Sunteți pe pagina 1din 33

The Ideological Context of Hobbes's Political Thought Author(s): Quentin Skinner Reviewed work(s): Source: The Historical Journal,

Vol. 9, No. 3 (1966), pp. 286-317 Published by: Cambridge University Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2637983 . Accessed: 18/04/2012 10:06
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Cambridge University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Historical Journal.

http://www.jstor.org

The Historical J7ournal,Ix, 3 (I966), Printed in Great Britain

pp.

286-3I7

III. THE IDEOLOGICAL CONTEXT OF HOBBES'S POLITICAL THOUGHT


By QUENTIN SKINNER Christ's College, Cambridge
THE modern reputation of Hobbes's Leviathan as a work 'incredibly overtopping all its successors in political theory'1 has concentrated so much attention on Hobbes's own text that it has tended at the same time to divert attention away from any attempt to study the relations between his thought and its age, or to trace his affinities with the other political writers of his time. It has by now become an axiom of the historiography2 that Hobbes's 'extraordinary boldness'3 set him completely 'outside the main stream of English political thought' in his time.4 The theme of the one study devoted to the reception of Hobbes's political doctrines has been that Hobbes stood out alone 'against all the powerful and still developing constitutionalist tradition',5 but that the tradition ('fortunately ')6 proved too strong for him. Hobbes was 'the first to attack its fundamental assumptions ',7 but no one followed his lead. Although he 'tried to sweep away the whole structure of traditional sanctions ',8 he succeeded only in provoking 'the widespread re-assertion of accepted principles ',9 a re-assertion, in fact, of 'the main English political tradition '.10 And the more Leviathan has become accepted as 'the greatest, perhaps the sole masterpiece '" of English political theory, the less has Hobbes seemed to bear any meaningful relation to the ephemeral political quarrels of his contemporaries. The doctrine of Leviathan has come to be regarded as 'an isolated phenomenon in English thought, without ancestry or posterity '.12 Hobbes's system, it is assumed, was related to its age only by the 'intense opposition' which its 'boldness and originality' were to provoke.'3 The view, however, that Hobbes 'impressed English thought almost entirely by rousing opposition ',4 and that consequently 'no man of his time
1
2

R. G. Collingwood, The New Leviathan (Oxford, 1942), p. iV. For studies of Hobbes's reception, see J. Laird, Hobbes (London,

I934),

part

III,

pp.

H. R. Trevor-Roper,'Thomas Hobbes' and 'The Anti-Hobbists', in Historical Essays (London, I957), pp. 233-8, 239-43; J. Bowle, Hobbes and his Critics (London,
243-3I7,

esp. 247-57;

I951); S. I. Mintz, The Hunting of Leviathan (Cambridge, I962), and incidental discussions in other works cited below. 3 Trevor-Roper, 'Thomas Hobbes', p. 233. 4 Bowle, op. cit. p. I3. 6 Ibid. p. 42. 6 7 Ibid. p. 42. Ibid. p. 47. 8 Ibid. p. 43. 9 Ibid. p. I3. 10

1 Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. M. Oakeshott (Oxford, I946), Introduction, p. x. 12 Trevor-Roper, 'Thomas Hobbes', p. 13 Mintz, op. cit. p. I 233. 5. 14 Leslie Stephen, Hobbes (London, I904), p. 67.

Ibid. p.

I4.

IDEOLOGICAL

CONTEXT

OF HOBBES

S POLITICAL

THOUGHT

287

occupied such a lonely position in the world of thought '15seems to be much in need of re-examination. For it can be shown that complex and ambiguous relationships between Hobbes and the other political writers of his age have in this way become misleadingly oversimplified. It has not been recognized that to set against the hostility of his numerous critics there was also a popular following for Hobbes's doctrines, particularly on the continent. It has not been realized that Hobbes's theory of obligation was also critically studied at the same time, and treated as authoritative, by a whole group of defacto theorists in the English Revolution. The fact that these aspects of Hobbes's contemporary reputation have been overlooked, moreover, can be shown to have given rise to a misleading view about the intentions even of his critics. These affinities between Hobbes's doctrine and its intellectual milieu have never been investigated.16 The attempt to see Hobbes against this ideological background, however, will not only produce an historically more complete picture. It can also be shown to be relevant in itself to questions about the nature of Hobbes's own contribution to political theory. For Hobbes's views have tended to get evaluated in a misleadingly unhistorical way. He has been treated as a figure in complete isolation, the inventor of 'an entirely new type of political doctrine'."7 He has thus come to seem an inevitable influence, a necessary point of departure, for other political writers of the time, including Harrington and even Locke.'8 All such judgments, however, become arbitrary or unhistorical when it is shown that Hobbes was in fact drawing on and contributing to existing traditions in political ideology, as well as helping to refine and modify them. The prevailing view, moreover, about the meaning of Hobbes's own political doctrine depends in effect on discounting all such evidence about his contemporary intellectual relations. It can be shown, similarly, that this in itself must reduce considerably the plausibility of such interpretations. It is the aim, in short, of the following study to show from an investigation of Hobbes's contemporary reputation that it is not possible to disconnect questions about the proper interpretation of Hobbes's views from questions about the ideological context in which they were developed. The accepted view of Hobbes as a complete outcast from the intellectual has society of his time, 'the bete noire of his age, '19 arisen at least in part from
G. P. Gooch, Political Thought in England: Bacon to Halifax (London, 19I5), p. 23. Bowle's book simply treats Hobbes's critics as 'representative' of a political tradition which Hobbes is alleged 'singlehandedly' to have challenged. For a brilliant discussion, however, of the relations between Hobbes's intellectual assumptions and their appropriate social context, see Keith Thomas, 'The Social Origins of Hobbes's Political Thought', in Hobbes Studies, ed. K. C. Brown (Cambridge, Mass., I965), pp. I85-236. 17 Leo Strauss, Natural Right and History (Chicago, I953), p. i82. 18 For this assumption, see esp. ibid. pp. 202-51; C. B. Macpherson, The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism (Oxford, I962), pp. 265-70; R. H. Cox, Locke on War and Peace (Oxford, I960), esp. pp. 136-47 on the relations between Commonwealths, where it is claimed that Locke's doctrine 'tacitly follows Hobbes', p. 146. 19 Mintz, op. cit. p. vii.
16 15

I9

HJ

ix

Z88

QUENTIN

SKINNER

a misleading restriction of the investigation. Although there have been valuable studies of the numerous attacks made on Hobbes by his clerical enemies in England, there has never been any study20of Hobbes's reception in his own time on the continent. It has in general been assumed that Hobbes's views 'proved equally noxious and combustible'21 abroad, and that he 'received the same hard usage' as in England.22 It is clear, however, that there is in fact an important distinction to be drawn between the many critics whom Hobbes provoked at home and the many admirers he was to gain on the continent, especially in France. Hobbes himself remarked with some bitterness in his later years on the contrast between his reputation abroad, which 'fades not yet ,23 and the opposition he continued to arouse in the English universities and in the Royal Society. The Royal Society always contrived to ignore him. But the foreign savants were to show no such hostility. When Pierre Bayle came to summarize so much of their achievement at the end of the century, in his Dictionary, he was to single Hobbes out as 'one of the greatest minds of the seventeenth century ' 24 And perhaps the greatest of the foreign savants, Leibniz himself, cited 'the famous Hobbes' with his 'extreme subtlety' on many points.25 Leibniz completely disagreed with Hobbes's ethical and political theory, 'which, if we were to adopt it, would bring nothing but anarchy'.26 Yet he still placed Hobbes among the highest, for (as he remarked in one of the Meditations) 'what could be more acute than Descartes in physics, or Hobbes in ethics? '27 Hobbes had first gained this high reputation among the continental savants a generation earlier, during his eleven years' exile from the civil wars in England. He was then a frequent visitor at Mersenne's cell, which served during the I64os as perhaps the most important salon for the learned. Many of the scientists and philosophers Hobbes is known to have met there were to become avowed followers and popularizers of his political theories. Several of them corresponded with Hobbes and even visited him after his return to England in i65I.28 Hobbes met there the physician Sorbiere, who was to publish the first French translation of Hobbes's De Cive, as well as a translation of De Corpore Politico, both with fulsome prefaces in praise of Hobbes's political
Except for the brief, though valuable, remarks in Laird, op. cit. part III. Mintz, op. cit. p. 62. 22 Ibid. p. 57. 23 Thomas Hobbes, 'Considerations', The English Works, ed. Sir WV. Molesworth (London, II vols., I839-45), IV, 435. 24 Pierre Bayle, Dictionnaire Historique et Critique (Rotterdam, 4 vols., i697), III, 99-I03. Note: in this and all following quotations from seventeenth-century sources all translations are mine, all spelling and punctuation are modernized. 25 G. W. Leibniz, Opera Omnia (Geneva, 6 vols., I768), I, 5, 256. 26 Ibid. IV, 360. 27 Ibid. VI, 303. 28 On visits, see Thomas Birch, The History of the Royal Society (London, 4 vols., I756), I, 26-7; S. Sorbiere, A Voyage to England (London, trans. I709), pp. 26-7.
21 20

IDEOLOGICAL

CONTEXT

OF HOBBES

S POLITICAL

THOUGHT

289

system.29 He also met the mathematician Du Verdus, who was later to produce a further translation of De Cive, with a preface recommending it to Louis XIV as suitable for use in all French schools.30 He met Gassendi, whose remarks about the freedom and clarity of Hobbes's political thought were to be inserted in the second edition of De Cive.3' Mersenne himself wrote similarly of 'the incomparable Hobbes', whose De Cive had shown that politics could be made a study as scientific as geometry.32 A large number of letters sent to Hobbes at this time by other French admirers reveal the extent of his popularity and ideological relevance in France, as well as the efforts which these disciples made to ensure that the works of 'this great politician' became widely known.33 This continental acceptance of the relevance of Hobbes's doctrine was to be reflected in the political propaganda of the De Witt party in Holland34 as well as among the apologists for absolutism in France. In Holland Velthuysen welcomed the publication of De Cive with a dissertation in the form of a letter to its 'most celebrated' author, pointing out 'how much you will see my own views bear the closest affinity to the views of the great Hobbes '.35 'The famous Hobbes' is cited throughout this Dissertatio as the authority on the nature of man, on the relations between natural and human laws, and on the power of the civil magistrate.36In France Merlat similarly used the viewpoint of 'that famous Englishman, Hobbes' as a basis for the argument of his Traite du Pouvoir Absolu.37Although he claimed to disagree strongly with Hobbes on the question of man's natural unsociability, his own view of the origins and the necessary form of political society both cited and closely followed Hobbes's characteristic account. Hobbes was 'undoubtedly correct' to see that 'the malice of most men would ruin a Society', and so was correct to deduce not only that this 'established in general the need for political power', but also that it required that such power should be absolute. And for further elucidation Merlat simply referred 'the curious' to Hobbes's own
works.38
29 See, in Elements Philosophiques du Citoyen (Amsterdam, I649), Sorbi6re's translation of De Cive; Le Corps Politique ou les Elements de la Loi Morale et Civile (Amsterdam, I652), his translation of De Corpore Politico. 30 See, in Les Elements de la Politique de Monsieur Hobbes (Paris, i66o), Du Verdus's translation of De Cive. 31 Gassendi to Sorbiere: printed in Thomas Hobbes, Elementa Philosophica De Cive (Amsterdam, Ii647), sig. **, ioa-b. 32 Mersenne to Sorbibre; printed in ibid. sig. ii a-b. i 33 For a special study of this group and its correspondence with Hobbes, see my article, 'Thomas Hobbes and his Disciples in France and England', Comparative Studies in Society and History, viii (I966), 153-67. 34 See Johan de la Court, Consideratien van Staat (n.p., i66i); A. Wolf, 'Annotations', Correspondence of Spinoza (London, 1928), p. 446. 32 Lambertino Velthuysen, Epistolica Dissertatio (Amsterdam, p. 2. i65I), 36 Ibid. pp. 35 ff., I36 ff., I75 ff. 37 E. Merlat, Traite du Pouvoir Absolu des Souverains (Cologne, i685). 38 Ibid. pp. 2I9-22.

I9-2

290

QUENTIN

SKINNER

Hobbes's political theory was to be critically studied as well as merely popularized among his contemporaries on the continent. His sympathetic readers, moreover, included some of the greatest names. It is a commonplace that Spinoza's Tractatus Politicus shows the effects of 'a critical reflection on Hobbes's theory' in 'its content and terminology as well as its method . The affinity was recognized at the time, particularly by critics, who often bracketed Spinoza together with Hobbes in a general denunciation.40 It is known from his correspondence that Spinoza himself recognized his affinities with Hobbes.41 It is known from Aubrey's biography that Hobbes himself (anticipating much modern commentary)42 recognized in Spinoza's political theory an equally pessimistic but even more rigorous development of his own assumptions.43 It was among the continental jurists, however, that Hobbes's political doctrines were to set off the strongest echoes. Even the hostile traditionalists were to acknowledge his immediate impact. Samuel Rachel, professor of Law at Holstein in the i66os, remarked-very instructively-on the dangerous fact that while 'many learned and good men in England have been roused' against 'this novel philosophy of Hobbes', yet it 'has been greedily swallowed by some in France and the Netherlands, and even in Germany . The jurists were sometimes hostile to Hobbes's views, but in their works he none the less joins the ranks of the great-a name to cite with the Ancients, and to stand with Grotius and Pufendorf among modern authorities. Gundling was to use Hobbes as a source throughout his works, and in his De J7ure Oppignorati Territorii cited Hobbes as his authority both in discussing the problems of establishing political society and on the need for a monopoly of power within it.45 Textor in his Synopsis J7uris Gentium gave Hobbes, along with Pufendorf, as the authority to be cited in discussing both the distinction between 'the Natural Law of Man and of States' and 'the origins of Kingdoms and the ways in which they are acquired under the Law of Nations '.46 Beckman in his Meditationes Politicae gave a list of authorities on political theory in which he singled out, as 'the two incomparable men to be consulted in these matters', Hugo Grotius and Thomas Hobbes.47 Grotius was conventionally the greatest name to cite in discussions
39 Benedict de Spinoza, The Political Works, trans. and ed. A. G. Wernham (Oxford, I958), Introduction, pp. I, I 2. 40 E.g. Richard Baxter in The Second Part of the Non-Conformists Plea for Peace (London, i68o); William Falkner in Christian Loyalty (London, I679); and Regnus 'a Mansvelt, as cited in the Introduction to The Moral and Political Works of ThlomasHobbes (London, I750), 41 See Wolf, op. cit. Letter 50, p. 269. p. xxvi n. 42 E.g. S. Hampshire, Spinoza (London, I95I), pp. I33-6. 43 See John Aubrey, Brief Lives, ed. A. Clark (Oxford, 2 vols., I898), I, 357. 44 Samuel Rachel, Dissertation on the Law of Nature and of Nations (I676), trans. in J. B. Scott (ed.), The Classics of International Law (Washington, 2 vols., I9I6), II, 75. 45 N. H. Gundling, De Jure Oppignorati Territorii (Magdeburg, I706), p. i6. Also mentioned Hobbes in De Praerogativa (n.d.) and in Dissertatio de Statu Naturali (I709). 46 J. W. Textor, Synopsis of the Law of Nations (i68o), trans. in L. von Bar (ed.), The Classics of International Law (Washington, 2 vols., I9I6), ii, 9 and 82. 47 J. C. Beckman, Meditationes Politicae (Frankfort, I679), p. 7.

IDEOLOGICAL

CONTEXT

OF HOBBES

S POLITICAL

THOUGHT

29I

about ius gentium, but Beckman was later to decide that it was Hobbes's name which 'deserved to be praised before all others'*48 The most careful student of Hobbes among the seventeenth-century jurists was to be Pufendorf himself, in his effort to construct a systematic jurisprudence out of a 'reconciliation between the principles of Grotius and Hobbes '.49 His great treatise of I672, De Yure Naturae et Gentium, treated Hobbes throughout as an authority on many of the points at which (in Pufendorf's favourite phrase) 'scholars are not yet agreed ',50 as well as providing perhaps the most intelligent analysis by a contemporary of Hobbes's political theory. Pufendorf was frequently critical of Hobbes, whose basic political axiom, he felt, was 'unworthy of human nature '.51 He was prepared, nevertheless, to defend even this part of Hobbes's system, since he felt (as did Leibniz)52 that Hobbes had been unfortunate in being 'interpreted with very great rigour, and with very little reason, by some learned men . Pufendorf remained close and sympathetic to Hobbes's views, moreover, at two important points, corresponding to Book II of his Treatise, on man and society, and Book VII, on the establishment of States. In Book ii, although Pufendorf remained sceptical about 'that War of all men against all which Hobbes would introduce', he conceded that Hobbes 'has been lucky enough in painting the insecurities of such a state', and concluded that if the theory is treated 'only by way of hypothesis' it may well have a distinct relevance and cautionary value.54 In Book VII Pufendorf is even closer to Hobbes-closer, perhaps, even than his acknowledgments suggest. He begins by agreeing that 'what Mr Hobbes observes concerning the genius of Mankind is not impertinent to our present argument: that all have a restless desire after power'. And, though he remained hostile to the theory of obligation which Hobbes deduced, he concluded (with extensive quotation from Leviathan) that 'Mr Hobbes hath given us a very ingenious draft of a civil State, conceived as an artificial man'.55 It becomes clear that the immediate reception of Hobbes's political theory on the continent was much less hostile than in England. There was a clearer sense of the relevance as well as the importance of his doctrine. The distinction has been largely ignored in modern commentary. It was recognized at the time, however, not only by Hobbes himself, but by the first of his biographers, his friend John Aubrey. When Aubrey came to draw up his list of Hobbes's 'learned familiar friends' for his biography, he treated it as a sad but undoubted fact that 'as a prophet is not esteemed in his own country, so he was more esteemed by foreigners than by his countrymen '.56
48 49

J. C. Beckman, Politica Parallela (Frankfort, Laird, Hobbes,p. 276.

I679), p. 4I7.

50 Samuel Pufendorf, Of the Law of Nature and Nations (London, trans. I7IO). Cited Hobbes as authority on Law of Nature (in Book ii, ch. iv, and in viii, I); on consensus (ii, iii); on contracts (v, ii); on sovereignty (vii, vii). 51 Ibid. p. 87. 52 Leibniz, op. cit. v, 53 Pufendorf, op. cit. p. II2. 468. 54 Ibid. Book ii, pp. 84-8. 55 Ibid. Book vii, pp. 5i8-26. 56 Aubrey, op. cit. I, 373.

292

QUENTIN

SKINNER

The relations of Hobbes's political thought to the ideologies of the English Revolution have been obscured as well as illuminated by the tendency of scholars to concentrate exclusively on the fulminations of Hobbes's numerous clerical opponents. It is true, of course, that among his contemporaries Hobbes was particularly marked out for his originality, particularly denounced for his heterodoxy. It is evident, none the less, that his impact has been viewed in a misleading perspective. It can be shown (quite apart from the central issue of Hobbes's following) that the treatment of Hobbes's critics as 'representative' of political theory at the time has been misleading in two important respects. It is a view based, in the first place, on a misleading oversimplification of the nuances and complexities of different political ideologies of the time. For despite the many attacks Hobbes also gained a serious reputation as an authority on political matters among many of the learned-even among the learned orthodox who remained uncommitted to any of his views. The accepted view of Hobbes's reputation has been based, in the second place, on a mistaken impression of the assumptions, and even the intentions, of Hobbes's critics. It has not been recognized how much they feared not merely Hobbes's dangerous doctrines, but their serious ideological purchase, not to mention their popular following. The serious reputation of Hobbes among 'the solemn, the judicious' was conceded at the time even by his enemies.57 By the end of the century Ilobbes had come to be accepted as an authority even among philosophers of avowedly opposed temperament. 'Tom Hobbes', as Shaftesbury was to admit, 'I must confess a genius, and even an original among these latter leaders in philosophy.'58 By this time Hobbes had attained the recognition he had always hoped for, in having his works placed (though amidst much controversy) in the libraries of his own university.59Within his own lifetime he was not without a similar recognition. Selden and Osborne, who both revealed in their writings a markedly 'Hobbesian' strain, were also (according to Aubrey) amongst the earliest serious students of Hobbes's political works. Osborne wrote of Hobbes as one of the men who had 'embellished the age ',60 while Selden is known to have sought Hobbes's acquaintance oIn the strength of reading Leviathan. In a similar spirit Hobbes's friend Abraham Cowley 'bestowed on him an immortal Pindaric Ode ',62 the fulsome sentiments of which were to be echoed by Blount's remarks on Hobbes as 'the great instructor of the most sensible part of Mankind'.63
57 J. Eachard, Somne Opinions of Mr Hobbes Considered. Introduction distinguished Hobbes's serious and popular following, anatomizing 'Hobbists' into pit, gallery and box 'friends'. See sig. A, 4a-b. 68 A. A. Cooper, 3rd earl of Shaftesbury, The Life, Unpublished Letters and Philosophical Regimen, ed. B. Rand (London, I900), Letter to Stanhope, p. 414. 59 See Thomas Hearne, Remarks and Collections (Oxford, ii vols., I885-1921), X, 75 and 322. 60 Francis Osborne, A Miscellany (London, I659), sig. A. 61 Aubrey, op. cit. I, 369. 63 62 Ibid. p. 368. Charles Blount, The Oracles of Reasonz(London, I693), p. 104.

IDEOLOGICAL

CONTEXT

OF HOBBES

S POLITICAL

THOUGHT

293

Although such tributes to Hobbes mainly came from his less conventional friends, his recognition was not confined to them. Hobbes had a number of clerical admirers,64among whom must be counted that very type of a Restoration bishop, Seth Ward. Ward was suspicious of Leviathan, disliking its attack on the universities. Yet he acknowledged 'a very great respect and a very high esteem' for its author,65 and possibly wrote the Epistle prefacing De CorporePolitico, in which Hobbes's 'excellent notions' on 'the grounds and principles of Policy' are 'commended as the best that ever were writ'.66 James Harrington wrote of Hobbes in a very similar way. Although suspicious and critical of Leviathan he nevertheless agreed 'that Mr Hobbes is and will in future ages be accounted the best writer at this day in the world '.67 And, while Harrington looked to future ages, a reference by Webster to Hobbes and the Ancients completes the eulogy. There was no need, Webster claimed, to revere too much the views of the Ancients on statecraft. Although they had produced works 'of singular use and commodity', yet 'even our own countryman Master Hobbes hath pieces of more exquisiteness and profundity in that subject than ever the Grecian wit was able to reach unto'.68 These anticipations of Hobbes's modern reputation were echoed at the time even among his critics. These acknowledgments of Hobbes's stature have been suppressed in modern commentary. Even the critics agreed, however, in seeing Hobbes not only as 'a man of excellent parts ',69 a man 'singularly deserving in moral and socratical philosophy ',70 but even as a writer 'of as eminent learning and parts as any this last age hath produced'.71 Leviathan, as even its bitterest critics allowed, was the work of 'a universal scholar '.72 The recognition of its author's 'mighty acumen ingenii ',7 moreover, caused the critics to move with some circumspection in their attacks. Hobbes was 'a man with so great a name for learning', as one critic admitted, that the best he could hope to do was to 'fling my stone at this giant, and I hope hit him '.7 Clarendon, too, prefaced his statesmanlike attack by conceding how difficult it was to contest the 'great credit and authority' which Leviathan had gained 'from the known name of the author, a man of excellent parts'. As much as any follower, he joined the other critics in acknowledging Leviathan64 65

Aubrey's list of Hobbes's closest friends included four clergymen (see Aubrey, op. cit.

I, 370).

Seth Ward, A Philosophical Essay (Oxford, I652), sig. A, 3 a. Thomas Hobbes, 'To the Reader', De Corpore Politico (London, 1650). Cf. Thomas Hlobbes, The Elements of Law, ed. F. Tonnies (London, I889), Introduction, p. vii. 67 J. Harrington, 'The Prerogative of Popular Government', Works (London, I771), p. 241. 68 J. Webster, Academiarum Exainen (London, I654), p. 88. 69 Alexander Rosse, Leviathan Drawn out with an Hook (London, I653), sig. A, I2a. 70 Philip Scot, A Treatise of the Schism of England (London, i650), p. 223. 71 Roger Coke, A Survey of the Politics (London, i662), sig. A, 4a. 72 Johln Dowel, The Leviathan Heretical (Oxford, I683), sig. A, 2a. 73 Villiam Lucy, Observations, Censures and Confutations of Notorious Errors in Mr Hobbes his Leviathan (London, I663), p. I I7. 74 William Lucy, Examinations, Cenisuires and Confutations of Divers Errors in the Two First Chapters of Mr Hobbes his Leviathan (London, I656), sig. A, 5a.
66

294

QUENTIN

SKINNER

with whatever alarm-to be a work 'which contains in it good learning of all kinds, politely extracted, and very wittily and cunningly digested, in a very commendable method, and in a vigorous and pleasant style '.75 It is clear, moreover, that what disturbed the critics was not merely the serious reputation or even the alarming content of Hobbes's doctrines, but their ideological purchase, and their even more alarming popularity. This point has been submerged under the weight given to the contemporary attacks on Hobbes-though the number of attacks might in itself be thought to offer some paradoxical guide to Hobbes's continuing popularity. The popular acceptance of Hobbes's views, however, was a point which weighed with his critics from the start. As early as i657 Lawson was to note how much Leviathan was 'judged to be a rational piece' both by 'many gentlemen' and by 'young students in the Universities '.76 Within two years of its publication Rosse had expected to be attacked himself for denouncing so fashionable a work.77By I670 Tenison felt obliged to admit that 'there is certainly no man who hath any share of the curiosity of this present age' who could still remain 'unacquainted with his name and doctrine'.78 Clarendon noted at the same time how much Hobbes's popularity continued to weather every attack, how much his works 'continue still to be esteemed as well abroad as at home '.7 By the time of his death Hobbes had grown 'so great in reputation', as Whitehall angrily remarked, that even apparently 'wise and prudent' men had come to accept his political views, which 'are daily undertaken to be defended '.80 Hobbes's enemies doubtless wished to emphasize the menace, but there is independent evidence about the extent of Hobbes's contemporary popularity. A catalogue of 'the most vendible books in England' which happens to survive for the year i658 included all of Hobbes's works on political theory, and showed him one of the most popular of all the writers listed under 'humane learning', surpassed in the number of his entries only by Bacon and Raleigh.81 Twenty years later Eachard was to make the figure of Hobbes in his Dialogue reply to his detractors by pointing out that despite their strictures on his works they 'have sold very well, and have been generally read and admired .82 The printing history for all of Hobbes's political works certainly bears this out.83 De CorporePolitico, originally published in i65o, reached a
7

Edward Hyde, earl of Clarendon, A Brief View and Survey of... Leviathan (Oxford,

I676), sig. A, i b.
76 George Lawson, An Examination of the Political Part of Mr Hobbes his Leviathan (London, I657), sig. A, 2b. 77 Rosse, op. cit. sig. A, 4b. 78 Thomas Tenison, The Creed of Mr Hobbes Examined (London, I670), p. 2. 79 Clarendon, op. cit. sig. A, 3 a. 80 John Whitehall, The Leviathan Found Out (London, I679), p. 3. "' W. London, A Catalogue of the Most Vendible Books in England (London, I658), sig. T, 3 a, to sig. Z, i b. 82 John Eachard, Mr Hobbes's State of Nature Considered, ed. P. Ure (Liverpool, 1958), p.

I4.
83 For following details, cf. H. Macdonald and M. Hargreaves, Thomas Hobbes: a Bibliography (London, I952), pp. I0-I4, 30-6, 76-7. i6-22,

IDEOLOGICAL

CONTEXT

OF HOBBES

S POLITICAL

THOUGHT

295

third edition by I652, was immediately translated, and in its French version went through two further editions within the year. De Cive was first published in a very small edition in i642, but on being re-issued five years later it went through three editions in one year. It was published again in I657, again in I669, as well as appearing in the two-volume collection of Hobbes's Opera Philosophica which went through two editions in i 668. Translated into French in I649, it had attained a third edition by I65I and a new translation by i 66o. Leviathan went through three editions in its first year of publication, and by i668 the book (as Pepys noted) was so 'mightily called for' that he had to pay three times the original price to get a copy,84 even though there had in fact been two further editions of the work in the same year. It is a record of publication not even rivalled by Locke (to take the most famous case from the next generation), within whose lifetime the Two Treatises reached only three English and two French editions.85 The failure to acknowledge this element of popularity has tended to give a misleading impression of the intentions of Hobbes's contemporary critics. They have been treated as attacking a single source of heterodox opinion. It can be shown, however, that they concentrated on Hobbes not because he was seen as the 'singlehanded' opponent of tradition, but rather because he was seen to give the ablest and most influential presentation to a point of view which was itself gaining increasingly in fashionable acceptance and in ideological importance. To the more hysterical critics it even seemed possible to believe that 'most of the bad principles of this Age are of no earlier a date than one very ill Book, are indeed but the spawn of the Leviathan '.86 By the time of the i688 Revolution, when the question of allegiance to de facto power was again (as when Leviathan was first published) the central issue of political debate, it seemed to the last exponents of passive obedience that the 'authority and the reasons' of Hobbes's political theory 'are of a sudden so generally received, as if the doctrine were Apostolical '.87 By this time (according to Anthony 'a Wood, Hobbes's old Oxford enemy) Leviathan had already 'corrupted half the gentry of the Nation '.88 The suspicion of Hobbes's leading contribution to 'the debauching of this generation'89 was the moving spirit even with some of Hobbes's most statesmanlike critics. Richard Cumberland excused his long philosophical attack on Hobbes with the hope that he might
84 Samuel Pepys, The Diary, ed. H. B. Wheatley (London, 8 vols., I904-5), VIII, 9I. The 'three editions' of Leviathan in i65 I may of course be slightly misleading, as the second two are evidently false imprints-contemporary, but precise dates unknown. 85 See John Locke, Two Treatises of Government, ed. P. Laslett (Cambridge, 1960), Introduction, appendix A, pp. I2I-9. 86 Charles Wolseley, The Reasonableness of Scripture-Belief (London, i672), sig. A, 4a. 87 Abednego Seller, The History of Passive Obedience since the Refornation (Amsterdam, i689), sig. A, 4a. 88 Anthony 'a Wood, 'Thomas Hobbes', Athenae Oxoniensis (London, 2 vols., i69I-2), II, 278-483. 89 J. Lymeric, life of Bramhall in Works of. .'.John Bramhall (Dublin, i676), sig. N, i b.

296

QUENTIN

SKINNER

limit the increasing acceptance of Hobbes's political views.90Even Clarendon, from the bitterness of his second exile, claimed to trace 'many odious opinions' back to Leviathan, 'the seed whereof was first sowed in that book'.91 A more realistic-and more revealing-assumption was that the reason for Hobbes's doctrines being so 'greedily sought and cried up'92 was rather 'the prevalence of a scoffing humour' in 'this unhappy time '.9 When Francis Atterbury came to reflect a generation later on the ease with which the 'false and foolish opinions' of that age had 'gotten footing and thriven', he had no doubt that there had been 'something in them which flattered either our vanity our lust or our pride, and fell in with a daring inclination'. And he particularly mentioned Hobbes as a man who had 'owed all his reputation and his followers' to this 'skill he had in fitting his principles to men's constitutions and tempers'.94Earlier critics had nearly all made the same point. According to Lucy the popularity of Leviathan merely indicated 'the genius that governs this age, in which all learning, with religion, hath suffered a change, and men are apt to entertain new opinions in any science, although for the worse, of which sort are Mr Hobbes his writings '.95 And according to Eachard-Hobbes's rudest, shrewdest critic-the age itself had thrown up so many 'who were sturdy, resolved practicants in Hobbianism' that they 'would most certainly have been so, had there never been any such man as Mr Hobbes in the world '.96 To some Hobbes was the leading symptom, to others the sole cause, of the increasingly rationalist temper of political debate. But the point on which all critics agreed was that Hobbes's popularity reflected a more widespread endorsement of his outlook. It was not Hobbes himself whom they were even mainly concerned to denounce, but rather Hobbes as the best example of the alarming and increasing phenomenon of 'Hobbism'. Within Hobbes's own lifetime the word 'Hobbism' was already in popular currency to denote 'a wild, atheistically disposed' attitude to the powers that be,97 while the 'Hobbists' were recognized as wanting to 'subvert our laws and liberties and set up arbitrary power '.98 The 'Hobbist' villain became a familiar parody on the Restoration stage: in Farquhar's Constant Couple he reads what appears to be The Practice of Piety, but is in fact Leviathan under plain cover.99The 'Hobbist' was also recognized, more seriously, as the political rationalist
90 Richard Cumberland, A Treatise of the Laws of Nature (i672) (trans. London, I727), Introduction, sect. xxx. 91 Clarendon, op. cit. sig. *, 3a. 92 Baxter, op. cit. p. 8. 93 Anonymous, Inquiry, cited from Mintz, op. cit. p. I36. "" Francis Atterbury, Maxims, Reflections and Observations (London, I723), p. 66. 96 Eachard, Some Opinions, sig. A, 3b. 95 Lucy, Examinations, sig. A, 3b. 97 R.F., A Sober Enquiry (London, i673), p. 5I98 John Crowne, City Politics (London, i683), p. 50. 99 T. Farquhar, The Constant Couple (London, I700), p. 2: Vizard, 'This Hobbes is an excellent fellow'. On this point generally, see L. Teeter, 'The Dramatic Use of Hobbes's Political Ideas', E.L.H. III (936), I40-69.

IDEOLOGICAL

CONTEXT

OF HOBBES' S POLITICAL

THOUGHT

297

who assumed that God had left it 'arbitrary to men (as the Hobbeans vainly fancy)'100to establish their own political societies 'according to the principles of equality and self-preservation agreed to by the Hobbists'.101 Locke in his Essay contrasted the 'Hobbist' with the Christian, as a man who would justify his keeping of 'compacts' not by saying 'because God, who has the power of eternal life and death, requires it of us', but 'because the public requires it, and the Leviathan will punish you if you do not'*102 Bramhall similarly addressed his Catching of Leviathan not merely to Hobbes, but to the man 'who is thoroughly an Hobbist', with the aim of showing him that 'the Hobbian principles do destroy all relations between man and man, and the whole frame of the Commonwealth '.103 The 'Hobbists' and the followers of Hobbes, so alarming to contemporaries, have been almost totally discounted by modern commentators. The positive ideological affinities between the political views of Hobbes and his contemporaries have in consequence received no attention. The one analysis of the relations between 'Hobbes and Hobbism' has claimed, in fact, that in Hobbes's own time there was to be only one 'favourable' as against fifty-one 'hostile' published reactions to Hobbes's political views.104It is evident, however, that a great deal of information has been missed here. It has not always been recognized, in the first place, that most of Hobbes's critics (apart from the mathematicians) were concerned not so much with his political doctrines as with the allegedly atheistic implications of his determinism.105Only half of the twelve tracts entirely aimed at Hobbes during his own lifetime were even mainly concerned with his political thought.'06 This did not mean that Hobbes's specifically political doctrines were to receive less notice in his own time. It can be shown that Hobbes had important affinities and connexions with other strands of contemporary political debate, and that these were both recognized and sympathetically discussed. It can also be shown that Hobbes came to be cited and accepted within his own lifetime-independently of any close critical study-simply as an authority on matters of political theory, even among writers who might never have read his works, or had read only to confute them. It was his famous attempt to explain political association in terms of man's need to mediate his nasty and brutish nature which was to give Hobbes his
100 Anonymous, A Letter to a Friend (London, I679), p. 6. 101Anonymous, The Great Law of Nature or Self-Preservation Examined (n.p., n.d.) (B.M. Catalogue gives I673), p. 6. 102 John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding (London, I690), Book i, ch. 3, para. 6. 103 John Bramhall, The Catching of Leviathan (London, I658), heading to ch. It, p. 503. 104 S. P. Lamprecht, 'Hobbes and Hobbism', American Political Science Review, xxxiv (I940), 3 1-53, esp. p. 32. 105 A point excellently made in Mintz, op. cit. p. vii, but also passim. 106

See checklistin ibid. pp.

157-60.

298

QUENTIN

SKINNER

immediate place in the accepted canon of writers on political theory. He became labelled as the writer who had thought of deducing the necessary form of the state from the imagined chaos of a 'state of Nature'. Just as Aristotle retained a reputation in the seventeenth century-even among his fashionable denigrators-as the first writer who had emphasized man's natural sociability, so Hobbes gained a reputation as the first writer to reverse this traditional emphasis. The point was often made even by writers who wished to repudiate it, or who wished to leave it an open question (as one writer put it) whether 'as it was said of old' man was 'naturally sociable', or whether 'as a learned modern has said' he is 'compelled into Society merely for the advantages and necessities of life '.107 The clearest evidence of the tendency to link Hobbes's authority with this particular view is provided by the 'whig' writers on allegiance. The greatest of them happened also to be the most cautious in citation, but it was undoubtedly on this point that John Locke came nearest to citing Hobbes in the Two Treatises. The 'some men', it has already been pointed out, whom he attacked in chapter III of the Second Treatise for 'confounding' the state of Nature with a state of war 'can only be the Hobbesists'*108 Other populist writers were more forthcoming. Locke's friend Tyrrell frequently cited Hobbes as the man who believed that if subjects were released from their obligation they would inevitably return to 'a state of Nature, that is (as he supposes) of war'*109 Samuel Mead's defence of the change of allegiance at i688 made the same point."10Shaftesbury even hinted slyly at the valuable lesson which the Hobbesian doctrine might contain. He wanted to 'agree heartily', he claimed, with those writers who had represented human nature, apart from government, 'under monstrous visages of dragons, Leviathans, and I know not what devouring creatures'. If there was a state of Nature, 'let it be a state of war, rapine and injustice', for 'to speak well of it is to render it inviting and tempt men to turn hermits'."1' And Algernon Sydney, the hero among the populist writers, not only cited Hobbes in his Discourses in the same way, but with unequivocal approval. Twice he pointed out that, if the contract between magistrate and people is ever 'extinguished', the inevitable result is a return to 'the condition Hobbes rightly calls bellum omnium contra omnes, wherein no man can promise to himself any other wife, children or goods than he can procure by his own sword '.112 Hobbes's theory about political 'pacts ',113 the views of this 'eminent
Anonymous, Confusion Confounded (London, i654), p. 9. See Locke, op. cit. p. 298 and note to para. I9. 109 James Tyrrell, 'Dialogue Three', Bibliotheca Politica (London, I694), p. I74. Also cites Hobbes, pp. 153, 155-6, I69, i8i. 'I0 Samuel Mead, Oratio pro Populo Anglicano (n.p., I689), sig. B, 3b-4a. "I A. A. Cooper, 3rd earl of Shaftesbury, Characteristics, ed. J. M. Robertson (London,
107

108

vols.,
112

I9OO),

ii,

83.

342.

Algernon Sydney, Discourses Concerning Government (London, 3rd ed., 175i), pp. 43, 113 Anonymous, Vindiciae Juris Regii (London, I689), p. 27.

IDEOLOGICAL

CONTEXT

OF HOBBES

S POLITICAL

THOUGHT

299

philosopher' about man's natural 'state of war',114 his attempt to base 'a scheme of human nature'115 on this supposition, were attitudes which became known to the whole range of contemporary political writers, even though many who cited this view showed no further concern with the deductions Hobbes was concerned to make from these axioms. The dread of anarchy which the view implied was to raise further sympathetic echoes at the time of the Revolution in i688. The dangers pointed out in 'Mr Hobbes's notion of power' were readily reinforced by the enemies of de facto theory. He had already shown the dangers of accepting power as a title to succession 'in making his state of war-for when all is left to strength and power, there is a state of war'*116 The de facto theorists, however, were able to make use of the same warning themselves. Several of them justified the change of allegiance when a prince 'can no longer govern' on the grounds that society would otherwise 'dissolve into a mob, or Mr Hobbes's state of Nature'*117 It is clear that 'Hobbes's state of Nature' was by then a phrase in recognized usage. In I673, for example, Dryden had been attacked on the grounds that he had represented men in one of his plays 'in a Hobbian state of war'.18 By i 694 Lownde assumed that to write of man's natural sociability might be thought absurd, as it differed so much from the views of 'learned persons', among whom he particularly mentioned Hobbes.119 It was undoubtedly this uncritical tendency to associate Hobbes with a particular view about the 'state of Nature' which gave him his widest contemporary reputation. It can also be shown, however, that his political theory was the subject of more genuine critical appraisal. Hobbes can occasionally be found cited as an authority by contemporaries even on details of his political theory-on the nature of political reasoning ;120 on the extent of sovereign power ;121 and especially on the rights of the civil power in ecclesiastical affairs.'22It was chiefly his view of political obligation, however, which caused Hobbes to be treated among contemporary writers as an authority. He was discussed (guardedly, but with some admiration) by some of the most traditionalist theorists of absolutism, with whose views on allegiance Hobbes retained close affinities. He was also discussed (with the closest and most sympathetic attention) by the most radical theorists of defacto rule, amongst whom his treatment of political obligation became an important model.
114 115

Anonymous, The Parallel (London, i682),

p. I2.

Anonymous, Animadversions on a Discourse (London, I69I), p. i6. 116 E.g. Anonymous, The Duty of Allegiance (London, I69I), p. 53. "' William Sherlock, The Case of the Allegiance Due to Sovereign Powzers(London, I69I), p. 38. 118 Anonymous, The Censure the Rota (Oxford, I673), p. 3. of 119 J. Lownde, A Discourse Concerning the Nature of Man (London, I694), sig. A, 5 a and 120 Harrington, 'Politicaster' in Works, p. 559. 6b. 121 Sir William Petty, The Petty Papers, ed. the marquis of Lansdowne (London, 2 vols.,
1927),
122

I, 219.

E.g. Anonymous, A Treatise of Human Reason (London,

I674),

pp. 44-5; Scot, op. cit.

p. 140.

300

QUENTIN

SKINNER

This contemporary acceptance of Hobbes's authority on defacto power has passed almost completely unnoticed. The first of these affinities, howeverwith the traditional absolutists-was widely commented on at the time. One critic even compared Hobbes to Sibthorpe and Manwaring, the two royal chaplains arraigned in the i6zos for preaching that the will of the king was above the law.123Aubrey too mentioned Manwaring (and Wood added Sibthorpe) as a preacher of Hobbism before Hobbes.124 The 'whig' critics of absolutism similarly exploited this affinity between Hobbes and monarchists like De Moulin, Wren, and especially Filmer-a point which has been taken up by several scholars.125 Tyrrell's attack on Filmer included the charge (echoed in Sydney's Discourses)'26 that he had borrowed directly from Hobbes.127 One of Locke's earliest notes about political theory copied out Filmer's words of warm approbation for Hobbes's views on sovereignty. And it was Locke (in one of his notebooks) who was to ask rhetorically, of Samuel Parker's erastianism: 'how far is this short of Mr Hobbes's doctrine?'128 The differences are great, but these critics were arguably correct to see a common tradition between Hobbes and the Patriarchalists. Although the Patriarchal discussion of man's nature was characteristically in scriptural terms, there was a curious parallel even here between their invocation of fallen man and Hobbes's assumption of innate wickedness as a political premiss. These links have even prompted speculation about the influence of Calvinist individualism on Hobbes129as well as the influence of Hobbes on other theorists of absolutism.130 There is a further parallel in the Patriarchal deduction of absolutism from the needs of political society. It has been remarked, indeed, by a great authority, that in a writer like Dudley Digges, with his discussion of men's 'unavoidable occasions of quarrel' in a state of Nature, and their 'prime dictate of nature, the preservation of themselves '131 we 'might be reading a popular abridgment of the Leviathan'.132 The parallels seemed sufficiently close to be uncomfortable to several of the Patriarchalists themselves. Among their works published at the time of the Exclusion Crisis there were several attempts-notably by Mackenzie and Falkner-explicitly to dissociate their views on monarchy from the views of
124 Aubrey, op. cit. I, 334. Whitehall, op. cit. p. 7. in On De Moulin and Hobbes, see P. Zagorin, A History of Political Thzought the English Revolution (London, I954), p. 7i and note; on Wren and Hobbes, see Locke, op. cit. p. 75 n.; on Filmer and Hobbes, see W. Haller, 'Introduction' to Tracts of Liberty in the Puritan Revolution (Columbia, 3 vols., I934), I, 3. 126 Sydney, Works, p. i88. 127 J. Tyrrell, Patriarcha Non Monarcha (i68i), cited in Locke, op. cit. p. 7i n. 128 For Locke on Filmer, see ibid. p. 33. For Locke on Parker, see Maurice Cranston, John Locke, a biography (London, I957), p. I33. 129 Phyllis Doyle, 'The Contemporary Background of Hobbes's 'State of Nature', Economica, vii (I927), 336-55. 130 E.g. G. Lanson, Bossuet (Paris, I89I), pp. I84-28I. 131 Dudley Digges, The Unlazfulness of Subjects TakinzgUp Arms (n.p., i643), p. 3. 132 J. N. Figgis, The Divine Right of Kings (London, 2nd ed., I9I4), p. 239. 123 125

IDEOLOGICAL

CONTEXT

OF HOBBES 'S POLITICAL

THOUGHT

30I

Hobbes.133Ten years before this, Tenison had taken care in his Examination of Hobbes's doctrines to explain away the fact that he had been the subject of 'reproach myself, as a favourer of such opinions'.134 Hobbes's unyielding support for the absolute power of kings, particularly in ecclesiastical matters, was nevertheless a doctrine attractive to many of the most traditional monarchists, a few of whom even acknowledged Hobbes's authority. Bishop Parker wrote of his own account of magistrates' powers that it 'savours not a little of the Leviathan. But how can I avoid it? Are not these my own words? Though that I might deny, yet I am content to confess that I have said something not much unlike them.'135Even Clarendon wrote of Hobbes's discussion about churches in a Christian Commonwealth that it was a 'faultless Chapter', and provided a particularly 'proper' theme 'for his excellent way of reasoning'*136 And the most fulsome tribute to Hobbes's theory of Sovereignty was to come from the most prominent of the Patriarchalists, Sir Robert Filmer himself. He wrote a shrewd critique of Hobbes's account, but prefaced it with the admission that 'with no small content I read Mr Hobbes's book De Cive, and his Leviathan, about the rights of sovereignty; which no man, that I know, hath so amply and judiciously handled '.137 It was amongst the theorists of de facto rule, however, that Hobbes in his own time was to receive the closest and most sympathetic consideration. It was essentially their rationalist and contractarian account of the rights both of subject and sovereign which was on trial at both of the great crises over political obligation in the English Revolution. It was on trial in I649, with the establishment of the Commonwealth's de facto rule after the execution of the king; it was on trial again in I689, with the replacement of James II's de iure power by the rule of the 'Great Deliverers' William and Mary. It can be shown that in both crises many theorists of defacto rule were to make specific use of Hobbes's authority in coming to terms with their new governors. It is the discussion of Hobbes's viewpoint by these writers which provides the most unequivocal though least recognized evidence about both the contemporary popularity and the serious ideological relevance of 'Hobbism' in the political thought of the English Revolution. By the time of the 'Glorious Revolution' most writers on political obligation had grown far too wary or sophisticated to think of trying to support any de facto case by invoking the dangerous reputation of the Commonwealth theorists. They preferred to argue that the new authority was based not on the need to submit but on the citizens' free consent. It was one of their hopes,
133

George Mackenzie, lus Regium (Edinburgh, i684), sig. H, i a; Falkner, op. cit. esp.
I.

PP.

407-I

Tenison, op. cit. sig. A, 2b. 135 Samuel Parker, A Defence and Continuation of the Ecclesiastical Polity (London, i67I), p. 279. 136 Clarendon, op. cit., cited in B. H. G. Wormald, Clarendon (Cambridge, I951), p. 304. 137 Sir Robert Filmer, 'Observations Concerning the Original of Government', Patriarcha and Other Political Works, ed. P. Laslett (Oxfoid, I949), p. 239.
134

302

QUENTIN

SKINNER

indeed, that they could demonstrate the need for submission 'without asserting the principles of Mr Hobbes'*138 Their typical assertion was 'that our Government is now thoroughly settled, and that we who submit to it cannot be charged with Hobbism, since we do not say that any Prince who has quiet possession of the throne can claim our obedience, but only such as are confirmed and settled in it by the determination of our representatives'. 139 One group of writers continued, however, to argue in terms of de facto power. And it is clear that this side of the debate was never far from repeating Hobbes's most characteristic views. The centre of this controversy, at the time of the i688 Revolution, was the 'de facto Tory' dean of St Paul's, William Sherlock, whose Case of Allegiance was written in I69I to justify his decision to take the new oaths of allegiance 'after so long a refusal'.14 Sherlock felt close enough to Hobbes's argument to want to distinguish their points of view with some care. Critics have pointed out, he admitted, 'that it is Hobbism' to argue the rights of defacto powers. 'But those who say this do not understand Mr Hobbes or me. For he makes power and nothing else -to give right to dominion, and therefore asserts that God himself is the natural lord and governor of the World, not because He made it, but because He is omnipotent. But I say that Government is founded in right, and that God is the natural lord of the World because He made it. '141 Other writers on Sherlock's side in the debate felt less scruple about invoking the similarity, and the authority, of Hobbes's treatment of this point. 'It is agreed', as one of them pointed out, 'by the best writers on the subject' that obligations are only conditional where there has been some prior agreement. 'Mr Hobbes indeed saith that those who submit upon compact are capable of no injury afterwards, because they have given up their wills already, and there can be no injury to a willing mind '.142 Another tract of the same year emphasized that 'Hobbes rightly observes' in a case of de facto rule that 'where an external right and dominion is admitted' there is 'no cause why an external obligation which does not touch the conscience may not also be admitted'. 143 Every critic of this group of defacto theorists claimed to see in their remarks a sinister attempt to revive 'Hobbist' principles of political obligation. They attacked not merely the reliance on Hobbes's authority, but also pointed out the links with other de facto theorists from the dark days of the Commonwealth. They might claim, it was said, to be endorsing the principles of the Church of England, but they were in fact taking their arguments 'from the rebels in the year '4z and from the advocates of Cromwell's usurpation'.144 They might claim to be corroborating the Convocation Book's doctrine of
138 Anonymous, Their Present Majesties' Government Proved to be Thoroughly Settled, and that we may Submit to it, without Asserting the Principles of Mr Hobbes (London, I69I). 139 Ibid. p. I5. 140 Sherlock, op. cit. sig. A, i a. 142 141 Ibid. p. I5. Anonymous, A Discourse (London, I689), p. 7. 143 Anonymous, A Full Anszwer(London, I689), p. 36. 144 Anonymous, An Answer to a Late Pamphlet (London, I69I), p. i.

IDEOLOGICAL

CONTEXT

OF HOBBES' S POLITICAL

THOUGHT

303

allegiance, but that work in fact 'did but little service' to them, while 'there were other writings that would have done the trick to an hair, such as Hobbes, Baxter, Owen, Jenkins etc.' 45 Hobbes was still seen as the major influence. Several of the attacks on Sherlock ('The Doctor' to his opponents) tried to establish by close textual comparisons that long before the Doctor's time 'Mr Hobbes had taught the same '.146 'The question', as it was put by one of these writers, 'is whether Mr Hobbes and the Doctor teach not the same doctrine about the legal right and possession of sovereignty, and the transferring of allegiance to usurpers?' And the answer-given after lengthy textual comparisons-was that on the questions of political obligation Hobbes and Sherlock were 'fratres fratrerrimi, and it is not within the power of metaphysics to distinguish them '.47 A similarly detailed textual comparison was provided by another critic who claimed to show that 'Mr Hobbes makes power and nothing else give right to dominion. And pray does not the doctor do the same? I am much mistaken if this be not the design of his whole book . Another less patient critic finally concluded that Hobbes's principles had been surpassed. For, while 'Mr Hobbes taught the absolute power of all Princes only as a philosopher, upon principles of mere reason', these latter-day Hobbists 'by adding the authority of scripture' also make themselves 'sure of a profitable office in the state'.149 The point of major importance is that Hobbes's critics were undoubtedly right in claiming a link between the de facto theorists of the I69os and an earlier group of 'Hobbesian' theorists in the i65os. This earlier group has been almost completely ignored, but it is of the greatest importance for establishing the contemporary reputation and the real ideological purchase of Hobbes's political thought. It can be shown that Hobbes was both cited and discussed in the works of these theorists as their authority on questions about both the grounds and the proper extent of a citizen's obligation to the State. It can also be shown that a reading of Hobbes's political theory among these writers both crystallized and endorsed several of their own political views. It is true that a list of Hobbes's authentic contemporary following would be short and would contain no writer of the front rank. The evidence for establishing such a list, however, can only be unequivocally provided from specific citations and sympathetic discussions of Hobbes's political works. And it must be recognized that such tests-although they provide the only definite means of gauging the acceptance of one particular writer-are not only especially rigorous when applied to the conventions of seventeenthAnonymous, Providence and Precept (London, i69i), pp. 4-5. Anonymous, An Examination [of Sherlock's Case of Allegiance] (London, 169I), p. 14. 147 Ibid. p. I5. p. 73. Parallels 148 Anonymous, Dr Sherlock's Case of Allegiance Considered (London, I691), with Leviathan cited pp. 80-2. 149 Anonymous, Dr Sherlock's Two Kings of Brainford (London, I69I), p. I 3.
146 20 HJ IX 145

304

QUENTIN

SKINNER

century political discussion, but will also tend of themselves substantially to underestimate the evidence. The evidence will tend to be underestimated partly by the fact that Hobbes's political theory did contribute to the attitudes of a larger group. There was thus no reason why such writers themselves should have focused exclusively on the authority of Hobbes. Several of the writers who discussed Hobbes's views were themselves to be treated as authorities on points which were in fact common to them all. It is not uncommon to find writers like Anthony Ascham, Marchamont Nedham, or Lewis de Aloulin cited as authorities on points where an acknowledgment of Hobbes might have served equally well.150 The evidence will tend further to be underestimated by the fact that all the conventions of political debate at the time were against the citation of authorities. The whole trend was towards informality, even anonymity: the failure to recognize the force of this convention has undoubtedly contributed something to the impression of Hobbes's lonely notoriety. Hobbes was not much cited in his own time, but nor was any other political writer: every acknowledgment had come to sound like a lack of originality, a slavish reversion to the typically medieval quest for the endorsement of every view.151 With Hobbes himself it was a famous boast that he had read few works by other His friend Francis Osborne similarly pointed men and had cited even fewer.152 out his own emancipation from the use of authorities, and even suggested a habit of reading sparingly, lest a man become diffident about his own views.153 And to John Selden, another of Hobbes's friends, it was a maxim that 'in quoting of books' one should cite only 'such authors as are usually read. Others you may read for your own satisfaction, but not name them.'154 It seems very likely, moreover, that even among writers who might have been expected to cite Hobbes's authority, the number may have been diminished further by considerations about Hobbes's dangerous reputation. A man who had been named in Parliament as the author of blasphemous and profane works155was not a writer to cite idly or without very necessary reason as an authority on anything. This type of suppression is difficult to prove. But it was regarded at the time as beyond dispute that among those who would 'scarce simper in favour or allowance' for Hobbes there were many who were none the less 'Hobbists' for that.156 It is certainly clear that in
150 E.g. of Ascham cited: Anonymous, A Combat Betzween Two Seconds (London, I649), p. 5; of Nedham: K. Goodwin, Peace Protected (London, I654), p. 75; of de Moulin: M. Hawke, The Right of Dominion (London, I655), p. 136. 151 Cf. R. F. Jones, Ancients and Moderns (St Louis, 2nd ed., 1961), stressing their assumption that 'if servility to the authority of the ancients precluded examination of traditional beliefs, no hope could be held out for increased knowledge', p. i I9. 152 Aubrey, op. cit. I, 349. 153 Francis Osborne, 'Conjectural Paradoxes', Works (London, gth ed., I689), pp. 538 and 548. 154 John Selden, Table Talk, ed. Sir Frederick Pollock (London, 1927), p. 24. 155 The Yournals of the House of Commons (n.p., n.d.), vol. viii, I660-I667, p. 636. 156 Eachard, SomzeOpinions, sig. A, 4b.

IDEOLOGICAL

CONTEXT

OF HOBBES

S POLITICAL

THOUGHT

305

seventeenth-century England there were political opinions which men might believe, even discuss, but much prefer not to see printed. Hobbes himself was thought to have acted too boldly in publishing views which 'though he believed them to be true' were none the less 'too dangerous to be spoken aloud . And there are certainly signs that a man who sympathized with Hobbes's views was better able to say so in private than in any published form. 'Hobbism' is anatomized without any sort of comment only in private commonplace books.158And Sir William Petty provides at least one further example of a contemporary writer on politics who commended Hobbes, in his private memoranda, as the leading authority on political theory, yet never once cited Hobbes in his own published works.159 When such considerations about the conditions as well as the conventions of discussion are given some weight, it becomes by no means necessarily tendentious to add that there may have been more silent reliance on Hobbes than there was citation of his works among contemporaries. The typically 'Hobbesian' premiss, for example, that political society must be based on man's mediation of a basically anti-social psychology, can also be found expressed in very similar language in many of the 'Engagement' tracts of i 650,160 in several discussions of the need for absolute power published under the Commonwealth,16' as well as in 'Hobbist' writers like Francis Osborne,'62 Thomas White,'63 and Matthew Wren.164 The typically 'Hobbesian' deduction, similarly, that this establishes a reciprocal relation between obligations to protest and to obey, can be found expressed in identical language in dozens of the tracts on allegiance written in the i650s.165 The fact that only a small group of writers acknowledged and avowedly followed the authority of Hobbes does not exclude the possibility of a wider influence. The crucial point, however, is that within these 'Hobbesian' groups there were several writers who did not stop short of an acknowledgment of Hobbes, both in their approach and in their theories of political obligation.
Thomas Pierce, 'ATTOKATAKPIXIE (London, i658), sig. *, 3b-4a. E.g. commonplace book entries 'Mr Hobbes's Creed' and 'The Principles of Mr Hobbes' in British Museum, Sloane MSS 904 and 1458. 1'9 See Petty Papers, II, 5. Cf. Sir William Petty, The Economic Writings, ed. C. H. Hull (Cambridge, 2 vols., 1899). 160 E.g. in T.B., The Engagement Vindicated (London, I650), pp. 5-6; in John Dury, Considerations Concerning the Present Engagement (London, 4th ed., 'enlarged', I650), pp. 13-14; and in Anonymous, A Disengaged Survey of the Engagement (London, I650), p. 20. 161 E.g. in Anonymous, Confusion Confounded, p. 9; in John Hall, Of Government and Obedience (London, I654), pp. 13-14 and 98. (N.B. that this John Hall differs from the John Hall of Durham (i627-56) cited in note 177, below.) 162 Francis Osborne, A Persuasive to a Mutual Compliance (London, I652), p. II. 163 Thomas White, The Grounds of Obedience and Government (London, i655), pp. 44-5. 164 Matthew Wren, Monarchy Asserted (London, I659), pp. 49-50. 165 E.g., Samuel Eaton, The Oath of Allegiance (London, i650), p. 8; Anonymous, Conscience Puzzled (London, I650), p. 7; J. Drew, The Northern Subscribers' Plea Vindicated (London, I653), p. 23; E. Elcock, Animadversions (London, i65I), p. 47; Anonymous, The Bounds and Bonds of Public Obedience (London, I649), p. 26; N.W., A Discourse Concerning the Engagement (London, i650), p. II.
158 157

20-2

306

QUENTIN

SKINNER

The best general statement of Hobbes's method and principles, against which the views of these 'Hobbists' may be compared, is contained in the preface 'To the Reader' of De Cive. Hobbes's essential concern, as he set it out there, was to 'demonstrate' the necessary form of the state, and the citizen's obligation to it, as a deduction from the known nature of human nature. The revolutionary 'principle' of Hobbes's political theory was thus-in direct opposition to the traditional picture of man as a political animal-the famous doctrine 'that the dispositions are naturally such, that except they be restrained through fear of some coercive power, every man will distrust and dread each other, and as by natural right he may, so by necessity he will be forced to make use of the strength he hath, toward the preservation of himself'.166Hobbes's first 'demonstration' was thus 'that the state of men without civil society (which state we may properly call the state of nature) is nothing else but a mere war of all against all; and in that war all men have equal right unto all things'*167 This was the view of man treated as axiomatic by Hobbes and his followers, as much as it was denounced by their clerical enemies. It was equally an axiom, for example, of the work published in I655 on The Right of Dominion that 'Dominion was first procured by arms '.168 'Everyone in a state of nature', the argument ran, 'hath a right to dominion, and conquest only puts him in possession.' And from this point, as the author added, 'I conceive Mr Hobbes might collect that the right of nature is a condition of war of every one against every one, and right of every man to every thing, even to another's body'. For, as he more picturesquely went on, every man in the state of Nature gained just as much 'as by force and strength through wounds and slaughters they could obtain or retain'.169 It was again an axiom in Killing is Murder, published two years later, that 'the natural state of man, before they were settled in a Society, as Master Hobbes truly saith, was a

mere warX170
The second 'demonstration' which Hobbes set out was that, as the basic law of man's nature made self-preservation his paramount aim, so 'all men as soon as they arrive to understanding of this hateful condition of universal war then desire (even nature itself compelling them) to be freed from this misery'."7' The laws of men's nature are thus said to make it possible for man to mediate his own natural condition. Each of these claims was to be similarly taken up and developed by other de facto theorists. As 'Mr Hobbes, Philos. Rudiments' has pointed out, 'it is the law of nature that men live peaceably, that they may tend the preservation of their lives, which whilst they are in war they cannot '.172 For this reason, as 'Mr Hobbes, Phil. Rud.' also pointed out,
166 167
169

Thomas Hobbes, De Cive, ed. S. P. Lamprecht (New York, I949), p. II. Ibid. p. I3. 168 Hawke, The Right of Dominion, ch.
Ibid. ch. IV, p.
32;

VII,

p.

4I.

ch.

VII,

p. 43.

Michael Hawke, Killing is Murder and No Murder (London, I657), p. 7. On Hawke, see also F. Raab, The English Face of Machiavelli (London, I694), p. 141. 171 Hobbes, De Cive, p. 13. 172 Hawke, Right of Dominion, P. 27.

170

IDEOLOGICAL

CONTEXT

OF HOBBES

S POLITICAL

THOUGHT

307

it is possible to regard 'human nature itself' as 'the mother of the natural law .173 The way that 'Mr Hobbes doth thus describe the laws of nature' was similarly treated as authoritative in The Idea of the Law, in which Hobbes's own account was extensively quoted.174 And The Right of Dominion similarly used Hobbes's account again to make the point that 'every one hath sufficient power to rein and moderate his outward demeanour, that he commit no outward or civil act repugnant to the law of nature. And in this sense is Mr Hobbes's saying true, that the law of nature is easily kept. '175 Hobbes's central 'demonstration' was that, although men's absolute selfseeking could be mediated 'by compact', it could only be adequately mediated by a compact which set up an absolute, preferably monarchical, power. For 'except they do so' there will 'evidently appear to be no civil government, but the rights which all men have to all things, that is the rights of war, will remain *176 The only possible shortcoming of this account which Hobbes conceded was the difficulty of 'demonstrating' that the form of this government had to be monarchical. The point was to be taken up by John Hall, the very 'Hobbesian' author of The Groundsand Reasons of Monarchy Considered. Like Hobbes, he claimed that he would 'rather be sceptical in my opinion, than maintain it upon grounds taken up and not demonstrated '.177 And, like Hobbes, he admitted that any attempt to demonstrate the 'intrinsic value and expediency' of monarchy 'is a business so ticklish, that even Mr Hobbes in his De Cive, though he assured himself that the rest of his book (which is principally erected to the assertion of Monarchy) is demonstrated, yet he doubts whether the arguments which he brings to this business be so firm or no '.78 This whole discussion, moreover, was to be reprinted by John Toland as the opening tract in his edition of Harrington's Works.179 Hobbes remained certain, however, that his basic contention about the relation between self-preservation and political obligation was completely demonstrated. The same confidence was again echoed by other theorists of de facto rule. It was recognized, in the first place, to mean that the possession of power itself established a title to be obeyed: as the aim of subscribing to government was self-preservation, so this presupposed an obligation to obey any power with the capacity to protect. It is a corollary, 'as Master Hobbes saith', that 'a sure and irresistable power confers the right of dominion and ruling over those who cannot resist '.180 It was thus demonstrated that 'by the law of war, whatsoever the victor obtaineth is his right: ius est in armis, andas Mr Hobbes-a sure and irresistable power conferreth the right of domin173 1'74 175

Ibid. p.

29.

John Heydon, The Idea of the Law (London, i66o), pp. 124-5. 176 Hobbes, De Cive, p. I3. Hawke, Right of Dominion, p. 25. 177 John Hall, The Grounds and Reasons of Monarchy Considered (Edinburgh, znd ed., I650), sig. A, 4a-b. 178 Ibid. p. 50. 179 James Harrington, Works, ed. J. Toland (London, I77I), p. 13. 180 Hawke, Killing is Murder, p. 12.

308

QUENTIN

SKINNER

ion' 181 Such power, moreover, had to be obeyed in all things, spiritual as well as temporal. The view, as it was agreed, 'that Holy Scriptures are to be understood according to each man's small use of reason' is one which 'Mr Hobbes very well confutes'*182 It was recognized by these 'Hobbists', in the second place, that the notion of a mutual relation between protection and obedience circumscribed as well as defined the limits of a citizen's obligations. If obligation is due to power, such obligation must cease where the power itself fails. Hobbes, it was said, rightly pointed out not only that 'power of coercion, of the sword, and consequently of life, is transferred from the people to the magistrate'; he also recognized-as do all 'rational men '-the sense in which this means that 'the power of life is derived to the magistrate from the consent and vote of the people'. And here the reader is referred to 'Hobbes, de Corp. Polit.'183 It would be a mistake to suppose that political obligation is created by natural laws of themselves, which cannot 'actually and formally oblige a creature, till it be made known'. It might seem that obligations in society are based on a 'natural law', in cases 'as Mr Hobbes describes' when people 'bind themselves by general compact to the observation of such laws as they judge to be for the good of them all'.184 But this would be to mistake the role of law. For 'before all this can rise to the height and perfection of a law, there must come a command from superior powers, whence from will spring a moral obligation also, and make up the formality of a law'.185 There was some contemporary endorsement of Hobbes's political doctrine at each of its most characteristic points. There is also another and even more revealing way, however, in which the contemporary ideological relevance of Hobbes's political views can be proved. Hobbes was not only discussed by other writers as a means of crystallizing their own political stance. He was also cited as an authority by a group of contemporary writers whose political views were extremely similar to Hobbes's most characteristic doctrines, but who can be shown to have arrived at these conclusions independently of studying Hobbes's own works. Hobbes was cited not as the source of their opinions, but rather to corroborate views they already held. They provide the clearest evidence that Hobbes's political theory was not a completely isolated phenomenon, but to some extent a contribution to a particular climate of opinion. The most important of these writers was undoubtedly Anthony Ascham, who deserves to be much better known. In I648 he published A Discourse, concerned (in the words of its own sub-title) with What is particularly lawful during the confusions and revolutions of governments. Ascham's point of departure, in his preface, was with the strong and Hobbesian fear that anarchy was the sole alternative as well as the ever-present threat to any given political
181 183

184

Hawke, Right of Dominion, p. 50. 182 Scot, Op. cit. p. I40. 'Euitactus Philodemius', An Anszwerto the Vindication (London, I650), pp. 15-I6.

Heydon, op. cit.

pp. I09,

I50-I.

185

Ibid. p.

I37.

IDEOLOGICAL

CONTEXT

OF HOBBES

S POLITICAL

THOUGHT

309

order. His equally Hobbesian conclusion was thus that the will of a power 'absolute without redress or appeal', and the virtues of passive obedience, provided the sole means of escape from the mutability of all things.186Part i of the book argued for this conclusion from very Hobbesian claims about the 'natural' laws of men's conduct in their basic and original social situation. The sole but essential right of men in such a condition was taken to be the right of self-preservation. This led first to a history, in chapter III, of 'first possessors', who could 'without scruple of doing other wrong, place their bodies where they would'.187 This discussion was then modified, in chapter IV,by positing a situation of extreme need, in which men would have to revert to a more communal system. The two points together suggested the whole of Ascham's thesis. On the one hand, there are no natural political rights, for 'possession therefore is the greatest title '.188 Appropriation has, ever since primitive times, served as a sufficient basis for political society. On the other hand, even rights of possession cannot be absolute. Any legal right automatically loses priority, in time of emergency, to the basic Hobbesian right to life. The presumption of the whole account was that necessity itself provided the only viable guide to political right. For, as in Leviathan, "tis necessity itself which makes laws, and by consequence ought to be the interpreter of them after they are made'.189 This strongly Hobbesian sense of the necessities laid on men by their own nature and condition lies at the centre of Ascham's whole outlook. The argument recurs, most revealingly and in a totally different context, in the only other work which it seems certain that Ascham wrote, the tract of I647 Of Marriage. Marriage was treated by Ascham as an example of a contract which there could never be a sufficient reason for voiding. A man in engaging marriage is said to will a situation which seems strongly parallel to the acceptance of an absolute political obligation. 'He is no longer himself, and makes use of his liberty but once, to lose it for ever after all his life.'190Ascham was thus drawn again into characterizing the nature of rational behaviour in such unalterable circumstances. The characteristic of wisdom is to recognize that the situation itself dictates the appropriate behaviour: 'the wise man is called the artificer of his own happiness, because he adjusts his desires to the
186 Anthony Ascham, A Discourse (London, I648), p. 37. To maintain uniformity of citation all pagination refers to the enlarged second edition (London, I649). See note 194, below. For further references to Ascham and to discussions of his work, see my article 'History and Ideology in the English Revolution', The Historical yournal, viii (I965), I55-78, esp. p. 163 and note. 187 Ascham, op. cit. p. 6. 188 Ibid. p. 6. 189 Ibid. p. Io. 190 Anthony Ascham, MS Tract on Marriage (56 fos., I647), ch. I, fo. i. Never published, and apparently unknown to Ascham's commentators. See Cambridge University Library MSS., MS. Gg, I, 4, Tracts MS. fo. xxvi ff. separately paginated as fos. I-56, bound up with MS. of P. Tomkinson, A Description of the City of Rome. Title-page gives five chapterheadings, beginning 'Of marriage in general', date, and ascription 'By Mr Askham, that was afterwards killed in Spain being agent for the parliament of England there'.

310

QUENTIN

SKINNER

necessity of events, and moves cheerfully through that way through which he
would otherwise be sullenly dragged'.191

Part I of Ascham's Discoursethus treated in a political context the same issue that he had already discussed in a familial context in the tract Of Marriage. Part II of the Discourse went on to develop from this point a totally Hobbesian political conclusion about the 'mutual relations between protection and obedience' as the grounds of obligation. The specific issue which Ascham went on to engage was the extent to which a man might properly take oaths and pay allegiance to a usurped power. Ascham showed complete and deliberate disregard here for any questions about either the rightful origins or the best forms of government. The only question, as with Hobbes, was whether the possessors of governmental power can sustain the lives of their subjects in a successful political order. If they fail in this, then the citizen's loyalties are at an end, while he endeavours instead to protect himself. As 'nature commends me to myself for my own protection and preservation', so 'he who hath sworn allegiance and fidelity to his Prince, is absolved and set at liberty, if his Prince abandon his kingdom'*192 But, if the government does manage to sustain order, then the citizen's duty can only be to obey, regardless of any judgments that could be made about the legality of the government's powers. Throughout the argument the sole touchstone is necessity: as the last chapter concluded, citizens are bound to obey governments 'so long as it pleases God to give them the Power to command us'.193 The language as well as the assumptions throughout Ascham's work are of a strongly Hobbesian character. Hobbes is never mentioned, however, his authority is never invoked, and there is no evidence that Ascham had at this time read De Cive, Hobbes's only published political work. In I649, however, Ascham re-issued his book in a second edition, its length augmented by nine chapters, its title changed to Of the Confusions and Revolutions of Governments.194 Ascham now reverted (at the end of part II) to his earlier discussion about the 'natural' state and character of men. Here he not only expanded and corroborated his earlier account; he now justified it further by invoking the authority of Hobbes. Ascham first added a justification of his views about political obligation by considering the origins of magistracy and civil government in the state of Nature. He now deduced the obligation of the citizen to obey any power capable of offering him protection from the typically Hobbesian assumption that without such protection no society at all would be possible. Liberty from all government would be 'a great prejudice to us; for
Ascham, On Marriage, ch. IV, fo. 36. Ascham, Discourse, pp. 2i and 39. 193 Ascham, Discourse, p. 45. The affinities with Hobbes seemed unquestionable to contemporaries. Filmer, for example, discussed Hobbes's doctrines not in isolation but as the views of 'Mr Hobbes, Mr Ascham; and others of that party'. See Filmer, op. cit. p. 231, and cf. p. i88. 194 Anthony Ascham, Of the Confusions and Revolutions of Goverments (sic, in original, London, I649), part II, additions at pp. 85-95, 104-8.
192 191

IDEOLOGICAL

CONTEXT

OF HOBBES

S POLITICAL

THOUGHT

3I1

hereby we were clearly left in a state of war, to make good this natural free state of the world, which referred all to the trial of force and not of law, against which no one could offend'. Complete subjection to power was the only solution, for (as Ascham now conceded) 'Mr Hobbes his supposition (if there be two omnipotents, neither could be obliged to obey the other) is very pertinent and conclusive to this subject '.195 Ascham finally added a further justification of his views about the relative obligations of protection and obedience. He repeated his view that change of allegiance is automatically permitted by failure of government. But he now called in two greater authorities to corroborate the point. The change is justified whenever '(as Grotius and Mr Hobbes say) there be a dereliction of command in the person of whom we speak, or if the country be so subdued that the conquerors can no longer be resisted '.196 A similar use of Hobbes's authority to corroborate an already completed political argument can be found in the writings of Marchamont Nedham. So close indeed was Hobbes's theory of obligation to the account which Nedham and the other defacto theorists used to justify the rule of the Commonwealth that in the pages of Mercurius Politicus, the official newspaper which Nedham edited,197 Hobbes's doctrines were to attain the rather invidious status of official propaganda for the Republic of England. Twice during I65I the serious editorials which always prefaced Nedham's news-sheet consisted simply of unsigned extracts from Hobbes's De CorporePolitico. The first was a long quotation from Hobbes's characteristic discussion of the citizen's obligation to obey any power with the capacity to protect him.198 The second set out Hobbes's insistence on the congruence of the civil authority's commands with God's purposes.199And twice apart from this Hobbes was to be advertised in Nedham's paper as an authority on political science.200 Nedham was to show in his own writing as well as in his journalism how much his opinions could be sustained by the authority of Hobbes. This can best be seen in The Case of the CommonwealthStated, which Nedham published in I650. Its aim was to prove in general (in part i) the 'necessity and equity' of submission to powers that be; and to vindicate in particular (in part II) the authority of the new Commonwealth government. The central contention in Nedham's as in Ascham's work was the Hobbesian claim that the basis of all government must lie in men's absolute need to protect themselves and their interests by a submission of will. Some kind of government is at all times an absolute necessity as the only alternative to anarchy. In part II of his book Nedham used this claim to denounce all changes proposed by
196 Ibid. p. "i9. Ibid. ch. ix, p. io8. On Nedham, particularly as editor, see J. Frank, The Beginnings of the English Newspaper (Cambridge, Mass., I96I), p. 2o6. 198 Editorial to Mercurius Politicus, no. 31 (2-9 January i651). 199 Ibid. no. 34 (23-30 January I65I). 200 Mercurius Politicus, no. 29 (I9-26 December i650), p. 486, and no. 352 (5-I2 March 1657), p. 7641. See also Frank, op. cit. p. 257. 195 197

312

QUENTIN

SKINNER

Royalists, by Levellers, and by all other enemies of the English Republic. In the central chapter of part I it is simply stated as axiomatic that, 'there being a necessity of some government at all times, for the maintenance of civil conversation, and to avoid confusion, therefore such as will not submit, because they cannot have such a government as themselves like, are in some sense mere anarchists'.201 Nedham is thus led, like Ascham, to the bleak and typically Hobbesian conclusion that, as government is an absolute necessity, so obedience must be absolutely given to whatever government is in fact capable of sustaining successful political order. Nedham has no doubts about the principle of allegiance moving with events. The wheel of fortune, as the opening chapter is devoted to showing, turns in an unpredictable but irrevocable manner. Once it has turned against a particular state, its citizens are merely building 'castles in the air against fatal necessity' if they then go on insisting on 'a fantasy of pretended loyalty'.2O2 There is no question, moreover, of insisting on allegiance to a rightful rather than a usurped power. Nedham endorsed his Hobbesian conclusions by refusing to accept that there is any such distinction to be made. He insisted, in chapter ii, that there never has been an ancient or a modern state capable of surviving an examination of its original 'right' to rule. All governments originally had 'no other dependence than upon the sword .203 The only possible rule of obligation is thus to recognize and submit to the necessity of power itself. As in the case of Ascham's work, this Hobbesian defence of defacto power was completed without reference to Hobbes. But, as with Ascham, the authority of Hobbes was subsequently used to corroborate the view. When his book reached a second edition in I650 Nedham added an appendix, explaining that 'nothwithstanding that I have already.. . sufficiently proved' its claims, yet 'I thought meet to fasten them more surely upon the reader' by 'inserting some additions' from Salmasius and 'out of Mr Hobbes his late book De CorporePolitico '.204 The last five pages of the appendix accordingly reprinted extracts from Hobbes's discussion at both the points critical to Nedham's own argument. 'It may plainly be inferred' from Hobbes's discussion that there can be 'no security for life, limbs and liberty' except 'by relinquishing our right of self-protection'.2O5 It may also be inferred from what 'Mr Hobbes saith' that 'since there is no other possible way to preserve the well-being of the Nation' except 'by a submission to the present power', it is entirely justifiable-as he had already claimed-'to pay subjection to them in order to our own security'.206
201 Marchamont Nedham, The Case of the Commonwealth Stated (London, I650), p. I7. As with Ascham, to maintain uniformity of citation, all pagination refers to the enlarged 202 Nedham, op. cit. p. 5. second edition (London, I650). See note 204 below. 203 Ibid. p. 9. 204 Ibid. 2nd ed., with appendix (London, i650), p. I03. 205 Ibid. p. 0og. 206 Ibid. pp. IO8-9.

IDEOLOGICAL

CONTEXT

OF HOBBES

S POLITICAL

THOUGHT

313

This attempt to suggest the appropriate ideological context for Hobbes's political doctrines-to show his contemporary following, his recognition abroad, and the fears of his opponents at his popularity-is an investigation which can be shown to carry analytical as well as historical implications for the student of political thought. To add this historical background is in effect to add a new test of plausibility for any suggested interpretation of Hobbes's political theory. It can no longer be assumed that the 'question of what his theory is' can properly be regarded as 'prior' to and separate207 from the question of its intellectual relations. Any interpretation must imply some links between Hobbes's viewpoint and the views of his contemporaries. It can now be made a condition for accepting any suggested interpretation that these links must themselves be of an historically possible and credible kind. In this way the historical study of Hobbes's intellectual milieu can be used to help assess the philosophers' various interpretations of Hobbes's meaning. The fashionable trend in the interpretation of Hobbes has been to increase the emphasis on his links with a more traditional political outlook. Hobbes's theory of obligation, on this interpretation of his intentions, is detached from its apparently 'scientific' psychological premisses, and grounded instead on a traditional doctrine of Natural Law. In the most persuasive of these expositions Hobbes's discussion is completely reformulated in the language of a theory of duty. A subject is then said to be obliged, not by any considerations of self-interest, but by his acknowledgment of a prior duty to obey the laws of Nature, in virtue of recognizing them to be the commands of God. Hobbes is thus regarded as 'essentially a natural law philosopher', believing that 'the laws of nature are eternal and unchangeable and, as the commands of God, they oblige all men who reason properly, and so arrive at a belief in an omnipotent being whose subjects they are '.208 In the most extreme presentation of this interpretation it has even been suggested that there is a dichotomy in Hobbes's account between an 'artificial' and a 'real' system of obligation, not resolved until Hobbes 'goes behind his philosophic fiction of command without a commander to the reality from which the fiction was derived, when he says that the second law of nature is the law of the Gospel '.209 The essential contention which all such interpretations have in common can be summarized in the words of the first writer who suggested this view of Hobbes's doctrine. Hobbes, we have to assume, 'meant quite seriously what he so often says, that the "natural law" is the command of God, and to be obeyed because it is God's command'.210 It is not intended to ask directly whether this interpretation of Hobbes's views on obligation offers the best account of his meaning. The relations, however, between Hobbes's views and the age which produced them is an
H. Warrender, The Political Philosophy of Hobbes (Oxford, I957), p. ix. Ibid. p. 322. 209 F. C. Hood, The Divine Politics of Thomas Hobbes (Oxford, I964), p. 97. 10 A. E. Taylor, 'The Ethical Doctrine of Hobbes', Philosophzy,XIII (I938), p. 4I8.
207 208

314

QUENTIN

SKINNER

investigation which can now be shown to bear on this point far more closely than has been supposed. For the view of Hobbes's intellectual relations implied by any such deontological interpretation, it can now be shown, would be historically incredible. The weight of this evidence is perhaps sufficient in itself for any such interpretation to stand discredited.211 If Hobbes intended to ground political obligation on a prior obligation to obey the commands of God, it follows, first, that every contemporary-every follower, opponent, sympathizer-all equally missed the point of his political doctrine. All of them, moreover (a remarkable chance) were mistaken in exactly the same way. For it was Hobbes's theory of obligation which most interested his critics as well as his followers, and all were agreed about the type of theory he was thought to have put forward. All his followers, it has been shown, were concerned to emphasize the obligation to obey any successfully constituted political power. All of them cited Hobbes as the authority who had demonstrated that the grounds and the necessity of this obligation lay in man's pre-eminent desire for self-preservation. This was also the popularly received impression of Hobbes's intentions. In one of the contemporary commonplace books in which 'Mr Hobbes's Creed' is anatomized, he is summarized as having taught 'That the prime law of nature in the soul of man is that of temporal self-love', and 'That the law of the civil sovereign is the only obliging rule of just and unjust'.212 Another put it more tersely as the view that 'whatever the civil magistrate commands is to be obeyed notwithstanding contrary to Divine Moral Law'.213 And when Daniel Scargill, the muchdiscussed 'penitent Hobbist,' recanted his 'Hobbist' views before the University of Cambridge in I669, the views which both he and they regarded as pre-eminently 'Hobbesian' were that 'all right of dominion is founded only in power' and that 'all moral righteousness is founded only in the positive law of the civil magistrate .214 These assumptions about Hobbes's doctrine were also shared by all Hobbes's contemporary critics. These writers were themselves Christian moralists, who might have been expected to be particularly attuned to seeing any similar overtones in Hobbes's works. Most of them, however, went out of their way to emphasize instead what Clarendon called Hobbes's 'thorough novelty'.215 They found in Hobbes no element of traditionalism: they saw him as a complete iconoclast who (as Bramhall put it) 'taketh a pride in removing all ancient land-marks, between Prince and subject, father and child, husband and wife, master and servant, man and man'.216 All of them agreed, moreover, on the
211 The following section attempts to document a suggestion originally made at the end of my article 'Hobbes's Leviathan', The HistoricalyJournal, vii (I964), 32I-33. 212 British Museum, Sloane MSS., no. I458, fo. 35. 213 Ibid. no. 904, fo. I4. 214 See James L. Axtell, 'The Mechanics of Opposition: Restoration Cambridge v. Daniel Scargill', Bulletin of the Institute of Historical Research, XXXVIII (I965), I02-I i and refs. there. 215 Clarendon, op. cit. sig. A, i b. 216 Bramhall, op. cit. p. 542.

IDEOLOGICAL

CONTEXT

OF HOBBES

S POLITICAL

THOUGHT

315

form which Hobbes's iconoclasm took. They associated Hobbes with two particular political doctrines, both of which (as Clarendon remarked) would 'overthrow or undermine all those principles of Government which have preserved the peace of this Kingdom through so many ages '.217 They assumed, first, that as Hobbes grounded political obligation on calculations of rational self-interest, so he believed that a man became absolutely obliged to obey any government that could protect him. Hobbes's point of departure, in the eyes of all his critics, was not with the obligations of natural law but with the fears of natural man. When the University of Oxford issued its famous condemnation of heterodox books in I683, Hobbes was mentioned and denounced by name as the writer who had invented the claim that 'self-preservation is the fundamental law of nature and supersedes the obligation of all others'.218 It was a view shared by all the rest of Hobbes's critics. Hobbes had taught that there was a 'right of nature' in every man ;219 that society can only 'arise from necessity and fear'220 upon 'the principles of equality and self-preservation '.221 The obligation which Hobbes describiedwas thus sustained not by congruence with any natural law, but by power itself. 'With this author', as Lawson put it, 'every Monarch is absolute.'222Hobbes may have insisted on 'Covenant and Oath' in the generation of his Leviathans, but 'the obligation is in vain, because the people cannot force them to the observation thereof'.223 And Clarendon agreed that 'Mr Hobbes hath erected such a sovereign and instituted such a people that the one may say and do whatever he finds convenient for his purpose, and the other must neither say or do any thing that may displease him .'224 The whole set of assumptions about Hobbes was best summed up, however, by one of his followers. 'Mr Hobbes', he claimed, believed 'that by nature all things are common, and the grounds of a distinct propriety, and of a Meum and Tuum, is not from nature but from the pact and consent of man, who is forced thereto by a kind of necessity for prevention of those evils, which would necessarily be the consequents of having all things common '.225 All the critics assumed, in the second place, that as Hobbes had made obligation depend on protection, so he had intended to add that when a subject was not adequately protected his obligation must cease. HIobbes intended no less, as Clarendon put it, than to give subjects 'leave to withdraw their obedience' from their ruler at the time 'when he hath most need of their assistance'.226 The critics agreed in seeing in this view the final proof that Hobbes had abandoned any belief in 'the obligation laid on us by fidelity (the law of God
Clarendon, op. cit. sig. A, 3b. 'Judgment ... of the University', given in D. Wilkins, Conciliae Magnae Britannicae et Hiberniae (4 vols., London, I737), Iv, 6Io-I2. 219 Filmer, op. cit. p. 242. 220 Philip Warwick, A Discourse of Government (London, i694), p. 55. 221 222 Anonymous, Great Law of Nature, p. 8. Lawson, op. cit. p. I7. 223 Ibid. p. 23. 224 Clarendon, op. cit. p. II5. 225 'Eutactus Philodemius', The Original and End of Civil Power (London, I649), p. I5. 226 Clarendon, op. cit. p. 90.
217 218

316

QUENTIN

SKINNER

Almighty in our nature) antecedent to all humane covenants '.227 He had instead made 'Civil laws the rules of good and evil'*228 So far from seeing in Hobbes any traditional elements of natural law doctrine, they regarded his utilitarian account of political obligation as the most dangerous attack on it. 'Where these principles prevail', as Bramhall almost despairingly concluded, 'adieu honour and honesty and fidelity and loyalty: all must give place to selfinterest.'229

Some modern commentators have taken the heroic course of denying that any of this contemporary evidence matters, on the grounds that 'any modern reader can see the general irrelevance' of Hobbes's critics.230But to concede this point would only be to complete the paradox, and to make the entire intellectual milieu impossible to understand. Hobbes himself is turned into the most incredible figure of all. He must be represented as presenting a traditional type of natural law theory of politics in a manner so convoluted that it was everywhere taken for the work of a complete utilitarian, a political calculator prepared (in Bramhall's memorable phrase) to 'take his sovereign for better but not for worse '.231 And despite Hobbes's own predilection for the quiet life, his terror at being arraigned for heterodoxy,232 he never once attempted either to disown the alarmingly radical writers who cited his authority, or to disarm his innumerable critics by pointing out their misconception of his intentions. In Hobbes's only known reply to a critic of his views on obligation it is clear that the issue for both of them was still the pre-eminent place that Hobbes had allowed to self-interest.233 The followers and the critics are turned into scarcely less incredible figures. It becomes impossible to understand why Hobbes's opponents should have felt so threatened. A more careful reading (we are assured) would have shown them that there was 'nothing that is original in Hobbes's moral thought'.234 A reading of any of the authors who cited Hobbes, however, would have revealed the same dangerous principles which they claimed to find in Hobbes. And yet it was Hobbes, and not these seemingly much more radical followers, on whom they continued to focus their attacks. In the same way it becomes impossible to understand why any of Hobbes's avowed followers should have taken such trouble to cite his authority. All of them had worked out a political outlook more radical than any exponent of Natural Law doctrines could ever attain or endorse. All of them (we are assured) had in any case completely misunderstood the intentions of the writer whom they gave as their most radical authority. It becomes clear, in short, that to accept a deontological
227 229 230

Tenison, op. cit. p. I47. 228 Anonymous, An Examination, p. I5. Bramhall, op. cit. p. 5I9. K. C. Brown, 'Hobbes's Grounds for Belief in a Deity', Philosophy, XXXVII (i962),

232 On this see Aubrey, op. cit. I, 339. Bramhall, op. cit. p. 519. I have published this reply and discussed it in my article 'Hobbes on Sovereignty: An Unknown Discussion', Political Studies, xiii (I965), 2I3-I8. 234 H-lood,op. cit. p. I3. 231 233

337 n.

IDEOLOGICAL

CONTEXT

OF HOBBES

S POLITICAL

THOUGHT

3I7

interpretation of Hobbes's views is to remove any meaningful points of contact between Hobbes and his own intellectual milieu. It has been intended in this study to emphasize a link, commonly ignored or even denied, between the activities of philosophers and historians. An attempt has been made to elucidate the ideological context of one classic setof texts, and to construct around them the framework of their appropriate intellectual milieu. The implication has been that where such a framework is lacking the classic text itseif may be 'understood' by philosophers in ways that are historically absurd. The aim has been to show that the historian's task of understanding climates of opinion is not disconnected from the philosopher's attempts to interpret texts.235It is still for the historian to point out that even the philosopher's most plausible interpretation must still be tested, and might even have to be abandoned, in the light of historical evidence.236
235 This essay is thus intended to supply a particular case-history for a more general theory about methods of trying to understand the history of ideas. I have tried to set out the theory itself in more abstract terms in my article ?The Limits of Historical Explanations', Philosophy, XLI (I966), I99-2I5. 236 This essay owes a great deal to correspondence with Professor J. G. A. Pocock and Professor J. M. Wallace, and to discussions with Mr Peter Laslett and Mr John Dunn, to whom I am indebted not only for reading various drafts but also for correcting mistakes and helping with several references.

S-ar putea să vă placă și