Sunteți pe pagina 1din 25

Ecologocentrism: Unworking Animals

Timothy Morton

SubStance, Issue 117 (Volume 37, Number 3), 2008, pp. 73-96 (Article)

Published by University of Wisconsin Press


DOI: 10.1353/sub.0.0019

For additional information about this article


http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/sub/summary/v037/37.3.morton.html

Access Provided by Auckland University of Technology at 02/23/11 3:37AM GMT


Ecologocentrism: Unworking Animals 73

Ecologocentrism:
Unworking Animals
Timothy Morton

. . . with a glance toward those who, in a society from


which I do not exclude myself, turn their eyes away
when faced by the as yet unnamable which is
proclaiming itself and which can do so, as is necessary
whenever a birth is in the offing, only under the species
of the nonspecies, in the formless, mute, infant, and
terrifying form of monstrosity.
— Jacques Derrida, “Structure, Sign, and Play in
the Discourse of the Human Sciences” (293)
Whoever is the wisest among you is also just a conflict
and a cross between plant and ghost.
— Friedrich Nietzsche, Thus Spoke Zarathustra (6)

Ecology without Nature1


One of the things that modernity has damaged in its appropriation
of the Earth has been thinking. Unfortunately, one of the damaged ideas
is that of Nature itself. (I shall be capitalizing this word where necessary,
to highlight its metaphysical qualities.) How do we transition from seeing
what we call “Nature” as an object “over yonder”? And how do we
avoid “new and improved” versions that end up doing much the same
thing (systems theory, Spinozan pantheism, or Deleuze-and-Guattari
type worlds of interlocking machines, and so on), just in a “cooler,” more
sophisticated way? What kinds of collectivity emerge when we think
ecology without Nature? How do we coexist with nonhumans without
what Dimitris Vardoulakis and Chris Danta in their introduction to this
issue call the “social fantasies that create and sustain a collective ‘we’ in
the name of whom violence is exercised”?
By “unworking animals” I reference Jean-Luc Nancy’s idea of the
“community of unworking” derived from Maurice Blanchot’s
interpretation of the Romantic fragment poem. If we make animals truly
“political,” if we include them on “this” side of social collectivity, this
collectivity will be radically redefined. Yet “unworking animals” also

© Board of Regents, University of Wisconsin System, 2008 73


SubStance #117, Vol. 37, no. 3, 2008
74 Timothy Morton

emphasizes the deconstructive work of undoing the general category of


“the animal,” a work (or unwork?) begun by Derrida in his essay on the
occasion of his cat looking back at his naked body (“The Animal That
Therefore I Am”). For to encounter what we commonly call animals is to
be confronted with the inadequacy of the idea of an essential, central
“nature.”
The issue is upgraded, but not transcended, in the notion of
“environment,” which tries to be a “new and improved” version of the
reified substance or essence called “nature.” Until recently, the left has
failed to take ecology into account together with race, class, and gender.
Ecology should be viewed as intrinsic to these complexly intermingled
spheres rather than as outside or beside them. As Walter Benjamin writes
in the Arcades Project, when the weather becomes a topic for collective
imagination (as now), it stops being that thing over there called the
weather. It “stand[s] in the cycle of the eternally selfsame, until the
collective seizes upon [it] in politics and history emerges” (convolute K1,
5).2 Likewise, when nonhumans become politicized, they lose their place
in “the eternally selfsame,” and “the animal”—that mythical, invisible
beast—withers away. Even “the animal question” (how like “the Jewish
question”) starts to look fishy.
The problem of “the political animal” is also a symptom of the failure
of ecological thinking, and of deconstruction, to approach each other
with anything like an understanding of their shared—even mutually
constitutive—claims. Deconstruction is the secret best friend of ecology.
Deconstruction is the way in which the collective can seize upon the
environment on the micro level. Deconstruction is a rigorous thinking of
difference and deferment or “spacing,” deriving from what Derrida’s
seminal lecture “Structure, Sign, and Play” calls an awareness of “the
structurality of structure” (278–80). If there were ever a structure whose
structurality had begun to be thought, in tandem with the emergence of
cybernetics and other contextualizing phenomena (Of Grammatology 8–
10), it would be the environment. Only consider the difficulty of thinking
the climate, and of explaining the difference between weather and climate.
Climate is a structure with a specific and highly complex structurality,
which emerged through the early applications of systems theory. Derrida
was already thinking deconstruction as the birth (though whether this
organic metaphor holds is precisely at issue) of another, entirely other,
“species of the nonspecies”—of animals, in their most radical sense
(“Structure” 293). Thinking the political animal is deconstruction.3
Derrida argues that logocentrism underlies Western philosophy’s
attempt to ground meaning in an essential form. This essay holds that

SubStance #117, Vol. 37, no. 3, 2008


Ecologocentrism: Unworking Animals 75

ecologocentrism underpins most environmentalist philosophy, preventing


access to the full scope of interconnectedness. Thinking, even
environmentalist thinking, sets up “Nature” as a reified thing in the
distance, “over yonder,” under the sidewalk, on the other side where the
grass is always greener, preferably in the mountains, in the wild.
“Nature” accords with Benjamin’s proposition about the aura: it is a
function of distance. Benjamin uses an image from “Nature”—or from
the picturesque? But that is my (and his) point—to describe the aura:
We define the aura . . . as the unique phenomenon of a distance,
however close [the object] may be. If, while resting on a summer
afternoon, you follow with your eyes a mountain range on the
horizon or a branch which casts its shadow over you, you experience
the aura of those mountains, of that branch. (222–3)
Since we are not living in the mountains, distracted in them by day-to-
day tasks, we can be aesthetically captivated by them, as we can by an
auratic work of art.
When it approaches fullness, ecological thinking does not allow this
kind of distance to congeal. Thinking genuine interdependence involves
dissolving the barrier between “over here” and “over there,” and more
fundamentally, the illusory boundary between inside and outside, which
Derrida asserts is the founding metaphysical opposition (“Violence and
Metaphysics,” 151–2). This means that society can no longer be defined
as purely human. Thinking interdependence involves thinking différance:
the fact that all beings, not just symbolic ones, are related to each other
negatively and differentially, in an open system without center or edge.
Consider the image of Indra’s net, used in Buddhist scripture to describe
the interrelationship between things:
At every connection in this infinite net hangs a magnificently polished
and infinitely faceted jewel, which reflects in each of its facets all the
facets of every other jewel in the net. Since the net itself, the number
of jewels, and the facets of every jewel are infinite, the number of
reflections is infinite as well. (Mingyur 174–5)

A cursory reading of Darwin shows that life forms are no less intricately,
intimately, and infinitely interrelated.4
In this essay, we shall slide from human being to nonhuman
“animals,” discovering how these neighbors confront us with the trauma
of infinite responsibility prior to any specific code of ethics such as
“animal rights.” We shall then slide from the animal to the vegetative, as
we recognize in the “idiotic” livingness of life forms an a-rational, “a-
cephalic” core. And insofar as animals raise the specter of consciousness,
we shall be sliding to the mineral realm—to the possibility that sentience
can be embodied in silicon, for example (the question of artificial

SubStance #117, Vol. 37, no. 3, 2008


76 Timothy Morton

intelligence). In a way, this essay mimics the history of evolution, in


which it is necessary to imagine a strange “pre-living life” consisting of
RNA replicators attached to self-replicating silicate crystals (Dawkins
582–94). To “unwork” the animal is to slide in this way.
Likewise, we shall be sliding from ethical responsibility to the
psychoanalytic question of enjoyment. The issue of the political animal
demands that once we start demolishing ecologocentrism, we go to the
end. My essay thus jettisons the usual phenomenological approach to
nonhuman beings with its too easy talk of “worlds,” and instead opts for
a disturbingly unsentimental mix of Lacan and Derrida. Curiously, this
mix allows for a greater intimacy with nonhuman beings than the normal
ideological lubricants such as Heideggerian mysticism, phenomenological
languages of embodiment and embeddedness, and Gaian holism. These
lubricants slip a rich, luscious film between us and other beings,
paradoxically to prevent us from articulating a theory of our coexistence
with them. Finally, this means that we shall slide from the ontological to
the ontic. Truly to address the political animal is to shake ontology to its
very foundations. It is only thus that we shall be able to articulate a
properly materialist ecology.

Strange Strangers: Animals in the Open


The category “animal” is among the ways in which thinking reifies
the ecological. Ecology without Nature implies a nonconceptual network
of infinite proliferation and diversity. This network resembles the
community of “unworking” that Nancy’s philosophy of social form
develops from Blanchot’s understanding of the Romantic fragment poem:
the way it offers not a total “work” of art, but a desœuvrement.5 The
“human” is not at the center of this almost unthinkable network. Nor is
“nature,” nor indeed the “animal.” For at each node of the network, there
is a radical gap. Our encounter with the network at any point is with an
irreducible alterity.
Our experience of the gap is perhaps best described in the language
of Emmanuel Levinas, in which other people directly are infinity. Levinas
strives towards a profoundly social view in which the “self” is always
already caught in a traumatic asymmetrical encounter with an “other.”
This other is what appears at each node of the ecological network: the
stranger, or in Derridean terminology the arrivant, the utterly unexpected
arrival, towards whom there must be an infinitely open hospitality (or
“hostipitality,” in Derrida’s extraordinary reworking). I use the word
“stranger” rather than “other” to emphasize the radically unknowable
quality of this arrivant.

SubStance #117, Vol. 37, no. 3, 2008


Ecologocentrism: Unworking Animals 77

Ecology without Nature is an endless network of strange strangeness:


the strangeness of the strangers is irreducible. We cannot predict exactly
who or what they are—indeed, whether they are a “who” or a “what.”
This radical openness to non-identity means that questions of
anthropocentrism and anthropomorphism are untenable. But so are
questions of “ecologocentrism” or “biophilia.” Preserving differences
between humans and animals has well documented disastrous effects
on philosophy, culture and politics. But erasing differences disastrously
collapses the profound alterity of the strange stranger. To preserve
strange strangers, we must do away with anthropocentrism and
ecologocentrism in a single stroke.
This essay’s view of nonhumans and humans is not far from
traditional animism. Because of the nonessentialism of ecology without
Nature, we must put this term under erasure (animism). Like animism,
ecology without Nature regards all beings as people, while not restricting
the idea of “people” to human being as such. There is no Nature, only
people, some of whom are human beings. On this view, there is no such
thing as “the animal” and no such beings as “animals.” Instead, there is
this cat, that tree, this nematode worm. I am always already in a social
relationship with these people, prior to any specific concept of social
formation—prior, in fact, to any ontology. Thus it is not that animals are
whatever we say they are—a form of nominalism. We are dealing here
with uniqueness, with singularity. The “The” in “The Political Animal”
becomes a marker of unicity, not generality. Curiously, this unicity is a
better way of beginning to imagine collectivity (not community), because
animism undermines the idea of “person” itself. Let us find out how.
In her poem “Come into Animal Presence,” Denise Levertov figures
animal “presence” as a space one enters:

Come into animal presence


No man is so guileless as
the serpent. The lonely white
rabbit on the roof is a star
twitching its ears at the rain.
The llama intricately
folding its hind legs to be seated
not disdains but mildly
disregards human approval.
What joy when the insouciant
armadillo glances at us and doesn’t
quicken his trotting
across the track into the palm brush.

SubStance #117, Vol. 37, no. 3, 2008


78 Timothy Morton

What is this joy? That no animal


falters, but knows what it must do?
That the snake has no blemish,
that the rabbit inspects his strange surroundings
in white star-silence? The llama
rests in dignity, the armadillo
has some intention to pursue in the palm-forest.
Those who were sacred have remained so,
holiness does not dissolve, it is a presence
of bronze, only the sight that saw it
faltered and turned from it.
An old joy returns in holy presence.6

Levertov achieves the sense of this animal as opposed to “the animal” in


general, and yet the general notion of “animal presence,” reappears as
the “holiness” that is “a presence / of bronze” (22–3). This is not a
community in the sense of an organic, close-knit fellowship. Nor are the
animals the kin of humans. There is an implied habitat, a high desert
plateau perhaps. This hinders the possibility that each animal is there to
exemplify something particular for the human gaze, in a neoclassical
allegorical style. The poem broaches the Rilkean idea that animals are
unique in their access to an “open” to which human eyes are temporarily
closed. What we turn from is “a presence of bronze” (23). Holiness itself
is an opacity, not a transparency but an aesthetic density (of material,
bronze) that impedes our view. We shall revisit this notion of ontic,
phenomenal holiness, rather than ontological, “worldly” holiness, at the
deepest level of this essay’s engagement with the political animal.
Giorgio Agamben’s The Open explores this community of animal
unworking via a transformed notion of the aesthetic, which he articulates
as “profound boredom” (63–70). Agamben interprets the post-coital
languor of lovers in a Titian painting as representative of “the inactivity
… and desœuvrement of the human and of the animal as the supreme and
unsavable figure of life” (87). Desœuvrement models a sociality prior to
any human–nonhuman split, because its fragmentariness is an open
form that includes what lies around it. Agamben discerns in this “a
higher stage beyond both nature and knowledge” (87)—higher than both
human and animal being. The “presence of bronze” (Levertov) is not yet
a reified object, but a materiality that resists the auratic distance of the
artwork. It is “unwork,” the unworking animal. Like a lump of metal in
an art gallery, we wonder where the work stops and the boundary begins.
Agamben unworks the human into the animal, moving from self-
consciousness to boredom. But might desœuvrement, unworking, go the

SubStance #117, Vol. 37, no. 3, 2008


Ecologocentrism: Unworking Animals 79

other way around? Might a feature of human being considered


distinctively human be found at the animal level? Dare we claim that
this feature is the very capacity to reflect, in particular the capacity for
aesthetic contemplation? It is a profound question, because the aesthetic
is not simply an intentional consciousness (consciousness of…). It shows
us sheer awareness as such. Kantian beauty is not so much in the eye of
the beholder as it is directly the eye of the beholder, projected onto the
object. The aesthetic implies an open, even passive receptivity, rather
than activity. It is fundamentally non-utilitarian: nonhuman life is not
simply fulfilling a telos (survival, adaptation, and so on). A good reading
of Darwin includes his intuition that life forms are not purely utilitarian,
for instance in the case of sexual selection (Morton, The Ecological Thought).
The question of aesthetics is significant for the politics of animality.
Anthropocentric and ecocentric ideologies alike perform what
Vardoulakis and Danta describe as “the gesture of aligning politics with
the rational and the reflexive—a cornerstone of humanism—[that] also
leads to a disturbing separation between the active (or legislative) ‘human’
and the passive (or collective) ‘animal’ ” (introduction to this issue). We
glimpse this perhaps in the “mild disregard” (6–9) of Levertov’s llama—
pun intended? Is this llama a lama? This may be borne out by “The llama
/ rests in dignity” (18–19), as if she were meditating. One of the deepest
questions is not, “Can animals think?” but “Are animals capable of
aesthetic contemplation?” Why? This would mean that the aesthetic was
not a “high” function of “greater” cognitive powers, but a “low” (who
knows, perhaps the lowest) one. What if the aesthetic were the default
mode of sentience as such? Humanists must at least ask the question.
Perhaps we should be in the business not simply of reacting to science,
but of proposing scientific experiments.
A threshold that resisted the separation of human and animal would
not only resist their collapse into each other. It would also resist the
“posthumanism” that all too readily dematerializes the nonhuman. It is
a paradox that alongside necessary political action on global warming
and animal rights, a more trenchant ecological approach in philosophy
and culture would hesitate precisely on this threshold, at the very
moment at which the world is telling us to stop hesitating and do
something. To do nothing, intelligently, is a good definition both of
“animal” passivity and of aesthetic contemplation, and even of religious
forms of contemplation found for instance in apophatic Christianity and
in Buddhism. Strangely, the political urgency today is about becoming
animal in this sense. Far from transcending animality, theory can think

SubStance #117, Vol. 37, no. 3, 2008


80 Timothy Morton

itself as becoming animal. 7 Along lines similar to Agamben’s,


contemporary Buddhism has established the connection between
boredom, existential angst and meditative insight (Trungpa, 56–7).
This “becoming animal” is not a Deleuzo-Guattarian “line of flight”
from the normative political sphere, but a radical deconstruction of that
sphere.8 The Deleuzo-Guattarian approach flies too hastily towards what
may turn out to be ideological mirages. The political urgency of thinking
animals is proportionate to its difficulty, not least because of the
increasingly fungible quality of everything in a hypercapitalist,
nanotechnological age of bioengineering and genomics—in which
everything might be capable of being liquefied into everything else. This
fungibility increases the compulsion towards the total domination of
life forms. Posthumanism and transhumanism are in danger of providing
a perfect alibi for another round of Nietzschean mastery. And there is a
further difficulty. Any attempt to get beyond the Nietzschean strategy
risks ending up simply reaffirming Nietzsche, since his is the philosophy
of winners rather than losers (Bull). An ecological approach would surely
identify with the losers, with the “subhuman” rather than the superman.
To think the political animal, then, is to think “lower” and “less than,” to
shrink in vulnerability and hide in introversion, to dig holes and
hibernate. Theory could be a mole’s-eye view rather than an eagle’s. Marx’s
favorite quotation from Hamlet springs to mind; “Old mole. Canst thou
work i’ th’ earth so fast?” (1.5.183).
This essay now exfoliates becoming-animal-theory, by closely
examining a text that is profoundly preoccupied with questions of
strangers, interdependence and intimacy. This text articulates the global
awareness promoted by environmental thinking through a radical
coexistence that still outruns normative ways of imagining ecological
care. The text is Stanislaw Lem’s novel Solaris and its film adaptations by
Andrei Tarkovsky and Steven Soderbergh.

Planet as an Ape: Solaris


Solaris is a planet whose surface is a vast ocean that exhibits signs of
sentience, as if the entire planet were a gigantic brain. Lem’s novel was
written about fifteen years earlier than James Lovelock’s formulation of
the Gaia hypothesis; the sentient ocean has striking similarities with
Lovelock’s image of a self-sustaining set of feedback loops that appear
from a distance to demonstrate something like sentience. Yet there are
some striking differences, not the least of which is that while Gaia is a
holistic concept, Solaris is portrayed in an absolutely nonholistic way.

SubStance #117, Vol. 37, no. 3, 2008


Ecologocentrism: Unworking Animals 81

Gaian language portrays the Earth as telling us that we are harming


it, through indirect, emergent messages—parts that communicate a
whole. Solaris communicates in a far more direct way, as a singular
being speaking to singular beings. Kris Kelvin, the protagonist, is a
psychologist conducting tests on the scientists on a space station orbiting
Solaris. He becomes aware that the planet may be telepathically aware
of him. It is precisely because we are not sure whether animals are
conscious or not that we should act ethically with regard to them. The
question about whether the Gaian ecosystem imagined by Lovelock is
genuinely intelligence, artificial or otherwise, is thus prone to a larger,
more deconstructive ethics in which, precisely because we will never
know for sure, we should treat “artificial” beings (who isn’t one?) as if
they were sentient beings.9 The Korean government recently released
guidelines for the ethical treatment of robots in this manner.10 It is worth
reiterating this essay’s hesitation concerning scholarship’s use of
“posthumanism.” Gandhi’s comment about Western civilization (“It
would be a very good idea”) also applies to humanism, an unfinished
project. Indeed humanism incorporates a not-yet. Ideally the
deconstructive encounter between the human and the nonhuman or
inhuman is the human [see Zizek 159–60]).
The question of an ethical regard towards nonhuman beings
deliquesces into a set of questions pertaining to artificial intelligence.
Where does one draw the line between personhood and non-personhood?
Where does one draw boundaries of sentience, if at all? Is intelligence
embodied in any way? 2001 addresses the question from the point of
view of multiple components—HAL 9000 is made up of them—while
Solaris tackles the theme from the point of view of the whole, imagining
the biosphere as a colossal brain. Fascinatingly, however, Solaris by no
means suggests holism as a solution. Every encounter in the story is an
encounter with a singular being. The planet is precisely not a mystical
web of life, greater than the sum of its parts, but a vulnerable, unique
being for whose existence Kris is directly responsible.
Solaris vividly poses the Levinasian notion of otherness as the way in
which the stranger always already subtends me, by imagining the planet
as a giant brain that sends out impossible-real embodied thoughts in the
form of people. These incarnations are derived from the scanned memories
of the scientists aboard the space station. Solaris holds up the mirror to
the souls of the inhabitants of the scientists. The Doppelgänger-like
“simulacra” are themselves only dimly aware of their uncanny illusion-
like status (65). Kris’s relationship with Solaris rapidly becomes his

SubStance #117, Vol. 37, no. 3, 2008


82 Timothy Morton

relationship with his ex-lover Rheya, who committed suicide and now
returns to haunt him in the flesh, as a metastasized version of the planet
Solaris’s drive to communicate, a superbly realized image of the Lacanian
sinthome, the inconsistent-impossible-real sprout of enjoyment.
In Andrei Tarkovsky’s 1972 film adaptation, Snaut calls this
simulacrum “the materialization of [Kris’s] conception of her.” Sartorius
calls her “A mechanical reproduction. A copy. A matrix.” Yet the people
whom Solaris materializes are no hallucinations, as Kris finds out quickly
in a Cartesian experiment to prove his sanity. They begin as all too real
sprouts of liquid imagery on the surface of the sentient ocean. Because
she is unaware of her status as an embodiment of this liquid being, Rheya
herself has to come to terms with her alien identity, giving the story a
Frankensteinian, Blade Runner-like theme of discovering the alien within
oneself. This discovery is surely the profound lesson of Darwinism, a
theory of mutagenic replicants whom we can only tentatively call species.
Lurking at the back of Kris’s encounter with his ex-lover Rheya (or
Hari in Tarkovsky’s film) is the existential life-substance, meaningless
spurts of ideation material. When Kris locks Hari in his room, she emits
terrible sounds and claws open the metal door. He tries to kill her by
sending her out into space, but she returns, a Xerox of his memory.
Disturbingly indestructible, when she drinks liquid oxygen, she
spontaneously revives. She is literally a text, information written in
material flesh, and like a text, she is utterly reproducible. We see the
living inkwell from which she springs. The sprouts of the ocean mind’s
enjoyment are called mimoids: the planet is a mimic—a parrot, or an ape
(OED, “ape,” n.1, 3). Mimoids are thus simple reflections, “apings” or
“parrotings.” When a parrot or a computer copies our language, is he, or
she, or it, behaving like us? Is it behaving consciously? Are we? The trouble
with animals is that their apparent mimicry of us reflects back on us,
making us wonder whether our own behavior is unique or deep.
Watching the mimoids and the simulacra is like reading text while
simultaneously watching it being written on a special page that writes
itself, automatically, without a separate author. This is a radical image of
the “book of Nature.” We see the “genotext” (the spurting matter) and
the “phenotext” (simulacra) at the same time (Kristeva 89–136). Or—to
translate Kristeva’s language back into the language of biology—we see
the genotype (genetic material) and the phenotype (what this material
“expresses”—from enzymes to organisms) at once. It is as if we were
watching replication, onto which were superimposed layers of
information. Of course, this is what actually does occur at the genomic

SubStance #117, Vol. 37, no. 3, 2008


Ecologocentrism: Unworking Animals 83

level. Given such a harrowing proximity between hardware and


software, between mimoid and apparently sentient being, can we call
Rheya a person or even a subject? Again, this is animality up close: DNA,
RNA, and enzymes can operate simultaneously both as hardware and
as software. The symbolic language of “life” is encoded directly in the
real. We need a rhetorical term like “anti-anamorphosis” or
“dedeformation,” a kind of metalepsis or “un-metaphor,” to evoke the
double twist in which what is ambient and environmental turns into
what is frontal and singular.
Kris transcends his fantasy projection. Having tried to destroy or
ignore the simulacrum of Rheya, Kris decides to relate with her precisely
as a living message from Solaris. Kris’s ethical dilemma is about learning
to treat the replica of his ex-lover as a unique person who just happens to
possess all the memories and characteristics of the woman from his past—
a person who is also an interface for the planet-brain. In joining Rheya,
Kris performs an impossible (inhuman?) identification with the planet
as ecological real, via a radical acceptance of one of the potentially endless
series of Rheya-replicas. This is beautifully embodied in the horrifying,
surreal end of Tarkovsky’s neo-Christian film interpretation. Tarkovsky
wants the encounter with the planet to be a metaphor for the encounter
with the really other other in the form of God. But as the imagery makes
explicit, this encounter (staged as the meeting between Kris and his father)
takes place on a little island of symbolic consistency (and only just: it’s
raining indoors) in a psychotic ocean of unmeaning. Kris has made a
drastic choice to stay on the space station and be drawn down onto the
sentient planet by the attractive force of its gravitational field (Newtonian
symbol of God’s love). The planet detects “islands of memory” in the
astronauts, and simulates them in the external world. The conclusion
materializes this when Kris himself inhabits a literal island of memory
with his father, kneeling to him on the threshold of their forest home.
Kris knows very well that Rheya/Hari is not his lover, and so he knows
as much as we the audience know about the final shot. In an extraordinary
ethical perversion (perversion as ethical), Kris is fully aware that his
Lebenswelt is a simulation. Kris exists without Nature, yet with a
profoundly ecological ethics.
The simulacra are metaleptic embodiments of the filmic surface itself,
the actual “environment” in which they appear. As well as being uncanny
Doppelgängers, they are also idiotic, idiomatic sprouts of planet stuff.
These beings are neighbors par excellence, strangers whose strangeness
is irreducible. The simulacra show us what is most traumatic about so-

SubStance #117, Vol. 37, no. 3, 2008


84 Timothy Morton

called animals. As Lacan says of alterity, “what constitutes pretence is


that, in the end, you don’t know whether it’s a pretence or not. Essentially
it is the unknown element in the alterity of the other which characterizes
the speech relation on the level on which it is spoken to the other” (48).
And as Slavoj Zizek explains, “The neighbor . . . as the Thing means that,
beneath the neighbor as my semblant, my mirror image, there always
lurks the unfathomable abyss of radical Otherness, of a monstrous Thing
that cannot be ‘gentrified’ ” (Zizek 143). If animals are people, according
to our hypothetical animist view, they are neighbors. Ethics is grounded
both on not knowing whether they are “for real” or not, and in glimpsing
an abyssal Real beneath the simulative surface. The question of the
political is inextricable from the problem of the political animal. Treating
nonhumans as people is a political choice that faces the vulnerability
and responsibility towards other beings in which we are entangled.

From Animal to Vegetable


Solaris brilliantly causes the forest and the trees, depersonalization
and the personal, to overlap. It works towards something like what
Dimitris Vardoulakis calls “a notion of subjective difference that is not
underpinned by subjective identity” (104). This view imagines
relationships along the lines of what Zizek says of Hegel, in a passage
that alters the normative view of Hegel’s intersubjectivity to accord with
a notion of non-identitarian subjectivity: “What if the Hegelian
‘recognition’ means that I have to recognize in the impenetrable Other
which appears as the obstacle of my freedom its positive-enabling
ground and condition?” (Zizek 142). Ontological hesitation thus becomes
the essence of aesthetic contemplation, which forms the basis for an ethics
of non-violence.
One should assert, moreover, that this subjective difference implies
somewhere that is not a “world,” that is not home, that is irreducibly,
uncannily homely and alien. This alien “unhomely” (Unheimlich) home is
impossible to think ecologocentrically as a total system bounded by an
outside. The home-as-alien is ecology without Nature. Ontological
hesitation is the most profound reason why aesthetic contemplation
may be the key to understanding life forms. If nonhumans can
contemplate thus, we are truly dealing with “unworking” animals, with
animals as those beings who not only provoke us to theory, but are
theory directly. Thus Levertov is incorrect to praise animals for not
“faltering” and “know[ing] what [they] must do” (14–15).
In Solaris, the environment of the planet turns itself “outside in” in
order to make intimate contact with the astronauts. The simulations

SubStance #117, Vol. 37, no. 3, 2008


Ecologocentrism: Unworking Animals 85

disclose the phantasmatic truths within the truism that all sentient
beings both constitute and are made up of their environments. The
problem with life forms is always in part a problem of semblance, a
problem of not knowing with whom we are dealing. The theory of
evolution makes this utterly explicit: every life form is made up of other
life forms. The simulacra are both too unreal, and too real.
There is something like this encounter with the environmental real
in Freud’s essay on the uncanny, in which environmental tropes
sometimes stand in for the encounter with the traumatic kernel of other
people and the otherness of people. Forests are iterations of trees, and so
uncanny: “when one is lost in a forest in high altitudes, caught, we will
suppose, by the mountain mist, and when every endeavor to find the
marked or familiar path ends again and again in a return to one and the
same spot, recognizable by some particular landmark” (Freud 17.237).11
The forest is a quintessential image of the text, which is why we say, “he
can’t see the forest for the trees.” We are always trying to make forests
into wholes. The scandal of Wordsworth’s so-called environmentalism
is that at crucial moments he expresses it as a perverse, singular love for
a unique thing: “There is a tree of many, one” (“Intimations of
Immortality,” 52). If there is no Nature, this does not mean that there is
nothing. We are not dealing with sheer nominalism here, but with an
ethics of singularity. Yet the forest-as-text is also an image of collectivity.
The dialectic of strange strangeness compels us to see “animals” both as
unique and as part of a non-holistic collective.
Solaris’s simulacra are called Phi-Creatures, which for a Lacanian is
almost too perfect. Phi (F) is Lacan’s symbol for the “imaginary Real.”
The “negress” Phi-Creature (30) is the imaginary Real of racist enjoyment
(Kris’s reaction is horror). What emerges from the sentient ocean are
pathetic embodiments of enjoyment whose excess parodies the
ideological frames in which they normally appear. The gigantic stature
of the negress is overwhelming, like Frankenstein’s creature, parodically
threatening the onlooker with her or his own racist desire, through the
trope of hyperbole: the textual overdoing of something, the sprouting
forth of something extra. The sprout of enjoyment persists, zombie-like,
even after the ideology that framed it is useless—like a “primitive negress”
walking around on a spaceship. The sprout is the a-rational,
nonconceptual and inconsistent core of ideological fantasy, and as such
it provides a way of dissolving the fantasy. When found walking around
the space station, outside their ideological frames, the Phi-Creatures put
the scientists to shame: “Shame, the feeling that will save humanity”
(Kris, in Tarkovsky’s Solaris). Shame, the awareness that I am caught in

SubStance #117, Vol. 37, no. 3, 2008


86 Timothy Morton

the gaze of the other, is always the “animal presence” in which one finds
oneself. (I part company here with Levertov, who suggests that we can
“Come into” this “presence.”)
Should we then suggest that when I see an animal, I am always
seeing something disturbing from my inner space, scuttling around
outside of me? I am ashamed precisely because “it is me” more directly
than I myself am. Surely this is the basis for the social practice of
scapegoating: literally loading the shame of the community onto an
animal and sending her or him out into the wilderness. Every attempt to
get rid of this disturbing “abject” thus directly wounds me and disturbs
even more profoundly the social space, thus readying the closed
community for another round of scapegoating. This is precisely why
animals cannot just be accepted as humans with fur and feathers into
the human “community,” because accepting animals implies dissolving
the holistic notion of community as such that always serves as a screen
to prevent me from witnessing my inextricable intimacy with other
beings.
Against this disturbing of human beingness—this maximal
externalized eccentricity—Kris attempts to formulate Cartesian sanity
in a closed loop (I know I am sane because I can prove that something
exists, 50). Unfortunately this must be done with the help of a giant
computer. The thinking machine is a prosthetic externalization of the res
intellectus. Because the “something that exists” is the computer whose
“brain” sticks out like a sore thumb, the experiment itself deconstructs
existence into ex-sistence (literally, “placement outside of oneself”). The
very form of Kris’s experiment makes clear that personal identity always
depends upon some external, supplementary substance that undermines
its identitarian claims. That Descartes was half conscious of this is
confirmed by his parapraxis of “res”—what we find beyond and above
matter is a thing that thinks. Likewise, the Phi-Creatures are emanations
of the ultimate wetware, the brain-ocean.
Human being collapses into “animal presence,” and “animal
presence” collapses into writhing, vegetative life. Tarkovsky decided to
begin with Kris amidst the fecund, wet, birdsung ambience of a rural
Russian upper middle class. Looking into a stream, Kris Kelvin sees what
could be reflections of a mass of undulating fronds—a figure both for the
Imaginary (we are seeing a water image, possibly a reflection, perhaps
distorted by the flow of water) and for the Real (we are beholding, in the
rippling anamorphosis of the flow of water itself, the sprouts of
enjoyment). The fronds wonderfully encapsulate the mimoids of Solaris—

SubStance #117, Vol. 37, no. 3, 2008


Ecologocentrism: Unworking Animals 87

the vegetable and vegetative lurking at the back of the animal. 12


Compared with Stanley Kubrick’s 2001, where everything is done to
erase the body’s specificity from the text, Tarkovsky’s Solaris contains
much meaningless physicality: the almost pungent sweatiness of Kris,
the familiar old routines of a run-down farmhouse (that frame the
technology ironically), the morphing mind-ocean that sends out sprouts
of enjoyment . . . The closest Dave (2001) comes is to the view outside the
space pod of the mucus-like colors and surfaces expanding and
contracting. Kelvin embraces the sentient ocean and decides to live the
rest of his life in contact with it. He plants himself in the phenomenal (not
even phenomenological) world: the ontic “sacred” (that is, disturbingly
intimate) world. The phenomenological world is for someone. It is this
“someone” that the phenomenal world does not permit.
A conservative reading suggests that at the end Kris decides to stay
on the planet to be reunited with a transcendent god or father—an
abstraction of mind. But a more radical reading suggests that Kris’s own
consciousness depends (as a child upon a parent) upon, literally “hangs
off” or “grows from” the undulating fronds that he contemplates at the
beginning of the film and to which he returns at the end. The fronds also
bring to mind the undead, vegetative quality of the palpitating film stock
and its uneasy equation with palpitating life—is it life? In this sense, the
film itself is a Phi-Creature, a mechanized, robotic simulation of sentient
being—again, we face the uncertainty as to whether all sentient being is
this robotic simulation.
It gradually becomes clear that the ocean is offering sprouts of
enjoyment as part of a seduction—an intimate communication, a caress.
A caress of shame! Indeed, the planet insists upon communication. The
astronauts kill, maim, attack and abandon their Phi-Creatures, but this
does not prevent the sentient sea from sending out more. To accept that
is to transcend the projection of imaginary identities onto the mimoids.
Solaris shows us how to love beyond identity. Both Tarkovsky’s and
Soderbergh’s films imply this, in the former case with the gigantic panning
shot that includes the island of father and son in the psychotic ocean,
and in the latter with the divine glide into seeming utter madness. In an
ecological twist on film noir, the protagonist in each case accepts the illusion
of the Phi-Creature, knowing that it is an illusion, as a way to join with
the sentient ocean itself. Kris radically opposes Sartorius, whose
experiments stand in contrast to his collaboration with the illusion. Kris
sends an “encephalogram” to the planet, an X-ray modulated by a brain
wave (155–6), a message that includes the totality of his mind, conscious

SubStance #117, Vol. 37, no. 3, 2008


88 Timothy Morton

and unconscious, and thus includes content of which he cannot be aware.


To quote Lacan again, “the unknown element in the alterity of the other”
(48) also applies to the communication of the speaker herself or himself.
Soderbergh’s version is in one sense more disturbing than
Tarkovsky’s, because instead of God, the sentient ocean is a metaphor for
consumerism. Soderbergh’s version is the nihilist misreading, just as
Tarkovsky’s is the theistic misreading. Kris becomes a solipsistic
consumerist who gets sucked into the vortex of narcissistic enjoyment.
At the end we are told that all has been forgiven. Kris gets to have his
cake and eat it too by joining with the planet and possessing Rheya all
over again, now capable of acting as if the suicide had never happened.
In Tarkovsky Kris notices that it is raining indoors, a poetic inversion. In
Soderbergh a self-inflicted cut on Kris’s hand, which we saw earlier in
the film, heals itself, indicating that he is fully in the world of the planet
Solaris—while not communicating with it at all (has he just been
downloaded?). Soderbergh renders Kris’s encounter with the real of the
planet in a penultimate scene, where white noise engulfs the ship,
temporarily overwhelming the Ligeti-esque score. But this penultimate-
ness suggests an ability to live through the psychotic encounter with the
real and achieve a minimal consistency that is denied, or is at any rate
far more precarious, in Tarkovsky’s version.
Space limitations do not permit further elaboration here of the
occluded correspondence between the nihilistic-consumerist and theistic-
Christian versions of Solaris, but there surely is one, since nihilism is
simply a form of belief, albeit an ostensibly more sophisticated one—
“believing in nothing.” Both film versions play with the way in which
Kris radically dissolves what Benjamin, in his work on capitalism as
religion, calls the “guilt history”—the timeless time of guilt—in which,
on this essay’s terms, the subject is suspended in a dualistic relationship
with its object, whether the object appears to belong to a consumerist
universe (the free fall of window shopping, Kantian browsing without
purpose, as the zero degree of consumerism), or to a theistic one (the
relationship of endless guilt and retribution).13 Collapsing the subject–
object dualism does not mean entering into a world where all is either
just brain firings or just God. It means entering into the traumatic
encounter with a strange stranger. Thus the manner in which both
adaptations of the story resolve the deadlock of the scientists takes the
form of a radical coexistence with the stranger, short-circuiting religion
and, or as, capitalism.
We thus return to the theme of the political animal, and its world-
historical significance. How does Solaris thematize this politics of the

SubStance #117, Vol. 37, no. 3, 2008


Ecologocentrism: Unworking Animals 89

animal? In Tarkovsky’s film, the zero gravity scene prefigures the image
of Kris’s home island floating on the psychedelically swirling, mimetic
ocean. Here the camera floats around the bounded horizon of a Brueghel
painting of a feudal village in a snowy forest clearing, an invocation of a
Lebenswelt made strange by the floating point of view. The planet’s
gravitational field is such that the space station temporarily loses its
artificial gravity, so the floating camera angle literally floats Brueghel’s
world in a wider, displacing ocean. We are drawn into a cinematic world
in which form enacts content. The images of and metaphors for the planet
ocean have an analogue in the imagery of fronds in flowing water that
recurs once at the beginning of the film and once before the concluding
shot. The fluid motion of the water, with floating detritus—living and
dead—is an analogue for the filmic surface itself.
Thus the closest the spectator comes to the encounter with the really
other other is in our encounter with the mute, metamorphic surface of
the film stock, as in Stan Brakhage’s experiments such as Dog Star Man, in
which he worked directly on the film stock itself. In 2001, the monolith
stands in for the dark letterbox shape of the blank screen, a space into
which ape creatures and humans project desire, and from which shoot
beams of technical knowledge, immersing them in a horrifying high
pitched scream of white noise—does this noise not strangely prefigure
the sound of a dialup modem connecting to a server? In the final sequence
of 2001 the monolith becomes a screen within a screen, out of which
emerge not undulating wet fronds but spectacular beams of light:
frightening, fast, “wowing” Dave and us with a lightshow, yet leading
him to cosmic rebirth. By contrast, Kris washes his hands in the water in
which the fronds slowly undulate, returning him and us to a world that
he and we know is an illusion. As in Brakhage’s experiments, the filmic
surface is already populated with an other, with being as otherness.
In answer to Kubrick’s presentation of the cinema screen as void,
Tarkovsky gives us the screen as fullness—but not as full presence. In his
later film Stalker, the screen is filled with garbage, the detritus of human
desire, as the camera tracks across the surface of the water in The Zone.
In Solaris the film stock becomes the (other) planet, the environment itself.
Zizek expresses it eloquently in a passage on Stalker:

in our standard ideological tradition, the approach to Spirit is


perceived as Elevation, as getting rid of the burden of weight, of the
gravitating force which binds us to earth, as cutting links with material
inertia and starting to “float freely”; in contrast to this, in Tarkovsky’s
universe, we enter the spiritual dimension only via intense direct
physical contact with the humid heaviness of earth (or stale water)—

SubStance #117, Vol. 37, no. 3, 2008


90 Timothy Morton

the ultimate Tarkovskian spiritual experience takes place when a


subject is lying stretched out on the earth’s surface, half submerged
in stale water; Tarkovsky’s heroes do not pray on their knees, with
their heads turned upwards, towards heaven; instead they listen
intensely to the silent palpitation of the humid earth. . . (Zizek, “The
Thing from Inner Space”)
A materialist ecology is faced with the choice between Nature and ecology.
We can have Nature, or ecology, but not both. We can have animals, or a
world, but not both. As this essay has argued in various different modes,
“Spirit”—self-reflection—must be installed at the material level rather
than on some “elevated” level. Thus “animal passivity” will have entered
into the political realm through a discovery that self-reflection is lowly
rather than lofty.
Solaris is ambient art at its finest—environmental art without
Nature.14 The encounter with the sentient real of the environment-turned-
person is staged at the formal level as the aesthetic encounter with the
medium of transmission itself—the material density of the film surface.
Tarkovsky’s films are to cinema what drone music is to popular music.
They annihilate the sense of time and use an experience of boredom that
Agamben asserts as the link between what we think of as the fully human
(aesthetic contemplation) and what we think of as nonhuman or animal.
The film itself is animality. Tarkovsky tries to achieve an encounter with
God in content, but only succeeds, and in a far more deconstructive
manner, at the level of form. We should recall the phrase of George
Morrison, the nineteenth-century theologian, who in the sermon “The
Reawakening of Mysticism” declares that “the one intense reality is God,
nearer than breathing, closer than hands and feet” (106). Kris decides to
live in this world of ultimate intimacy, rather than fending off the shaming
Phi-Creatures. It is as if Kris leaps out of the film’s content and into its
form, deciding to live on the surface of the film stock itself. In this sense he
traverses the fantasy and commits to living in the traumatic, impossible-
real environment that is the person of Solaris. God is one word for this
intimacy, “nearer than breathing.” But so is animality.
According to this logic, properly inhabiting the Earth is the opposite
of self-delusion, and the delusion of the self. And yet, at the same time, it
is a full acceptance of the phantasmic illusion, in the radical form of
coexisting with the monstrous, sprouting thing embodied by the cinema
screen and its writhing imagery. The form of Solaris becomes the limit of
animality: the planet as an ape. The political animal is a matter of intimacy
with the neighbor, not of being-one with Nature.
This raises a question concerning the notion of the animal as a being
with an identity, a person. Furthermore, it raises the question of what

SubStance #117, Vol. 37, no. 3, 2008


Ecologocentrism: Unworking Animals 91

counts as a person. If we accept Gaia, why resist the opposite idea: that
rather than the weather being sentient, sentient beings are like the
weather? If the two terms are indeed related by identity, or even simply
resemblance—which is what the Gaia metaphor implies—then surely
the concept is reversible? And if so, where do we draw the line between
this and that weather, or even between weather and non-weather? We
can tell that Gaia is ideological because the copula is not reversible: Gaia
is a whole greater than the sum of its parts. A careful reading of Solaris
shows that to enter into relationship with a strange stranger is precisely
not to forge a communion with a Gaia-like, holistic entity.
Again, neither a theistic nor a nihilistic outcome appears possible or
desirable. The philosopher John McDowell claims, “it is doubtful that we
can conceive of thinking as a subjectless occurrence, like a state of the
weather” (McDowell 256). Derek Parfit, whose Reasons and Persons strongly
argues for the idea that there is no independent, single or lasting self,
refutes McDowell’s claim that a reductionist or “no-self” view would
entail a process without a subject (“Experiences, Subjects, and Conceptual
Schemes”). Such a view might simply require that we expand or limit
our view of what a subject is—in the language of this essay, this is the
encounter with the strange stranger. Something like this is required of
Kris in his relationship with replica-Rheya, who is at once a person in
her own right, and an interface for Solaris itself. Kris has to perform two
difficult operations: to recognize that replica-Rheya is not Rheya; and to
acknowledge at the same time that she is not an independent person, but
something like an avatar (to use the internet term) of the planet-mind.

The Cost of Intimacy


It should by now be painfully, frighteningly obvious that we are
entering an age where ecology will be one of the most dominant, if not
the dominant, way of describing our world and discussing policy.
Advances in science are helping us understand just how enmeshed we
all are in the world. Like that charity song from the 1980s, “We Are The
World”—and it doesn’t feel so good. I know that my body probably
contains some mercury and has been affected by radiation. I can take
tests to make sure. But even without them, there remains a sneaking
suspicion that I might be contaminated, just like most of the plants and
animals. And thus, even if by some remote chance I’m not swimming in
my own poison, then I have still been affected by ecological thinking. So
yes, we are all interconnected, but not, it turns out, in a nice utopian,
hippy manner. We are starting to learn just how interlinked everything

SubStance #117, Vol. 37, no. 3, 2008


92 Timothy Morton

is, the hard way. This idea has now lost its charming, naïve 1960s aura.
Such is the effect of risk society (Beck).15
Since the late eighteenth century (the period we call Romantic), the
arts and humanities have held an idea that “nature” is something (some
thing) “over yonder.” Science, and current events, have outstripped this
idea. How can the arts and humanities catch up? Unfortunately for some,
this will mean de-Bambifying nature: it cannot be just cute any more.
The logic of the movie Happy Feet is that you can only be nice to one
species at a time: seals look nasty from a penguin’s eye view. A somewhat
cynical reading might be “Dance for us, or we’ll keep on killing you.”
Children flushed their goldfish down toilets when Finding Nemo came
out. Sentimentality is not working. Nor is the wild energy of the sublime.
For nature to be sublime, we have to be at least a little distant from it. A
toxic leak is not sublime by the time it has entered the lungs. Global
warming is not sublime: it is far more disorienting, and painful, than
that.
This essay has not advocated “postmodern” relativism, nor has it
claimed that trees and rabbits and coral do not exist. It is simply that
human beings cannot afford (in all senses) to pursue old-school thinking
about our coexistence with all the other beings on this Earth. Thinking
must take a step back and rearticulate “the environment” at the very
moment at which it is flooding into our homes on the airwaves and as
the all too real waves of events such as Hurricane Katrina. Crises make
us panic, and panic wants us to act, and act fast. We are going to need to
act and think at the same time, and this praxis is not as easy as walking
and chewing gum. Ecology without Nature is itself a form of the
ontological hesitation with which the political animal confronts us.
Ecology without Nature does not mean that it is okay to keep on
drilling for oil rather than exploring solar and wind energy. Entities
such as coral reefs do exist. It is not scholarship but modern life that is
doing its best to make sure that they really do not exist. While tackling
global warming with all deliberate speed and trusting the near total
scientific consensus, we should be using culture not only to create a
framework in which global warming science becomes recognizable and
legible. And in general, we should be slowing down, reflecting, and using
this moment as an opportunity to change and develop.
In The Communist Manifesto, Marx and Engels state that under the
current economic conditions, “National one-sidedness and narrow-
mindedness become more and more impossible, and from the numerous
national and local literatures, there arises a world literature” (224–5). If
this idea is to mean more than people from several different countries

SubStance #117, Vol. 37, no. 3, 2008


Ecologocentrism: Unworking Animals 93

writing the same thing in the same ways, it must include the idea that
writing in general can, under certain circumstances, meditate upon the
idea of world as such. This capability is not unconnected to the
globalization of specific kinds of misery. It eventually becomes possible
to sing a song called “We Are The World,” and wince about it, or to see
the many levels of painful irony within the phrase “United Nations.”
Ecology has reminded us that in fact we are the world, if only in the
negative. In material historical terms, environmental phenomena
participate in dialectical interplay insofar as they bring an awareness of
environmental negatives such as global warming, the Asian “brown
cloud” and toxic events such as Chernobyl. Far from needing filling out
with some positive “thing” such as “nature” or the ecofeminist and
Lovelockian image of Gaia, this negative awareness is just what we need.
Stanislaw Lem’s Solaris and its film versions thematize the drastic, queer
quality of what has been normatively and neuteringly called the love of
nature. Solaris is about getting over our projections, and yet staying with
the planet. I return to the idea of subjective difference not grounded in
identity: the Buddhist metaphor of Indra’s net is never experienced as an
integrated whole, only as traumatic and singular encounters with a
stranger qua irreducible-real Thing, an animal whose vegetative being
is not far from the surface. Are we intimate with ghosts or with plants?
In the ecological society to come, we are going to need more and less than
nature lovers and tree huggers.
If leftist ecology is to have an ethics, then it cannot be the fascist one
in which we are components of a greater whole. It must instead reside in
the singularity of, and conscious commitment to, the other. Such a
responsibility cannot be reciprocal, otherwise we return to the holistic
web of life. This asymmetry is elegantly demonstrated in the Solaris
thought experiment. The planet is not a biosphere on which the
astronauts depend. Indeed, no life forms do. This dependency comes after
the ethical commitment, when Kris decides to let the space station fall
into Solaris’s gravitational field. Biospheric holism, then, is at odds with
the infinite responsibility towards the political animal opened up by a
decision to coexist—that is, to coexist ultimately with coexistence itself,
which happens whether we like it or not. Solaris is a radical text of
animality, since it deprives us of the phantasmatic support of a
background world, a wonderful Gaian web of life in which, like couch
potatoes spectating the Iraq War, we are “embedded.”
In our age of ecological panic, what we are losing is precisely this
sense of “nature” or “the environment” as an enveloping, nonhuman
and/or non-sentient “world.” This world provided a background to our

SubStance #117, Vol. 37, no. 3, 2008


94 Timothy Morton

foreground, offering meaningfulness precisely in its opacity, acting as a


screen on which we project our fantasies. Wordsworthian Romanticism
is a locus of the artistic production of this screen. Geoffrey Hartman’s
analysis of Wordsworth’s view of nature as a sounding board has not
been surpassed, even by the ecocriticism that claims that Hartman
reduces Wordsworthian nature. Ironically, no matter how much
Romantic forms of deep ecology try to imbue this screen with a kind of
personality, deep ecology is firmly on the side of the abstract “world” as
opposed to that of the strange stranger. The pre-ontological gap between
persons is far more properly infinite than the palpable vastness of the
natural or nonhuman world of deep ecology. Deep-ecological vastness is
measurable or immeasurable, but always there, like the authoritarian
image of the Burkean sublime—a huge mountain or a thunderstorm. In
striving to patch up the tear in the ontic substrate of our existence with
an ideologically integrated, holistic Nature, ecological panic is thus part
of the problem. Ecology without Nature, then, is part of a left solution—
not a flight from Earth (really or metaphorically) but dwelling with the
necessarily traumatic encounter with the torn ontic level. We must come
to terms with the fact not that we are destroying Nature, but that there
was no Nature.
The University of California, Davis

Notes
1. Thanks to Scott Shershow, David Simpson and Dimitris Vardoulakis for their helpful
comments on this essay, and to Derek Parfit for corresponding with me about per-
sonal identity.
2. I develop this further in Morton, Ecology without Nature, 160–9. Other scholars have
noted the ways in which figures of the weather can stand in for history, in more and
less problematic ways. See for example Cadava.
3. The recent publication of Derrida’s complete seminar on animals is a case in point. See
Works Cited.
4. I discuss this fully in The Ecological Thought.
5. See Lacoue-Labarthe and Nancy 57–8. Scott Shershow has powerfully demonstrated
this linkage (165–82, 193–205).
6. Denise Levertov, “Come into Animal Presence,” from Poems 1960–1967, copyright ©
by Denise Levertov, reprinted by permission of New Directions, Pollinger Limited
and the proprietor.
7. This has been strongly asserted by Dimitris Vardoulakis in “The Politics of Impassiv-
ity in Agamben and Spinoza.” See also Wall.
8. I am thinking of the argument in A Thousand Plateaus, reprinted in Atterton and
Calarco’s Animal Philosophy.
9. I take my cue from Ferry 53–4.
10. http://news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/technology/6425927.stm.
11. For a comprehensive study see Harrison, especially 2, 5, 84, 186.

SubStance #117, Vol. 37, no. 3, 2008


Ecologocentrism: Unworking Animals 95

12. This is surely the environmental significance of Agamben’s and Zizek’s discussion
of the Muselmann (Homo Sacer 184–5; Zizek 160–2).
13. I am grateful to Dimitris Vardoulakis for discussing this with me. See Hamacher for
further discussion.
14. For further discussion, see Morton, Ecology without Nature, 29–78.
15. For further discussion see Morton, Ecology without Nature, 84–5, and Heise 53–4,
119–23.

Works Cited
Agamben, Giorgio. Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life. Trans. Daniel Heller-
Roazen. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998.
——. The Open: Man and Animal. Trans. Kevin Attell. Stanford: Stanford University
Press, 2004.
Beck, Ulrich. Risk Society: Towards a New Modernity. Trans. Mark Ritter. London: Sage,
1992.
Benjamin, Walter. “The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction.” Illumina-
tions. Ed. Hannah Arendt, trans. Harry Zohn. London: Harcourt, Brace and World,
1973.
——. The Arcades Project. Trans. Howard Eiland and Kevin McLaughlin. Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1999.
Bull, Malcolm. “Where is the Anti-Nietzsche?” New Left Review second series 3 (May/
June 2000): 121–45.
Brakhage, Stan. Dog Star Man (1962–1964). By Brakhage: Anthology. (Criterion, 2003).
Cadava, Eduardo. Emerson and the Climates of History. Stanford: Stanford University
Press, 1997.
Dawkins, Richard. The Ancestor’s Tale: A Pilgrimage to the Dawn of Life. London: Phoenix,
2005.
Deleuze, Gilles, and Félix Guattari. “Becoming-Animal.” In Peter Atterton and Matthew
Calarco, eds. Animal Philosophy: Ethics and Identity. London and New York: Con-
tinuum, 2007. 87–100.
Derrida, Jacques. Of Grammatology. Trans. Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak. Baltimore and
London: the Johns Hopkins University Press, 1987.
——. The Animal that Therefore I Am. Ed. Marie-Louise Mallet. Trans. David Wills. New
York: Fordham University Press, 2008.
La voix et le phénomène: introduction au problème du signe dans la phénoménologie de Husserl.
Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1967.
——. “Violence and Metaphysics.” Writing and Difference. Trans. Alan Bass. London and
Henley: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1978. 79–153.
——. “Structure, Sign, and Play in the Discourse of the Human Sciences.” Writing and
Difference. Trans. Alan Bass. London and Henley: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1978.
278–93.
——. “The Animal That Therefore I Am (More to Follow).” Trans. David Wills. Critical
Inquiry 28.2 (2002): 369–418.
Ferry, Luc. The New Ecological Order. Trans. Carol Volk. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1995.
Freud, Sigmund, The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund
Freud. Ed. and trans. James Strachey. 24 vols. London: Hogarth, 1953.
Hamacher, Werner. “Guilt History: Benjamin’s Sketch ‘Capitalism as Religion.’ ” Trans.
Kirk Wetters. Diacritics 32.3–4 (2002): 81–106.
Harrison, Robert Pogue. Forests: The Shadow of Civilization. Chicago and London: Uni-
versity of Chicago Press, 1993.

SubStance #117, Vol. 37, no. 3, 2008


96 Timothy Morton

Heise, Ursula K. Sense of Place and Sense of Planet: The Environmental Imagination of the
Global. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 2008.
Jackson, Michael and Richie, Lionel. “We Are the World.” Columbia Records, 1985.
Kristeva, Julia. Revolution in Poetic Language. Trans. Margaret Waller. The Kristeva Reader.
Ed. Toril Moi. Oxford: Blackwell, 1986. 89–136.
Kubrick, Stanley. 2001: A Space Odyssey. MGM, 1968.
Lacan, Jacques. Le seminaire, Livre III: Les psychoses. Paris: Editions de Seuil, 1981.
Lacoue-Labarthe, Philippe and Nancy, Jean-Luc. The Literary Absolute: The Theory of
Literature in German Romanticism. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1988.
Lem, Stanislaw. Solaris. Trans. Joana Kilmartin and Steve Cox. San Diego, New York and
London: Harcourt Brace, 1970; first published 1961.
Levertov, Denise. Poems 1960–1967. New York: New Directions, 1967.
McDowell, John. “Reductionism and the First Person.” Jonathan Dancy, ed. Reading
Parfit. Oxford and New York: Blackwell, 1997. 230–50.
Miller, George and Coleman, Warren. Happy Feet. Kingdom Feature Productions, 2006.
Marx, Karl. Selected Writings. Ed. David McLellan. Oxford and New York: Oxford Univer-
sity Press, 1977.
Mingyur, Yongey, Rinpoche. The Joy of Living: Unlocking the Secret of Science and Happi-
ness. New York: Harmony Books, 2007.
Morrison, George. The Weaving of Glory. Grand Rapids, MI: Kregel Publications, 1994.
Morton, Timothy. Ecology without Nature: Rethinking Environmental Aesthetics. Cambridge,
Mass. and London: Harvard University Press, 2007.
——. The Ecological Thought. Cambridge, Mass. and London: Harvard University Press,
2009.
Nancy, Jean-Luc. The Inoperative Community. Trans. Peter Connor et al. Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 1991.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. Thus Spoke Zarathustra. Trans. Adrian Del Caro. Ed. Robert Pippin.
Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 2006.
Oxford English Dictionary. http://www.dictionary.oed.com.
Parfit, Derek. “Experiences, Subjects, and Conceptual Schemes.” Philosophical Topics
26.1–2 (Spring and Fall 2007): 217–70.
Shakespeare, William. Hamlet. New York: Washington Square Press, 2003.
Shershow, Scott. The Work and the Gift. Chicago and London: University of Chicago
Press, 2005.
Soderbergh, Steven. Solaris. Twentieth-Century Fox, 2002.
Stanton, Andrew, and Lee Unkrich. Finding Nemo. Walt Disney Pictures, 2003.
Tarkovsky, Andrei. Solaris. Creative Unit of Writers and Cinema Workers, Mosfilm, Unit
Four, 1972.
——. Stalker. Mosfilm, 1979.
Trungpa, Chögyam, Rinpoche. The Myth of Freedom and the Way of Meditation. Boston
and London: Shambhala Publications, 1988.
Vardoulakis, Dimitris, “The Return of Negation: The Doppelgänger in Freud’s ‘The
Uncanny’.” SubStance 35.2 (2006): 100–16.
——. “The Politics of Impassivity in Agamben and Spinoza.” Paper given at the Centre
for Comparative and Cultural Studies, Monash University, August 9, 2006.
Wall, Thomas Carl. Radical Passivity: Levinas, Blanchot, and Agamben. Albany: SUNY
Press, 1999.
Wordsworth, William. William Wordsworth. Ed. Stephen Gill. Oxford and New York:
Oxford University Press, 1984; repr. 1986, 1987.
Zizek, Slavoj. “Neighbors and Other Monsters: A Plea for Ethical Violence.” Slavoj
Zizek, Eric Santner and Kenneth Reinhard, eds. The Neighbor: Three Inquiries in Politi-
cal Theology. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 2005. 134–90.
——. “The Thing from Inner Space.” http://www.lacan.com/zizekthing.htm.

SubStance #117, Vol. 37, no. 3, 2008

S-ar putea să vă placă și