we have witnessed a growing ur-
ward the mistaken belief that medical practice is indif- gency for scientists to demonstrate the practical benefits
ferent to human values (pp. 58–59). In the nineteenth of their work. In the telling words of Congressman
century, the physiologist Claude Bernard spoke of his George Brown: ‘‘All the basic science funding in the
discipline as ‘‘the difference between a well-functioning world will have no positive effect on the well-being of
heart and a mal-functioning one.’’ As Toulmin [84] our nation if the research is not carried out within a
observes, ‘‘If that was not a ÔvalueÕ difference, it is hard system that can effectively digest and apply the results’’
to say what is!’’ (p. 106). ([89], p. 131). The Carnegie Commission on Science,
It is appropriate that Patel and associates speak of Technology, and Government [90] was a guiding force
their critique of CDT as having a philosophical basis in promoting efforts to enhance the utility of scientific
([49], p. 58), because CDT is part of a distinct philo- knowledge. Recently, the National Advisory Mental
sophical tradition. Today, Pascal is remembered prin- Health Council issued a call to enhance the translation
cipally for his contributions to mathematics. But for of scientific findings into practice [91]. In response, the
him, rationality and optimality were not mere features National Institute of Mental Health has established new
of mathematical formulae, but metaphysical concepts. priority areas for behavioral translation research [92].
PascalÕs distrust of ordinary human senses was legend- According to Hammond, the conceptual problems of
ary, as was his disdain for empirical evidence ([85], pp. uncertainty and sub-optimality have posed major ob-
231–249). The tradition of rationalism dates back to stacles to realizing the practical benefits of scientific
Descartes, a contemporary of PascalÕs, who is princi- knowledge ([89], p. 133). It is suggested here that these
pally responsible for ushering in the modern age. problems have been exacerbated by a hands-off ap-
Toulmin, a severe critic of rationalism, depicts it as proach to values. Abstraction and universality are stip-
championing abstraction and the quest for universal ulated, but they are not made the subject of further
principles over practical understanding ([86], pp. 32–33). discussion or analysis. Fortunately, NDM has changed
The critique of optimality that Patel and associates have the landscape by regarding values as legitimate subjects
advanced resonates with ToulminÕs vehement dismissal of investigation and assessing their role empirically.
of the rationalistic tradition. In IT, the value image is one of the theoryÕs three
Universality and abstraction are not mere goals: They cognitive schema. This image comprises the collection of
are values that were ingrained into CDT by the ratio- standards, principles, and norms of practice that deter-
nalism of Descartes and his vision of indubitable truth. mine why decisions are made. IT enables values to enter
In the 21st century, the injunction that science be value into decision making as either screening and choice
free is a call to adhere to these principles, so that uni- criteria [81,93]. The importance of this capability ought
versality, optimality, and rationality are not contami- not be overlooked. For instance, in the treatment
nated by mere impression or subjective belief ([86], pp. planning illustration in the previous section, the goal of
31–34). When Ioannidis and Law [87] claim that EBP is treatment was a reduction of auditory hallucinations.
an effort to supplant traditional ‘‘experienced-based’’ The question that must be asked is, whose goal is this?
medicine with a medical practice that is derived from The patient may be taking an anti-psychotic medication
sound empirical evidence, they are speaking on behalf of because it helps him to go to work, not to reduce hal-
a tradition that began over three centuries ago. This lucinations. One might suppose that the two goals are
tradition is sustained not only by the progress that has compatible, but in practice, patients and physicians are
occurred in the interim, but also by the values that have frequently choosing between a medication that is less
predicated this tradition from the outset. effective in relieving symptoms, but interferes less with
Clinicians who work with schizophrenia are re- the ability to concentrate. A non-EBP may be preferred
sponding to a pervasive disorder of thought and cog- when values such as engaging the patient, promoting
nition, but they are also treating something that vitiates independent living, improving social functioning, or
functioning and creates a miserable life. An assessment increasing self esteem outweigh the value of symptom
of values is built into the current nomenclature of reduction. Determining which course of action is most
mental disorders [88], and a diagnosis of schizophrenia appropriate becomes a matter of expert judgment, pro-
requires a disturbance in psychosocial functioning as gram priority, and administrative policy. Values clearly
well as evidence of symptoms and course. Trained cli- play a role in these decisions, but not the values of op-
nicians recognize schizophrenia as both a disorder, in timality and universality. Evidence plays a role as well,
the narrowest sense, and a patently bad state; they gauge but what is most relevant to medical decision making is
the effectiveness of treatments by how substantially how the evidence is applied.
symptoms are diminished, and no less important, by the CDT-based approaches can make allowances, but
improvement in their patientsÕ lives. ultimately they are striving for an optimal solution. For
96 P.R. Falzer / Journal of Biomedical Informatics 37 (2004) 86–98

NDM, values are ingrained in clinical decisions, but [19] Lipshitz R, Klein G, Orasanu J, Salas E. Taking stock of naturalistic
they can be explicated. Perhaps a crucial step in facili- decision making. J Behav Decis Making 2001;14(5):331–52.
[20] Hammond KR. Coherence and correspondence theories in
tating the implementation of EBPs is an acknowledge- judgment and decision making. In: Connolly T, Arkes HR,
ment that values are too important to be left outside the Hammond KR, editors. Judgment and decision making: an
domain of theory. Surely, we can acknowledge that as interdisciplinary reader. 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-
physicians learn their craft, they learn the values of the sity Press; 2000. p. 53–65.
traditions in which they operate, and eventually they [21] Brunswik E. Systematic and representative design of psychological
experiments, with results in physical and social perception.
will incorporate these values into their practice. It is Berkeley, CA: University of California Press; 1947.
through the development of expertise that values be- [22] Gigerenzer G, Hoffrage U, Kleinbolting H. Probabilistic mental
come practical, and without the ability to study how models: a Brunswikian theory of confidence. Psychol Rev
values affect practice, the gap between knowledge and 1991;98(4):506–28.
implementation will not be abated. [23] Tversky A, Kahneman D. Judgment under uncertainty: heuristics
and biases. In: Connolly T, Arkes HR, Hammond KR, editors.
Judgment and decision making: an interdisciplinary reader. New
York: Cambridge University Press; 2000. p. 38–55.
[24] Peterson CR, Beach LR. Man as an intuitive statistician. Psychol
References Bull 1967;68(1):29–46.
[25] Hoffman PJ. The paramorphic representation of clinical judg-
[1] Sackett DL, Rosenberg WMC, Gray JAM, Haynes RB, Rich- ment. Psychol Bull 1960;57:116–31.
ardson WS. Evidence based medicine: what it is and what it isnÕt. [26] Dawes RM. Proper and improper linear models. In: Connolly T,
Br Med J 1996;312(7023):71–2. Arkes HR, Hammond KR, editors. Judgment and decision
[2] Elstein AS. Naturalistic decision making and clinical judgment. J making: an interdisciplinary reader. 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cam-
Behav Decis Making 2001;14(5):363–5. bridge University Press; 2000. p. 378–94.
[3] Garb HN. Studying the clinician: judgment research and psycho- [27] Round A. Introduction to clinical reasoning. J Eval Clin Pract
logical assessment. Washington, DC: American Psychological 2001;7(2):109–17.
Association; 1998. [28] Connolly T, Beach LR. The theory of Image Theory: an
[4] Carey S, Hall DJ. PsychiatristsÕ views of evidence-based psychi- examination of the central conceptual structure. In: Beach LR,
atric practice. Psychiatr Bull 1999;23(3):159–61. editor. Image Theory: theoretical and empirical foundations.
[5] Buchanan RW, Kreyenbuhl J, Zito JM, Lehman A. The schizo- Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum; 1998. p. 249–59.
phrenia PORT pharmacological treatment recommendations: [29] Meehl PE. Clinical versus statistical predictions: a theoretical
conformance and implications for symptoms and functional analysis and revision of the literature. Minneapolis MN: Univer-
outcome. Schizophr Bull 2002;28(1):63–74. sity of Minnesota Press; 1954.
[6] Marinelli-Casey P, Domier CP, Rawson RA. The gap between [30] Goldberg LR, Faust D, Kleinmuntz B, Dawes RM. Clinical
research and practice in substance abuse treatment. Psychiatr Serv versus statistical prediction. In: Cicchetti D, Grove WM, editors.
2002;53(8):984–7. Thinking clearly about psychology: essays in honor of Paul E
[7] Sernyak MJ, Dausey D, Desai R, Rosenheck R. PrescribersÕ Meehl. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press; 1991. p.
nonadherence to treatment guidelines for schizophrenia when 173–264.
prescribing neuroleptics. Psychiatr Serv 2003;54(2):246–8. [31] Kleinmuntz B. Why we still use our heads instead of formulas:
[8] Williams DDR, Garner J. The case against Ôthe evidenceÕ: a toward an integrative approach. Psychol Bull 1990;107(3):296–
different perspective on evidence-based medicine. Br J Psychiat 310.
2002;180(1):8–12. [32] Peterson CR, Ulehla ZJ, Miller AJ, Bourne Jr LE, Stilson DW.
[9] Edwards W. The theory of decision making. Psychol Bull Internal consistency of subjective probabilities. J Exp Psychol
1954;51:380–417. 1965;70(5):526–33.
[10] von Neumann J, Morgenstern O. Theory of games and economic [33] Goldberg LR. Simple models or simple processes? Some research
behavior. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press; 1947. on clinical judgments. In: Arkes HR, Hammond KR, editors.
[11] Slovic P, Fischhoff B, Lichtenstein S. Behavioral decision theory. Judgment and decision making: an interdisciplinary reader 1986.
Annu Rev Psychol 1977;28:1–39. p. 335–53.
[12] Keeney RL, Raiffa H. Decisions with multiple objectives: prefer- [34] Kahneman D, Tversky A. Subjective probability: a judgment of
ences and value tradeoffs. New York: Wiley; 1976. representativeness. Cogn Psychol 1972;3(3):430–54.
[13] Monahan J, Heilbrum K, Silver E, Nabors E, Bone J, Slovic P. [35] Tversky A, Kahneman D. Belief in the law of small numbers.
Communicating violence risk: frequency formats, vivid outcomes, Psychol Bull 1971;76(2):105–10.
and forensic settings. Int J Forensic Ment Health 2002;1(2):121–6. [36] Kahneman D, Tversky A. On the reality of cognitive illusions.
[14] Bogardus Jr ST, Holmboe E, Jekel JF. Perils, pitfalls, and Psychol Rev 1996;103(3):582–91.
possibilities in talking about medical risk. JAMA 1999;281(11): [37] Tversky A, Kahneman D. The framing of decisions and the
1037–41. psychology of choice. Science 1981;211(4481):453–8.
[15] Fischhoff B, Goitein B. The informal use of formal models. Acad [38] McNeil BJ, Pauker SG, Tversky A. On the framing of
Manage Rev 1984;9(3):512–5. medical decisions. In: Bell DE, Raiffa H, Tversky A, editors.
[16] Beach LR, Lipshitz R. Why classical decision theory is an Decision making: descriptive, normative, and prescriptive inter-
inappropriate standard for evaluating and aiding most human actions. New York: Cambridge University Press; 1988. p.
decision making. In: Beach Klein GA, Lipshitz Orasanu J, 562–8.
Calderwood R, Zsambok CE, editors. Decision making in action: [39] Cebul RD, Beck LH, editors. Teaching clinical decision making.
models and methods. Norwood, NJ: Ablex; 1993. New York: Praeger; 1985.
[17] Simon HA. A behavioral model of rational choice. Q J Econ [40] Bensing J. Bridging the gap. The separate worlds of evidence-
1955;69:99–118. based medicine and patient-centered medicine. Patient Educ
[18] Simon HA. Models of man. New York: Wiley; 1957. Couns 2000;39(1):17–25.
P.R. Falzer / Journal of Biomedical Informatics 37 (2004) 86–98 97

[41] Larkin J, McDermott J, Simon DP, Simon HA. Expert and novice [62] Beach LR. Image Theory: decision making in personal and
performance in solving physics problems. Science 1980;208:1335– organizational contexts. New York: Wiley; 1990.
42. [63] Beach LR. The psychology of decision making: people in
[42] Patel VL, Cranton PA. Transfer of student learning in medical organizations. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage; 1997.
education. J Med Educ 1983;58(2):126–35. [64] Beach LR, Mitchell TR. The basics of Image Theory. In: Beach
[43] Patel VL, Groen GJ. Knowledge based solution strategies in LR, editor. Image Theory: theoretical and empirical foundations.
medical reasoning. Cogn Sci 1986;10(1):91–116. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum; 1998. p. 3–18.
[44] Groen GJ, Patel VL. The relationship between comprehension [65] Dunegan KJ. Image Theory: testing the role of image compati-
and reasoning in medical expertise. In: Chi MT, Glaser R, Farr bility in progress decisions. Organ Behav Human Decis Process
MJ, editors. The nature of expertise. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence 1995;62(1):79–86.
Erlbaum Associates; 1988. p. 287–310. [66] Beach LR, Smith B, Lundell J, Mitchell TR. Image Theory:
[45] Patel VL, Arocha JF, Kaufman DR. Diagnostic reasoning and descriptive sufficiency of a simple rule for the compatibility test. J
medical expertise. In: Medin DL, editor. The psychology of Behav Decis Making 1988;1(1):17–28.
learning and motivation: advances in research and theory. New [67] Beach LR, Strom E. A toadstool among the mushrooms:
York: Academic Press; 1994. p. 187–250. screening decisions and Image TheoryÕs compatibility test. Acta
[46] Patel VL, Kaufman DR. Medical informatics and the science of Psychol 1989;72(1):1–12.
cognition. J Am Med Inform Assoc 1998;5(6):493–502. [68] Patel VL, Groen GJ, Arocha JF. Medical expertise as a function
[47] Patel VL, Cytryn KN, Shortliffe EH, Safran C. The collaborative of task difficulty. Mem Cogn 1990;18(4):394–406.
health care team: the role of individual and group expertise. Teach [69] Beach LR, Puto CP, Heckler SE, Naylor G, Marble TA.
Learn Med 2000;12(3):117–32. Differential versus unit weighting of violations, framing, and the
[48] Patel VL, Arocha JF, Kaufman DR. A primer on aspects of role of probability in Image TheoryÕs compatibility test. Organ
cognition for medical informatics. J Am Med Inform Assoc Behav Human Decis Process 1996;65(2):77–82.
2001;8(4):324–43. [70] Ordonez LD, Benson III L, Beach LR. Testing the compatibility
[49] Patel VL, Kaufman DR, Arocha JF. Emerging paradigms of test: how instructions, accountability, and anticipated regret affect
cognition in medical decision-making. J Biomed Inform prechoice screening of options. Organ Behav Hum Decis Process
2002;35(1):52–75. 1999;78(1):63–80.
[50] Kaufman DR, Kushnirukb AW, Yalec J-F, Patel VL. Conceptual [71] Beach LR, Mitchell TR. A contingency model for the selection of
knowledge and decision strategies in relation to hypercholester- decision strategies. In: Beach LR, editor. Image Theory: theoret-
olemia and coronary heart disease. Int J Med Inf 1999;55(3):159– ical and empirical foundations. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum;
77. 1998. p. 145–58.
[51] Miller GA, Galanter E, Pribram KH. Plans and the structure of [72] Van Zee EH, Paluchowski TF, Beach LR. The effects of screening
behavior. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston; 1960. and task partitioning upon evaluations of decision options. J
[52] Svenson O. Some propositions for the classification of decision Behav Decis Making 1992;5(1):1–19.
situations. In: Borcherding K, Larichev OI, Messick DM, editors. [73] Dunegan KJ. Image compatibility and framing. In: Beach LR,
Contemporary issues in decision making. New York: North- editor. Decision making in the workplace: a unified perspective.
Holland; 1990. p. 17–32. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum; 1996. p. 181–95.
[53] Ashby WR. An introduction to cybernetics. London: Metheun; [74] McNeil BJ, Pauker SG, Sox Jr HC, Tversky A. On the elicitation
1964. of preferences for alternative therapies. In: Connolly T, Arkes
[54] Kushniruk AW, Patel VL. Cognitive evaluation of decision HR, Hammond KR, editors. Judgment and decision making: an
making processes and assessment of information technology in interdisciplinary reader. 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-
medicine. Int J Med Inf 1998;51(2–3):83–90. sity Press; 2000. p. 272–80.
[55] Patel VL, Evans DA, Kaufman DR. A cognitive framework for [75] Beach LR. EditorÕs introduction to part two—the compatibility
doctor-patient interaction. In: Evans DA, Patel VL, editors. test: screening and progress decisions. In: Beach LR, editor. Image
Cognitive science in medicine: biomedical modeling. Cambridge, Theory: theoretical and empirical foundations. Mahwah, NJ:
MA: MIT Press; 1989. p. 257–312. Lawrence Erlbaum; 1998. p. 21–30.
[56] Bordley RF. Naturalistic decision making and prescriptive deci- [76] Breier A, Berg PH. The psychosis of schizophrenia: prevalence,
sion theory. J Behav Decis Making 2001;14(5):355–7. response to atypical antipsychotics, and prediction of outcome.
[57] Lehman AF, Steinwachs DM, Dixon LB, Goldman HH, Biol Psychiat 1999;46(3):361–4.
Osher F, Postrado L, et al. Translating research into [77] Harvey PD, Meltzer H, Simpson GM, Potkin SG, Loebel A, Siu
practice: the schizophrenia patient outcomes research team C, et al. Improvement in cognitive function following a switch to
(PORT) treatment recommendations. Schizophr Bull 1998; ziprasidone from conventional antipsychotics, olanzapine, or
24(1):1–10. risperidone in outpatients with schizophrenia. Schizophr Res
[58] Lehman AF, Steinwachs DM, Dixon LB, Postrado L, Scott JE, 2004;66(2–3):101–13.
Fahey M, et al. Patterns of usual care for schizophrenia: [78] Hamilton SH, Revicki DA, Genduso LA, Beasley Jr CM.
initial results from the schizophrenia patient outcomes Olanzapine versus placebo and haloperidol: quality of life and
research team (PORT) client survey. Schizophr Bull 1998; efficacy results of the North American double-blind trial. Neuro-
24(1):11–20. psychopharmacology 1998;18(1):41–9.
[59] Elstein AS. Cognitive processes in clinical inference and decision [79] Emsley RA. Risperidone in the treatment of first-episode psy-
making. In: Turk DC, Salovey P, editors. Reasoning, inference, chotic patients: a double-blind multicenter study. Risperidone
and judgment in clinical psychology. New York: The Free Press; Working Group. Schizophr Bull 1999;25(4):721–9.
1988. p. 17–50. [80] Ubell E. It quiets the torment. Parade 1992 22 August.
[60] Corrigan PW, Steiner L, McCracken SG, Blaser B, Barr M. [81] Weatherly KA, Beach LR. Organizational culture and decision
Strategies for disseminating evidence-based practices to staff who making. In: Beach LR, editor. Decision making in the workplace:
treat people with serious mental illness. Psychiatr Serv a unified perspective. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum; 1996. p.
2001;52:1598–606. 117–32.
[61] Rosenheck RA. Organizational process: a missing link between [82] Fleming CC, von Halle B. Handbook of relational database
research and practice. Psychiatr Serv 2001;52(12):1597–607. design. Menlo Park, CA: Addison-Wesley; 1989.
98 P.R. Falzer / Journal of Biomedical Informatics 37 (2004) 86–98

[83] Klayman J. Ambivalence in (not about) naturalistic decision making: an interdisciplinary reader. 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cam-
making. J Behav Decis Making 2001;14(5):372–3. bridge University Press; 2000. p. 131–43.
[84] Toulmin SE. Return to reason. Cambridge, MA: Harvard [90] Carnegie Commission on Science, Technology, and Government.
University Press; 2001. Science, Technology, and Congress: Expert Advice and the
[85] Jonsen AR, Toulmin S. The abuse of casuistry: a history of moral Decision-Making Process. [Text document] 1991 [Retrieved Dec.
reasoning. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press; 1988. 31 2003 Feb.]. Available from: http://www.carnegie.org/sub/pubs/
[86] Toulmin SE. Cosmopolis: the hidden agenda of modernity. science_tech/cong-exp.txt.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press; 1990. [91] National Advisory Mental Health CouncilÕs Clinical Treatment
[87] Ioannidis JPA, Lau J. Evidence-based medicine: a quantitative and Services Research Workgroup. Bridging Science and Service.
approach to decision making. In: Chapman GB, Sonnenberg FA, [World Wide Web document] 2002 [Retrieved 2002 August 16].
editors. Decision making in health care. New York: Cambridge Available from: http://www.nimh.nih.gov/research/bridge.htm.
University Press; 2000. p. 110–41. [92] National Advisory Mental Health Council Behavioral Science
[88] American Psychiatric Association. Diagnostic and statistical Workgroup. Translating Behavioral Science into Action. [Adobe
manual of mental disorders: DSM-IV-TR (4th edition, text Acrobat document] 2002 [Retrieved 2002 August 16]. Available
revision 2000). Washington DC: American Psychiatric Associa- from: http://www.nimh.nih.gov/council/bswreport.pdf.
tion; 2000. [93] Nelson KA, Puto CP. Using Image Theory to examine value-
[89] Hammond KR, Harvey Jr LO, Hastie R. Making better use of laden decisions: the case of the socially responsible consumer. In:
scientific knowledge: separating truth from justice. In: Connolly T, Beach LR, editor. Image Theory: theoretical and empirical
Arkes HR, Hammond KR, editors. Judgment and decision foundations. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum; 1998. p. 199–210.

S-ar putea să vă placă și