Sunteți pe pagina 1din 57

PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE:

Bayesian inference
Thomas Bayes 1702-1761

Zoltn Dienes

Subjective probability: Personal conviction in an opinion to which a number is assigned that obeys the axioms of probability.

Probabilities reside in the mind of the individual not the external world. Your subjective probability/conviction in a proposition is just up to you
but you must revise your probability in the light of data in ways consistent with the axioms of probability.

Personal probabilities:

Which of the following alternatives would you prefer? If your choice turns out to be true I will pay you 10 pounds:

1. It will rain tomorrow in Brighton 2. I have a bag with one blue chip and one red chip. I randomly pull out one chip and it is red.

Personal probabilities:

Which of the following alternatives would you prefer? If your choice turns out to be true I will pay you 10 pounds:

1. It will rain tomorrow in Brighton 2. I have a bag with one blue chip and one red chip. I randomly pull out one and it is red. If you chose 2, your p(it will rain) is less than .5 If you chose 1, your p(it will rain) is greater than .5

Assume you think it more likely than not that it will rain.

Now which do you chose? I will give you 10 pounds if your chosen statement turns out correct.

1. It will rain tomorrow in Brighton.

2. I have a bag with 3 red chips and 1 blue. I randomly pick a chip and it is red.

Assume you think it more likely than not that it will rain.

Now which do you chose? I will give you 10 pounds if your chosen statement turns out correct.

1. It will rain tomorrow in Brighton.

2. I have a bag with 3 red chips and 1 blue. I randomly pick a chip and it is red. If you chose 2, your p(it will rain) is less than .75 (but more than .5)
If you chose 1, your p(it will rain) is more than .75.

By imagining a bag with differing numbers of red and blue chips, you can make your personal probability as precise as you like.

This is a notion of probability that applies to the truth of theories (Remember objective probability does not apply to theories) So that means we can answer questions about p(H) the probability of a hypothesis being true and also p(H|D) the probability of a hypothesis given data (which we cannot do on the Neyman-Pearson approach).

Consider a theory you might be testing in your project.

What is your personal probability that the theory is true?

ODDS in favour of a theory = P(theory is true)/P(theory is false)

For example, for the theory you may be testing extroverts have high cortical arousal
Then you might think (its completely up to you)

P(theory is true) = 0.5

It follows you think that

P(theory is false) = 1 P(theory is true) = 0.5


So odds in favour of theory = 0.5/0.5 = 1 Even odds

If you think
P(theory is true) = 0.8 Then you must think

P(theory is false) = 0.2

So your odds in favour of the theory are 0.8/0.2 = 4 (4 to 1)

What are your odds in favour of the theory you are testing in your project?

Odds before you have collected your data are called your prior odds

Experimental results tell you by how much to increase your odds (the Bayes Factor, B)
Odds after collecting your data are called your posterior odds

Posterior odds = B * Prior odds

For example, a Bayesian analysis might lead to a B of 5.

What would your posterior odds for your project hypothesis be?

You can convert back to probabilities with the formula:

P (Theory is true) = odds/(odds + 1)

So if your prior odds had been 1 and the Bayes factor 5 Then posterior odds = 5 Your posterior probability of your theory being true = 5/6 = .83

Not a black and white decision like significance testing (conclude one thing if p = .048 and another if p = .052)

While your prior odds are subjective

ALL assumptions going into B are explicit, and can be argued about until - in principle - agreed on by everyone

Then B is to that degree objective

Contrast Neyman Pearson e.g. nobody might know what the actual stopping rule was. Assumptions are not necessarily explicit. People can cheat in this way with Neyman Pearson one cant in Bayes.

If B is greater than 1 then the data supported your experimental hypothesis over the null

If B is less than 1, then the data supported the null hypothesis over the experimental one

If B = about 1, experiment was not sensitive. (Automatically get a notion of sensitivity; contrast: just relying on p values in significance testing.)

For each experiment you run, just keep updating your odds/personal probability by multiplying by each new Bayes factor

No need for p values at all! No need for power calculations! No need for critical values of t-tests! And as we will see: No need for post hoc tests!

No need to plan number of subjects in advance!

To know which theory data support need to know what the theories predict

The null is normally the prediction of e.g. no difference

Need to decide what difference or range of differences are consistent with ones theory Difficult - but forces one to think clearly about ones theory.

And this is what is required for power calculations, so psychologists should be doing it anyway. Bayes forces one to.

Contrasts with Neyman-Pearson:


1. A) A non-significant result can mean one should decrease ones confidence in the null hypothesis.

A theory predicts a difference between conditions, but a null result is obtained.

Prediction of null

Mean of data

SE

Difference between conditions

10

15

20

Should one be less confident in the theory relative to the null hypothesis?

What does the theory predict?

What does the theory predict?

Prediction of null

Mean of data If theory predicts a difference of 10 units, should slightly increase confidence in theory over null

SE

10

15

20

Difference between conditions

What does the theory predict?


But if theory predicts a difference of 20 units, data should decrease confidence in theory over null Prediction of null

Mean of data

SE

10

15

20

Difference between conditions

NB It is simplistic to think the theory predicts only one value but Bayes can deal with a range of values

(it typically does)

Contrasts with Neyman-Pearson:


1. A) A non-significant result can mean one should decrease ones confidence in the null.

Conversely

B) A significant result (i.e. accepting the experimental hypothesis on Neyman Pearson) can mean one should increase ones confidence in the null

A theory predicts a difference between conditions, and one is obtained. Should one be more confident in the theory relative to the null?
Data mean

Prediction of null

SE

10

15

20

Difference between conditions

What does the theory predict?

Data mean

Prediction of null

If theory predicts e.g. 20 or more, then significant result is evidence against theory

SE

10 15 Difference between conditions

20

More normally it is because the theory is vague that a significant result leads to less confidence in the theory

i.e. many of the possible predictions of the theory are far from the data

i.e. because the theory makes no precise prediction at all!

The fact the null makes a precise prediction makes it more falsifiable, and hence preferred this CAN mean one should be more confident in null Bayesian inference would encourage scientists to make more falsifiable theories; significance testing (without power) encourages theories of low falsifiability

2. On Neyman Pearson, it matters whether you formulated your hypothesis before or after looking at the data. Post hoc vs planned comparisons Predictions made in advance of rather than before looking at the data are treated differently

Bayesian inference: It does not matter what day of the week you thought of your theory The evidence for your theory is just as strong regardless of its timing

3. On Neyman Pearson standardly you should plan in advance how many subjects you will run.
If you just miss out on a significant result you cant just run 10 more subjects and test again.

You cannot run until you get a significant result.

Bayes: It does not matter when you decide to stop running subjects. You can always run more subjects if you think it will help.

4. On Neyman Pearson you must correct for how many tests you conduct in total.
For example, if you ran 100 correlations and 4 were just significant, researchers would not try to interpret those significant results.

On Bayes, it does not matter how many other statistical hypotheses you investigated. All that matters is the data relevant to each hypothesis under investigation.

The strengths of Bayesian analyses are also its weaknesses:

1) P-values do not require specifying a predicted effect size so significance testing is simple. Bayes requires saying what the theory predicts there may be argument over what effect size a theory predicts. Using p-values side steps this argument.

The strengths of Bayesian analyses are also its weaknesses:

1) P-values do not require specifying a predicted effect size so is simple. Bayes requires saying what the theory predicts there may be argument over what effect size a theory predicts.

BUT isnt this just the sort of argument the field needs?
If someone disagrees they can argue their case in Bayes all assumptions must be explicit.

In Neyman Pearson some important aspects are hidden.

Neyman Pearson done properly requires specifying effect size.

The strengths of Bayesian analyses are also its weaknesses:


2) Bayesian procedures because they are not concerned with long term frequencies - are not guaranteed to control error probabilities (Type I, type II).

The strengths of Bayesian analyses are also its weaknesses:


2) Bayesian procedures because they are not concerned with long term frequencies - are not guaranteed to control error probabilities (Type I, type II). Which is more important to you to use a procedure with known long term error rates or to know the degree of support for your theory (the amount by which you should change your conviction in a theory)?

To calculate a Bayes factor must decide what range of differences is consistent with the theory

1)Uniform distribution

2)Half normal
3)Normal

Example: The theory predicts a difference will be in one direction.

Minimally informative prior, other than difference is positive:

Probability density

10

20
Maximum difference allowed

Difference between conditions

Seems more plausible to think the larger effects are less likely than the smaller ones:

Probability density

Difference between conditions

But how to scale the rate of drop?

Similar sorts of effects as those predicted in the past have been on the order of a 5% difference between conditions in classification accuracy.

Probability density

Difference between conditions

Implies: Smaller effects more likely than bigger ones; effects bigger than 10% very unlikely

Probability density

10
Difference between conditions

To calculate Bayes factor in a t-test situation Need same information from the data as for a t-test:

Mean difference, Mdiff


SE of difference, SEdiff

To calculate Bayes factor in a t-test situation Need same information from the data as for a t-test:

Mean difference, Mdiff


SE of difference, SEdiff

Note: t = Mdiff / SEdiff


So if a paper gives Mdiff and t For any of between- or within-subjects or single-sample t-test you know SEdiff = Mdiff / t
NB: F(1,x) = t2(x)

To calculate a Bayes factor: 1) Google Zoltan Dienes 2) First site to come up is the right one: http://www.lifesci.sussex.ac.uk/home/Zoltan_Dienes/ 3) Click on link to book 4) Click on link to Chapter Four 5) Scroll down and click on Click here to calculate your Bayes factor!

Example: On a task where people make binary classifications about 65% correct (i.e. 15% above chance) we load working memory to see if it interferes difference = control condition memory load condition

Probability density

10

15
Maximum difference expected

Difference between conditions

Jeffreys, 1961: Bayes factors more than 3 or less than a third are substantial

Similar sorts of effects as those predicted in the past have been on the order of a 5% difference between conditions in classification accuracy.

Probability density

Difference between conditions

Implies: Smaller effects more likely than bigger ones; effects bigger than 10% very unlikely

Probability density

10
Difference between conditions

Assignment: 12) What was the mean difference obtained in the study? 13) What was the standard error of this difference? 14) Extending your answer in (7), specify a probability distribution for the difference expected by the theory and justify it

15) What is the Bayes factor in favour of the theory over the null hypothesis?
16) What does this Bayes factor tell you that the t-test does not?

S-ar putea să vă placă și