Sunteți pe pagina 1din 9

JOURNAL OF RITUAL STUDIES 23 (2) 2009 69

Catherine Bell and Her Davidsonian Critics


Curtis Hutt
University of the Holy Land/Center for the Study of Early Christianity Jerusalem

Abstract
In recent years, Catherine Bell's work on ritual has been challenged by scholars influenced by Donald David-
son. In this paper, I review some pertinent criticisms of Bell's practice-theory. While agreeing with Bell's
Davidsonian critics on several points, I argue that a modified version of her practice theory can and should
be defended.

Introduction room for pragmatic, post-representationalist verification


of ascription through theorized inquiry.
Catherine Bell, in a number of important and thought
provoking publications, advanced a critique of a tradition
long prevalent in religious, cultural, and specifically rit-
ual studies which gives prominence to thought over ac-
Bell's Project
tion, ideas over the material—artifacts, practices, and the Bell famously questioned in Ritual Theory, Ritual Prac-
body (Bell 1992; 1997; 1998; 2002). Her work leads read- tice and other texts the cultural method of an "earlier
ers to be suspicious regarding the ascription of proposi- generation" of scholars who optimistically viewed ritual
tional attitudes, about how the language of thought de- as an almost ideal portal through which the thinking the-
scribes "itself" using the terminology of meanings, beliefs, orist could access other cultures whether in the present
and intentions. These misgivings and a "practice qua prac- or the past. While participants in rituals were popularly
tice" approach has prompted much debate (e.g. Godlove characterized as engaging in thoughtless activity, spe-
2002; Schilbrack 2004; Hutt 2007). In my short paper, I cialist observers were felt to possess the ability to discern
shall argue in agreement with Bell that there are good rea- religious and cultural meanings or rationales structur-
sons to be distrustful of ascriptions of propositional atti- ing ritual behavior. Ritual was conceived of as a mech-
tudes— of appeals to the "intentional." I am unwilling, anism whereby problems generated from contradictions
however, to rule out the usefulness of such ascription and oppositions in culture are resolved. Bell presents a
strategies in explaining human behavior. After reviewing quite radical, alternative view to what she recently re-
Bell's project and the response of some detractors influ- ferred to as the "old jalopy" of the cultural method (Bell
enced by Donald Davidson (including myself), I will for- 2006, 315). Not only are practices, typically devalued in
ward a proposal for a more restrained anti-intentionalism. examinations of the union between thought and action
This program is quite similar to one that I have advanced in ritual, elevated to a position of interpretive priority.
before in opposition to certain aspects of the use of Max But crucially, Bell collapses—like many contemporary
Weber's verstehende Soziologie and puts a stress, following scholars, including some famous pragmatists and post-
W.V. Quine, on the reliability of different types of evi- modernists—the classical divide between thought and
dence within a holistic and self-supporting "web of be- action (as well as mind and body / idea and material) it-
liefs" (Hutt 2007; 1999). While it may discourage those self. Bell argued that her approach, unlike others, does
seeking to ground what is "true" in correspondence to the not fall victim to any "myth of fundamental contradic-
"real" or others who atomistically isolate the connotations tion" (Bell 1992, 35). She censured most who have come
of actions and expressions made by agents, it does leave before her in the study of ritual (e.g., Geertz, Gluckman,
70 JOURNAL OF RITUAL STUDIES 23 (2) 2009

Turner, Bateson, Lévi-Strauss, Hegelians, Marxists, and sis of ritual "presupposes a corpse" (D.H. Lawrence), also
even Bourdieu) for not having been sufficiently reflec- treated ritual as an arena where social conflicts are
tive and unknowingly supplying themselves through the worked out. They too maintained the distinction that
imposition of their own selections and biases with man- Bell criticizes between the "thinking" researcher and the
ufactured objects of study. Bell wrote: "The theoretical "acting" object of research. The performance theorist
construction of ritual becomes a reflection of the theo- simply makes herself a member of the audience, no
rist's method and the motor of a discourse in which the longer reliant upon the recorded and stale (Bell 1992,
concerns of the theorist take center stage" (Bell 1992, 36). Gregory Bateson and Claude Lévi-Strauss similarly
54). Theoretical discourse about ritual, according to Bell asserted that the resolution of conflict in ritual, ulti-
who cites Frederic Jameson (though one imagines she mately between culture and nature, is less functional and
could be borrowing from Hayden White or even Richard more symbolic. Hegelian and Marxist notions of con-
Rorty), is a result of an "organizational fiction" (Bell tradiction play heavily in this type of sociological theo-
1992, 8). rizing, also finding a fundamental contradiction—his-
Bell highlights the deserved centrality of ritual for tra- torical change versus culture — at the roots of social
ditional scholars of religious studies, at the same time as experience.
censuring those like Clifford Geertz—a figure who she According to Bell, Pierre Bourdieu—at least in Out-
places at the end of a long line of cultural theorists be- line of a Theory of Practice—made a mistake comparable
ginning with W. Robertson Smith (Bell 1992, 14)—who to that made by Lévi-Strauss. "Fundamental oppositions"
mistakenly distort our understanding of such activity. were utilized in the "internal organization of taxonomic
Geertz, for example, views ritual activity as a prominent schemes" that generate a sense of coherent cultural unity
"window" through which "meaningfiilness" for actors be- (Bourdieu 1977, 114-24). 2 Of course, these are not fun-
comes visible (Bell 1992, 25-9). The problem with his damental in any Platonic sense—absolute, metaphysical,
work, however, is not his focus upon ritual but the way ontological, or logical values. For Bourdieu, these oppo-
in which he constitutes what Bell refers to as the "raw sitions were useful tools for use with taxonomic schemes
data" of ritual as an object of interpretation. Such tradi- only. Ritual causes a disruption in the taxonomic order
tional ritual theory, Bell asserts, imposes "a powerful limit imposing a reordering of "culture." Ritual works out the
on our theoretical flexibility, our divisions of human ex- opposition between conflicting social orders — na-
perience, and our ability to perceive the logical relations ture/culture, old order/new order. Bell thought that even
inscribed within these divisions" (Bell 1992, 17). Ac- this delimited use of fundamental oppositions or what
cording to Bell, Geertz—like many others before him— others might refer to as "ideal types" is suspect. She wrote:
thinks studying ritual is key because it is a place where "The notion that ritual resolves a fundamental social con-
fundamental dichotomies can be investigated. This is es- tradiction can be seen as a type of myth legitimating the
pecially clear when Geertz makes evident the predomi- whole apparatus of ritual studies Equally mythical,
nance of religious ideas in the organization of society. In perhaps, is the notion that there is anything fundamen-
doing so, he posited a basic distinction between "world- tal." Her position is closer to Michel Foucault's whom she
view" (comprehensive ideal view—real order, cognitive, quotes: "There are only reciprocal relations, and the per-
existential) and "ethos" (dispositions, moods or motiva- petual gaps between intentions in relation to one another"
tions—moral, aesthetic, religious) with beliefs being sub- (Bell 1992, 34).
sumed under the former and ritual under the latter. In Bell in Ritual Theory Ritual Practice likewise praised
ritual activity, conceptions of order and dispositions for Stanley Tambiah who reworks J.L. Austin and John Searle
participants are "fused." They are then "homologized" describing the social conditions under which ritual is seen
with the theorist's project. Bell notes that for Geertz rit- as social communicative action. Tambiah's work is note-
uals are not only the point of fusion of worldview and worthy because whereas Geertz, Turner, and others found
ethos for the insider or believer, but are considered to be ritual to be highly symbolic and full of metaphorical
the best locus for the "detached observer" to view the in- meaning, Tambiah doubts this, rejecting "intentionality"
teraction (Bell 1992, 27-8). Finally, priority is then given theories in anthropology. Bell expands on Tambiah's anti-
by Geertz—if we are to believe Bell1—to the accounts of intentionality, deploying Jameson again — this time
these special observers or theorists who "think" while the against Geertz. The proclivity of social scientists to "tex-
perspectives of insiders who simply "act" are devalued. tualize" objects of study is a mistake. Rites are not texts
Bell argued that Geertz was not alone in making such though they are often treated as such because it is held
mistakes. Performance theorists like Max Gluckman and that their meanings can be "deciphered, decoded, or in-
Victor Turner, who rightly complained that most analy- terpreted" (Bell 1992, 44-5). An alternative to not only
JOURNAL OF RITUAL STUDIES 23 (2) 2009 71

cultural but also literary method in the study of ritual is same way that "religion" has been critiqued as an "over-
required. reaching folk category that misreads and even does vio-
Bell, citing the practice theory of Bourdieu more fa- lence to other cultures," belief is censured. Bell does not
vorably (though in my view probably inaccurately—see stop here though. By highlighting the beliefs and inner
Hutt 2007, 234, 253), refuses to conduct analyses of rit- motivations of religious practitioners, she claims that
ual as communicative at all. She writes: scholars take the focus off where it should be. Causal con-
nections more readily detectable in practices are obscured
Bourdieu.... avoids every semblance of literary or
by the prominence of the conceptual. Bell's goal was to
verbal analysis. He eschews, for example, all use of
reveal the hidden biases in the way that the language of
the terms metaphor, metonomy, and analogy in de-
belief is deployed and to link this up to a particular way
scribing the operations of ritual practice. Practice
of discussing religion itself.
qua practice, he insists, remains on the "hither side
Of particular significance for this paper, Bell in " cThe
of discourse," and that is precisely the key to how it
Chinese Believe in Spirits' " resisted and critiqued a trend
does what it does. Even those rites that are just a
in contemporary philosophy associated with Ludwig
practical mimesis of the natural process to be facil-
Wittgenstein and in more recent years Donald Davidson.
itated are not at all like metaphor or analogy sim-
In this tradition, the ability to interpret the meaning of a
ply because they are not nearly as explicit. Ritual
belief or what someone holds to be true is still considered
practice as such is always much fuzzier, avoiding
indispensable in the appraisal of human behavior. What
the distinctive change in state that occurs when
separates Davidsonian "radical interpretation" from more
things are brought to the level of explicit discourse
traditional interpretive practices, is that what counts as
(Bell 1992, 112).
meaningful and true is determined very differently. In
To her credit, Bell—like Bourdieu—developed a theory classical representationalist thought, beliefs are construed
of agency in which people are more than thinkers with to be meaningful or true because they correspond to ac-
interests pursuing rational ends. The most important tual "states of affairs." For Davidson, like Wittgenstein in
kinds of mastery are not the product of over aggrandized his Philosophical Investigations, however, the meaning and
reason, but are practices implicitly learned in social set- truth of beliefs is established inferentially relative to one's
tings through imitation and habit. Examining the use of other beliefs in specific linguistic contexts. Just as the
propositions in ritual activities, Bell finds that even where meaning of a sentence hinges upon the meanings of other
these occupy a crucial position such as in the "I do" in a sentences in its language, the accurate ascription of propo-
court of law or wedding ceremony, they "do not open a sitional attitudes like beliefs to actors—the goal of David-
discourse within the rite about what the ritual is doing" sonian "radical interpretation"—depends upon the rela-
(Bell 1992, 113). In fact, she explains in the longest foot- tion of beliefs to a greater web of generally reliable,
note of Ritual Theory Ritual Practice relying upon the connected beliefs. In " cThe Chinese Believe in Spirits',"
work of Mark Johnson and George Lakoff, that "non- Bell might have emphasized at least a couple of impor-
propositional schemata" — divided into three different tant similarities between her own work and that of David-
structural types—produce meaning without appeal to son. For instance, both Bell and Davidson made similar
propositional attitudes. These preconceptual, basic-level criticisms of earlier theories of meaning. More interest-
cognitive structures which "directly organize bodily ex- ingly, Davidson's undermining of the scheme/content du-
perience and indirectly organize conceptual categories" alism (where thought is traditionally described as being
are visible in the taxonomic systems of cultures (Bell 1992, composed of two distinct parts—a conceptual framework
113, 157-8 fn. 184). I think that a great deal depends supplied by mind and preconceptual objective content)
upon the validity of this theory of preconceptual mean- also effectively collapses the divide Bell attacks between
ing and that Bell needed to further spell out and defend thought and action. Instead, Bell takes direct aim at David-
her position in this regard. son's claim—extended by Richard Shweder—that it is
In her article, "'The Chinese Believe in Spirits': Belief impossible to make sense of a person's words without hav-
and Believing in the Study of Religion," Bell is skeptical ing extensive and accurate knowledge of their intentions
of and agitates against the language of belief. She ar- and what they believe to be true (Bell 2002, 102, 106).
gued— following Donald Lopez, J.Z. Smith, and Talal Bell likewise disagrees with Davidson's famous prin-
Asad—that the emphasis upon belief has arisen specifi- ciple of charity. Bell refuses to assume, like Davidson,
cally within Western post-Reformation Christian culture that people have mostly true beliefs about the world and
and is not portable to other contexts (Bell 2002, 101, 104; that even where people disagree they must minimally
Lopez, Jr. 1998; Smith 1998; Asad 1993, 27-54). In the share much more in common in order to be able to ree-
72 JOURNAL OF RITUAL STUDIES 23 (2) 2009

ognize their differences. According to Davidson, differ- fact that she did not shy away from writing about belief.
ence can only be linguistically articulated in a system What matters though is how inquiry into beliefs, inten-
where broad agreement is the rule rather than the ex- tions, and meanings is implemented. Bell positively main-
ception. Bell has two objections. First, Davidson's prin- tained, following the work of anthropologists like James
ciple of charity presents a danger to contemporary "post- W. Fernandez and Jack Goody, that it is possible to em-
theological" adherence to cultural relativism. The pirically test the motivations and associations of people
different, aberrant, and idiosyncratic are fundamentally engaged in ritual practices (Bell 1992, 183, 186; Fernan-
downplayed by Davidsonian radical interpreters and this dez 1965; Goody 1977). More critically, Godlove em-
is unacceptable (Bell 2002, 107-9). Second, as noted phasizes the fact that Bell refuses to ever grant priority or
above in reference to Ritual Theory Ritual Practice, Bell even relevance to beliefs motivating ritual practices for
refuses to "push analysis to the level of the sentence" (Bell methodological reasons. According to Bell, who draws
2002, 102). Any methodological approach that does so, upon a great deal of evidence not cited by Godlove, par-
such as is found in the work of Wittgenstein or David- ticipants engaged in the same ritual activity often have
son, is far too concentrated on linguistic "meaning" to be different, confused, or even no beliefs about what it is
of much use to practice theorists. that they are doing. There is thus no reason to assume
that ritual acts are transparent, effortlessly divulging sin-
gular meanings. Godlove rightly associates Bell's view of
Recent Criticisms of Bell's Practice Theory the process of "ritualization" with the work of Barbara
The response of scholars influenced by Davidson to Myerhoff. Ritualization is able to produce meaning out
Catherine Bell's article " 'The Chinese Believe in Spir- of "raw happenings" or the "movements of the body in
its' "—published in full-view of Davidsonians studying space and time" without recourse to the intentions of the
religion in Nancy Frankenberry's volume of collected es- actors involved (Godlove 2002, 18; Bell 1998, 212, 216).3
says titled Radical Interpretation in Religion—was pre- The attaining of ritual mastery by participants does not
dictable. As evidenced in the work of Terry Godlove, require any significant knowledge of the meaning of
who critiqued Bell's earlier work in the article "Saving learned behavior. Instead, as rituals are performed diverse
Belief: On the New Materialism in Religious Studies" predilections and habits become inscribed upon individ-
contained in Frankenberry's collection as well, Bell's ual bodies. Thereby, the activities of the "socialized" are
skepticism towards the ascription of propositional atti- molded by communities and their dominant preferences.
tudes and a supposedly narrow, uninclusive practice the- Godlove simply thinks that students of religion should
ory are targeted. Others, presumably following Wittgen- attend to both what he labels, also somewhat vaguely,
stein, could likewise have been expected to be critical of non-discursive and discursive meanings alike. While I
her unwillingness to restrict meaning to linguistic con- agree with Godlove on several critical points including
texts. My take is, however, somewhat different from the need to attend both to material culture and proposi-
Bell's critics like fellow Davidsonian Terry Godlove, oth- tional attitudes, I think modifying Godlove with Bell nec-
ers influenced by Davidson like Kevin Schilbrack, and essary. More attention, even priority, needs to be paid to
probably a good number of self proclaimed Wittgen- the structures underlying and producing so-called "non-
steinians. While agreeing with Bell's opponents on sev- discursive" meanings when determining why people do
eral counts, I still think that she was correct to insist the things that they do. As attested to by that ancient rule
upon giving priority to practices over meanings — of thumb, in the evaluation of human behavior, actions
whether linguistic, intended, or cultural — in the ex- count more than intentions.
planation of human behavior. Kevin Schilbrack, in his article "Ritual Metaphysics,"
Terry Godlove does praise Bell's targeting of the onesid- adds one more important criticism of Bell's work that
edness in earlier studies of ritual that value ideas and the at first glance appears to sit well with Godlove's argu-
mental over actions and materiality. Admittedly, Godlove's ment above. Bell in Ritual Theory Ritual Practice de-
objections to Bell's "materialism" are muted compared to scribed ritualization as a process of writing upon one's
his scathing critique of Donald Lopez, Jr.'s entry "Belief " body and practices schemes put in place by the ascen-
in the Mark C. Taylor volume titled Critical Terms for Re- dant social order understood inevitably—though not
ligious Studies (Lopez, Jr. 1998). Part of the reason for unproblematically—as the "true" nature of reality. This
this is Godlove's stated inability to pin down what Bell is not done via overt coercion, but instead following An-
has to say on belief. On the one hand, he notes that Bell tonio Gramsci, Bell thought that such "dominance and
claims to have "nothing against belief per se" (Godlove subordination ... exist within people's practical and un-
2002, 18). This is clearly evidenced, I would add, by the self-conscious awareness of the world" (Bell 1992, 83).
JOURNAL OF RITUAL STUDIES 23 (2) 2009 73

Ritualization is, therefore, best understood in terms of through the motions) or as mere windows through which
learned mastery and empowerment—a process detailed more significant cultural meanings are made visible. Such
by Bell in her discussion of "redemptive hegemony." practices may be utilized instead in a wide variety of ways,
Schilbrack's problem is that Bell, like Bourdieu and ap- of which primary actors are not necessarily aware. In sum-
parently Peter Berger, refused to assume that what is rit- mary, the assumptions of Bell's critics underlying theo-
ualized is a reflection of any substantive actual state of retical disagreements include:
affairs or "truth." Schilbrack quotes Bell: "Of course the
1. Misgivings forwarded regarding Bell's skepticism
redemptive hegemony of practice does not reflect real-
of the ascription of propositional attitudes.
ity more or less effectively; it creates it more or less ef-
2. Disapproval of Bell's cultural relativism.
fectively" (Bell 1992, 85). Ritualization simply begins
3. Objections to her reluctance to restrict meaning to
with the establishing of any ritual order. Subsequently,
linguistic contexts.
this order is "objectified" so that agents will not view it
as manufactured but instead as real or true. Those agents 4. Criticism of her presumably one-sided practice
engaged in ritual behavior are described as taking part theory.
in a grand misrecognition of an arbitrary world Starting with number four and working backwards,
(Schilbrack 2004, 84-5). Schilbrack finds Bell at this I agree with Schilbrack that Bell's ultimate refusal to
point to be unreasonably committed to an a priori hy- characterize the truth claims of a given culture as any-
pothesis that is implicitly Kantian. He writes: "One need thing but arbitrary or manufactured is problematic. On
not deny that ritual metaphysics are the product of the the other hand, I do think that Bell's rejection of David-
human imagination and reflect the linguistic and cul- son's principle of charity in the Frankenberry volume is
tural context from which they are projected; from the provocative. It is easy to see how some influenced by
fact that metaphysical knowledge involves imaginative Davidson might take the softening of linguistic and cul-
projection it does not follow that all understandings of tural differences to an extreme on the basis of their com-
reality are necessarily false." Bell reassures us in the mitment to the dictum: diversity only within the con-
Frankenberry volume that this is her position. Bell as- text of shared belief. Just how far though can such
serts in 'The Chinese Believe in Spirits' " that by con- charity take you? Are remaining differences less stark?
necting up belief, intentions, and meaning with the real Is the inability to communicate (Babel) overcome — or,
or the true, the "post-theological" stress upon the co- at least in principle, overcome-able? Notably, Terry
gency of a plurality of world-views is unacceptably called Godlove is not optimistic in these regards. He has em-
into question (Bell 2002, 102). Bell consistently defends phasized the need to account for an exceptional variety
a strong version of cultural relativism which of beliefs while at the same time rejecting relativism by
Schilbrack—at least in part influenced by Davidson — sidestepping the Kantian "framework model"—which
rejects. rests upon the discredited view that knowledge results
from a transaction between "organizing scheme and neu-
tral content" (Godlove 1997, 4). While agreeing with
Between Bell and Davidson Davidson that difference can only be posited within the
I have outlined the assumptions of Bell's critics that context of shared beliefs, I, like Godlove, think that dif-
underlie four main points of disagreement with her work. ferences can be substantive — stymieing not only un-
I will conclude by addressing the first and most impor- derstanding but basic recognition as well. An alterna-
tant of these—namely, Bell on the ascription of propo- tive way of construing Davidsonian charity, consistent
sitional attitudes to ritual actors. I will begin by adding a I believe with Davidson's own writing such as found in
few cursory comments about the final three. Generally, his response to Andrew Cutrofello's article on "The Tran-
in spite of agreeing with Godlove, Schilbrack, and imag- scendental Pretensions of the Principle of Charity," is
ined Davidsonian and Wittgensteinian detractors on a that it assumes the existence of only enough agreement
number of counts, I am more sympathetic to some of to enable us to make sense of our disagreements—but
Bell's main positions. I definitely think that Bell was right not necessarily any more! There is much that people
to challenge the extremely influential rhetoric of belief know that others don't, and Davidson understood that
that all too often obscures precisely what practice theo- his theory of charity must take this into account (David-
rists want to bring into relief. Ritual practices are not of son 1999, 342-3). Radical interpreters, while acknowl-
secondary importance when it comes to understanding edging that differences can only be posited within the
how humans and human culture work—whether con- context of shared beliefs, should be open to diversity
ceived of as hollow, insignificant movements (just going and the anomalous in a way that separates them from
74 JOURNAL OF RITUAL STUDIES 23 (2) 2009

earlier generations of comparativists who too often sti- that guide action, expectations, and even perception is
fled or ignored significant cultural differences. disappointing. Bell's apparent common ground with
Most startling to readers in the tradition of Wittgen- Davidsonians does leave her overall project open to rééval-
stein and Davidson are Bell's comments in " 'The Chi- uation and possible reproach. Because radical interpreters
nese Believe in Spirits' " and Ritual Theory Ritual Prac- have continued to emphasize an important foundational
tice challenging the usefulness of reducing meaning to role for belief while patently not succumbing to criticisms
the sentential and her emphasis upon the role played by Bell made of others who adopted the thought/action du-
non-propositional, preconceptual schemata in the pro- alism, Bell's strategy of downplaying linguistic in addi-
duction of meaning. Bell is certainly confusing on these tion to cultural meaning in the study of ritual as the only
two points. Acknowledging that Bell has not always ad- option to move forward in ritual studies is called into
equately distinguished between "cognitive" and "linguis- question.
tic" meaning, the focus of her work is clearly on non-
cognitive structures and non-linguistic practices Conclusion: On the Ascription of
underlying the output of "meaning." What Bell meant by
non-cognitive and non-linguistic "meaning"—which Propositional Attitudes
shows up in "bodily movements in space and time" — As noted in the opening paragraph, some years ago I
also needs to be delineated. For example, it sometimes made an attempt to outline a methodology for use by his-
looks as if Bell wished to connect the work of philoso- torians in evaluating the ascription of propositional atti-
phers of mind with Bourdieu's focus on imitation and tudes in ancient literary sources - specifically, as related
habit. For Bourdieu, however, human behavior is so- to the identity of the communities responsible for the
cially generated and is not addressed as a byproduct of scrolls found at Khirbet Qumran (Hutt 1999). While the
cognitive structures at all. For the purpose of clarity, not strategy outlined was fine-tuned to meet special require-
only should separate vocabularies for the "cognitive" and ments, its general features are applicable to a variety of
"linguistic" be adopted and adhered to, but new termi- research programs including those concerned with the
nology for non-cognitive/non-linguistic "meaning as well. near present and not the distant past. Crucial to this proj-
Finally, in defense of Bell's tactic of privileging practices ect was the assigning of weights based upon verifiability
over beliefs in the explanation of human behavior, I and the integration of different types of evidence.4 Ap-
would invoke the work of the pragmatist John Dewey for peals to intentions, while not entirely dismissed, were
whom "beliefs" were best labeled "habits of action." downgraded and ordered relative to data confirmed
Dewey, like Bell, viewed beliefs to be practices and em- through inquiry. In conclusion, I am going to not only
phasized the importance of evaluating propositional at- compare my proposal—now slightly revised in light of
titudes through theorized inquiry. Going further than learned suggestions—to that made by Catherine Bell but
Bell, Dewey—as noted by Schilbrack—recognized the also to those of her critics.
role played by non-cognitive/non-linguistic influences I will begin by stating that in spite of Bell's claim made
like "biological functions and structures" on people's in- in " 'The Chinese Believe in Spirits' " that sometimes but
teraction with the world (Schilbrack 2004, 86). Dewey by no means most of the time belief acts as instigator of
like Godlove, however, more insightfully maintained the action, she is definitely suspicious of the ascription of
pertinence of beliefs and commitments to special quests propositional attitudes (Bell 2002, 107). In this regard,
and values which Bell ignores. Religious beliefs may have there is much substantive agreement between Bell and
what Godlove calls an "interpretive priority" for believ- me. It is not merely the fact that appeals to human in-
ers—though these are always formed in local social, ma- tentions and beliefs of ancient writers are extraordinar-
terial contexts. ily difficult to evaluate. This is the case, though of course
Any reproof of practice theory, whether as forwarded to a much lesser degree, with pinning down the beliefs,
by Bell or Bourdieu, which does not begin by acknowl- intentions, and meanings of even those individuals with
edging the thesis of J.L. Austin and John Searle that all whom we are intimately familiar. Recalling Geertz' fa-
speech is first and foremost activity is not deserving of mous distinction, it is difficult to distinguish between a
serious consideration. This stated, it is clear that Bell, "twitch" and a "wink" except in familiar settings. Even
while perhaps having nothing against limited inquiries then, one might miss something if caught off guard. On
into the motivating significance of beliefs and intentions, the other hand, while epistemically speaking these as-
plainly spent the vast majority of her time looking else- criptions stand upon shaky foundations as they are not
where for the production of meaning. Bell's decision to grounded in a direct awareness or correspondence to the
pay very limited attention to the "truths" of coherence facts of the matter, they are not formed arbitrarily. We
JOURNAL OF RITUAL STUDIES 23 (2) 2009 75

do manage, sometimes more easily than others, to as- ity, ritualized practices, or other people's beliefs. Occu-
certain with relative certainty "what" people have done pying the central position in a Quinean web of beliefs,
and the motivations behind their actions. This, as where beliefs do not change piecemeal but always in con-
Wittgenstein has shown so well, depends upon seeing junction with other beliefs, are inner core commitments
what the "lever" is attached to (Wittgenstein 1968, §6). of which people are generally certain. Our trust in the
Intentions only become apparent against specific back- usefulness and reliability of empirical inquiry is one of
drops. Surmising the "truth" of someone's intentions, these commitments. As one moves out of the core to-
moreover, invariably depends upon the consistency of wards the periphery, things become more malleable. They
our own beliefs. must be consistent with the inner or an occasion for de-
There is another sort of claim to truth which, while fensive compartmentalization or, optimally, problem-
never encountered disassociated from a web of self-sup- solving inquiry arises. The less secure outer rings of be-
porting and mostly consistent beliefs, depends upon lief are, except in very unusual circumstances, obliged to
active, theorized inquiry for its special character. Re- conform to the inner and not vice versa (Quine 1978).
sults derived from the testing of hypotheses—through The ascription of propositional attitudes, and generally
the use of procedures that are public and repeatable — more traditional literary approaches to interpretation,
have (and certainly deserve) core status in our webs of should be—where possible—tested and judged relative
belief. To once again deploy the terminology and ar- to what is empirically verifiable. Where not possible, our
guments of John Dewey in defense of Bell, only beliefs understandings of specific beliefs are more tenuous and
that have been examined are worthy of the warrant "jus- subject to revision.
tified." Certainly many very influential core habits of The practice theory of Bell, Bourdieu, and others is
belief and other practices are seldom brought to light, intriguing from my perspective—influenced by Dewey,
much less questioned. To dismiss them as irrelevant all Quine, and Davidson as well! It encourages investiga-
too often renders their occasionally harmful effects — tors to give an interpretive priority to practices over as-
for example, in the reproduction of social disparities— cribed propositional attitudes in the explanation of
invisible and free to function undeterred. We might pre- human behavior. Bridging the thought/action dualism
sume that such core beliefs are generally reliable. How- and emphasizing practices first, however, should lead
ever, the inquiring mind must acknowledge that this us onto some middle ground. Practice theorists like Bell,
remains to be established. Such beliefs, as seen in the in my view, have needlessly prompted a backlash from
work of Bell above, can be sought out and tested. Es- Davidsonians and others by at least giving the appear-
pecially when they have been theorized as habits and ance that they disregard the intentions that animate so
practices! Sometimes it is only feasible to inquire into much human behavior. Meanings, beliefs, and inten-
the consistency and coherence of our beliefs, to selec- tions may be difficult to identify, but without such pos-
tively alter variables, and see if the proposed change tulated referents human behavior is often completely in-
makes better sense than what has come before it. His- explicable. Likewise, Godlove and Schilbrack's call for
torians of the ancient world are unfortunately often left an unqualified double approach focusing upon the non-
to such means, unable to plan out or implement fur- discursive and discursive also requires revision — this
ther useful investigation. time in the direction of Bell. Appeal to intentions al-
My suggestion is simple, namely, that we grant prece- ways needs to be measured against data gained by the
dence to our beliefs about the world that have accrued as most reliable means possible.
the result of inquiry—whether in regard to neural activ-

Endnotes

1. This is Bell's view of Geertz's work and not my own. I choose 3. This claim by Bell is extremely suspicious to theorists in prag-
to read Geertz as stressing the importance of native or insider per- matic and other post-representationalist traditions who maintain
spectives. As Geertz wrote, anthropologists shouldn't "study vil- that humans never have access to "raw" data or happenings.
lages" but instead "study in villages" (Geertz 1973, 22). 4. Following Dewey and Davidson, I think that differences of
2. Keep in mind that Bell criticized a part of Bourdieu's work type or kind are really nothing more than differences of degree.
that he himself questioned on numerous occasions (Hutt 2007,
246). Bourdieu moved away from such structuralist analyses in
later publications.
76 JOURNAL OF RITUAL STUDIES 23 (2) 2009

References

Asad, T. Press; reprinted, Macon: Mercer University


1993 Genealogies of Religion: Discipline and Reasons Press.
of Power in Christianity and Islam. Baltimore: 2002 "Saving Belief: On the New Materialism in Re-
Johns Hopkins University Press. ligious Studies," Radical Interpretation in Reli-
Bell, C. gion, N. Frankenberry, ed., Cambridge: Cam-
1992 Ritual Theory Ritual Practice. New bridge University Press: 10-24.
York/Oxford: Oxford: University Press. Goody, J.
1997 Ritual: Perspectives and Dimensions. New 1977 "Against 'Ritual' " Loosely Structured Thoughts
York/Oxford: Oxford University Press. on a Loosely Defined Topic," Secular Ritual, S.
1998 "Performance," Critical Terms for Religious Moore and B. Meyerhoff, eds., Amsterdam:
Studies, M. C. Taylor, ed., Chicago: Chicago Van Gorcum, 25-35.
University Press, 1998: 205-24. Hutt, C.
2002 "The Chinese Believe in Spirits': Belief and Be- 1999 "Qumran and the Ancient Sources," The Provo
lieving in the Study of Religion," Radical Inter- International Conference on the Dead Sea
pretation and Religion, N. Frankenberry, ed., Scrolls: Technological Innovations, New Texts,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: and Reformulated Issues, D. Parry and E. Ul-
100-16. rich, eds., Leiden/Boston/Köln: Brill, 274-93.
2006 "Culture: What Does One Do With It Now?" 2007 "Pierre Bourdieu on the verstehende Soziologie
Method and Theory in the Study of Religion 18: of Max Weber," Method and Theory in the
315-24. Study of Religion 19: 232-54.
2006 "Paradigms Behind (And Before) The Mod- Lopez, Jr., D. S.
ern Concept of Religion," History and Theory 1998 "Belief," Critical Terms for Religious Studies,
45: 27-46. M.C. Taylor, ed., Chicago: Chicago University
Bourdieu, P. Press: 21-35.
1977 Outline of a Theory of Practice, R. Nice, tr., Quine, W. V.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 1978 The Web of Belief, 2nd ed., New York: Ran-
Davidson, D. dom House.
1999 "Reply to Andrew Cutrofello," The Philosophy Schilbrack, K.
of Donald Davidson, L.E. Hahn, ed., Peru, 111.: 2002 "The Study of Religious Belief After Donald
Open Court Publishing Co.: 342-3. Davidson," Method and Theory in the Study of
Fernandez, J. W. Religion 14: 334-49.
1965 "Symbolic Consensus in a Fang Reformative 2004 "Ritual Metaphysics," Journal of Ritual Studies
Cult," American Anthropologist 67, 902-29. 18/1: 77-90.
Geertz, C. Smith, J. Z.
1973 "Thick Description: Toward an Interpretive 1998 "Religion, Religions, Religious," Critical Terms
Theory of Culture," The Interpretation of Cul- for Religious Studies, M.C. Taylor, ed., Chicago:
ture, New York: Basic Books. Chicago University Press: 269-84.
Godlove, Jr., T. Wittgenstein, L.
1997 Religion, Interpretation, and Diversity of Belief: 1968 Philosophical Investigations, 3rd ed., G.E.M.
The Framework Model from Kant to Durkheim to Anscombe, tr., New York: MacMillan Publish-
Davidson, Cambridge: Cambridge University ing Company.

Biographical Sketch

Curtis Hutt is presently in the Graduate Studies Fac- historian of early Christianities, he teaches courses and
ulty at the University of the Holy Land in Jerusalem. He publishes work in philosophy, the anthropology of reli-
received his Ph.D. in 2007 from Brown University in Re- gion, historiography, and comparative religious ethics.
ligion and Critical Thought. In addition to being a trained
^ s
Copyright and Use:

As an ATLAS user, you may print, download, or send articles for individual use
according to fair use as defined by U.S. and international copyright law and as
otherwise authorized under your respective ATLAS subscriber agreement.

No content may be copied or emailed to multiple sites or publicly posted without the
copyright holder(s)' express written permission. Any use, decompiling,
reproduction, or distribution of this journal in excess of fair use provisions may be a
violation of copyright law.

This journal is made available to you through the ATLAS collection with permission
from the copyright holder(s). The copyright holder for an entire issue of a journal
typically is the journal owner, who also may own the copyright in each article. However,
for certain articles, the author of the article may maintain the copyright in the article.
Please contact the copyright holder(s) to request permission to use an article or specific
work for any use not covered by the fair use provisions of the copyright laws or covered
by your respective ATLAS subscriber agreement. For information regarding the
copyright holder(s), please refer to the copyright information in the journal, if available,
or contact ATLA to request contact information for the copyright holder(s).

About ATLAS:

The ATLA Serials (ATLAS®) collection contains electronic versions of previously


published religion and theology journals reproduced with permission. The ATLAS
collection is owned and managed by the American Theological Library Association
(ATLA) and received initial funding from Lilly Endowment Inc.

The design and final form of this electronic document is the property of the American
Theological Library Association.

S-ar putea să vă placă și